Revision as of 02:12, 22 September 2022 editSrich32977 (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers299,660 edits copy editsTags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit iOS app edit← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 14:54, 5 September 2024 edit undoDevgirl (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users600 edits →In philosophy | ||
(39 intermediate revisions by 26 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{short description|Approach to historiography}} | {{short description|Approach to historiography}} | ||
{{Use dmy dates|date=April 2022}} | {{Use dmy dates|date=April 2022}} | ||
'''Whig history''' (or '''Whig historiography''') is an approach to ] that presents history as a journey from an oppressive and benighted past to a "glorious present".<ref>{{ |
'''Whig history''' (or '''Whig historiography''') is an approach to ] that presents history as a journey from an oppressive and benighted past to a "glorious present".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Blackburn |first=Simon |chapter=Whig view of history |title=The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy |year=2008 |url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001/acref-9780199541430-e-3300 |location=Oxford |publisher=Oxford University Press |language=en |doi=10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001 |isbn=978-0-19-954143-0 }}</ref> The present described is generally one with modern forms of ] and ]: it was originally a term for the ]s praising Britain's adoption of constitutional monarchy and the historical development of the ].{{Sfn|Cronon|2012}} The term has also been applied widely in historical disciplines outside of ] (e.g. in the ]) to describe "any subjection of history to what is essentially a ] view of the historical process".{{sfn|Burrow|2008|p=473}} When the term is used in contexts other than British history, "whig history" (lowercase) is preferred.{{sfn | Burrow | 2008 | p=473}} | ||
In the British context, whig historians emphasize the rise of ], ]s and ].{{sfn|Marwick|2001|p=74}}{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=20}} The term is often applied generally (and ]) to histories that present the past as the inexorable march of ] towards enlightenment. The term is also used extensively in the ] to refer to historiography that focuses on the successful chains of theories and experiments that led to present-day theories, while ignoring failed theories and dead ends.{{Sfn|Mayr|1990}} | In the British context, whig historians emphasize the rise of ], ]s and ].{{sfn|Marwick|2001|p=74}}{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=20}} The term is often applied generally (and ]) to histories that present the past as the inexorable march of ] towards enlightenment. The term is also used extensively in the ] to refer to historiography that focuses on the successful chains of theories and experiments that led to present-day theories, while ignoring failed theories and dead ends.{{Sfn|Mayr|1990}} | ||
Line 8: | Line 8: | ||
== Terminology == | == Terminology == | ||
The British historian ] |
The British historian ] used the term "Whig history" in his short but influential book ''The Whig Interpretation of History'' (1931).<ref>{{Cite book|last=Butterfield |first=Sir Herbert |author-link=Herbert Butterfield |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/218992532|title=The Whig Interpretation of History|date=1981|publisher=University of New South Wales Library|oclc=218992532}}</ref> It takes its name from the British ], advocates of the power of ], who opposed the ], advocates of the power of the king.{{Sfn|Torr|2000|p=52–53}} | ||
Butterfield's usage of the term was |
Butterfield's usage of the term was not in relation to the British or American Whig parties or Whiggism, but rather took aim at "the nineteenth-century school of historiography that praised all progress and habitually associated Protestantism with liberal views of liberty".{{Sfn|Sewell|2005}} The terms "whig" and "whiggish" are now used broadly, becoming "universal descriptors for all progressive narratives".{{Sfn|Cronon|2012}} | ||
⚫ | When ] in 1928 gave a Raleigh lecture, he implied that the "whig historians" really were Whigs (i.e. associated with the Whig party or its Liberal successor) and had written centrist histories that were "good history despite their enthusiasm for Gladstonian or Liberal Unionist causes"; on introduction the term was mostly approbatory, unlike Butterfield's later use, since Fisher applauded ]'s "instructive and illuminating" history.{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=171}} By the time Butterfield wrote his ''Whig Interpretation'', he may have been beating a dead horse: P. B. M. Blaas, in his 1978 book ''Continuity and Anachronism'', argued that whig history itself had lost all vitality by 1914.{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=95|ps=. Bentley however argues against Blaas' conclusion: Blaas' historiography is mostly focused on parliamentary history, which "pre-dates significant changes in whig typologies... sometimes by several decades the case of imperial historiography"; in contrast to what Blaas' assumes, there was no strong connection between whig historians and the Liberal party; new pre-1914 archival information also is now available.}} Subsequent generations of academic historians have rejected Whig history because of its ] and teleological assumption that history is driving toward some sort of goal. | ||
== Herbert Butterfield == | |||
⚫ | When ] in 1928 gave a Raleigh lecture, he implied that the "whig historians" really were Whigs (i.e. associated with the Whig party or its Liberal successor) and had written centrist histories that were "good history despite their enthusiasm for Gladstonian or Liberal Unionist causes"; |
||
=== ''The Whig Interpretation of History'' === | === ''The Whig Interpretation of History'' === | ||
Line 24: | Line 23: | ||
He also criticised it for modernising the past: "the result is that to many of us seem much more modern than they really were, and even when we have corrected this impression by closer study we find it difficult to keep in mind the differences between their world and ours".{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=34}} | He also criticised it for modernising the past: "the result is that to many of us seem much more modern than they really were, and even when we have corrected this impression by closer study we find it difficult to keep in mind the differences between their world and ours".{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=34}} | ||
Whig history is also criticised as having an overly dualist view with heroes on the side of liberty and freedom against traditionalist villains opposing the inevitability of progress.{{Sfn|Hart|1965 |
Whig history is also criticised as having an overly dualist view with heroes on the side of liberty and freedom against traditionalist villains opposing the inevitability of progress.{{Sfn|Hart|1965|p=39}} It also casts an overly negative view of opposing parties to heroes described, taking such parties "to have contributed nothing to the making of the present" and at worst converting them into a "dummy that acts as a better foil to the grand whig virtues".{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=35}} Butterfield illustrated this by criticising views of ] and the ] which "are inclined to write sometimes as though Protestantism in itself was somehow constituted to assist "{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=37}} and misconceptions that the ] was created by Whigs opposed by Tories rather than created by compromise and interplay mediated by then-political contingencies.{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=41}} | ||
He also felt that whig history viewed the world in terms of a morality play: that " inconclusive unless he can give a verdict; and studying Protestant and Catholic in the 16th century he feels that loose threads are still left hanging unless he can show which party was in the right".{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=65}} | He also felt that whig history viewed the world in terms of a morality play: that " inconclusive unless he can give a verdict; and studying Protestant and Catholic in the 16th century he feels that loose threads are still left hanging unless he can show which party was in the right".{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|p=65}} | ||
Butterfield instead advances a view of history stressing the accidental and contingent nature of events rather than some kind of inevitable and structural shift.{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|pp=68–69}} Moreover, he called upon historians "to evoke a certain sensibility towards the past, the sensibility which studies the past 'for the sake of the past', which delights in the concrete and the complex, which 'goes out to meet the past', which searches for 'unlikenesses between past and present'".{{Sfn|Wilson|Ashplant|2009|p=10}}{{Failed verification|date=April 2021}} | Butterfield instead advances a view of history stressing the accidental and contingent nature of events rather than some kind of inevitable and structural shift.{{Sfn|Butterfield|1965|pp=68–69}} Moreover, he called upon historians "to evoke a certain sensibility towards the past, the sensibility which studies the past 'for the sake of the past', which delights in the concrete and the complex, which 'goes out to meet the past', which searches for 'unlikenesses between past and present{{'"}}.{{Sfn|Wilson|Ashplant|2009|p=10}}{{Failed verification|date=April 2021}} | ||
A decade later however, if under wartime pressure from the ], Butterfield would note of the Whig interpretation that "whatever it may have done to our history, it has had a wonderful effect on our politics....In every Englishman there is hidden something of a whig that seems to tug at the heart-strings".{{sfn | Burrow | 2008 | p=474}} | A decade later however, if under wartime pressure from the ], Butterfield would note of the Whig interpretation that "whatever it may have done to our history, it has had a wonderful effect on our politics....In every Englishman there is hidden something of a whig that seems to tug at the heart-strings".{{sfn | Burrow | 2008 | p=474}} | ||
Line 37: | Line 36: | ||
{{blockquote|It was fiercely partisan and righteously judgemental, dividing the personnel of the past into the good and the bad. And it did so on the basis of the marked preference for ] and progressive causes, rather than ] and reactionary ones ... Whig history was, in short, an extremely biased view of the past: eager to hand out moral judgements, and distorted by teleology, anachronism and present-mindedness.{{sfn|Cannadine|1993|p=197}}}} | {{blockquote|It was fiercely partisan and righteously judgemental, dividing the personnel of the past into the good and the bad. And it did so on the basis of the marked preference for ] and progressive causes, rather than ] and reactionary ones ... Whig history was, in short, an extremely biased view of the past: eager to hand out moral judgements, and distorted by teleology, anachronism and present-mindedness.{{sfn|Cannadine|1993|p=197}}}} | ||
] in ''What |
] in '']'' (1961) gave the book the backhanded compliment of being "a remarkable book in many ways" noting that "though it denounced the whig interpretation over some 130 pages, it did not... name a single whig except ], who was no historian, or a single historian save ], who was no whig".{{Sfn|Carr|1990|p=41}}{{Sfn|Cronon|2012}} | ||
] analyses Butterfield's whig theory as referring to a canon of 19th-century historians in and of England (such as ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ] and ]) that in fact excludes few except ].{{Sfn|Bentley|2005|p=65}} The theory identifies the common factors and Bentley comments: | ] analyses Butterfield's whig theory as referring to a canon of 19th-century historians in and of England (such as ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ] and ]) that in fact excludes few except ].{{Sfn|Bentley|2005|p=65}} The theory identifies the common factors and Bentley comments: | ||
Line 49: | Line 48: | ||
]'s history of England, published in 1723, became "the classic Whig history" for the first half of the eighteenth century.{{sfn|Trevor-Roper|1979|p=10}}{{Verify source|date=April 2021}} Rapin claimed that the English had preserved their ] against the absolutist tendencies of the ]. However, Rapin's history lost its place as the standard history of England in the late 18th century and early 19th century to that of ].{{Citation needed|date=April 2021}} | ]'s history of England, published in 1723, became "the classic Whig history" for the first half of the eighteenth century.{{sfn|Trevor-Roper|1979|p=10}}{{Verify source|date=April 2021}} Rapin claimed that the English had preserved their ] against the absolutist tendencies of the ]. However, Rapin's history lost its place as the standard history of England in the late 18th century and early 19th century to that of ].{{Citation needed|date=April 2021}} | ||
]'s '']'' (1765–1769) reveals many Whiggish traits.{{Citation needed|date=April 2021}} | |||
According to ], however, ] was the first whig historian, publishing ''Constitutional History of England'' in 1827, which "greatly exaggerated the importance of 'parliaments' or of bodies thought were parliaments" while tending "to interpret all political struggles in terms of the parliamentary situation in Britain the nineteenth century, in terms, that is, of Whig reformers fighting the good fight against Tory defenders of the status quo".{{sfn|Marwick|2001|pp=74–75}} | According to ], however, ] was the first whig historian, publishing ''Constitutional History of England'' in 1827, which "greatly exaggerated the importance of 'parliaments' or of bodies thought were parliaments" while tending "to interpret all political struggles in terms of the parliamentary situation in Britain the nineteenth century, in terms, that is, of Whig reformers fighting the good fight against Tory defenders of the status quo".{{sfn|Marwick|2001|pp=74–75}} | ||
Line 60: | Line 57: | ||
Hume still dominated English historiography, but this changed when ] entered the field, utilising Fox and Mackintosh's work and manuscript collections. Macaulay's '']'' was published in a series of volumes from 1848 to 1855.{{sfn|Marwick|2001|pp=74–75}} It proved an immediate success, replacing Hume's history and becoming the new orthodoxy.{{sfn|Trevor-Roper|1979|pp=25–26}} As if to introduce a linear progressive view of history, the first chapter of Macaulay's ''History of England'' proposes: | Hume still dominated English historiography, but this changed when ] entered the field, utilising Fox and Mackintosh's work and manuscript collections. Macaulay's '']'' was published in a series of volumes from 1848 to 1855.{{sfn|Marwick|2001|pp=74–75}} It proved an immediate success, replacing Hume's history and becoming the new orthodoxy.{{sfn|Trevor-Roper|1979|pp=25–26}} As if to introduce a linear progressive view of history, the first chapter of Macaulay's ''History of England'' proposes: | ||
<blockquote>The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical, of moral, and of intellectual improvement.<ref>{{Cite wikisource|title=The History of England from the Accession of James II|first=Thomas Babington|last=Macaulay|year=1848|wslink=The History of England from the Accession of James II|volume=1|chapter=Chapter I|page=14}}</ref>{{sfn|Marwick|2001|p=74}}</blockquote>While Macaulay was a popular and celebrated historian of the whig school, his work did not feature in Butterfield's 1931 ''Whig Interpretation of History''.{{sfn|Carr|1990|p=41}} According to Ernst Breisach, "his style captivated the public as did his good sense of the past and firm whiggish convictions".<ref name="Breisach 2007">{{cite book | last=Breisach | first=E. | title=Historiography: Ancient, Medieval, and Modern, Third Edition | publisher=University of Chicago Press | series=ACLS Humanities E-Book | year=2007 | isbn=978-0-226-07283-8 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7Juypp-VVg4C | access-date=2021-04-25 | page=}}</ref> | <blockquote>The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical, of moral, and of intellectual improvement.<ref>{{Cite wikisource|title=The History of England from the Accession of James II|first=Thomas Babington|last=Macaulay|year=1848|wslink=The History of England from the Accession of James II|volume=1|chapter=Chapter I|page=14}}</ref>{{sfn|Marwick|2001|p=74}}</blockquote>While Macaulay was a popular and celebrated historian of the whig school, his work did not feature in Butterfield's 1931 ''Whig Interpretation of History''.{{sfn|Carr|1990|p=41}} According to Ernst Breisach, "his style captivated the public as did his good sense of the past and firm whiggish convictions".<ref name="Breisach 2007">{{cite book | last=Breisach | first=E. | title=Historiography: Ancient, Medieval, and Modern, Third Edition | publisher=University of Chicago Press | series=ACLS Humanities E-Book | year=2007 | isbn=978-0-226-07283-8 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7Juypp-VVg4C | access-date=2021-04-25 | page=}}</ref> | ||
=== William Stubbs === | === William Stubbs === | ||
] (1825–1901), the constitutional historian and influential teacher of a generation of historians, was the author of the extremely influential ''Constitutional History of England'' (published between 1873–78){{Sfn|Bentley|2006|pp=23 et seq}} and became a crucial figure in the later survival and respectability of whig history. According to Reba Soffer, | ] (1825–1901), the constitutional historian and influential teacher of a generation of historians, was the author of the extremely influential ''Constitutional History of England'' (published between 1873–78){{Sfn|Bentley|2006|pp=23 et seq}} and became a crucial figure in the later survival and respectability of whig history. According to ], | ||
{{blockquote|Stubbs was a true believer who concealed his biases, even from himself, behind the |
{{blockquote|Stubbs was a true believer who concealed his biases, even from himself, behind the façade of a dispassionate historian translating original documents into magisterial prose. His rhetorical gifts often obscured his combination of high church Anglicanism, whig history, and civic responsibility. In the Church of England, Stubbs saw the original model for the development and maintenance of English liberties.<ref name="Soffer1994">{{cite book|author=Reba N. Soffer |author-link=Reba Soffer |title=Discipline and Power: The University, History, and the Making of an English Elite, 1870–1930 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Z17aoQEACAAJ |year=1994 |publisher=Stanford University Press |isbn=978-0-8047-2383-1 |pages=87–88 }}</ref>}} | ||
Stubb's history began with an imagined Anglo-Saxon past into which representative parliamentary institutions emerged and fought for control with the absolutist crown in various stages (including overreaches in during the ]) before uniting in "nation, church, peers and people" in the ].{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=32}} This view of events was substantially challenged: Maitland discovered in 1893 that the early "parliaments" had "no hint of operating as a representative body but resembled instead a meeting of the King's Council, called to meet the king's purposes; it passed no 'legislation', but rather considered petitions or 'bills' as though acting as an ultimate court of justice".{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=33}} ], writing in 1920, also shot through much of Stubbs' ideas on the representative and law-making powers of early English parliaments, pulling the emergence of a semi-independent House of Commons to the 1620s.{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=37}} | Stubb's history began with an imagined Anglo-Saxon past into which representative parliamentary institutions emerged and fought for control with the absolutist crown in various stages (including overreaches in during the ]) before uniting in "nation, church, peers and people" in the ].{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=32}} This view of events was substantially challenged: Maitland discovered in 1893 that the early "parliaments" had "no hint of operating as a representative body but resembled instead a meeting of the King's Council, called to meet the king's purposes; it passed no 'legislation', but rather considered petitions or 'bills' as though acting as an ultimate court of justice".{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=33}} ], writing in 1920, also shot through much of Stubbs' ideas on the representative and law-making powers of early English parliaments, pulling the emergence of a semi-independent House of Commons to the 1620s.{{Sfn|Bentley|2006|p=37}} | ||
=== Robert Hebert Quick === | === Robert Hebert Quick === | ||
Political history was the usual venue for whig history in Great Britain, but it also appears in other areas. ] (1831–1891) was one of the leaders of the Whig school of the history of education, along with G. A. N. Lowndes. In 1898, Quick explained the value of studying the history of educational reform, arguing that the great accomplishments of the past were cumulative and comprised the building blocks that “would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us”.<ref name="McCulloch 2011">{{cite book | last=McCulloch | first=Gary | title=The Struggle for the History of Education | publisher=Taylor & Francis | series=Foundations and Futures of Education | year=2011 | isbn=978-1-136-81124-1 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CKmdgRVlHpMC | access-date=2021-04-25 | page=28 |quote= |
Political history was the usual venue for whig history in Great Britain, but it also appears in other areas. ] (1831–1891) was one of the leaders of the Whig school of the history of education, along with G. A. N. Lowndes. In 1898, Quick explained the value of studying the history of educational reform, arguing that the great accomplishments of the past were cumulative and comprised the building blocks that “would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us”.<ref name="McCulloch 2011">{{cite book | last=McCulloch | first=Gary | title=The Struggle for the History of Education | publisher=Taylor & Francis | series=Foundations and Futures of Education | year=2011 | isbn=978-1-136-81124-1 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CKmdgRVlHpMC | access-date=2021-04-25 | page=28 |quote=Indeed, he concluded, 'the great thinkers would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us, and lead us to press forward in it with good heart and hope' (Quick 1868/1902, p. 526).}}</ref> | ||
=== End of whig history === | === End of whig history === | ||
Line 79: | Line 76: | ||
<blockquote>Accelerated by the sceptical power of a new breed of historian epitomized in the brilliance of F. W. Maitland, whiggery had begun its turn downwards (we are told) and met its Waterloo on the Somme{{sfn|Bentley|2006|p=7}} ... win thrusts—on the one hand cultural despair in face of a dead civilization, on the other a determination to make history say something different for the post-war generation—worked between them to put whig susceptibilities between a rock and a hard place.{{sfn|Bentley|2006|p=104}}</blockquote> | <blockquote>Accelerated by the sceptical power of a new breed of historian epitomized in the brilliance of F. W. Maitland, whiggery had begun its turn downwards (we are told) and met its Waterloo on the Somme{{sfn|Bentley|2006|p=7}} ... win thrusts—on the one hand cultural despair in face of a dead civilization, on the other a determination to make history say something different for the post-war generation—worked between them to put whig susceptibilities between a rock and a hard place.{{sfn|Bentley|2006|p=104}}</blockquote> | ||
Bentley also speculates that 19th |
Bentley also speculates that 19th-century British historiography took the form of an indirect social history which "attempted to embrace society by absorbing it into the history of the state", a project gravely disrupted by the First World War and renewed questions on "the pretensions of the state as an avatar of social harmony".{{sfn|Bentley|2005|p=71|ps=. Bentley speculates that "for men such as Stubbs, the attraction of law and constitutional practice lay in their ability to reflect the lives of thousands of anonymous people and thus provide access to those who could never be reached via direct oral testimony".}} He, however, notes that whig history has not died "outside the academy" and lives on partially in criticism of history as something published in "a row of small-minded monographs written by authors calling themselves 'doctor', whose life-experience and sense of English culture extended no further than taking cups of tea in the ]".{{sfn|Bentley|2006|p=8}} | ||
== Later instances and criticism == | == Later instances and criticism == | ||
=== In science === | === In science === | ||
It has been argued that the ] is "riddled with Whiggish history".<ref>{{Cite book|last=McIntire|first=C. T.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9s1dAjUbDzMC|title=Herbert Butterfield: Historian as Dissenter|date=2004|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=978-0-300-09807-5|pages=205|language=en}}</ref>{{Verify source|date=April 2021}} Like other whig histories, whig history of science tends to divide historical actors into "good guys" who are on the side of truth (as is now known), and "bad guys" who opposed the emergence of these truths because of ignorance or bias.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Schuster|first=John Andrew|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cxxiAAAACAAJ|title=The Scientific Revolution: An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science|publisher=Department of Science & Technology Studies, University of Wollongong|year=1995|isbn=978-0-86418-337-8|language=en|chapter=The Problem of 'Whig History |
It has been argued that the ] is "riddled with Whiggish history".<ref>{{Cite book|last=McIntire|first=C. T.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9s1dAjUbDzMC|title=Herbert Butterfield: Historian as Dissenter|date=2004|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=978-0-300-09807-5|pages=205|language=en}}</ref>{{Verify source|date=April 2021}} Like other whig histories, whig history of science tends to divide historical actors into "good guys" who are on the side of truth (as is now known), and "bad guys" who opposed the emergence of these truths because of ignorance or bias.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Schuster|first=John Andrew|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cxxiAAAACAAJ|title=The Scientific Revolution: An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science|publisher=Department of Science & Technology Studies, University of Wollongong|year=1995|isbn=978-0-86418-337-8|language=en|chapter=The Problem of 'Whig History' in the History of Science|chapter-url=https://descartesagonistes.files.wordpress.com/2020/03/schuster-scirev-ch-3.pdf}}</ref> Science is seen as emerging from "a series of victories over pre-scientific thinking".{{sfn | Burrow | 2008 | p=474}} From this whiggish perspective, ] would be criticized because his astronomical system placed the Earth at the center of the universe while ] would be praised because he placed the Sun at the center of the ]. This kind of evaluation ignores historical background and the evidence that was available at a particular time: Did Aristarchus have evidence to support his idea that the Sun was at the center? Were there good reasons to reject Ptolemy's system before the sixteenth century? | ||
The writing of Whig history of science is especially found in the writings of scientists{{sfn|Bowler|Morus|2005|p=2|ps=. "The conventional stories of the past that appear in the introductory chapters of science textbooks are certainly a form of Whiggism. Historians take great delight in exposing the artificially constructed nature of these stories, and some scientists find the results uncomfortable".}} and general historians,{{sfn|Alder|2002|p=301 |ps=. "The history of |
The writing of Whig history of science is especially found in the writings of scientists{{sfn|Bowler|Morus|2005|p=2|ps=. "The conventional stories of the past that appear in the introductory chapters of science textbooks are certainly a form of Whiggism. Historians take great delight in exposing the artificially constructed nature of these stories, and some scientists find the results uncomfortable".}} and general historians,{{sfn|Alder|2002|p=301 |ps=. "The history of science—as composed by both ex-scientists and general historians—has largely consisted of Whig history, in which the scientific winners write the account in such a way as to make their triumph an inevitable outcome of the righteous logic of their cause".}} while this whiggish tendency is commonly opposed by professional historians of science. ] describes the changing attitude to whiggishness this way:<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Jardine|first=Nick|date=2003-06-01|title=Whigs and Stories: Herbert Butterfield and the Historiography of Science|url=https://doi.org/10.1177/007327530304100201|journal=History of Science|language=en|volume=41|issue=2|pages=127–128|doi=10.1177/007327530304100201|bibcode=2003HisSc..41..125J|s2cid=160281821|issn=0073-2753}}</ref> | ||
<blockquote>By the mid-1970s, it had become commonplace among historians of science to employ the terms "Whig" and "Whiggish", often accompanied by one or more of "hagiographic", "internalist", "triumphalist", even "positivist", to denigrate grand narratives of scientific progress. At one level there is, indeed, an obvious parallel with the attacks on Whig constitutional history in the opening decades of the century. For, as P. B. M. Blaas has shown, those earlier attacks were part and parcel of a more general onslaught in the name of an autonomous, professional and scientific history, on popular, partisan and moralising historiography. Similarly, ... For post-WWII champions of the newly professionalized history of science the targets were quite different. Above all, they were out to establish a critical distance between the history of science and the teaching and promotion of the sciences. In particular, they were suspicious of the grand celebratory and didactic narratives of scientific discovery and progress that had proliferated in the inter-war years.</blockquote> | <blockquote>By the mid-1970s, it had become commonplace among historians of science to employ the terms "Whig" and "Whiggish", often accompanied by one or more of "hagiographic", "internalist", "triumphalist", even "positivist", to denigrate grand narratives of scientific progress. At one level there is, indeed, an obvious parallel with the attacks on Whig constitutional history in the opening decades of the century. For, as P. B. M. Blaas has shown, those earlier attacks were part and parcel of a more general onslaught in the name of an autonomous, professional and scientific history, on popular, partisan and moralising historiography. Similarly, ... For post-WWII champions of the newly professionalized history of science the targets were quite different. Above all, they were out to establish a critical distance between the history of science and the teaching and promotion of the sciences. In particular, they were suspicious of the grand celebratory and didactic narratives of scientific discovery and progress that had proliferated in the inter-war years.</blockquote> | ||
More recently, some scholars have argued that Whig history is essential to the history of science. At one level, "the very term 'the history of science' has itself profoundly Whiggish implications. One may be reasonably clear what 'science' means in the 19th century and most of the 18th century. In the 17th century 'science' has very different meaning. Chemistry, for example, was then inextricably mixed up with alchemy. Before the 17th century dissecting out such a thing as 'science' in anything like the modern sense of the term involves profound distortions."<ref>{{Cite web|last=Hyman|first=Anthony|date=1 Oct 1996|title=Whiggism in the History of Science and the Study of the Life and Work of Charles Babbage|url=http://projects.exeter.ac.uk/babbage/whiggism.html |
More recently, some scholars have argued that Whig history is essential to the history of science. At one level, "the very term 'the history of science' has itself profoundly Whiggish implications. One may be reasonably clear what 'science' means in the 19th century and most of the 18th century. In the 17th century 'science' has very different meaning. Chemistry, for example, was then inextricably mixed up with alchemy. Before the 17th century dissecting out such a thing as 'science' in anything like the modern sense of the term involves profound distortions."<ref>{{Cite web|last=Hyman|first=Anthony|date=1 Oct 1996|title=Whiggism in the History of Science and the Study of the Life and Work of Charles Babbage|url=http://projects.exeter.ac.uk/babbage/whiggism.html|access-date=2021-04-25|website=The Babbage Pages}}</ref> The science historians' rejection of whiggishness has been criticised by some scientists for failing to appreciate "the temporal depth of scientific research".<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Harrison|first=Edward|date=September 1987|title=Whigs, prigs and historians of science|url=https://www.nature.com/articles/329213a0|journal=Nature|language=en|volume=329|issue=6136|pages=213–214|doi=10.1038/329213a0|bibcode=1987Natur.329..213H|s2cid=4347987|issn=1476-4687}}</ref> | ||
=== In economics === | === In economics === | ||
Retrospectives on modern macroeconomics are generally whiggish histories. For example, the popularisation of mathematical models by ]'s ''Foundations of Economic Analysis'', when viewed by economists trained in a mathematical framework becomes "an important milestone on the road to the mathematization of economics" in a story told by the victorious.{{Sfn|Torr|2000|pp= |
Retrospectives on modern macroeconomics are generally whiggish histories. For example, the popularisation of mathematical models by ]'s ''Foundations of Economic Analysis'', when viewed by economists trained in a mathematical framework becomes "an important milestone on the road to the mathematization of economics" in a story told by the victorious.{{Sfn|Torr|2000|pp=56–57}} Yet "those who do not agree that such mathematization is a good thing could argue that the mathematical developments... represent a regression rather than a progression".{{Sfn|Torr|2000|p=57}} The introduction of ] similarly carries implicit ]: people who disagree on the reality of agents making decisions in the manner assumed (e.g. ]) "would not necessarily rejoice in present ascendancy".{{Sfn|Torr|2000|p=57}} | ||
Burrow views Marxist history, with its " anticipated terminus from which it derives its moral and political point", as "characteristically whig".{{sfn|Burrow|2008|p=474}} | Burrow views Marxist history, with its " anticipated terminus from which it derives its moral and political point", as "characteristically whig".{{sfn|Burrow|2008|p=474}} | ||
=== In philosophy === | === In philosophy === | ||
One very common example of Whig history is the work of ], to whom is often ascribed a teleological view of history with an inexorable trajectory in the direction of progress.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Pinkard|first=Terry|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Z6Z7DgAAQBAJ|title=Does History Make Sense?| |
One very common example of Whig history is the work of ], to whom is often ascribed a teleological view of history with an inexorable trajectory in the direction of progress.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Pinkard|first=Terry|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Z6Z7DgAAQBAJ|title=Does History Make Sense?|year=2017|publisher=Harvard University Press|isbn=978-0-674-97880-5|language=en}}</ref> | ||
Marxists have had varied views on Whig history. The traditional inheritance of Hegel, interpreted through |
Marxists have had varied views on Whig history. The traditional inheritance of Hegel, interpreted through ]' articulation of ], implied that history progressed from a "primitive communism", through slave societies, feudal societies, capitalism, and finally to socialism and communism. However, contemporary Marxists, such as ], have aggressively challenged those assumptions as deterministic and ahistorical.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Wood |first=Ellen Meiksins |title=Democracy or Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism |publisher=Verso Books |year=2016 |isbn=978-1784782443 |location=United States |pages=108–181}}</ref> ] criticized conception of history which assumed a necessarily progressive or teleological course, though he did not employ the term "Whig history". "The danger affects both the content of the tradition and its receivers. The same threat hangs over both: that of becoming a tool of the ruling classes. In every era the attempt must be made anew to wrest tradition away from a conformism that is about to overpower it."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Benjamin |first=Walter |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/1179424430 |title=Illuminations |publisher=Mariner Books |year=1968 |isbn=978-1328470232 |edition=2nd |location=United States |pages=198–199 |oclc=1179424430}}</ref> | ||
=== In Canadian history === | === In Canadian history === | ||
Regarding Canada, Allan Greer argues: | Regarding Canada, Allan Greer argues: | ||
{{blockquote|The interpretive schemes that dominated Canadian historical writing through the middle decades of the twentieth century were built on the assumption that history had a discernible direction and flow. Canada was moving towards a goal in the nineteenth century; whether this endpoint was the construction of a transcontinental, commercial, and political union, the development of parliamentary government, or the preservation and resurrection of French Canada, it was certainly a Good Thing. Thus the rebels of 1837 were quite literally on the wrong track. They lost because they ''had'' to lose; they were not simply overwhelmed by superior force, they were justly chastised by the God of History.<ref>{{cite journal | last=Greer | first=Allan | title=1837–38: Rebellion Reconsidered | journal=The Canadian Historical Review | volume=76 | issue=1 | date=2016-04-06 | issn=1710-1093 | page=3 | url=https://muse.jhu.edu/article/574662 | access-date=2021-04-25}}</ref>}} | {{blockquote|The interpretive schemes that dominated Canadian historical writing through the middle decades of the twentieth century were built on the assumption that history had a discernible direction and flow. Canada was moving towards a goal in the nineteenth century; whether this endpoint was the construction of a transcontinental, commercial, and political union, the development of parliamentary government, or the preservation and resurrection of French Canada, it was certainly a Good Thing. Thus the ] were quite literally on the wrong track. They lost because they ''had'' to lose; they were not simply overwhelmed by superior force, they were justly chastised by the God of History.<ref>{{cite journal | last=Greer | first=Allan | title=1837–38: Rebellion Reconsidered | journal=The Canadian Historical Review | volume=76 | issue=1 | date=2016-04-06 | issn=1710-1093 | page=3 | url=https://muse.jhu.edu/article/574662 | access-date=2021-04-25}}</ref>}} | ||
=== In the emergence of intelligent life === | === In the emergence of intelligent life === | ||
Line 109: | Line 106: | ||
=== In general history and biography === | === In general history and biography === | ||
James A. Hijiya points out the persistence of whiggish history in history textbooks.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Hijiya|first=James A.|date=1994|title=Why the West Is Lost|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2946864|journal=The William and Mary Quarterly|volume=51|issue=2|page=284|doi=10.2307/2946864|jstor=2946864|issn=0043-5597}}</ref> In the debate over Britishness, ] praised the whig approach on the grounds that "ordered freedom and evolutionary progress ''have'' been among the hallmarks of modern British history, and they ''should'' command respect".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Marquand|first=David|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=bHq_UTjNidQC&q=Gamble+ed.%2C+Britishness&pg=PR7|title=Britishness: Perspectives on the British Question| |
James A. Hijiya points out the persistence of whiggish history in history textbooks.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Hijiya|first=James A.|date=1994|title=Why the West Is Lost|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2946864|journal=The William and Mary Quarterly|volume=51|issue=2|page=284|doi=10.2307/2946864|jstor=2946864|issn=0043-5597}}</ref> In the debate over Britishness, ] praised the whig approach on the grounds that "ordered freedom and evolutionary progress ''have'' been among the hallmarks of modern British history, and they ''should'' command respect".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Marquand|first=David|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=bHq_UTjNidQC&q=Gamble+ed.%2C+Britishness&pg=PR7|title=Britishness: Perspectives on the British Question|year=2009|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|isbn=978-1-4051-9269-9|editor-last=Gamble|editor-first=Andrew|pages=15|language=en|chapter='Bursting with Skeletons': Britishness after Empire|editor-last2=Wright|editor-first2=Tony}}</ref> | ||
Historian ] in his book ''Summer for the Gods: The Scopes Trial and America's Continuing Debate Over Science and Religion'' (1997) challenged a whiggish view of the ]. The book won the ] in 1998.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ladouceur|first=Ronald P.|date=2008-09-01|title=Ella Thea Smith and the Lost History of American High School Biology Textbooks|url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3|journal=Journal of the History of Biology|language=en|volume=41|issue=3|pages=435–471|doi=10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3|pmid=19244720|s2cid=25320197|issn=1573-0387}}</ref> | Historian ] in his book ''Summer for the Gods: The Scopes Trial and America's Continuing Debate Over Science and Religion'' (1997) challenged a whiggish view of the ]. The book won the ] in 1998.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Ladouceur|first=Ronald P.|date=2008-09-01|title=Ella Thea Smith and the Lost History of American High School Biology Textbooks|url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3|journal=Journal of the History of Biology|language=en|volume=41|issue=3|pages=435–471|doi=10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3|pmid=19244720|s2cid=25320197|issn=1573-0387}}</ref> | ||
Line 117: | Line 114: | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
Line 125: | Line 123: | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* '']'' | * '']'' | ||
* '']'' | |||
* '']'' | |||
}} | }} | ||
Line 137: | Line 137: | ||
* {{cite book | last=Burrow | first=John | title=A History of Histories | publisher=Allen Lane | year=2008 | isbn=978-0-307-26852-5 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=G9_yT1eDMuoC | access-date=2021-04-25}} | * {{cite book | last=Burrow | first=John | title=A History of Histories | publisher=Allen Lane | year=2008 | isbn=978-0-307-26852-5 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=G9_yT1eDMuoC | access-date=2021-04-25}} | ||
*{{Cite book|last=Butterfield|first=Herbert|author-link=Herbert Butterfield|title=The Whig Interpretation of History|publisher=WW Norton and Company|year=1965|location=New York|orig-year=1931}} | *{{Cite book|last=Butterfield|first=Herbert|author-link=Herbert Butterfield|title=The Whig Interpretation of History|publisher=WW Norton and Company|year=1965|location=New York|orig-year=1931}} | ||
* {{cite book|last=Cannadine|first=David|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=EcwWAQAAIAAJ|title=G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History|publisher=W.W. Norton|year=1993|isbn=978-0-393-03528-5|page=208}} | * {{cite book|last=Cannadine|first=David|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=EcwWAQAAIAAJ|title=G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History|publisher=W. W. Norton|year=1993|isbn=978-0-393-03528-5|page=208}} | ||
* {{Cite book|last=Carr|first=Edward Hallett |title=What |
* {{Cite book|last=Carr|first=Edward Hallett |title=What Is History?|publisher=Penguin Books|year=1990|edition=2nd|location=London|pages=41|orig-year=1961}} | ||
* {{Cite web|last=Cronon|first=William|date=1 Sep 2012|title=Two Cheers for the Whig Interpretation of History|url=https://www.historians.org/publications-and-directories/perspectives-on-history/september-2012/two-cheers-for-the-whig-interpretation-of-history |
* {{Cite web|last=Cronon|first=William|date=1 Sep 2012|title=Two Cheers for the Whig Interpretation of History|url=https://www.historians.org/publications-and-directories/perspectives-on-history/september-2012/two-cheers-for-the-whig-interpretation-of-history|access-date=2021-04-25|website=Perspectives on History|publisher=American Historical Association}} | ||
*{{cite book|last=Ferguson|first=James|url=https://archive.org/details/antipoliticsmach00ferg|title=The Anti-Politics Machine: "Development," Depoliticization, and Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1990|isbn=9780521373821|url-access=registration}} | *{{cite book|last=Ferguson|first=James|url=https://archive.org/details/antipoliticsmach00ferg|title=The Anti-Politics Machine: "Development," Depoliticization, and Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1990|isbn=9780521373821|url-access=registration}} | ||
* {{cite book|last=Feske|first=Victor|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0ixnAAAAMAAJ|title=From Belloc to Churchill: Private Scholars, Public Culture, and the Crisis of British Liberalism, 1900–1939|publisher=University of North Carolina Press|year=1996|isbn=978-0-8078-4601-8|page=2}} | * {{cite book|last=Feske|first=Victor|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0ixnAAAAMAAJ|title=From Belloc to Churchill: Private Scholars, Public Culture, and the Crisis of British Liberalism, 1900–1939|publisher=University of North Carolina Press|year=1996|isbn=978-0-8078-4601-8|page=2}} | ||
* {{cite book|last1=Gardner|first1=Katy|title=Anthropology and development: challenges for the twenty-first century|last2=Lewis|first2=David|publisher=Pluto Press|year=2015}} | * {{cite book|last1=Gardner|first1=Katy|title=Anthropology and development: challenges for the twenty-first century|last2=Lewis|first2=David|publisher=Pluto Press|year=2015}} | ||
* {{Cite journal|last=Hart|first=Jenifer|date=1965|title=Nineteenth-Century Social Reform: A Tory Interpretation of History|journal=Past & Present |
* {{Cite journal|last=Hart|first=Jenifer|author-link=Jenifer Hart|date=1965|title=Nineteenth-Century Social Reform: A Tory Interpretation of History|journal=Past & Present|issue=31|pages=39–61|doi=10.1093/past/31.1.39|issn=0031-2746|jstor=650101|quote=According to its critics, a whig interpretation of history requires human heroes and villains in the story.|doi-access=free}} | ||
*{{cite book | last1=Kramer | first1=Lloyd | last2=Maza | first2=Sara | title=A Companion to Western Historical Thought | publisher=Wiley | series=Wiley Blackwell Companions to World History | year=2002 | isbn=978-0-631-21714-5 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E2eKDjo4B_IC | access-date=2021-04-25}} | *{{cite book | last1=Kramer | first1=Lloyd | last2=Maza | first2=Sara | title=A Companion to Western Historical Thought | publisher=Wiley | series=Wiley Blackwell Companions to World History | year=2002 | isbn=978-0-631-21714-5 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E2eKDjo4B_IC | access-date=2021-04-25}} | ||
** {{harvc |last=Alder |first= Ken |c=The History of Science, or, an Oxymoronic Theory of Relativistic Objectivity |year=2002 |in=Kramer |in2=Maza }} | ** {{harvc |last=Alder |first= Ken |c=The History of Science, or, an Oxymoronic Theory of Relativistic Objectivity |year=2002 |in=Kramer |in2=Maza }} | ||
* {{cite book|author=Marwick|first=Arthur |author-link=Arthur Marwick |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6JHtAAAAMAAJ|title=The New Nature of History: Knowledge, Evidence, Language|publisher=Lyceum Books|year=2001|isbn=978-0-925065-61-2}} | * {{cite book|author=Marwick|first=Arthur |author-link=Arthur Marwick |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6JHtAAAAMAAJ|title=The New Nature of History: Knowledge, Evidence, Language|publisher=Lyceum Books|year=2001|isbn=978-0-925065-61-2}} | ||
* {{Cite journal|last=Mayr|first=Ernst|date=1990|title=When is Historiography Whiggish?|journal=Journal of the History of Ideas|volume=51|issue=2|pages=301–309|doi=10.2307/2709517|issn=0022-5037|jstor=2709517}} | * {{Cite journal|last=Mayr|first=Ernst|date=1990|title=When is Historiography Whiggish?|journal=Journal of the History of Ideas|volume=51|issue=2|pages=301–309|doi=10.2307/2709517|issn=0022-5037|jstor=2709517}} | ||
* {{cite web|last1=Scruton|first1=Roger|year=2007|title=Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Political Thought|url=http://text-translator.com/wp-content/filesfa/Dictionary-of-political-thoughts.pdf |
* {{cite web|last1=Scruton|first1=Roger|year=2007|title=Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Political Thought|url=http://text-translator.com/wp-content/filesfa/Dictionary-of-political-thoughts.pdf|website=text-translator.com|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|page=735|edition=3}} | ||
* {{cite book |last=Sewell |first=Keith C |chapter=Butterfield's Critique of the Whig Interpretation|date=2005 |url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057%2F9780230000933_3 |title=Herbert Butterfield and the Interpretation of History |pages=30–47 |editor-last=Sewell |editor-first=Keith C |series=Studies in Modern History |location=London |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |doi=10.1057/9780230000933_3 |isbn=978-0-230-00093-3 |access-date=2021-04-25}} | * {{cite book |last=Sewell |first=Keith C |chapter=Butterfield's Critique of the Whig Interpretation|date=2005 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057%2F9780230000933_3 |title=Herbert Butterfield and the Interpretation of History |pages=30–47 |editor-last=Sewell |editor-first=Keith C |series=Studies in Modern History |location=London |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |doi=10.1057/9780230000933_3 |isbn=978-0-230-00093-3 |access-date=2021-04-25}} | ||
* {{cite book |last1=Macaulay |first1=Thomas Babington |title=The History of England |date=1979 |publisher=Penguin Classics |orig-year=1849 |contribution=Introduction |contributor-last=Trevor-Roper |contributor-first=Hugh |isbn=978-0140431339}} | * {{cite book |last1=Macaulay |first1=Thomas Babington |title=The History of England |date=1979 |publisher=Penguin Classics |orig-year=1849 |contribution=Introduction |contributor-last=Trevor-Roper |contributor-first=Hugh |isbn=978-0140431339}} | ||
*{{Cite journal|last=Torr|first=Christopher|year=2000|title=The whig interpretation of history|url=https://journals.co.za/doi/abs/10.10520/AJA10158812_263|journal=South African Journal of Economic and Management Sciences|volume=3|issue=1|pages=52–58|doi=10.4102/sajems.v3i1.2598|hdl=10520/AJA10158812_263|doi-access=free}} | *{{Cite journal|last=Torr|first=Christopher|year=2000|title=The whig interpretation of history|url=https://journals.co.za/doi/abs/10.10520/AJA10158812_263|journal=South African Journal of Economic and Management Sciences|volume=3|issue=1|pages=52–58|doi=10.4102/sajems.v3i1.2598|hdl=10520/AJA10158812_263|doi-access=free}} | ||
* {{cite journal|last1=Wilson|first1=Adrian|last2=Ashplant|first2=T. G.|date=2009-02-11|title=Whig History and Present-centred History |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/historical-journal/article/abs/whig-history-and-presentcentred-history/728D72D470DC4EDE741907E96BDCAA50|journal=The Historical Journal|volume=31|issue=1|page=10|doi=10.1017/S0018246X00011961|issn=1469-5103}} | * {{cite journal|last1=Wilson|first1=Adrian|last2=Ashplant|first2=T. G.|date=2009-02-11|title=Whig History and Present-centred History |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/historical-journal/article/abs/whig-history-and-presentcentred-history/728D72D470DC4EDE741907E96BDCAA50|journal=The Historical Journal|volume=31|issue=1|page=10|doi=10.1017/S0018246X00011961|s2cid=159748098 |issn=1469-5103}} | ||
{{refend}} | {{refend}} | ||
== Further reading == | == Further reading == | ||
*{{ |
* {{Cite book |last=Burrow |first=J. W. |author-link=J. W. Burrow |year=1981 |title=A Liberal Descent: Victorian historians and the English past |url=https://archive.org/details/liberaldescentvi0000burr |url-access=registration |place=Cambridge |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521240796}} | ||
* {{ |
* {{Cite book |last=Burrow |first=J. W. |author-link=J. W. Burrow |year=1988 |title=Whigs and Liberals |place=Oxford |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0198201397}} | ||
* {{ |
* {{Cite book |last=Burrow |first=J. W. |author-link=J. W. Burrow |year=2000 |title=The Crisis of Reason: European Thought, 1848–1914 |url=https://archive.org/details/isbn_9780300083903 |url-access=registration |place=New Haven, CT |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0300083903}} | ||
* {{ |
* {{Cite book |last=Butterfield |first=Herbert |year=1931 |title=The Whig Interpretation of History |url=http://www.eliohs.unifi.it/testi/900/butterfield/index.html |place=London |publisher=G. Bell and Sons |oclc=217470144}} at the Internet Archive. | ||
* Mayr, Ernst (1990). "When is Historiography Whiggish?". Journal of the History of Ideas. 51 (2): 301–309. doi:10.2307/2709517. ISSN 0022-5037. JSTOR 2709517. | |||
== External links == | == External links == | ||
{{Wikiquote}} | {{Wikiquote}} | ||
* | * | ||
* | * | ||
* {{ |
* {{Dead link|date=December 2017 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }} | ||
** {{Cite journal |title=Catholic Whiggery |journal=Angelus |date=April 2003 |url=https://angeluspress.org/products/angelus-apr-2003 |url-access=subscription}} | |||
{{Historiography}} | {{Historiography}} | ||
Line 173: | Line 173: | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] |
Latest revision as of 14:54, 5 September 2024
Approach to historiographyWhig history (or Whig historiography) is an approach to historiography that presents history as a journey from an oppressive and benighted past to a "glorious present". The present described is generally one with modern forms of liberal democracy and constitutional monarchy: it was originally a term for the metanarratives praising Britain's adoption of constitutional monarchy and the historical development of the Westminster system. The term has also been applied widely in historical disciplines outside of British history (e.g. in the history of science) to describe "any subjection of history to what is essentially a teleological view of the historical process". When the term is used in contexts other than British history, "whig history" (lowercase) is preferred.
In the British context, whig historians emphasize the rise of constitutional government, personal freedoms and scientific progress. The term is often applied generally (and pejoratively) to histories that present the past as the inexorable march of progress towards enlightenment. The term is also used extensively in the history of science to refer to historiography that focuses on the successful chains of theories and experiments that led to present-day theories, while ignoring failed theories and dead ends.
Whig history laid the groundwork for modernization theory and the resulting deployment of development aid around the world after World War II, which has sometimes been criticized as destructive to its recipients.
Terminology
The British historian Herbert Butterfield used the term "Whig history" in his short but influential book The Whig Interpretation of History (1931). It takes its name from the British Whigs, advocates of the power of Parliament, who opposed the Tories, advocates of the power of the king.
Butterfield's usage of the term was not in relation to the British or American Whig parties or Whiggism, but rather took aim at "the nineteenth-century school of historiography that praised all progress and habitually associated Protestantism with liberal views of liberty". The terms "whig" and "whiggish" are now used broadly, becoming "universal descriptors for all progressive narratives".
When H. A. L. Fisher in 1928 gave a Raleigh lecture, he implied that the "whig historians" really were Whigs (i.e. associated with the Whig party or its Liberal successor) and had written centrist histories that were "good history despite their enthusiasm for Gladstonian or Liberal Unionist causes"; on introduction the term was mostly approbatory, unlike Butterfield's later use, since Fisher applauded Macaulay's "instructive and illuminating" history. By the time Butterfield wrote his Whig Interpretation, he may have been beating a dead horse: P. B. M. Blaas, in his 1978 book Continuity and Anachronism, argued that whig history itself had lost all vitality by 1914. Subsequent generations of academic historians have rejected Whig history because of its presentist and teleological assumption that history is driving toward some sort of goal.
The Whig Interpretation of History
Butterfield's purpose with writing his 1931 book was to criticise oversimplified narratives (or "abridgements") which interpreted past events in terms of the present for the purposes of achieving "drama and apparent moral clarity". Butterfield especially noted:
It is part and parcel of the whig interpretation of history that it studies the past with reference to the present.
Butterfield argued that this approach to history compromised the work of the historian in several ways. The emphasis on the inevitability of progress leads to the mistaken belief that the progressive sequence of events becomes "a line of causation", tempting the historian to go no further to investigate the causes of historical change. The focus on the present as the goal of historical change leads the historian to a special kind of "abridgement", selecting only those events that seem important from the present point of view.
He also criticised it for modernising the past: "the result is that to many of us seem much more modern than they really were, and even when we have corrected this impression by closer study we find it difficult to keep in mind the differences between their world and ours".
Whig history is also criticised as having an overly dualist view with heroes on the side of liberty and freedom against traditionalist villains opposing the inevitability of progress. It also casts an overly negative view of opposing parties to heroes described, taking such parties "to have contributed nothing to the making of the present" and at worst converting them into a "dummy that acts as a better foil to the grand whig virtues". Butterfield illustrated this by criticising views of Martin Luther and the Reformation which "are inclined to write sometimes as though Protestantism in itself was somehow constituted to assist " and misconceptions that the British constitution was created by Whigs opposed by Tories rather than created by compromise and interplay mediated by then-political contingencies.
He also felt that whig history viewed the world in terms of a morality play: that " inconclusive unless he can give a verdict; and studying Protestant and Catholic in the 16th century he feels that loose threads are still left hanging unless he can show which party was in the right".
Butterfield instead advances a view of history stressing the accidental and contingent nature of events rather than some kind of inevitable and structural shift. Moreover, he called upon historians "to evoke a certain sensibility towards the past, the sensibility which studies the past 'for the sake of the past', which delights in the concrete and the complex, which 'goes out to meet the past', which searches for 'unlikenesses between past and present'".
A decade later however, if under wartime pressure from the Second World War, Butterfield would note of the Whig interpretation that "whatever it may have done to our history, it has had a wonderful effect on our politics....In every Englishman there is hidden something of a whig that seems to tug at the heart-strings".
Subsequent views
Butterfield's formulation has subsequently received much attention and the kind of historical writing he argued against in generalized terms is no longer academically respectable. Despite its polemical success, Butterfield's celebrated book was criticized by David Cannadine as "slight, confused, repetitive and superficial". However, of the English tradition more broadly, Cannadine wrote:
It was fiercely partisan and righteously judgemental, dividing the personnel of the past into the good and the bad. And it did so on the basis of the marked preference for liberal and progressive causes, rather than conservative and reactionary ones ... Whig history was, in short, an extremely biased view of the past: eager to hand out moral judgements, and distorted by teleology, anachronism and present-mindedness.
E. H. Carr in What Is History? (1961) gave the book the backhanded compliment of being "a remarkable book in many ways" noting that "though it denounced the whig interpretation over some 130 pages, it did not... name a single whig except Fox, who was no historian, or a single historian save Acton, who was no whig".
Michael Bentley analyses Butterfield's whig theory as referring to a canon of 19th-century historians in and of England (such as William Stubbs, James Anthony Froude, E. A. Freeman, J. R. Green, W. E. H. Lecky, Lord Acton, J. R. Seeley, S. R. Gardiner, C. H. Firth and J. B. Bury) that in fact excludes few except Thomas Carlyle. The theory identifies the common factors and Bentley comments:
Carlyle apart, the so-called Whigs were predominantly Christian, predominantly Anglican, thinkers for whom the Reformation supplied the critical theatre of enquiry when considering the origins of modern England. When they wrote about the history of the English constitution, as so many of them did, they approached their story from the standpoint of having Good News to relate ... If they could not have found the grandeur that they developed had they been writing half a century earlier, neither could they have supported their optimism had they lived to endure the barbarisms of the Somme and Passchendaele.
Roger Scruton takes the theory underlying whig history to be centrally concerned with social progress and reaction, with the progressives shown as victors and benefactors. According to Victor Feske, there is too much readiness to accept Butterfield's classic formulation from 1931 as definitive.
British whig history
In Britain, whig history is a view of British history that sees it as a "steady evolution of British parliamentary institutions, benevolently watched over by Whig aristocrats, and steadily spreading social progress and prosperity". It described a "continuity of institutions and practices since Anglo-Saxon times that lent to English history a special pedigree, one that instilled a distinctive temper in the English nation (as whigs liked to call it) and an approach to the world issued in law and lent legal precedent a role in preserving or extending the freedoms of Englishmen".
Paul Rapin de Thoyras's history of England, published in 1723, became "the classic Whig history" for the first half of the eighteenth century. Rapin claimed that the English had preserved their ancient constitution against the absolutist tendencies of the Stuarts. However, Rapin's history lost its place as the standard history of England in the late 18th century and early 19th century to that of David Hume.
According to Arthur Marwick, however, Henry Hallam was the first whig historian, publishing Constitutional History of England in 1827, which "greatly exaggerated the importance of 'parliaments' or of bodies thought were parliaments" while tending "to interpret all political struggles in terms of the parliamentary situation in Britain the nineteenth century, in terms, that is, of Whig reformers fighting the good fight against Tory defenders of the status quo".
David Hume
In The History of England (1754–1761), Hume challenged whig views of the past and the whig historians in turn attacked Hume; but they could not dent his history. In the early 19th century, some whig historians came to incorporate Hume's views, dominant for the previous fifty years. These historians were members of the New Whigs around Charles James Fox (1749–1806) and Lord Holland (1773–1840) in opposition until 1830 and so "needed a new historical philosophy". Fox himself intended to write a history of the Glorious Revolution of 1688, but only managed the first year of James II's reign. A fragment was published in 1808. James Mackintosh then sought to write a Whig history of the Glorious Revolution, published in 1834 as the History of the Revolution in England in 1688.
Thomas Babington Macaulay
Hume still dominated English historiography, but this changed when Thomas Babington Macaulay entered the field, utilising Fox and Mackintosh's work and manuscript collections. Macaulay's History of England was published in a series of volumes from 1848 to 1855. It proved an immediate success, replacing Hume's history and becoming the new orthodoxy. As if to introduce a linear progressive view of history, the first chapter of Macaulay's History of England proposes:
The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical, of moral, and of intellectual improvement.
While Macaulay was a popular and celebrated historian of the whig school, his work did not feature in Butterfield's 1931 Whig Interpretation of History. According to Ernst Breisach, "his style captivated the public as did his good sense of the past and firm whiggish convictions".
William Stubbs
William Stubbs (1825–1901), the constitutional historian and influential teacher of a generation of historians, was the author of the extremely influential Constitutional History of England (published between 1873–78) and became a crucial figure in the later survival and respectability of whig history. According to Reba Soffer,
Stubbs was a true believer who concealed his biases, even from himself, behind the façade of a dispassionate historian translating original documents into magisterial prose. His rhetorical gifts often obscured his combination of high church Anglicanism, whig history, and civic responsibility. In the Church of England, Stubbs saw the original model for the development and maintenance of English liberties.
Stubb's history began with an imagined Anglo-Saxon past into which representative parliamentary institutions emerged and fought for control with the absolutist crown in various stages (including overreaches in during the English Civil War) before uniting in "nation, church, peers and people" in the Glorious Revolution. This view of events was substantially challenged: Maitland discovered in 1893 that the early "parliaments" had "no hint of operating as a representative body but resembled instead a meeting of the King's Council, called to meet the king's purposes; it passed no 'legislation', but rather considered petitions or 'bills' as though acting as an ultimate court of justice". Albert Pollard, writing in 1920, also shot through much of Stubbs' ideas on the representative and law-making powers of early English parliaments, pulling the emergence of a semi-independent House of Commons to the 1620s.
Robert Hebert Quick
Political history was the usual venue for whig history in Great Britain, but it also appears in other areas. Robert Hebert Quick (1831–1891) was one of the leaders of the Whig school of the history of education, along with G. A. N. Lowndes. In 1898, Quick explained the value of studying the history of educational reform, arguing that the great accomplishments of the past were cumulative and comprised the building blocks that “would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us”.
End of whig history
Frederic William Maitland is "now universally recognised as the first practitioner of the modern discipline of history", using "medieval law as a tool to prise open the mind of medieval men". Blaas, in Continuity and Anachronism (1978) discerns new methods in the work of J. H. Round, F. W. Maitland and A. F. Pollard; Bentley believes that their work "contained the origins of much twentieth-century thinking in England". Marwick also positively mentions Gardiner, Seeley, Lord Acton, and T. F. Tout as transforming the teaching and study of history at British universities into a recognisable modern form.
The First World War, however, did substantial damage to whig history's fundamental assumption of progress and improvement:
Accelerated by the sceptical power of a new breed of historian epitomized in the brilliance of F. W. Maitland, whiggery had begun its turn downwards (we are told) and met its Waterloo on the Somme ... win thrusts—on the one hand cultural despair in face of a dead civilization, on the other a determination to make history say something different for the post-war generation—worked between them to put whig susceptibilities between a rock and a hard place.
Bentley also speculates that 19th-century British historiography took the form of an indirect social history which "attempted to embrace society by absorbing it into the history of the state", a project gravely disrupted by the First World War and renewed questions on "the pretensions of the state as an avatar of social harmony". He, however, notes that whig history has not died "outside the academy" and lives on partially in criticism of history as something published in "a row of small-minded monographs written by authors calling themselves 'doctor', whose life-experience and sense of English culture extended no further than taking cups of tea in the Institute of Historical Research".
Later instances and criticism
In science
It has been argued that the historiography of science is "riddled with Whiggish history". Like other whig histories, whig history of science tends to divide historical actors into "good guys" who are on the side of truth (as is now known), and "bad guys" who opposed the emergence of these truths because of ignorance or bias. Science is seen as emerging from "a series of victories over pre-scientific thinking". From this whiggish perspective, Ptolemy would be criticized because his astronomical system placed the Earth at the center of the universe while Aristarchus would be praised because he placed the Sun at the center of the Solar System. This kind of evaluation ignores historical background and the evidence that was available at a particular time: Did Aristarchus have evidence to support his idea that the Sun was at the center? Were there good reasons to reject Ptolemy's system before the sixteenth century?
The writing of Whig history of science is especially found in the writings of scientists and general historians, while this whiggish tendency is commonly opposed by professional historians of science. Nicholas Jardine describes the changing attitude to whiggishness this way:
By the mid-1970s, it had become commonplace among historians of science to employ the terms "Whig" and "Whiggish", often accompanied by one or more of "hagiographic", "internalist", "triumphalist", even "positivist", to denigrate grand narratives of scientific progress. At one level there is, indeed, an obvious parallel with the attacks on Whig constitutional history in the opening decades of the century. For, as P. B. M. Blaas has shown, those earlier attacks were part and parcel of a more general onslaught in the name of an autonomous, professional and scientific history, on popular, partisan and moralising historiography. Similarly, ... For post-WWII champions of the newly professionalized history of science the targets were quite different. Above all, they were out to establish a critical distance between the history of science and the teaching and promotion of the sciences. In particular, they were suspicious of the grand celebratory and didactic narratives of scientific discovery and progress that had proliferated in the inter-war years.
More recently, some scholars have argued that Whig history is essential to the history of science. At one level, "the very term 'the history of science' has itself profoundly Whiggish implications. One may be reasonably clear what 'science' means in the 19th century and most of the 18th century. In the 17th century 'science' has very different meaning. Chemistry, for example, was then inextricably mixed up with alchemy. Before the 17th century dissecting out such a thing as 'science' in anything like the modern sense of the term involves profound distortions." The science historians' rejection of whiggishness has been criticised by some scientists for failing to appreciate "the temporal depth of scientific research".
In economics
Retrospectives on modern macroeconomics are generally whiggish histories. For example, the popularisation of mathematical models by Paul Samuelson's Foundations of Economic Analysis, when viewed by economists trained in a mathematical framework becomes "an important milestone on the road to the mathematization of economics" in a story told by the victorious. Yet "those who do not agree that such mathematization is a good thing could argue that the mathematical developments... represent a regression rather than a progression". The introduction of rational expectations similarly carries implicit hindsight bias: people who disagree on the reality of agents making decisions in the manner assumed (e.g. behavioral economics) "would not necessarily rejoice in present ascendancy".
Burrow views Marxist history, with its " anticipated terminus from which it derives its moral and political point", as "characteristically whig".
In philosophy
One very common example of Whig history is the work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, to whom is often ascribed a teleological view of history with an inexorable trajectory in the direction of progress.
Marxists have had varied views on Whig history. The traditional inheritance of Hegel, interpreted through Engels' articulation of historical materialism, implied that history progressed from a "primitive communism", through slave societies, feudal societies, capitalism, and finally to socialism and communism. However, contemporary Marxists, such as Ellen Meiksins Wood, have aggressively challenged those assumptions as deterministic and ahistorical. Walter Benjamin criticized conception of history which assumed a necessarily progressive or teleological course, though he did not employ the term "Whig history". "The danger affects both the content of the tradition and its receivers. The same threat hangs over both: that of becoming a tool of the ruling classes. In every era the attempt must be made anew to wrest tradition away from a conformism that is about to overpower it."
In Canadian history
Regarding Canada, Allan Greer argues:
The interpretive schemes that dominated Canadian historical writing through the middle decades of the twentieth century were built on the assumption that history had a discernible direction and flow. Canada was moving towards a goal in the nineteenth century; whether this endpoint was the construction of a transcontinental, commercial, and political union, the development of parliamentary government, or the preservation and resurrection of French Canada, it was certainly a Good Thing. Thus the rebels of 1837 were quite literally on the wrong track. They lost because they had to lose; they were not simply overwhelmed by superior force, they were justly chastised by the God of History.
In the emergence of intelligent life
In The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (1986), John D. Barrow and Frank J. Tipler identify whiggishness with a teleological principle of convergence in history to liberal democracy. This is in line with what Barrow and Tipler call the "anthropic principle".
In general history and biography
James A. Hijiya points out the persistence of whiggish history in history textbooks. In the debate over Britishness, David Marquand praised the whig approach on the grounds that "ordered freedom and evolutionary progress have been among the hallmarks of modern British history, and they should command respect".
Historian Edward J. Larson in his book Summer for the Gods: The Scopes Trial and America's Continuing Debate Over Science and Religion (1997) challenged a whiggish view of the Scopes trial. The book won the Pulitzer Prize for History in 1998.
See also
- Chronological snobbery
- Classical liberalism
- End of history
- Ethnocentrism
- Great man theory
- Meliorism
- Moral progress
- Philosophic Whigs
- Precursorism
- Predestination
- The End of History and the Last Man
- The Better Angels of Our Nature
- The Moral Arc
References
- Blackburn, Simon (2008). "Whig view of history". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0.
- ^ Cronon 2012.
- ^ Burrow 2008, p. 473.
- ^ Marwick 2001, p. 74.
- ^ Bentley 2006, p. 20.
- Mayr 1990.
- Gardner & Lewis 2015.
- Ferguson 1990.
- Butterfield, Sir Herbert (1981). The Whig Interpretation of History. University of New South Wales Library. OCLC 218992532.
- Torr 2000, p. 52–53.
- Sewell 2005.
- Bentley 2006, p. 171.
- Bentley 2006, p. 95. Bentley however argues against Blaas' conclusion: Blaas' historiography is mostly focused on parliamentary history, which "pre-dates significant changes in whig typologies... sometimes by several decades the case of imperial historiography"; in contrast to what Blaas' assumes, there was no strong connection between whig historians and the Liberal party; new pre-1914 archival information also is now available.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 11.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 12.
- Butterfield 1965, pp. 24–25.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 34.
- Hart 1965, p. 39.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 35.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 37.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 41.
- Butterfield 1965, p. 65.
- Butterfield 1965, pp. 68–69.
- Wilson & Ashplant 2009, p. 10.
- ^ Burrow 2008, p. 474.
- Cannadine 1993, p. 203.
- Cannadine 1993, p. 197.
- ^ Carr 1990, p. 41.
- Bentley 2005, p. 65.
- Bentley 2005, p. 66.
- Bentley 2005, p. 67.
- Scruton 2007, p. 735.
- Feske 1996, p. 2.
- Trevor-Roper 1979, p. 10.
- ^ Marwick 2001, pp. 74–75.
- Trevor-Roper 1979, p. 12.
- Trevor-Roper 1979, pp. 25–26.
- Macaulay, Thomas Babington (1848). "Chapter I" . The History of England from the Accession of James II . Vol. 1. p. 14 – via Wikisource.
- Breisach, E. (2007). Historiography: Ancient, Medieval, and Modern, Third Edition. ACLS Humanities E-Book. University of Chicago Press. p. 251. ISBN 978-0-226-07283-8. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Bentley 2006, pp. 23 et seq.
- Reba N. Soffer (1994). Discipline and Power: The University, History, and the Making of an English Elite, 1870–1930. Stanford University Press. pp. 87–88. ISBN 978-0-8047-2383-1.
- Bentley 2006, p. 32.
- Bentley 2006, p. 33.
- Bentley 2006, p. 37.
- McCulloch, Gary (2011). The Struggle for the History of Education. Foundations and Futures of Education. Taylor & Francis. p. 28. ISBN 978-1-136-81124-1. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
Indeed, he concluded, 'the great thinkers would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us, and lead us to press forward in it with good heart and hope' (Quick 1868/1902, p. 526).
- Marwick 2001, p. 77. Quotation marks omitted.
- Bentley 2006, p. 96.
- Marwick 2001, pp. 77–78. Contra Butterfield, who mentions Acton et al negatively.
- Bentley 2006, p. 7.
- Bentley 2006, p. 104.
- Bentley 2005, p. 71. Bentley speculates that "for men such as Stubbs, the attraction of law and constitutional practice lay in their ability to reflect the lives of thousands of anonymous people and thus provide access to those who could never be reached via direct oral testimony".
- Bentley 2006, p. 8.
- McIntire, C. T. (2004). Herbert Butterfield: Historian as Dissenter. Yale University Press. p. 205. ISBN 978-0-300-09807-5.
- Schuster, John Andrew (1995). "The Problem of 'Whig History' in the History of Science" (PDF). The Scientific Revolution: An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science. Department of Science & Technology Studies, University of Wollongong. ISBN 978-0-86418-337-8.
- Bowler & Morus 2005, p. 2. "The conventional stories of the past that appear in the introductory chapters of science textbooks are certainly a form of Whiggism. Historians take great delight in exposing the artificially constructed nature of these stories, and some scientists find the results uncomfortable".
- Alder 2002, p. 301. "The history of science—as composed by both ex-scientists and general historians—has largely consisted of Whig history, in which the scientific winners write the account in such a way as to make their triumph an inevitable outcome of the righteous logic of their cause".
- Jardine, Nick (1 June 2003). "Whigs and Stories: Herbert Butterfield and the Historiography of Science". History of Science. 41 (2): 127–128. Bibcode:2003HisSc..41..125J. doi:10.1177/007327530304100201. ISSN 0073-2753. S2CID 160281821.
- Hyman, Anthony (1 October 1996). "Whiggism in the History of Science and the Study of the Life and Work of Charles Babbage". The Babbage Pages. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Harrison, Edward (September 1987). "Whigs, prigs and historians of science". Nature. 329 (6136): 213–214. Bibcode:1987Natur.329..213H. doi:10.1038/329213a0. ISSN 1476-4687. S2CID 4347987.
- Torr 2000, pp. 56–57.
- ^ Torr 2000, p. 57.
- Pinkard, Terry (2017). Does History Make Sense?. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-97880-5.
- Wood, Ellen Meiksins (2016). Democracy or Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism. United States: Verso Books. pp. 108–181. ISBN 978-1784782443.
- Benjamin, Walter (1968). Illuminations (2nd ed.). United States: Mariner Books. pp. 198–199. ISBN 978-1328470232. OCLC 1179424430.
- Greer, Allan (6 April 2016). "1837–38: Rebellion Reconsidered". The Canadian Historical Review. 76 (1): 3. ISSN 1710-1093. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Barrow, John D.; Tipler, Frank J. (1986). The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 9–11, 135. ISBN 978-0-19-282147-8. LCCN 87028148.
- Hijiya, James A. (1994). "Why the West Is Lost". The William and Mary Quarterly. 51 (2): 284. doi:10.2307/2946864. ISSN 0043-5597. JSTOR 2946864.
- Marquand, David (2009). "'Bursting with Skeletons': Britishness after Empire". In Gamble, Andrew; Wright, Tony (eds.). Britishness: Perspectives on the British Question. John Wiley & Sons. p. 15. ISBN 978-1-4051-9269-9.
- Ladouceur, Ronald P. (1 September 2008). "Ella Thea Smith and the Lost History of American High School Biology Textbooks". Journal of the History of Biology. 41 (3): 435–471. doi:10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3. ISSN 1573-0387. PMID 19244720. S2CID 25320197.
Sources
- Bentley, Michael (2005) . Modern Historiography: An Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-63192-6.
- Bentley, Michael (2006). Modernizing England's Past: English Historiography in the Age of Modernism, 1870-1970. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-84178-8.
- Bowler, Peter J; Morus, Iwan Rhys (2005). Making Modern Science: A Historical Survey (1st ed.). University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-06861-9. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Burrow, John (2008). A History of Histories. Allen Lane. ISBN 978-0-307-26852-5. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Butterfield, Herbert (1965) . The Whig Interpretation of History. New York: WW Norton and Company.
- Cannadine, David (1993). G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History. W. W. Norton. p. 208. ISBN 978-0-393-03528-5.
- Carr, Edward Hallett (1990) . What Is History? (2nd ed.). London: Penguin Books. p. 41.
- Cronon, William (1 September 2012). "Two Cheers for the Whig Interpretation of History". Perspectives on History. American Historical Association. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Ferguson, James (1990). The Anti-Politics Machine: "Development," Depoliticization, and Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521373821.
- Feske, Victor (1996). From Belloc to Churchill: Private Scholars, Public Culture, and the Crisis of British Liberalism, 1900–1939. University of North Carolina Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-8078-4601-8.
- Gardner, Katy; Lewis, David (2015). Anthropology and development: challenges for the twenty-first century. Pluto Press.
- Hart, Jenifer (1965). "Nineteenth-Century Social Reform: A Tory Interpretation of History". Past & Present (31): 39–61. doi:10.1093/past/31.1.39. ISSN 0031-2746. JSTOR 650101.
According to its critics, a whig interpretation of history requires human heroes and villains in the story.
- Kramer, Lloyd; Maza, Sara (2002). A Companion to Western Historical Thought. Wiley Blackwell Companions to World History. Wiley. ISBN 978-0-631-21714-5. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Alder, Ken. "The History of Science, or, an Oxymoronic Theory of Relativistic Objectivity". In Kramer & Maza (2002).
- Marwick, Arthur (2001). The New Nature of History: Knowledge, Evidence, Language. Lyceum Books. ISBN 978-0-925065-61-2.
- Mayr, Ernst (1990). "When is Historiography Whiggish?". Journal of the History of Ideas. 51 (2): 301–309. doi:10.2307/2709517. ISSN 0022-5037. JSTOR 2709517.
- Scruton, Roger (2007). "Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Political Thought" (PDF). text-translator.com (3 ed.). Palgrave Macmillan. p. 735.
- Sewell, Keith C (2005). "Butterfield's Critique of the Whig Interpretation". In Sewell, Keith C (ed.). Herbert Butterfield and the Interpretation of History. Studies in Modern History. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 30–47. doi:10.1057/9780230000933_3. ISBN 978-0-230-00093-3. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
- Trevor-Roper, Hugh (1979) . Introduction. The History of England. By Macaulay, Thomas Babington. Penguin Classics. ISBN 978-0140431339.
- Torr, Christopher (2000). "The whig interpretation of history". South African Journal of Economic and Management Sciences. 3 (1): 52–58. doi:10.4102/sajems.v3i1.2598. hdl:10520/AJA10158812_263.
- Wilson, Adrian; Ashplant, T. G. (11 February 2009). "Whig History and Present-centred History". The Historical Journal. 31 (1): 10. doi:10.1017/S0018246X00011961. ISSN 1469-5103. S2CID 159748098.
Further reading
- Burrow, J. W. (1981). A Liberal Descent: Victorian historians and the English past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521240796.
- Burrow, J. W. (1988). Whigs and Liberals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0198201397.
- Burrow, J. W. (2000). The Crisis of Reason: European Thought, 1848–1914. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300083903.
- Butterfield, Herbert (1931). The Whig Interpretation of History. London: G. Bell and Sons. OCLC 217470144. 1963 edition at the Internet Archive.
External links
- Text of The Whig Interpretation of History
- James A. Hijiya, "Why the West Is Lost"
- 2003 article "Catholic Whiggery"
- "Catholic Whiggery". Angelus. April 2003.