Misplaced Pages

Weakly compact cardinal

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Type of large cardinal in set theory

In mathematics, a weakly compact cardinal is a certain kind of cardinal number introduced by Erdős & Tarski (1961); weakly compact cardinals are large cardinals, meaning that their existence cannot be proven from the standard axioms of set theory. (Tarski originally called them "not strongly incompact" cardinals.)

Formally, a cardinal κ is defined to be weakly compact if it is uncountable and for every function f: → {0, 1} there is a set of cardinality κ that is homogeneous for f. In this context, means the set of 2-element subsets of κ, and a subset S of κ is homogeneous for f if and only if either all of maps to 0 or all of it maps to 1.

The name "weakly compact" refers to the fact that if a cardinal is weakly compact then a certain related infinitary language satisfies a version of the compactness theorem; see below.

Equivalent formulations

The following are equivalent for any uncountable cardinal κ:

  1. κ is weakly compact.
  2. for every λ<κ, natural number n ≥ 2, and function f: → λ, there is a set of cardinality κ that is homogeneous for f. (Drake 1974, chapter 7 theorem 3.5)
  3. κ is inaccessible and has the tree property, that is, every tree of height κ has either a level of size κ or a branch of size κ.
  4. Every linear order of cardinality κ has an ascending or a descending sequence of order type κ. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)
  5. κ is Π 1 1 {\displaystyle \Pi _{1}^{1}} -indescribable.
  6. κ has the extension property. In other words, for all UVκ there exists a transitive set X with κ ∈ X, and a subset SX, such that (Vκ, ∈, U) is an elementary substructure of (X, ∈, S). Here, U and S are regarded as unary predicates.
  7. For every set S of cardinality κ of subsets of κ, there is a non-trivial κ-complete filter that decides S.
  8. κ is κ-unfoldable.
  9. κ is inaccessible and the infinitary language Lκ,κ satisfies the weak compactness theorem.
  10. κ is inaccessible and the infinitary language Lκ,ω satisfies the weak compactness theorem.
  11. κ is inaccessible and for every transitive set M {\displaystyle M} of cardinality κ with κ M {\displaystyle \in M} , < κ M M {\displaystyle {}^{<\kappa }M\subset M} , and satisfying a sufficiently large fragment of ZFC, there is an elementary embedding j {\displaystyle j} from M {\displaystyle M} to a transitive set N {\displaystyle N} of cardinality κ such that < κ N N {\displaystyle ^{<\kappa }N\subset N} , with critical point c r i t ( j ) = {\displaystyle crit(j)=} κ. (Hauser 1991, Theorem 1.3)
  12. κ = κ < κ {\displaystyle \kappa =\kappa ^{<\kappa }} ( κ < κ {\displaystyle \kappa ^{<\kappa }} defined as λ < κ κ λ {\displaystyle \sum _{\lambda <\kappa }\kappa ^{\lambda }} ) and every κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -complete filter of a κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -complete field of sets of cardinality κ {\displaystyle \leq \kappa } is contained in a κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -complete ultrafilter. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)
  13. κ {\displaystyle \kappa } has Alexander's property, i.e. for any space X {\displaystyle X} with a κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -subbase A {\displaystyle {\mathcal {A}}} with cardinality κ {\displaystyle \leq \kappa } , and every cover of X {\displaystyle X} by elements of A {\displaystyle {\mathcal {A}}} has a subcover of cardinality < κ {\displaystyle <\kappa } , then X {\displaystyle X} is κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -compact. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.182--185)
  14. ( 2 κ ) κ {\displaystyle (2^{\kappa })_{\kappa }} is κ {\displaystyle \kappa } -compact. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)

A language Lκ,κ is said to satisfy the weak compactness theorem if whenever Σ is a set of sentences of cardinality at most κ and every subset with less than κ elements has a model, then Σ has a model. Strongly compact cardinals are defined in a similar way without the restriction on the cardinality of the set of sentences.

Properties

Every weakly compact cardinal is a reflecting cardinal, and is also a limit of reflecting cardinals. This means also that weakly compact cardinals are Mahlo cardinals, and the set of Mahlo cardinals less than a given weakly compact cardinal is stationary.

If κ {\displaystyle \kappa } is weakly compact, then there are chains of well-founded elementary end-extensions of ( V κ , ) {\displaystyle (V_{\kappa },\in )} of arbitrary length < κ + {\displaystyle <\kappa ^{+}} .

Weakly compact cardinals remain weakly compact in L {\displaystyle L} . Assuming V = L, a cardinal is weakly compact iff it is 2-stationary.

See also

References

Citations

  1. Villaveces, Andres (1996). "Chains of End Elementary Extensions of Models of Set Theory". arXiv:math/9611209.
  2. T. Jech, 'Set Theory: The third millennium edition' (2003)
  3. Bagaria, Magidor, Mancilla. On the Consistency Strength of Hyperstationarity, p.3. (2019)
Category: