Misplaced Pages

Bad faith (existentialism): Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 18:10, 31 January 2024 editThaesOfereode (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users14,992 edits Multiple issues formattingTags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit← Previous edit Latest revision as of 10:10, 24 October 2024 edit undoMonkbot (talk | contribs)Bots3,695,952 editsm Task 20: replace {lang-??} templates with {langx|??} ‹See Tfd› (Replaced 1);Tag: AWB 
(4 intermediate revisions by 4 users not shown)
Line 2: Line 2:
{{Short description|Inauthentic action}} {{Short description|Inauthentic action}}
{{multiple issues| {{multiple issues|
{{Essay-like|date=November 2020}} {{confusing|date=February 2024}}
{{more citations needed|date=March 2023}} {{more citations needed|date=March 2023}}
}} }}
In the philosophy of ], '''bad faith''' (''mauvaise foi'') is the psychological phenomenon whereby individuals act ], by yielding to the external pressures of society to adopt false ] and disown their innate freedom as sentient human beings.<ref>''The Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism'' (1995) J. Childers and G. Hentzi Eds., p. 103</ref> Bad faith also derives from the related concepts of ] and '']''. In ], '''bad faith''' ({{langx|fr|mauvaise foi}}) is the psychological phenomenon whereby individuals act ], by yielding to the external pressures of society to adopt false ] and disown their innate freedom as sentient human beings.<ref>''The Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism'' (1995) J. Childers and G. Hentzi Eds., p. 103</ref> Bad faith also derives from the related concepts of ] and '']''.


==Freedom and choice== ==Freedom and choice==
A critical claim in ] thought is that individuals are always ] and guide their lives towards their own chosen goal or "project". This claim suggests that individuals cannot escape this freedom, even in overwhelming circumstances. For instance, even an empire's colonized victims possess choices: to submit to rule, to negotiate, to commit suicide, to resist nonviolently, or to counter-attack. A critical claim in ] thought is that individuals are always ] and guide their lives towards their own chosen goal or "project". This claim suggests that individuals cannot escape this freedom, even in overwhelming circumstances. For instance, even an empire's colonized victims possess choices: to submit to rule, to negotiate, to commit suicide, to resist nonviolently, or to counter-attack.


Although external circumstances may limit individuals (this limitation from the outside is called ]), they cannot force a person to follow one of the remaining courses over another. In this sense the individual still has some freedom of choice. For this reason, an individual may choose in ''],'' fully aware that this will have consequences. For ], to claim that one amongst many conscious possibilities takes undeniable precedence (for instance, "I cannot risk my life, because I must support my family") is to assume the role of an object in the world, not a free agent, but merely at the mercy of circumstance (a '']'' that is only its own facticity, i.e., it "is" inside itself, and acts there as a limitation).<ref>Jack Reynolds, ''Understanding Existentialism'' (2006) p. 73</ref> For Sartre, this attitude is manifestly self-deceiving. Although external circumstances may limit individuals, called ], they cannot force a person to follow one of the remaining courses over another. In this sense, the individual still has some freedom of choice. For this reason, an individual may choose in '']'', fully aware that this will have consequences. For ], to claim that one amongst many conscious possibilities takes undeniable precedence (for instance, "I cannot risk my life, because I must support my family") is to assume the role of an object in the world, not a free agent, but merely at the mercy of circumstance (a ] that is only its own facticity, i.e., it "is" inside itself, and acts there as a limitation).<ref>Jack Reynolds, ''Understanding Existentialism'' (2006) p. 73</ref> For Sartre, this attitude is manifestly self-deceiving.


==Intentional consciousness and freedom== ==Intentional consciousness and freedom==
According to this philosophy, humans are always aware that they are more than what they are aware of. They are not solely what they are aware of. In this sense, humans cannot be defined as "intentional objects" of consciousness that includes the restrictions imposed by ], personal history, character, bodies, or objective responsibility. According to Sartre, "Human reality is what it is not, and it is not what it is." An example of what he means is being a doctor but wishing to "transcend" that to become a pig farmer. One is who one is not: a pig farmer, not who one is, a doctor. According to this philosophy, humans are always aware that they are more than what they are aware of; they are not solely what they are aware of. In this sense, humans cannot be defined as "intentional objects" of consciousness that includes the restrictions imposed by ], personal history, character, bodies, or objective responsibility. According to Sartre, "Human reality is what it is not, and it is not what it is." For example, being a doctor but wishing to "transcend" that to become a pig farmer. One is who one is not, a pig farmer, not who one is, a doctor.


According to Satre a person can only be defined negatively, as "what it is not", and this negation is the only positive definition of "what it is."<ref>{{Cite web|last=Flynn|first=Thomas|date=2011|title=Jean-Paul Sartre|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/|website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> According to Sartre, a person can only be defined negatively, as "what it is not", and this negation is the only positive definition of "what it is".<ref>{{Cite web|last=Flynn|first=Thomas|date=2011|title=Jean-Paul Sartre|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/|website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref>


From this we are aware of a host of alternative reactions to our freedom to choose an objective situation, since no situation can dictate a single response. We pretend that these possibilities are denied to us by assuming social roles and value systems external to this nature {{clarification needed|date=June 2018}}. But this is itself a decision made possible by our freedom and our separation from these things. From this, an individual is aware of a host of alternative reactions to our freedom to choose an objective situation, since no situation can dictate a single response. An individual may pretend that these possibilities are denied to them by assuming social roles and value systems external to this nature,{{clarification needed|date=June 2018}} but this is itself a decision made possible by their freedom and separation from these things.


"Bad faith" is the paradoxical free decision to deny to ourselves this inescapable freedom. "Bad faith" is the paradoxical free decision to deny to oneself this inescapable freedom.


==Examples== ==Examples==
===Sartre=== ===Sartre===
Sartre cites a café waiter, whose movements and conversation are a little too "waiter-esque". His voice oozes with an eagerness to please; he carries food rigidly and ostentatiously; "his movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too rapid".<ref>Sartre, quoted in ], ''Self and Others'' (1969) p 44</ref> His exaggerated behaviour illustrates that he is play-acting as a waiter, as an object in the world: an automaton whose essence is to be a waiter. But that he is obviously acting belies that he is aware that he is not (merely) a waiter, but is rather consciously deceiving himself.<ref>Sartre, Jean-Paul, ''Essays in Existentialism'', Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 167-169</ref> Sartre cites a café waiter, whose movements and conversation are a little too "waiter-esque". His voice has an eagerness to please; he carries food rigidly and ostentatiously; "his movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too rapid".<ref>Sartre, quoted in ], ''Self and Others'' (1969) p 44</ref> His exaggerated behavior illustrates that he is play-acting as a waiter, as an object in the world and as an automaton whose essence is to be a waiter. That he is obviously acting belies that he is aware that he is not (merely) a waiter, but is rather consciously deceiving himself.<ref>Sartre, Jean-Paul, ''Essays in Existentialism'', Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 167-169</ref>


Another of Sartre's examples involves a young woman on a first date. She ignores the obvious sexual implications of her date's compliments to her physical appearance, but accepts them instead as words directed at her as a human consciousness. As he takes her hand, she lets it rest indifferently in his, "neither consenting nor resisting&nbsp;– a thing"<ref>Sartre, quoted in ], ''Relations in Public'' (1972)in p. 248</ref>&nbsp;– refusing either to return the gesture or to rebuke it. Thus she delays the moment when she must choose either to acknowledge and reject his advances, or consent to them. She conveniently considers her hand only a thing in the world, and his compliments as unrelated to her body, playing on her dual human reality as a physical being, and as a consciousness separate and free from this physicality.<ref>Sartre, Jean-Paul, ''Essays in Existentialism'', Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 160-164</ref> Another of Sartre's examples involves a young woman on a first date. She ignores the obvious sexual implications of her date's compliments to her physical appearance, but accepts them instead as words directed at her as a human consciousness. As he takes her hand, she lets it rest indifferently in his, "neither consenting nor resisting&nbsp;– a thing"<ref>Sartre, quoted in ], ''Relations in Public'' (1972)in p. 248</ref>&nbsp;– refusing either to return the gesture or to rebuke it. Thus, she delays the moment when she must choose either to acknowledge his intention and reject or consent to his advances. She conveniently considers her hand only a thing in the world and his compliments as unrelated to her body, playing on her dual human reality as a physical being and as a consciousness separate and free from this physicality.<ref>Sartre, Jean-Paul, ''Essays in Existentialism'', Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 160-164</ref>


Sartre suggests that by acting in bad faith the waiter and the woman are denying their own freedom, by using their freedom to do so. They manifestly know they are free, but are actively choosing not to acknowledge it. Bad faith is paradoxical in this regard: when acting in bad faith, a person is actively denying their own freedom, while relying on it to perform the denial. Sartre suggests that, by acting in bad faith, the waiter and the woman are denying their own freedom by using their freedom to do so. They manifestly know they are free, but are actively choosing not to acknowledge it. Bad faith is paradoxical in this regard; when acting in bad faith, a person is actively denying their own freedom, while relying on it to perform the denial. However, Leslie Stevenson believes this characterization of the waiter itself as being an example of bad faith is a misrepresentation of Sartre's intentions.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Stevenson |first1=Leslie |title=Sartre on Bad Faith |journal=Philosophy |date=1983 |volume=58 |page=253 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/3750658 |access-date=26 April 2024}}</ref>


===De Beauvoir=== ===De Beauvoir===
De Beauvoir described three main types of women acting in bad faith: the '']'' who denies her freedom by construing herself as a desirable object; the ''Mystic'', who invests her freedom in an absolute; and the ''Woman in Love'', who submerges her identity in that of her male object.<ref>Reynolds, p. 143</ref> ] described three main types of women acting in bad faith: the ''Narcissist'' who denies her freedom by construing herself as a desirable object; the ''Mystic'', who invests her freedom in an absolute; and the ''Woman in Love'', who submerges her identity in that of her male object.<ref>Reynolds, p. 143</ref>


She also considered what she called the ''Serious Man'', who subordinated himself to some outside cause, to be in bad faith inasmuch as he denies his own freedom.<ref>Reynolds, p. 150 and p. 161</ref> She also considered what she called the ''Serious Man'', who subordinated himself to some outside cause, to be in bad faith inasmuch as he denies his own freedom.<ref>Reynolds, p. 150 and p. 161</ref>


==Two modes of consciousness== ==Two modes of consciousness==
Sartre claims that the consciousness with which we generally consider our surroundings is different from our reflecting on this consciousness, i.e., the consciousness of "ourselves being conscious of these surroundings". The first kind of consciousness, before we think about, or reflect on, our previous consciousness, is called ''pre-reflective''. Reflecting on the pre-reflective consciousness is called ''reflective'' consciousness.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/#SH3a|title=Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> But this cannot be called unconsciousness, as Freud used the term. Sartre gives the example of running after a bus: one does not become conscious of "one's running after the bus" until one has ceased to run after it, because until then one's consciousness is focused on the bus itself, and not one's chasing it. Sartre claims that the consciousness with which we generally consider our surroundings is different from our reflecting on this consciousness; that is, the consciousness of "ourselves being conscious of these surroundings". The first kind of consciousness, before we think about or reflect on our previous consciousness, is ''pre-reflective consciousness''. Reflecting on the pre-reflective consciousness is ''reflective consciousness''.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/#SH3a|title=Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> Sartre contends that this cannot be called unconsciousness, as Freud used the term. He gives the example of running after a bus: one does not become conscious of "one's running after the bus" until one has ceased to run after it, because until then one's consciousness is focused on the bus itself, and not one's chasing it.


In this sense consciousness always ] being self-aware (''being for-itself''). Since for Sartre consciousness also entails a consciousness of our separation from the world, and hence freedom, we are also always aware of this. But we can manipulate these two levels of consciousness, so that our reflective consciousness interprets the factual limits of our objective situation as insurmountable, whilst our pre-reflective consciousness remains aware of alternatives. In this sense, consciousness always entails being self-aware ("being for-itself"). Since, for Sartre, consciousness also entails a consciousness of one's separation from the world and, hence, freedom, an individual may also always be aware of this. However, one can manipulate these two levels of consciousness, so that their reflective consciousness interprets the factual limits of an objective situation as insurmountable while the pre-reflective consciousness remains aware of alternatives.


==Freedom and morality== ==Freedom and morality==
One convinces oneself, in some sense, to be bound to act by external circumstance in order to escape the anguish of freedom. Sartre says that people are "condemned to be free"; whether they adopt an "objective" moral system to do this choosing for them or follow only their pragmatic concerns, they cannot help but be aware that they are not&nbsp;– fundamentally&nbsp;– part of them.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Existentialism is a Humanism|last=Sartre|first=Jean-Paul|publisher=Yale University Press|year=2007|isbn=9780300115468|location=New Haven|pages=29|oclc=80180903}}</ref> Moreover, as possible intentional objects of one's consciousness, one is fundamentally ''not'' part of oneself, but rather exactly what one, as consciousness, defines oneself in opposition to along with everything else one could be conscious of.
{{unreferenced section|date=September 2012}}
One convinces oneself, in some sense, to be bound to act by external circumstance, in order to escape the anguish of freedom. Sartre says that people are "condemned to be free": whether they adopt an "objective" moral system to do this choosing for them, or follow only their pragmatic concerns, they cannot help but be aware that they are not&nbsp;– fundamentally&nbsp;– part of them.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Existentialism is a Humanism|last=Sartre|first=Jean-Paul|publisher=Yale University Press|year=2007|isbn=9780300115468|location=New Haven|pages=29|oclc=80180903}}</ref> Moreover, as possible intentional objects of one's consciousness, one is fundamentally ''not'' part of oneself, but rather exactly what one, as consciousness, defines oneself in opposition to; along with everything else one could be conscious of.


Fundamentally, Sartre believes humankind cannot escape responsibility by adopting an external moral system, as the adoption of such is in itself a choice that we endorse, implicitly or explicitly, for which we must take full responsibility.<ref>{{Cite web|last=Onof|first=Christian J.|title=Jean Paul Sartre: Existentialism|url=https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/|access-date=1 November 2020|website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> Sartre argues that one cannot escape this responsibility, as each attempt to part one's self from the freedom of choice is in itself a demonstration of choice, and choice is dependent on a person's wills and desires. He states "I am responsible for my very desire of fleeing responsibilities."<ref>{{Cite book|last=Sartre|first=Jean-Paul|title=Existentialism and Human Emotions|publisher=Les Editions Nagel, Methuen & Co|year=1948|isbn=978-0413313003|location=France}}</ref> Fundamentally, Sartre believed humankind cannot escape responsibility by adopting an external moral system, as the adoption of such is in itself a choice that we endorse implicitly or explicitly for which we must take full responsibility.<ref>{{Cite web|last=Onof|first=Christian J.|title=Jean Paul Sartre: Existentialism|url=https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/|access-date=1 November 2020|website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> He argues that one cannot escape this responsibility, as each attempt to part one's self from the freedom of choice is in itself a demonstration of choice and choice is dependent on a person's wills and desires. He states, "I am responsible for my very desire of fleeing responsibilities."<ref>{{Cite book|last=Sartre|first=Jean-Paul|title=Existentialism and Human Emotions|publisher=Les Editions Nagel, Methuen & Co|year=1948|isbn=978-0413313003|location=France}}</ref>


As a human, one cannot claim one's actions are determined by external forces; this is the core statement of existentialism. One is "condemned" to this eternal freedom; human beings exist before the definition of human identity exists. One cannot define oneself as a thing in the world, as one has the freedom to be otherwise. One is not "a philosopher", as at some point one must/will cease the activities that define the self as "a philosopher". Any role that one might adopt does not define one as there is an eventual end to one's adoption of the role; i.e. other roles will be assigned to us, "a chef", "a mother". The self is not constant, it cannot be a thing in the world. Though one cannot assign a positive value to definitions that may apply to oneself, one remains able to say what one is not. As a human, one cannot claim their own actions are determined by external forces; this is the core statement of existentialism. One is "condemned" to this eternal freedom; human beings exist before the definition of human identity exists. One cannot define oneself as a thing in the world, as one has the freedom to be otherwise. An individual is not "a philosopher" as, at some point they will cease the activities that define the self as "a philosopher". Any role that one might adopt does not define them, as there is an eventual end to one's adoption of the role; that is, other roles will be assigned to us, "a chef", "a mother", and so on. The self is not constant and it cannot be a thing in the world. Though one cannot assign a positive value to definitions that may apply to oneself, there remains the ability to be able to say what one is not.


This inner anguish over moral uncertainty is a central underlying theme in existentialism, as the anguish demonstrates a personal feeling of responsibility over the choices one makes throughout life.<ref>{{Cite web|last=Natanson|first=Maurice|date=1951|title=A CRITIQUE OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE'S ONTOLOGY|url=https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1023&context=univstudiespapers}}</ref> Without an emphasis on personal choice, one may make use of an external moral system as a tool to moralize otherwise immoral acts, leading to negation of the self. According to existentialism, dedicated professionals of their respective moral codes&nbsp;– priests interpreting sacred scriptures, lawyers interpreting the ], doctors interpreting the ]&nbsp;– should, instead of divesting the self of responsibility in the discharge of their duties, be aware of their own significance in the process. This recognition involves the questioning of the morality of all choices, taking responsibility for the consequences of one's own choice and, therefore, a constant reappraisal of one's own and others' ever-changing humanity. One must not exercise bad faith by denying the self's freedom of choice and accountability. Taking on the burden of personal accountability in all situations is an intimidating proposition&nbsp;– by pointing out the freedom of the individual, Sartre seeks to demonstrate that the social roles and moral systems we adopt protect us from being morally accountable for our actions. This inner anguish over moral uncertainty is a central underlying theme in existentialism, as the anguish demonstrates a personal feeling of responsibility over the choices one makes throughout life.<ref>{{Cite web|last=Natanson|first=Maurice|date=1951|title=A CRITIQUE OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE'S ONTOLOGY|url=https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1023&context=univstudiespapers}}</ref> Without an emphasis on personal choice, one may make use of an external moral system as a tool to moralize otherwise immoral acts, leading to negation of the self. According to existentialism, dedicated professionals of their respective moral codes&nbsp;– ]s interpreting sacred scriptures, lawyers interpreting the ], doctors interpreting the ]&nbsp;– should, instead of divesting the self of responsibility in the discharge of their duties, be aware of their own significance in the process. This recognition involves the questioning of the morality of all choices, taking responsibility for the consequences of one's own choice, and, therefore, a constant reappraisal of one's own and others' ever-changing humanity. One must not exercise bad faith by denying the self's freedom of choice and accountability. Taking on the burden of personal accountability in all situations may be an intimidating proposition&nbsp;– by pointing out the freedom of the individual, Sartre seeks to demonstrate that the social roles and moral systems people adopt protect them from being morally accountable for their actions.


==See also== ==See also==

Latest revision as of 10:10, 24 October 2024

For other uses, see Bad faith (disambiguation). Inauthentic action
This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these messages)
This article may be confusing or unclear to readers. Please help clarify the article. There might be a discussion about this on the talk page. (February 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Bad faith" existentialism – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (March 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
(Learn how and when to remove this message)

In existentialism, bad faith (French: mauvaise foi) is the psychological phenomenon whereby individuals act inauthentically, by yielding to the external pressures of society to adopt false values and disown their innate freedom as sentient human beings. Bad faith also derives from the related concepts of self-deception and ressentiment.

Freedom and choice

A critical claim in existentialist thought is that individuals are always free to make choices and guide their lives towards their own chosen goal or "project". This claim suggests that individuals cannot escape this freedom, even in overwhelming circumstances. For instance, even an empire's colonized victims possess choices: to submit to rule, to negotiate, to commit suicide, to resist nonviolently, or to counter-attack.

Although external circumstances may limit individuals, called facticity, they cannot force a person to follow one of the remaining courses over another. In this sense, the individual still has some freedom of choice. For this reason, an individual may choose in anguish, fully aware that this will have consequences. For Jean-Paul Sartre, to claim that one amongst many conscious possibilities takes undeniable precedence (for instance, "I cannot risk my life, because I must support my family") is to assume the role of an object in the world, not a free agent, but merely at the mercy of circumstance (a being-in-itself that is only its own facticity, i.e., it "is" inside itself, and acts there as a limitation). For Sartre, this attitude is manifestly self-deceiving.

Intentional consciousness and freedom

According to this philosophy, humans are always aware that they are more than what they are aware of; they are not solely what they are aware of. In this sense, humans cannot be defined as "intentional objects" of consciousness that includes the restrictions imposed by facticity, personal history, character, bodies, or objective responsibility. According to Sartre, "Human reality is what it is not, and it is not what it is." For example, being a doctor but wishing to "transcend" that to become a pig farmer. One is who one is not, a pig farmer, not who one is, a doctor.

According to Sartre, a person can only be defined negatively, as "what it is not", and this negation is the only positive definition of "what it is".

From this, an individual is aware of a host of alternative reactions to our freedom to choose an objective situation, since no situation can dictate a single response. An individual may pretend that these possibilities are denied to them by assuming social roles and value systems external to this nature, but this is itself a decision made possible by their freedom and separation from these things.

"Bad faith" is the paradoxical free decision to deny to oneself this inescapable freedom.

Examples

Sartre

Sartre cites a café waiter, whose movements and conversation are a little too "waiter-esque". His voice has an eagerness to please; he carries food rigidly and ostentatiously; "his movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too rapid". His exaggerated behavior illustrates that he is play-acting as a waiter, as an object in the world and as an automaton whose essence is to be a waiter. That he is obviously acting belies that he is aware that he is not (merely) a waiter, but is rather consciously deceiving himself.

Another of Sartre's examples involves a young woman on a first date. She ignores the obvious sexual implications of her date's compliments to her physical appearance, but accepts them instead as words directed at her as a human consciousness. As he takes her hand, she lets it rest indifferently in his, "neither consenting nor resisting – a thing" – refusing either to return the gesture or to rebuke it. Thus, she delays the moment when she must choose either to acknowledge his intention and reject or consent to his advances. She conveniently considers her hand only a thing in the world and his compliments as unrelated to her body, playing on her dual human reality as a physical being and as a consciousness separate and free from this physicality.

Sartre suggests that, by acting in bad faith, the waiter and the woman are denying their own freedom by using their freedom to do so. They manifestly know they are free, but are actively choosing not to acknowledge it. Bad faith is paradoxical in this regard; when acting in bad faith, a person is actively denying their own freedom, while relying on it to perform the denial. However, Leslie Stevenson believes this characterization of the waiter itself as being an example of bad faith is a misrepresentation of Sartre's intentions.

De Beauvoir

Simone de Beauvoir described three main types of women acting in bad faith: the Narcissist who denies her freedom by construing herself as a desirable object; the Mystic, who invests her freedom in an absolute; and the Woman in Love, who submerges her identity in that of her male object.

She also considered what she called the Serious Man, who subordinated himself to some outside cause, to be in bad faith inasmuch as he denies his own freedom.

Two modes of consciousness

Sartre claims that the consciousness with which we generally consider our surroundings is different from our reflecting on this consciousness; that is, the consciousness of "ourselves being conscious of these surroundings". The first kind of consciousness, before we think about or reflect on our previous consciousness, is pre-reflective consciousness. Reflecting on the pre-reflective consciousness is reflective consciousness. Sartre contends that this cannot be called unconsciousness, as Freud used the term. He gives the example of running after a bus: one does not become conscious of "one's running after the bus" until one has ceased to run after it, because until then one's consciousness is focused on the bus itself, and not one's chasing it.

In this sense, consciousness always entails being self-aware ("being for-itself"). Since, for Sartre, consciousness also entails a consciousness of one's separation from the world and, hence, freedom, an individual may also always be aware of this. However, one can manipulate these two levels of consciousness, so that their reflective consciousness interprets the factual limits of an objective situation as insurmountable while the pre-reflective consciousness remains aware of alternatives.

Freedom and morality

One convinces oneself, in some sense, to be bound to act by external circumstance in order to escape the anguish of freedom. Sartre says that people are "condemned to be free"; whether they adopt an "objective" moral system to do this choosing for them or follow only their pragmatic concerns, they cannot help but be aware that they are not – fundamentally – part of them. Moreover, as possible intentional objects of one's consciousness, one is fundamentally not part of oneself, but rather exactly what one, as consciousness, defines oneself in opposition to along with everything else one could be conscious of.

Fundamentally, Sartre believed humankind cannot escape responsibility by adopting an external moral system, as the adoption of such is in itself a choice that we endorse – implicitly or explicitly – for which we must take full responsibility. He argues that one cannot escape this responsibility, as each attempt to part one's self from the freedom of choice is in itself a demonstration of choice and choice is dependent on a person's wills and desires. He states, "I am responsible for my very desire of fleeing responsibilities."

As a human, one cannot claim their own actions are determined by external forces; this is the core statement of existentialism. One is "condemned" to this eternal freedom; human beings exist before the definition of human identity exists. One cannot define oneself as a thing in the world, as one has the freedom to be otherwise. An individual is not "a philosopher" as, at some point they will cease the activities that define the self as "a philosopher". Any role that one might adopt does not define them, as there is an eventual end to one's adoption of the role; that is, other roles will be assigned to us, "a chef", "a mother", and so on. The self is not constant and it cannot be a thing in the world. Though one cannot assign a positive value to definitions that may apply to oneself, there remains the ability to be able to say what one is not.

This inner anguish over moral uncertainty is a central underlying theme in existentialism, as the anguish demonstrates a personal feeling of responsibility over the choices one makes throughout life. Without an emphasis on personal choice, one may make use of an external moral system as a tool to moralize otherwise immoral acts, leading to negation of the self. According to existentialism, dedicated professionals of their respective moral codes – priests interpreting sacred scriptures, lawyers interpreting the Constitution, doctors interpreting the Hippocratic oath – should, instead of divesting the self of responsibility in the discharge of their duties, be aware of their own significance in the process. This recognition involves the questioning of the morality of all choices, taking responsibility for the consequences of one's own choice, and, therefore, a constant reappraisal of one's own and others' ever-changing humanity. One must not exercise bad faith by denying the self's freedom of choice and accountability. Taking on the burden of personal accountability in all situations may be an intimidating proposition – by pointing out the freedom of the individual, Sartre seeks to demonstrate that the social roles and moral systems people adopt protect them from being morally accountable for their actions.

See also

References

  1. The Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism (1995) J. Childers and G. Hentzi Eds., p. 103
  2. Jack Reynolds, Understanding Existentialism (2006) p. 73
  3. Flynn, Thomas (2011). "Jean-Paul Sartre". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  4. Sartre, quoted in R. D. Laing, Self and Others (1969) p 44
  5. Sartre, Jean-Paul, Essays in Existentialism, Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 167-169
  6. Sartre, quoted in Erving Goffman, Relations in Public (1972)in p. 248
  7. Sartre, Jean-Paul, Essays in Existentialism, Citadel Press. 1993, pp. 160-164
  8. Stevenson, Leslie (1983). "Sartre on Bad Faith". Philosophy. 58: 253. Retrieved 26 April 2024.
  9. Reynolds, p. 143
  10. Reynolds, p. 150 and p. 161
  11. "Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  12. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2007). Existentialism is a Humanism. New Haven: Yale University Press. p. 29. ISBN 9780300115468. OCLC 80180903.
  13. Onof, Christian J. "Jean Paul Sartre: Existentialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 November 2020.
  14. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1948). Existentialism and Human Emotions. France: Les Editions Nagel, Methuen & Co. ISBN 978-0413313003.
  15. Natanson, Maurice (1951). "A CRITIQUE OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE'S ONTOLOGY".

Further reading

External links

Existentialism
Variants
Concepts
People
Artists
Philosophers
Related
Categories: