Misplaced Pages

Fermat's Last Theorem: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 19:16, 24 January 2013 editMagidin (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users6,282 editsm Undid revision 534683650 by 186.45.138.234 (talk) rv GF edit; that just redirects to "Modularity theorem", which is linked in the immediately prior sentence fragment← Previous edit Latest revision as of 13:37, 19 November 2024 edit undoFavonian (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Administrators287,467 editsm Reverted 2 edits by 139.55.45.67 (talk) to last revision by 129.104.241.211Tags: Twinkle Undo 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|17th-century conjecture proved by Andrew Wiles in 1994}}
{{For|other theorems named after Pierre de Fermat|Fermat's theorem (disambiguation){{!}}Fermat's theorem}}
{{For-multi|other theorems named after Pierre de Fermat|Fermat's theorem|the book by Simon Singh|Fermat's Last Theorem (book)}}
]' ''Arithmetica'' includes Fermat's commentary, particularly his "Last Theorem" (''Observatio Domini Petri de Fermat'').]]
{{External links|date=June 2021}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=August 2023}}
{{Infobox mathematical statement
| name = Fermat's Last Theorem
| image = Diophantus-II-8-Fermat.jpg
| caption = The 1670 edition of ]'s '']'' includes Fermat's commentary, referred to as his "Last Theorem" (''Observatio Domini Petri de Fermat''), posthumously published by his son.
| field = ]
| statement = For any integer {{math|''n'' > 2}}, the equation {{math|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} has no positive integer solutions.
| first stated by = ]
| first stated date = {{c.}} 1637
| first proof by = ]
| first proof date = Released 1994<br/>Published 1995
| implied by = {{ubl | ] | ] | ] }}
| generalizations = {{ubl| ] | ] }}
}}


In ], '''Fermat's Last Theorem''' (sometimes called '''Fermat's conjecture''', especially in older texts) states that no three ] ]s ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' can satisfy the equation ''a''<sup>''n''</sup>&nbsp;+&nbsp;''b''<sup>''n''</sup>&nbsp;=&nbsp;''c''<sup>''n''</sup> for any integer value of ''n'' greater than two. In ], '''Fermat's Last Theorem''' (sometimes called '''Fermat's conjecture''', especially in older texts) states that no three ] ]s {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}}, and {{math|''c''}} satisfy the equation {{math|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} for any integer value of {{math|''n''}} greater than {{math|2}}. The cases {{math|1=''n'' = 1}} and {{math|1=''n'' = 2}} have been known since antiquity to have infinitely many solutions.<ref name="auto">Singh, pp. 18–20</ref>


The proposition was first stated as a theorem by ] around 1637 in the margin of a copy of '']''. Fermat added that he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin. Although other statements claimed by Fermat without proof were subsequently proven by others and credited as theorems of Fermat (for example, ]), Fermat's Last Theorem resisted proof, leading to doubt that Fermat ever had a correct proof. Consequently, the proposition became known as a ] rather than a theorem. After 358 years of effort by mathematicians, ] was released in 1994 by ] and formally published in 1995. It was described as a "stunning advance" in the citation for Wiles's ] award in 2016.<ref name="abelcitation">{{Cite web |url=http://www.abelprize.no/c67107/binfil/download.php?tid=67059 |title=Abel prize 2016 – full citation |access-date=16 March 2016 |archive-date=20 May 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200520195920/https://www.abelprize.no/c67107/binfil/download.php?tid=67059 |url-status=dead }}</ref> It also proved much of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture, subsequently known as the ], and opened up entire new approaches to numerous other problems and mathematically powerful ] techniques.
This theorem was first ] by ] in 1637, famously in the margin of a copy of '']'' where he claimed he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin. No successful proof was published until 1995 despite the efforts of countless mathematicians during the 358 intervening years. The unsolved problem stimulated the development of ] in the 19th century and the proof of the ] in the 20th century. It is among the most famous theorems in the ] and prior to its ] was in the '']'' for "most difficult mathematical problems".


The unsolved problem stimulated the development of ] in the 19th and 20th centuries. It is among the most notable theorems in the ] and prior to its proof was in the '']'' as the "most difficult mathematical problem", in part because the theorem has the largest number of unsuccessful proofs.<ref>{{cite book|title=The Guinness Book of World Records|url=https://archive.org/details/guinnessbookofwo00mark|url-access=registration|year=1995|section=Science and Technology|publisher=Guinness Publishing Ltd.|isbn=9780965238304}}</ref>
==History==
Fermat left no proof of the conjecture for all ''n'', but he did prove the special case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4. This reduced the problem to proving the theorem for ]s ''n'' that are ]s. Over the next two centuries (1637–1839), the conjecture was proven for only the primes 3, 5, and 7, although ] proved a special case for all primes less than 100. In the mid-19th century, ] proved the theorem for ]s. Building on Kummer's work and using sophisticated computer studies, other mathematicians were able to prove the conjecture for all odd primes up to four million.


{{TOC limit|3}}
The final proof of the conjecture for all ''n'' came in the late 20th century. In 1984, ] suggested the approach of proving the conjecture through a proof of the ] for ]s. Building on work of ], ] succeeded in proving enough of the modularity theorem to prove Fermat's Last Theorem, with the assistance of ]. Wiles's achievement was reported widely in the popular press, and has been popularized in books and television programs.


== Overview ==
==Mathematical context==
===Pythagorean triples=== === Pythagorean origins ===
The ], {{nowrap|1=''x''<sup>2</sup> + ''y''<sup>2</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup>}}, has an infinite number of positive ] solutions for ''x'', ''y'', and ''z''; these solutions are known as ]s (with the simplest example being 3, 4, 5). Around 1637, Fermat wrote in the margin of a book that the more general equation {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} had no solutions in positive integers if ''n'' is an integer greater than 2. Although he claimed to have a general ] of his conjecture, Fermat left no details of his proof, and none has ever been found. His claim was discovered some 30&nbsp;years later, after his death. This claim, which came to be known as ''Fermat's Last Theorem'', stood unsolved for the next three and a half centuries.<ref name="BostonFLTproof">{{Cite web|url=https://www.math.wisc.edu/~boston/869.pdf |author=Nigel Boston |page=5|title=The Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem}}</ref>
{{Main|Pythagorean triple}}


The claim eventually became one of the most notable unsolved problems of mathematics. Attempts to prove it prompted substantial development in ], and over time Fermat's Last Theorem gained prominence as an ].
Pythagorean triples are a set of three integers (''a'', ''b'', ''c'') that satisfy a special case of Fermat's equation (''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;2)<ref>Stark, pp. 151–155.</ref>


=== Subsequent developments and solution ===
:<math>a^2 + b^2 = c^2.\ </math>
{{more citations needed|section|date=August 2020}}
The special case {{math|1=''n'' = 4}}, proved by Fermat himself, is sufficient to establish that if the theorem is false for some ] ''n'' that is not a ], it must also be false for some smaller ''n'', so only prime values of ''n'' need further investigation.<ref group=note>If the exponent ''n'' were not prime or 4, then it would be possible to write ''n'' either as a product of two smaller integers ({{nowrap|1=''n'' = ''PQ''}}), in which ''P'' is a prime number greater than 2, and then {{nowrap|1=''a<sup>n</sup>'' = ''a<sup>PQ</sup>'' = (''a<sup>Q</sup>'')<sup>''P''</sup>}} for each of ''a'', ''b'', and ''c''. That is, an equivalent solution would ''also'' have to exist for the prime power ''P'' that is ''smaller'' than ''n''; or else as ''n'' would be a power of 2 greater than 4, and writing {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4''Q''}}, the same argument would hold.</ref> Over the next two centuries (1637–1839), the conjecture was proved for only the primes 3, 5, and 7, although ] innovated and proved an approach that was relevant to an entire class of primes. In the mid-19th century, ] extended this and proved the theorem for all ]s, leaving irregular primes to be analyzed individually. Building on Kummer's work and using sophisticated computer studies, other mathematicians were able to extend the proof to cover all prime exponents up to four million,<ref name=":0"/> but a proof for all exponents was inaccessible (meaning that mathematicians generally considered a proof impossible, exceedingly difficult, or unachievable with current knowledge).<ref>Singh, p. 223</ref>


Separately, around 1955, Japanese mathematicians ] and ] suspected a link might exist between ]s and ]s, two completely different areas of mathematics. Known at the time as the ] (eventually as the modularity theorem), it stood on its own, with no apparent connection to Fermat's Last Theorem. It was widely seen as significant and important in its own right, but was (like Fermat's theorem) widely considered completely inaccessible to proof.<ref>Singh 1997, pp. 203–205, 223, 226</ref>
Examples of Pythagorean triples include (3, 4, 5) and (5, 12, 13). There are infinitely many such triples,<ref name="Stillwell_2003">{{cite book | author = ] | year = 2003 | title = Elements of Number Theory | url = http://books.google.com/books?id=LiAlZO2ntKAC&pg=PA110 | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 0-387-95587-9 | pages = 110–112}}</ref> and methods for generating such triples have been studied in many cultures, beginning with the ]<ref>Aczel, pp. 13–15</ref> and later ], ], and ] mathematicians.<ref>Singh, pp. 18–20.</ref> The traditional interest in Pythagorean triples connects with the ];<ref>Singh, p. 6.</ref> in its converse form, it states that a ] with sides of lengths ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' has a ] between the ''a'' and ''b'' legs when the numbers are a Pythagorean triple. ]s have various practical applications, such as ], ], ], and ]. Fermat's Last Theorem is an extension of this problem to higher powers, stating that no solution exists when the exponent 2 is replaced by any larger integer.


In 1984, ] noticed an apparent link between these two previously unrelated and unsolved problems. An outline suggesting this could be proved was given by Frey. The full proof that the two problems were closely linked was accomplished in 1986 by ], building on a partial proof by ], who proved all but one part known as the "epsilon conjecture" (see: '']'' and '']'').<ref name="abelcitation"/> These papers by Frey, Serre and Ribet showed that if the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture could be proven for at least the semi-stable class of elliptic curves, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem would also follow automatically. The connection is described ]: any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then by definition, no solution contradicting Fermat's Last Theorem could exist, meaning that Fermat's Last Theorem must also be true.
===Diophantine equations===
{{Main|Diophantine equation}}


Although both problems were daunting and widely considered to be "completely inaccessible" to proof at the time,<ref name="abelcitation"/> this was the first suggestion of a route by which Fermat's Last Theorem could be extended and proved for all numbers, not just some numbers. Unlike Fermat's Last Theorem, the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture was a major active research area and viewed as more within reach of contemporary mathematics.<ref>Singh, p. 144 quotes Wiles's reaction to this news: "I was electrified. I knew that moment that the course of my life was changing because this meant that to prove Fermat's Last Theorem all I had to do was to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. It meant that my childhood dream was now a respectable thing to work on."</ref> However, general opinion was that this simply showed the impracticality of proving the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture.<ref name="singh144">Singh, p. 144</ref> Mathematician ]' quoted reaction was a common one:<ref name="singh144"/>
Fermat's equation ''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''n''</sup> is an example of a Diophantine equation.<ref>Stark, pp. 145–146.</ref> A Diophantine equation is a polynomial equation in which the solutions must be integers.<ref>Stark, p. 4–5.</ref> Their name derives from the 3rd-century ]n mathematician, ], who developed methods for their solution. A typical Diophantine problem is to find two integers ''x'' and ''y'' such that their sum, and the sum of their squares, equal two given numbers ''A'' and ''B'', respectively:


{{blockquote|I myself was very sceptical that the beautiful link between Fermat's Last Theorem and the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture would actually lead to anything, because I must confess I did not think that the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture was accessible to proof. Beautiful though this problem was, it seemed impossible to actually prove. I must confess I thought I probably wouldn't see it proved in my lifetime.}}
:<math>A = x + y\ </math>
:<math>B = x^2 + y^2.\ </math>


On hearing that Ribet had proven Frey's link to be correct, English mathematician ], who had a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem and had a background of working with elliptic curves and related fields, decided to try to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture as a way to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. In 1993, after six years of working secretly on the problem, Wiles ] enough of the conjecture to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles's paper was massive in size and scope. A flaw was discovered in one part of his original paper during ] and required a further year and collaboration with a past student, ], to resolve. As a result, the final proof in 1995 was accompanied by a smaller joint paper showing that the fixed steps were valid. Wiles's achievement was reported widely in the popular press, and was popularized in books and television programs. The remaining parts of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, now proven and known as the modularity theorem, were subsequently proved by other mathematicians, who built on Wiles's work between 1996 and 2001.<ref name="Diamond-1996">{{Cite journal|last=Diamond|first=Fred|date=July 1996|title=On Deformation Rings and Hecke Rings|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2118586|journal=The Annals of Mathematics|volume=144|issue=1|pages=137–166|doi=10.2307/2118586|jstor=2118586}}</ref><ref name="Conrad-etal-1999">{{Cite journal|last1=Conrad|first1=Brian|last2=Diamond|first2=Fred|last3=Taylor|first3=Richard|date=1999|title=Modularity of certain potentially Barsotti-Tate Galois representations|url=https://www.ams.org/jams/1999-12-02/S0894-0347-99-00287-8/|journal=Journal of the American Mathematical Society|language=en|volume=12|issue=2|pages=521–567|doi=10.1090/S0894-0347-99-00287-8|issn=0894-0347|doi-access=free}}</ref><ref name="Breuil-etal-2001">{{Cite journal|last1=Breuil|first1=Christophe|last2=Conrad|first2=Brian|last3=Diamond|first3=Fred|last4=Taylor|first4=Richard|date=2001-05-15|title=On the modularity of elliptic curves over '''Q''': Wild 3-adic exercises|url=https://www.ams.org/jams/2001-14-04/S0894-0347-01-00370-8/|journal=Journal of the American Mathematical Society|language=en|volume=14|issue=4|pages=843–939|doi=10.1090/S0894-0347-01-00370-8|issn=0894-0347|doi-access=free}}</ref> For his proof, Wiles was honoured and received numerous awards, including the 2016 ].<ref name="natureAbel">{{cite journal |title=Fermat's last theorem earns Andrew Wiles the Abel Prize |journal=] |volume=531 |issue=7594 |pages=287 |date=15 March 2016 |doi=10.1038/nature.2016.19552 |pmid=26983518 |last=Castelvecchi |first=Davide |bibcode=2016Natur.531..287C |s2cid=4383161 |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref> – The Washington Post.</ref><ref> – CNN.com.</ref>
Diophantus's major work is the '']'', of which only a portion has survived.<ref>Singh, pp. 50–51.</ref> Fermat's conjecture of his Last Theorem was inspired while reading a new edition of the ''Arithmetica'',<ref>Stark, p. 145.</ref> which was translated into Latin and published in 1621 by ].<ref>Aczel, pp. 44–45; Singh, pp. 56–58.</ref>


=== Equivalent statements of the theorem ===
Diophantine equations have been studied for thousands of years. For example, the solutions to the quadratic Diophantine equation ''x''<sup>2</sup> + ''y''<sup>2</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup> are given by the ]s, originally solved by the Babylonians (c. 1800 BC).<ref>Aczel, pp. 14–15.</ref> Solutions to linear Diophantine equations, such as 26''x'' + 65''y'' = 13, may be found using the ] (c. 5th century BC).<ref>Stark, pp. 44–47.</ref>
There are several alternative ways to state Fermat's Last Theorem that are mathematically equivalent to the original statement of the problem.
Many ]s have a form similar to the equation of Fermat's Last Theorem from the point of view of algebra, in that they have no ''cross terms'' mixing two letters, without sharing its particular properties. For example, it is known that there are infinitely many positive integers ''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' such that ''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''m''</sup> where ''n'' and ''m'' are ] natural numbers.<ref group=note>For example, <math>\left((j^r+1)^s\right)^r + \left(j(j^r+1)^s)\right)^r = (j^r+1)^{rs+1}.</math></ref>


In order to state them, we use the following notations: let {{math|'''N'''}} be the set of natural numbers 1, 2, 3, ..., let {{math|'''Z'''}} be the set of integers 0, ±1, ±2, ..., and let {{math|'''Q'''}} be the set of rational numbers {{math|''a''/''b''}}, where {{mvar|a}} and {{mvar|b}} are in {{math|'''Z'''}} with {{math|''b'' ≠ 0}}. In what follows we will call a solution to {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}} where one or more of {{mvar|x}}, {{mvar|y}}, or {{mvar|z}} is zero a ''trivial solution''. A solution where all three are nonzero will be called a ''non-trivial'' solution.
==Fermat's conjecture==


For comparison's sake we start with the original formulation.
]. On the right is the famous margin which was too small to contain Fermat's alleged proof of his "last theorem".]]
* '''Original statement'''. With {{mvar|n}}, {{mvar|x}}, {{mvar|y}}, {{mvar|z}} ∈ {{math|'''N'''}} (meaning that ''n'', ''x'', ''y'', ''z'' are all positive whole numbers) and {{math|''n'' > 2}}, the equation {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}} has no solutions.


Most popular treatments of the subject state it this way. It is also commonly stated over {{math|'''Z'''}}:<ref>{{cite web |last=Weisstein |first=Eric W. |title=Fermat's Last Theorem. |url=https://mathworld.wolfram.com/FermatsLastTheorem.html |website=MathWorld – A Wolfram Web Resource |access-date=7 May 2021}}</ref>
Problem II.8 of the '']'' asks how a given square number is split into two other squares; in other words, for a given ] ''k'', find rational numbers ''u'' and ''v'' such that ''k''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;=&nbsp;''u''<sup>2</sup>&nbsp;+&nbsp;''v''<sup>2</sup>. Diophantus shows how to solve this sum-of-squares problem for ''k''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 (the solutions being ''u'' = 16/5 and ''v'' = 12/5).<ref>Friberg, pp. 333– 334.</ref>
* '''Equivalent statement 1:''' {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}}, where integer {{mvar|n}} ≥ 3, has no non-trivial solutions {{mvar|x}}, {{mvar|y}}, {{mvar|z}} ∈ {{math|'''Z'''}}.


The equivalence is clear if {{mvar|n}} is even. If {{mvar|n}} is odd and all three of {{math|''x'', ''y'', ''z''}} are negative, then we can replace {{math|''x'', ''y'', ''z''}} with {{math|−''x'', −''y'', −''z''}} to obtain a solution in {{math|'''N'''}}. If two of them are negative, it must be {{mvar|x}} and {{mvar|z}} or {{mvar|y}} and {{mvar|z}}. If {{math|''x'', ''z''}} are negative and {{mvar|y}} is positive, then we can rearrange to get {{math|(−''z'')<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} (−''x'')<sup>''n''</sup>}} resulting in a solution in {{math|'''N'''}}; the other case is dealt with analogously. Now if just one is negative, it must be {{mvar|x}} or {{mvar|y}}. If {{mvar|x}} is negative, and {{mvar|y}} and {{mvar|z}} are positive, then it can be rearranged to get {{math|(−''x'')<sup>''n''</sup> + ''z''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''y''<sup>''n''</sup>}} again resulting in a solution in {{math|'''N'''}}; if {{mvar|y}} is negative, the result follows symmetrically. Thus in all cases a nontrivial solution in {{math|'''Z'''}} would also mean a solution exists in {{math|'''N'''}}, the original formulation of the problem.
Around 1637, Fermat wrote his Last Theorem in the margin of his copy of the ''Arithmetica'' next to Diophantus' sum-of-squares problem:<ref>Dickson, p. 731; Singh, pp. 60–62; Aczel, p. 9.</ref>
* '''Equivalent statement 2:''' {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}}, where integer {{math|''n'' ≥ 3}}, has no non-trivial solutions {{math|''x'', ''y'', ''z'' ∈ '''Q'''}}.
{| style="font-style:italic;"
| style="padding:0 1em;vertical-align:top;" | Cubum autem in duos cubos, aut quadratoquadratum in duos quadratoquadratos, et generaliter nullam in infinitum ultra quadratum potestatem in duos eiusdem nominis fas est dividere cuius rei demonstrationem mirabilem sane detexi. Hanc marginis exiguitas non caperet.
| style="padding:0 1em;vertical-align:top;" | it is impossible to separate a cube into two cubes, or a fourth power into two fourth powers, or in general, any power higher than the second, into two like powers. I have discovered a truly marvelous proof of this, which this margin is too narrow to contain.<ref>Panchishkin, </ref>
|}
Although Fermat's general proof is unknown, his proof of one case (''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4) by ] has survived.<ref>Dickson, pp. 615–616; Aczel, p. 44.</ref> Fermat posed the cases of ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 and of ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 as challenges to his mathematical correspondents, such as ], ], and ].<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 13, 24.</ref> However, in the last thirty years of his life, Fermat never again wrote of his "truly marvellous proof" of the general case.


This is because the exponents of {{math|''x'', ''y'',}} and {{mvar|z}} are equal (to {{mvar|n}}), so if there is a solution in {{math|'''Q'''}}, then it can be multiplied through by an appropriate common denominator to get a solution in {{math|'''Z'''}}, and hence in {{math|'''N'''}}.
After Fermat's death in 1665, his son Clément-Samuel Fermat produced a new edition of the book (1670) augmented with his father's comments.<ref>Singh, pp. 62–66.</ref> The margin note became known as ''Fermat's Last Theorem'',<ref name="Dickson, p. 731">Dickson, p. 731.</ref> as it was the last of Fermat's asserted theorems to remain unproven.<ref>Singh, p. 67; Aczel, p. 10.</ref>
* '''Equivalent statement 3:''' {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} 1}}, where integer {{math|''n'' ≥ 3}}, has no non-trivial solutions {{math|''x'', ''y'' ∈ '''Q'''}}.


A non-trivial solution {{mvar|a}}, {{mvar|b}}, {{mvar|c}} ∈ {{math|'''Z'''}} to {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}} yields the non-trivial solution {{math|''a''/''c''}}, {{math|''b''/''c''}} ∈ {{math|'''Q'''}} for {{math|''v''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''w''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} 1}}. Conversely, a solution {{math|''a''/''b''}}, {{math|''c''/''d''}} ∈ {{math|'''Q'''}} to {{math|''v''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''w''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} 1}} yields the non-trivial solution {{math|''ad'', ''cb'', ''bd''}} for {{math|''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> {{=}} ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}}.
==Proofs for specific exponents==
{{Main|Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for specific exponents}}


This last formulation is particularly fruitful, because it reduces the problem from a problem about surfaces in three dimensions to a problem about curves in two dimensions. Furthermore, it allows working over the field {{math|'''Q'''}}, rather than over the ring {{math|'''Z'''}}; ] exhibit more structure than ], which allows for deeper analysis of their elements.
Only one ] has survived, in which Fermat uses the technique of infinite descent to show that the area of a right triangle with integer sides can never equal the square of an integer.<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's One Proof | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-one-proof.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}}</ref> His proof is equivalent to demonstrating that the equation
* '''Equivalent statement 4 – connection to elliptic curves:''' If {{mvar|a}}, {{mvar|b}}, {{mvar|c}} is a non-trivial solution to {{math|''a''<sup>''p''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''p''</sup> {{=}} ''c''<sup>''p''</sup>}}, {{mvar|p}} odd prime, then {{math|''y''<sup>''2''</sup> {{=}} ''x''(''x'' − ''a''<sup>''p''</sup>)(''x'' + ''b''<sup>''p''</sup>)}} (]) will be an ] without a modular form.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Wiles |first=Andrew |authorlink=Andrew Wiles |year=1995 |title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem |url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf |quotation=Frey's suggestion, in the notation of the following theorem, was to show that the (hypothetical) elliptic curve {{math|''y''<sup>''2''</sup> {{=}} ''x''(''x'' + ''u''<sup>''p''</sup>)(''x'' – ''v''<sup>''p''</sup>)}} could not be modular. |journal=] |volume=141 |issue=3 |page=448 |oclc=37032255 |doi=10.2307/2118559 |jstor=2118559 |access-date=11 August 2003 |archive-date=10 May 2011 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110510062158/http://math.stanford.edu/%7Elekheng/flt/wiles.pdf |url-status=dead }}</ref>


Examining this elliptic curve with ] shows that it does not have a ]. However, the proof by Andrew Wiles proves that any equation of the form {{math|''y''<sup>''2''</sup> {{=}} ''x''(''x'' − ''a''<sup>''n''</sup>)(''x'' + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup>)}} does have a modular form. Any non-trivial solution to {{math|{{itco|''x''}}<sup>''p''</sup> + {{itco|''y''}}<sup>''p''</sup> {{=}} {{itco|''z''}}<sup>''p''</sup>}} (with {{mvar|p}} an odd prime) would therefore create a ], which in turn proves that no non-trivial solutions exist.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Ribet |first=Ken |authorlink=Ken Ribet |title=On modular representations of Gal({{overline|'''Q'''}}/'''Q''') arising from modular forms |journal=Inventiones Mathematicae |volume=100 |year=1990 |issue=2 |page=432 |doi=10.1007/BF01231195 |mr=1047143 |url=http://math.berkeley.edu/~ribet/Articles/invent_100.pdf |bibcode=1990InMat.100..431R|hdl=10338.dmlcz/147454 |s2cid=120614740 }}</ref>
:<math>x^4 - y^4 = z^2</math>


In other words, any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the modularity theorem. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then it would follow that no contradiction to Fermat's Last Theorem could exist either. As described above, the discovery of this equivalent statement was crucial to the eventual solution of Fermat's Last Theorem, as it provided a means by which it could be "attacked" for all numbers at once.
has no primitive solutions in integers (no ] solutions). In turn, this proves Fermat's Last Theorem for the case ''n''=4, since the equation ''a''<sup>4</sup> + ''b''<sup>4</sup> = ''c''<sup>4</sup> can be written as ''c''<sup>4</sup> − ''b''<sup>4</sup> = (''a''<sup>2</sup>)<sup>2</sup>.


== Mathematical history ==
Alternative proofs of the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 were developed later<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 15–24.</ref> by ] (1676),<ref>Frénicle de Bessy, ''Traité des Triangles Rectangles en Nombres'', vol. I, 1676, Paris. Reprinted in ''Mém. Acad. Roy. Sci.'', '''5''', 1666–1699 (1729).</ref> ] (1738),<ref name="Euler_1738">{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1738 | title = Theorematum quorundam arithmeticorum demonstrationes | journal = Comm. Acad. Sci. Petrop. | volume = 10 | pages = 125–146}}. Reprinted ''Opera omnia'', ser. I, "Commentationes Arithmeticae", vol. I, pp. 38–58, Leipzig:Teubner (1915).</ref> Kausler (1802),<ref name="Kausler_1802" /> ] (1811),<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1811 | title = An Elementary Investigation of Theory of Numbers | location = St. Paul's Church-Yard, London | publisher = J. Johnson | pages = 144–145}}</ref> ] (1830),<ref name="Legendre_1830" /> Schopis (1825),<ref>{{cite book | author = Schopis | year = 1825 | title = Einige Sätze aus der unbestimmten Analytik | publisher = Programm | location = Gummbinnen}}</ref> Terquem (1846),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Terquem O | year = 1846 | title = Théorèmes sur les puissances des nombres | journal = Nouv. Ann. Math. | volume = 5 | pages = 70–87}}</ref> ] (1851),<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1851 | title = Traité Élémentaire d'Algèbre | publisher = Hachette | location = Paris | pages = 217–230, 395}}</ref> ] (1853, 1859, 1862),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1853 | title = Résolution des équations biquadratiques ''z''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''<sup>4</sup> ± 2<sup>''m''</sup>''y''<sup>4</sup>, ''z''<sup>2</sup> = 2<sup>''m''</sup>''x''<sup>4</sup> − ''y''<sup>4</sup>, 2<sup>''m''</sup>''z''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''<sup>4</sup> ± ''y''<sup>4</sup> | journal = J. Math. Pures Appl. | volume = 18 | pages = 73–86}}<br />{{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1859 | title = Exercices d'Analyse Numérique | publisher = Leiber et Faraguet | location = Paris | pages = 83–84, 89}}<br />{{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1862 | title = Introduction à la Théorie des Nombres | publisher = Mallet-Bachelier | location = Paris | pages = 71–73}}</ref> Theophile Pepin (1883),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Pepin T | year = 1883 | title = Étude sur l'équation indéterminée ''ax''<sup>4</sup> + ''by''<sup>4</sup> = ''cz''<sup>2</sup> | journal = Atti Accad. Naz. Lincei | volume = 36 | pages = 34–70}}</ref> Tafelmacher (1893),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Tafelmacher WLA | year = 1893 | title = Sobre la ecuación ''x''<sup>4</sup> + ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup> | journal = Ann. Univ. Chile | volume = 84 | pages = 307–320}}</ref> ] (1897),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1897 | title = Die Theorie der algebraischen Zahlkörper | journal = ] | volume = 4 | pages = 175–546}} Reprinted in 1965 in ''Gesammelte Abhandlungen, vol. I'' by New York:Chelsea.</ref> Bendz (1901),<ref>{{cite book | author = Bendz TR | year = 1901 | title = Öfver diophantiska ekvationen ''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''n''</sup> | publisher = Almqvist & Wiksells Boktrycken | location = Uppsala}}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901" /> ] (1901),<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1901 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie, vol. I | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig | pages = 35–38}} Reprinted by New York:Springer-Verlag in 1978.</ref> Bang (1905),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bang A | year = 1905 | title = Nyt Bevis for at Ligningen ''x''<sup>4</sup> − ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup>, ikke kan have rationale Løsinger | journal = Nyt Tidsskrift Mat. | volume = 16B | pages = 35–36}}</ref> Sommer (1907),<ref>{{cite book | author = Sommer J | year = 1907 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig}}</ref> Bottari (1908),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bottari A | year = 1908 | title = Soluzione intere dell'equazione pitagorica e applicazione alla dimostrazione di alcune teoremi dellla teoria dei numeri | journal = Period. Mat. | volume = 23 | pages = 104–110}}</ref> ] (1910),<ref name="Rychlik_1910" /> Nutzhorn (1912),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Nutzhorn F | year = 1912 | title = Den ubestemte Ligning ''x''<sup>4</sup> + ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup> | journal = Nyt Tidsskrift Mat. | volume = 23B | pages = 33–38}}</ref> ] (1913),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1913 | title = On the impossibility of certain Diophantine equations and systems of equations | journal = Amer. Math. Monthly | volume = 20 | pages = 213–221 | doi = 10.2307/2974106 | issue = 7 | publisher = Mathematical Association of America | jstor = 2974106}}</ref> Hancock (1931),<ref>{{cite book | author = Hancock H | year = 1931 | title = Foundations of the Theory of Algebraic Numbers, vol. I | publisher = Macmillan | location = New York}}</ref> and Vrǎnceanu (1966).<ref>{{cite journal | author = Vrǎnceanu G | year = 1966 | title = Asupra teorema lui Fermat pentru ''n''=4 | journal = Gaz. Mat. Ser. A | volume = 71 | pages = 334–335}} Reprinted in 1977 in ''Opera matematica'', vol. 4, pp. 202–205, Bucureşti:Edit. Acad. Rep. Soc. Romana.</ref>
=== Pythagoras and Diophantus ===
==== Pythagorean triples ====
{{Main|Pythagorean triple}}


In ancient times it was known that a triangle whose sides were in the ratio 3:4:5 would have a right angle as one of its angles. This was used in construction and later in early geometry. It was also known to be one example of a general rule that any triangle where the length of two sides, each squared and then added together {{nowrap|1=(3<sup>2</sup> + 4<sup>2</sup> = 9 + 16 = 25)}}, equals the square of the length of the third side {{nowrap|1=(5<sup>2</sup> = 25)}}, would also be a right angle triangle. This is now known as the ], and a triple of numbers that meets this condition is called a Pythagorean triple; both are named after the ancient Greek ]. Examples include (3, 4, 5) and (5, 12, 13). There are infinitely many such triples,<ref name="Stillwell_2003">{{cite book | author = Stillwell J | year = 2003 | title = Elements of Number Theory | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=LiAlZO2ntKAC&pg=PA110 | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 0-387-95587-9 | pages = 110–112 | access-date = 2016-03-17| authorlink=John Stillwell }}</ref> and methods for generating such triples have been studied in many cultures, beginning with the ]{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=13–15|ps=}} and later ], ], and ] mathematicians.<ref name="auto"/> Mathematically, the definition of a Pythagorean triple is a set of three integers {{nowrap|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'')}} that satisfy the equation{{sfn|Stark|1978|pp=151–155|ps=}} {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>2</sup> + ''b''<sup>2</sup> = ''c''<sup>2</sup>}}.
For another proof for ''n''=4 by infinite descent, see ]. For various proofs for ''n''=4 by infinite descent, see Grant and Perella (1999),<ref>Grant, Mike, and Perella, Malcolm, "Descending to the irrational", ''Mathematical Gazette'' 83, July 1999, pp.263-267.</ref> Barbara (2007),<ref>Barbara, Roy, "Fermat's last theorem in the case n=4", ''Mathematical Gazette'' 91, July 2007, 260-262.</ref> and Dolan (2011).<ref>Dolan, Stan, "Fermat's method of ''descente infinie''", '']'' 95, July 2011, 269-271.</ref>


==== Diophantine equations ====
After Fermat proved the special case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4, the general proof for all ''n'' required only that the theorem be established for all odd prime exponents.<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 1–2.</ref> In other words, it was necessary to prove only that the equation ''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup> has no integer solutions (''a'', ''b'', ''c'') when ''n'' is an odd ]. This follows because a solution (''a'',&nbsp;''b'',&nbsp;''c'') for a given ''n'' is equivalent to a solution for all the factors of ''n''. For illustration, let ''n'' be factored into ''d'' and ''e'', ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;''de''. The general equation
{{Main|Diophantine equation}}


Fermat's equation, {{nowrap|1=''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''n''</sup>}} with positive ] solutions, is an example of a ],{{sfn|Stark|1978|pp=145–146|ps=}} named for the 3rd-century ]n mathematician, ], who studied them and developed methods for the solution of some kinds of Diophantine equations. A typical Diophantine problem is to find two integers ''x'' and ''y'' such that their sum, and the sum of their squares, equal two given numbers ''A'' and ''B'', respectively:
: ''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>
: <math>A = x + y</math>
: <math>B = x^2 + y^2.</math>


Diophantus's major work is the '']'', of which only a portion has survived.<ref>Singh, pp. 50–51</ref> Fermat's conjecture of his Last Theorem was inspired while reading a new edition of the ''Arithmetica'',{{sfn|Stark|1978|p=145|ps=}} that was translated into Latin and published in 1621 by ].{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=44–45|ps=}}<ref>Singh, pp. 56–58</ref>
implies that (''a''<sup>''d''</sup>,&nbsp;''b''<sup>''d''</sup>,&nbsp;''c''<sup>''d''</sup>) is a solution for the exponent ''e''


Diophantine equations have been studied for thousands of years. For example, the solutions to the quadratic Diophantine equation {{nowrap|1=''x''<sup>2</sup> + ''y''<sup>2</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup>}} are given by the ]s, originally solved by the Babylonians ({{circa|1800 BC}}).{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=14–15|ps=}} Solutions to linear Diophantine equations, such as {{nowrap|1=26''x'' + 65''y'' = 13}}, may be found using the ] (c. 5th century BC).{{sfn|Stark|1978|pp=44–47|ps=}}
Many ]s have a form similar to the equation of Fermat's Last Theorem from the point of view of algebra, in that they have no ''cross terms'' mixing two letters, without sharing its particular properties. For example, it is known that there are infinitely many positive integers ''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' such that {{nowrap|1=''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''m''</sup>}}, where ''n'' and ''m'' are ] natural numbers.<ref group="note">For example, {{nowrap|((''j''<sup>''r''</sup> + 1)<sup>''s''</sup>)<sup>''r''</sup> + (''j''(''j''<sup>''r''</sup> + 1)<sup>''s''</sup>)<sup>''r''</sup>}} = {{nowrap|(''j''<sup>''r''</sup> + 1)<sup>''rs''+1</sup>}}.</ref>

=== Fermat's conjecture ===
]. On the right is the margin that was too small to contain Fermat's alleged proof of his "last theorem".]]

Problem II.8 of the {{lang|la|]}} asks how a given square number is split into two other squares; in other words, for a given ] ''k'', find rational numbers ''u'' and ''v'' such that {{nowrap|1=''k''<sup>2</sup> = ''u''<sup>2</sup> + ''v''<sup>2</sup>}}. Diophantus shows how to solve this sum-of-squares problem for {{nowrap|1=''k'' = 4}} (the solutions being {{nowrap|1=''u'' = 16/5}} and {{nowrap|1=''v'' = 12/5}}).{{sfn|Friberg|2007|pp=333–334|ps=}}

Around 1637, Fermat wrote his Last Theorem in the margin of his copy of the {{lang|la|Arithmetica}} next to ]:{{sfn|Dickson|1919|p=731|ps=}}<ref>Singh, pp. 60–62</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=9|ps=}}

{{Verse translation|lang=la|Cubum autem in duos cubos, aut quadratoquadratum in duos quadratoquadratos & generaliter nullam in infinitum ultra quadratum potestatem in duos eiusdem nominis fas est dividere cuius rei demonstrationem mirabilem sane detexi. Hanc marginis exiguitas non caperet.|It is impossible to separate a cube into two cubes, or a fourth power into two fourth powers, or in general, any power higher than the second, into two like powers. I have discovered a truly marvelous proof of this, which this margin is too narrow to contain.<ref>T. Heath, ''Diophantus of Alexandria'' Second Edition, Cambridge University Press, 1910, reprinted by Dover, NY, 1964, pp.&nbsp;144–145</ref>{{sfn|Manin|Panchishkin|2007|loc=|ps=}}}}

After Fermat's death in 1665, his son Clément-Samuel Fermat produced a new edition of the book (1670) augmented with his father's comments.<ref>Singh, pp. 62–66</ref> Although not actually a theorem at the time (meaning a mathematical statement for which ] exists), the marginal note became known over time as ''Fermat's Last Theorem'',{{sfn|Dickson|1919|p=731|ps=}} as it was the last of Fermat's asserted theorems to remain unproved.<ref>Singh, p. 67</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=10|ps=}}

It is not known whether Fermat had actually found a valid proof for all exponents ''n'', but it appears unlikely. Only one related proof by him has survived, namely for the case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}}, as described in the section {{slink||Proofs for specific exponents}}.

While Fermat posed the cases of {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}} and of {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 3}} as challenges to his mathematical correspondents, such as ], ], and ],<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 13, 24</ref> he never posed the general case.<ref name="van der Poorten-p.5">van der Poorten, Notes and Remarks 1.2, p. 5</ref> Moreover, in the last thirty years of his life, Fermat never again wrote of his "truly marvelous proof" of the general case, and never published it. Van der Poorten<ref name="van der Poorten-p.5"/> suggests that while the absence of a proof is insignificant, the lack of challenges means Fermat realised he did not have a proof; he quotes ]<ref>{{cite book | author = André Weil | year = 1984 | title = Number Theory: An approach through history. From Hammurapi to Legendre | publisher = Birkhäuser | location = Basel, Switzerland | page = 104| authorlink=André Weil }}</ref> as saying Fermat must have briefly deluded himself with an irretrievable idea. The techniques Fermat might have used in such a "marvelous proof" are unknown.

Wiles and Taylor's proof relies on 20th-century techniques.<ref>{{cite AV media|url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ua8K8HW2Qsg#t=47m|title=BBC Documentary}}{{cbignore}}{{Dead YouTube link|date=February 2022}}</ref> Fermat's proof would have had to be elementary by comparison, given the mathematical knowledge of his time.

While ]'s ] implies that any provable theorem (including Fermat's last theorem) can be proved using only ']', such a proof need be 'elementary' only in a technical sense and could involve millions of steps, and thus be far too long to have been Fermat's proof.

=== Proofs for specific exponents ===
{{Main|Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for specific exponents}}
] for Fermat's Last Theorem case n=4 in the 1670 edition of the ''Arithmetica'' of ] (pp. 338–339).]]

==== Exponent = 4 ====
Only one relevant ] has survived, in which he uses the technique of ] to show that the area of a right triangle with integer sides can never equal the square of an integer.<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's One Proof | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-one-proof.html | access-date = 23 May 2009| date = 12 May 2005 }}</ref>{{sfn|Dickson|1919|pp=615–616|ps=}}{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=44|ps=}} His proof is equivalent to demonstrating that the equation
: <math>x^4 - y^4 = z^2</math>
has no primitive solutions in integers (no pairwise ] solutions). In turn, this proves Fermat's Last Theorem for the case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}}, since the equation {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>4</sup> + ''b''<sup>4</sup> = ''c''<sup>4</sup>}} can be written as {{nowrap|1=''c''<sup>4</sup> − ''b''<sup>4</sup> = (''a''<sup>2</sup>)<sup>2</sup>}}.

Alternative proofs of the case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}} were developed later<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 15–24</ref> by ] (1676),<ref>Frénicle de Bessy, ''Traité des Triangles Rectangles en Nombres'', vol. I, 1676, Paris. Reprinted in ''Mém. Acad. Roy. Sci.'', '''5''', 1666–1699 (1729)</ref> ] (1738),<ref name="Euler_1738">{{cite journal | author = Euler L | year = 1738 | title = Theorematum quorundam arithmeticorum demonstrationes | journal = Novi Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Petropolitanae | volume = 10 | pages = 125–146| authorlink=Leonhard Euler }}. Reprinted ''Opera omnia'', ser. I, "Commentationes Arithmeticae", vol. I, pp. 38–58, Leipzig:Teubner (1915)</ref> Kausler (1802),<ref name="Kausler_1802"/> ] (1811),<ref>{{cite book | author = Barlow P | year = 1811 | title = An Elementary Investigation of Theory of Numbers | location = St. Paul's Church-Yard, London | publisher = J. Johnson | pages = 144–145| authorlink=Peter Barlow (mathematician) }}</ref> ] (1830),<ref name="Legendre_1830"/> Schopis (1825),<ref>{{cite book | author = Schopis | year = 1825 | title = Einige Sätze aus der unbestimmten Analytik | publisher = Programm | location = Gummbinnen}}</ref> ] (1846),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Terquem O | year = 1846 | title = Théorèmes sur les puissances des nombres | journal = ] | volume = 5 | pages = 70–87| authorlink=Olry Terquem }}</ref> ] (1851),<ref>{{cite book | author = Bertrand J | year = 1851 | title = Traité Élémentaire d'Algèbre | publisher = Hachette | location = Paris | pages = 217–230, 395| authorlink=Joseph Louis François Bertrand }}</ref> ] (1853, 1859, 1862),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1853 | title = Résolution des équations biquadratiques ''z''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''<sup>4</sup> ± 2<sup>''m''</sup>''y''<sup>4</sup>, ''z''<sup>2</sup> = 2<sup>''m''</sup>''x''<sup>4</sup> − ''y''<sup>4</sup>, 2<sup>''m''</sup>''z''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''<sup>4</sup> ± ''y''<sup>4</sup> | journal = ] | volume = 18 | pages = 73–86}}<br/>{{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1859 | title = Exercices d'Analyse Numérique | publisher = Leiber et Faraguet | location = Paris | pages = 83–84, 89}}<br/>{{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1862 | title = Introduction à la Théorie des Nombres | publisher = Mallet-Bachelier | location = Paris | pages = 71–73}}</ref> ] (1883),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Pepin T | year = 1883 | title = Étude sur l'équation indéterminée ''ax''<sup>4</sup> + ''by''<sup>4</sup> = ''cz''<sup>2</sup> | journal = Atti della Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei. Classe di Scienze Fisiche, Matematiche e Naturali. Rendiconti Lincei. Serie IX. Matematica e Applicazioni. | volume = 36 | pages = 34–70}}</ref> Tafelmacher (1893),<ref>{{cite journal | author = A. Tafelmacher | year = 1893 | title = Sobre la ecuación ''x''<sup>4</sup> + ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup> | journal = ] | volume = 84 | pages = 307–320 |url=https://anales.uchile.cl/index.php/ANUC/article/view/20645}}</ref> ] (1897),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Hilbert D | year = 1897 | title = Die Theorie der algebraischen Zahlkörper | journal = ] | volume = 4 | pages = 175–546| authorlink=David Hilbert }} Reprinted in 1965 in ''Gesammelte Abhandlungen, vol. I'' by New York:Chelsea.</ref> Bendz (1901),<ref>{{cite thesis | author = Bendz TR | year = 1901 | title = Öfver diophantiska ekvationen {{nowrap|1=x<sup>n</sup> + y<sup>n</sup> = z<sup>n</sup>}} | publisher = Almqvist & Wiksells Boktrycken | location = Uppsala}}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901"/> ] (1901),<ref>{{cite book | author = Kronecker L | year = 1901 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie, vol. I | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig | pages = 35–38| authorlink=Leopold Kronecker }} Reprinted by New York:Springer-Verlag in 1978.</ref> Bang (1905),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bang A | year = 1905 | title = Nyt Bevis for at Ligningen {{nowrap|1=''x''<sup>4</sup> − ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup>}}, ikke kan have rationale Løsinger | journal = Nyt Tidsskrift for Matematik | volume = 16B | pages = 31–35 |jstor=24528323}}</ref> Sommer (1907),<ref>{{cite book | author = Sommer J | year = 1907 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig}}</ref> Bottari (1908),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bottari A | year = 1908 | title = Soluzione intere dell'equazione pitagorica e applicazione alla dimostrazione di alcune teoremi della teoria dei numeri | journal = Periodico di Matematiche | volume = 23 | pages = 104–110}}</ref> ] (1910),<ref name="Rychlik_1910"/> Nutzhorn (1912),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Nutzhorn F | year = 1912 | title = Den ubestemte Ligning ''x''<sup>4</sup> + ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>4</sup> | journal = Nyt Tidsskrift for Matematik | volume = 23B | pages = 33–38}}</ref> ] (1913),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Carmichael RD | year = 1913 | title = On the impossibility of certain Diophantine equations and systems of equations | journal = ] | volume = 20 | pages = 213–221 | doi = 10.2307/2974106 | issue = 7 | publisher = Mathematical Association of America | jstor = 2974106| authorlink=Robert Daniel Carmichael }}</ref> Hancock (1931),<ref>{{cite book | author = Hancock H | year = 1931 | title = Foundations of the Theory of Algebraic Numbers, vol. I | publisher = Macmillan | location = New York}}</ref> ] (1966),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Gheorghe Vrănceanu | year = 1966 | title = Asupra teorema lui Fermat pentru {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}} | journal = Gazeta Matematică Seria A | volume = 71 | pages = 334–335 }} Reprinted in 1977 in ''Opera matematica'', vol. 4, pp. 202–205, București: Editura Academiei Republicii Socialiste România.</ref> Grant and Perella (1999),<ref>Grant, Mike, and Perella, Malcolm, "Descending to the irrational", ''Mathematical Gazette'' 83, July 1999, pp. 263–267.</ref> Barbara (2007),<ref>Barbara, Roy, "Fermat's last theorem in the case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}}", ''Mathematical Gazette'' 91, July 2007, 260–262.</ref> and Dolan (2011).<ref>Dolan, Stan, "Fermat's method of ''descente infinie''", '']'' 95, July 2011, 269–271.</ref>

==== Other exponents ====
After Fermat proved the special case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}}, the general proof for all ''n'' required only that the theorem be established for all odd prime exponents.<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 1–2</ref> In other words, it was necessary to prove only that the equation {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} has no positive integer solutions {{nowrap|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'')}} when ''n'' is an odd ]. This follows because a solution {{nowrap|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'')}} for a given ''n'' is equivalent to a solution for all the factors of ''n''. For illustration, let ''n'' be factored into ''d'' and ''e'', ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;''de''. The general equation
: ''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>
implies that {{nowrap|(''a''<sup>''d''</sup>, ''b''<sup>''d''</sup>, ''c''<sup>''d''</sup>)}} is a solution for the exponent ''e''
: (''a''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup> + (''b''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup> = (''c''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup>. : (''a''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup> + (''b''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup> = (''c''<sup>''d''</sup>)<sup>''e''</sup>.


Thus, to prove that Fermat's equation has no solutions for ''n''&nbsp;>&nbsp;2, it suffices to prove that it has no solutions for at least one prime factor of every ''n''. All integers ''n''&nbsp;>&nbsp;2 contain a factor of 4, or an odd prime number, or both. Therefore, Fermat's Last Theorem can be proven for all ''n'' if it can be proven for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 and for all odd primes (the only ''even'' prime number is the number 2) ''p''. Thus, to prove that Fermat's equation has no solutions for {{nowrap|''n'' > 2}}, it would suffice to prove that it has no solutions for at least one prime factor of every ''n''. Each integer {{nowrap|''n'' > 2}} is divisible by 4 or by an odd prime number (or both). Therefore, Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved for all ''n'' if it could be proved for {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 4}} and for all odd primes ''p''.


In the two centuries following its conjecture (1637–1839), Fermat's Last Theorem was proven for three odd prime exponents ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3, 5 and 7. The case ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 was first stated by ] (10th century), but his attempted proof of the theorem was incorrect.<ref>Dickson, p. 545.<br />{{MacTutor|id=Al-Khujandi|title=Abu Mahmud Hamid ibn al-Khidr Al-Khujandi}}</ref> In 1770, ] gave a proof of ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3,<ref>] (1770) ''Vollständige Anleitung zur Algebra'', Roy. Acad. Sci., St. Petersburg.</ref> but his proof by infinite descent<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n3.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}}</ref> contained a major gap.<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 24–25; Mordell, pp. 6–8; Edwards, pp. 39-40.</ref> However, since Euler himself had proven the lemma necessary to complete the proof in other work, he is generally credited with the first proof.<ref>Aczel, p. 44; Edwards, pp. 40, 52-54.<br />{{cite journal |author=J. J. Mačys |title=On Euler's hypothetical proof |journal=Mathematical Notes |year=2007 |volume=82 |issue=3–4 |pages=352–356 |url=http://www.springerlink.com/content/u46jj0nuk3678591/ |doi=10.1134/S0001434607090088 |mr=2364600}}</ref> Independent proofs were published<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 33, 37–41.</ref> by Kausler (1802),<ref name="Kausler_1802" >{{cite journal | author = Kausler CF | year = 1802 | title = Nova demonstratio theorematis nec summam, nec differentiam duorum cuborum cubum esse posse | journal = Novi Acta Acad. Petrop. | volume = 13 | pages = 245–253}}</ref> Legendre (1823, 1830),<ref name="Legendre_1830" >{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1830 | title = Théorie des Nombres (Volume II) | edition = 3rd | publisher = Firmin Didot Frères | location = Paris}} Reprinted in 1955 by A. Blanchard (Paris).</ref><ref name="Legendre_1823" >{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1823 | title = Recherches sur quelques objets d'analyse indéterminée, et particulièrement sur le théorème de Fermat | journal = Mém. Acad. Roy. Sci. Institut France | volume = 6 | pages = 1–60}} Reprinted in 1825 as the "Second Supplément" for a printing of the 2nd edition of ''Essai sur la Théorie des Nombres'', Courcier (Paris). Also reprinted in 1909 in ''Sphinx-Oedipe'', '''4''', 97–128.</ref> Calzolari (1855),<ref>{{cite book | author = Calzolari L | year = 1855 | title = Tentativo per dimostrare il teorema di Fermat sull'equazione indeterminata ''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''n''</sup> | publisher = Ferrara}}</ref> ] (1865),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1865 | title = Étude des binômes cubiques ''x''<sup>3</sup> ± ''y''<sup>3</sup> | journal = C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris | volume = 61 | pages = 921–924, 961–965}}</ref> ] (1872),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1872 | title = Mathematical Notes | journal = Proc. Roy. Soc. Edinburgh | volume = 7 | page = 144}}</ref> Günther (1878),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Günther S | year = 1878 | title = Über die unbestimmte Gleichung ''x''<sup>''3''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''3''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''3''</sup> | journal = Sitzungsberichte Böhm. Ges. Wiss. | pages = 112–120}}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901" >{{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | year = 1901 | title = Memoria bibliographica sull'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Period. Mat. | volume = 16 | pages = 145–192}}</ref> Krey (1909),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Krey H | year = 1909 | title = Neuer Beweis eines arithmetischen Satzes | journal = Math. Naturwiss. Blätter | volume = 6 | pages = 179–180}}</ref> Rychlík (1910),<ref name="Rychlik_1910" >{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 and ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 (in Bohemian) | journal = Časopis Pěst. Mat. | volume = 39 | pages = 65–86}}</ref> Stockhaus (1910),<ref>{{cite book | author = Stockhaus H | year = 1910 | title = Beitrag zum Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes | publisher = Brandstetter | location = Leipzig}}</ref> Carmichael (1915),<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1915 | title = Diophantine Analysis | publisher = Wiley | location = New York}}</ref> ] (1915),<ref name="van_der_Corput_1915" >{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1915 | title = Quelques formes quadratiques et quelques équations indéterminées | journal = Nieuw Archief Wisk. | volume = 11 | pages = 45–75}}</ref> ] (1917),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1917 | title = Et bevis for at ligningen ''A''<sup>3</sup> + ''B''<sup>3</sup> = ''C''<sup>3</sup> er unmulig i hele tal fra nul forskjellige tal ''A'', ''B'' og ''C'' | journal = Arch. Mat. Naturv. | volume = 34 | issue = 15}} Reprinted in ''Selected Mathematical Papers'' (1977), Oslo:Universitetsforlaget, pp. 555–559.</ref> and Duarte (1944).<ref>{{cite journal | author = Duarte FJ | year = 1944 | title = Sobre la ecuación ''x''<sup>3</sup> + ''y''<sup>3</sup> + ''z''<sup>3</sup> = 0 | journal = Ciencias Fis. Mat. Naturales (Caracas) | volume = 8 | pages = 971–979}}</ref> The case ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;5 was proven<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;5 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/10/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n5_28.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}}</ref> independently by Legendre and ] around 1825.<ref>Ribenboim, p. 49; Mordell, p. 8–9; Aczel, p. 44; Singh, p. 106.</ref> Alternative proofs were developed<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 55–57.</ref> by ] (1875, posthumous),<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1875, posthumous | chapter = Neue Theorie der Zerlegung der Cuben | title = Zur Theorie der complexen Zahlen, Werke, vol. II | edition = 2nd | publisher = Königl. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen | pages = 387–391}}</ref> Lebesgue (1843),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1843 | title = Théorèmes nouveaux sur l'équation indéterminée ''x''<sup>5</sup> + ''y''<sup>5</sup> = ''az''<sup>5</sup> | journal = J. Math. Pures Appl. | volume = 8 | pages = 49–70}}</ref> Lamé (1847),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1847 | title = Mémoire sur la résolution en nombres complexes de l'équation ''A''<sup>5</sup> + ''B''<sup>5</sup> + ''C''<sup>5</sup> = 0 | journal = J. Math. Pures Appl. | volume = 12 | pages = 137–171}}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901" /><ref>{{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | year = 1903/4 | title = Intorno all'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Il Pitagora | volume = 10 | pages = 11–13, 41–42}}</ref> Werebrusow (1905),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Werebrusow AS | year = 1905 | title = On the equation ''x''<sup>5</sup> + ''y''<sup>5</sup> = ''Az''<sup>5</sup> ''(in Russian)'' | journal = Moskov. Math. Samml. | volume = 25 | pages = 466–473}}</ref> Rychlík (1910),<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;5 ''(in Bohemian)'' | journal = Časopis Pěst. Mat. | volume = 39 | pages = 185–195, 305–317}}</ref> van der Corput (1915),<ref name="van_der_Corput_1915" /> and ] (1987).<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1987 | title = Sur une question de V. A. Lebesgue | journal = Ann. Inst. Fourier | volume = 37 | pages = 19–37 | doi=10.5802/aif.1096}}</ref> The case ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;7 was proven<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 57–63; Mordell, p. 8; Aczel, p. 44; Singh, p. 106.</ref> by Lamé in 1839.<ref name="Lame_1839" >{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1839 | title = Mémoire sur le dernier théorème de Fermat | journal = C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris | volume = 9 | pages = 45–46}}<br />{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1840 | title = Mémoire d'analyse indéterminée démontrant que l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> = ''z''<sup>7</sup> est impossible en nombres entiers | journal = J. Math. Pures Appl. | volume = 5 | pages = 195–211}}</ref> His rather complicated proof was simplified in 1840 by Lebesgue,<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1840 | title = Démonstration de l'impossibilité de résoudre l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 en nombres entiers | journal = J. Math. Pures Appl. | volume = 5 | pages = 276–279, 348–349}}</ref> and still simpler proofs<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;7 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2006/01/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n7.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}}</ref> were published by ] in 1864, 1874 and 1876.<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1864 | title = Intorno all'equazioni ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = Annali Mat. | volume = 6 | pages = 287–288}}<br />{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1874 | title = Sur l'impossibilité de quelques égalités doubles | journal = C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris | volume = 78 | pages = 433–436}}<br />{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1876 | title = Généralisation du théorème de Lamé sur l'impossibilité de l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris | volume = 82 | pages = 910–913}}</ref> Alternative proofs were developed by Théophile Pépin (1876)<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1876 | title = Impossibilité de l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris | volume = 82 | pages = 676–679, 743–747}}</ref> and Edmond Maillet (1897).<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1897 | title = Sur l'équation indéterminée ''ax''<sup>λ<sup>''t''</sup></sup> + ''by''<sup>λ<sup>''t''</sup></sup> = ''cz''<sup>λ<sup>''t''</sup></sup> | journal = Assoc. Française Avanc. Sci., St. Etienne (sér. II) | volume = 26 | pages = 156–168}}</ref> In the two centuries following its conjecture (1637–1839), Fermat's Last Theorem was proved for three odd prime exponents ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3, 5 and 7. The case {{nowrap|1=''p'' = 3}} was first stated by ] (10th century), but his attempted proof of the theorem was incorrect.{{sfn|Dickson|1919|p=545|ps=}}<ref>{{MacTutor|id=Al-Khujandi|title=Abu Mahmud Hamid ibn al-Khidr Al-Khujandi|mode=cs1}}</ref> In 1770, ] gave a proof of ''p''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3,<ref>] (1770) ''Vollständige Anleitung zur Algebra'', Roy. Acad. Sci., St. Petersburg.</ref> but his proof by infinite descent<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n3.html | access-date = 23 May 2009|date = 22 May 2005}}</ref> contained a major gap.<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 24–25</ref>{{sfn|Mordell|1921|pp=6–8|ps=}}{{sfn|Edwards|1996|pp=39–40|ps=}} However, since Euler himself had proved the lemma necessary to complete the proof in other work, he is generally credited with the first proof.{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=44|ps=}}{{sfn|Edwards|1996|pp=40,52–54|ps=}}<ref>{{cite journal |author=J. J. Mačys |title=On Euler's hypothetical proof |journal=Mathematical Notes |year=2007 |volume=82 |issue=3–4 |pages=352–356 |doi=10.1134/S0001434607090088 |mr=2364600|s2cid=121798358 }}</ref> Independent proofs were published<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 33, 37–41</ref> by Kausler (1802),<ref name="Kausler_1802" >{{cite journal | author = Kausler CF | year = 1802 | title = Nova demonstratio theorematis nec summam, nec differentiam duorum cuborum cubum esse posse | journal =Novi Acta Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae | volume = 13 | pages = 245–253}}</ref> Legendre (1823, 1830),<ref name="Legendre_1830" >{{cite book | author = Legendre AM | year = 1830 | title = Théorie des Nombres (Volume II) | edition = 3rd | publisher = Firmin Didot Frères | location = Paris| authorlink=Adrien-Marie Legendre }} Reprinted in 1955 by A. Blanchard (Paris).</ref><ref name="Legendre_1823" >{{cite journal | author = Legendre AM | year = 1823 | title = Recherches sur quelques objets d'analyse indéterminée, et particulièrement sur le théorème de Fermat | journal = Mémoires de l'Académie royale des sciences | volume = 6 | pages = 1–60| authorlink=Adrien-Marie Legendre }} Reprinted in 1825 as the "Second Supplément" for a printing of the 2nd edition of ''Essai sur la Théorie des Nombres'', Courcier (Paris). Also reprinted in 1909 in ''Sphinx-Oedipe'', '''4''', 97–128.</ref> Calzolari (1855),<ref>{{cite book | author = Calzolari L | year = 1855 | title = Tentativo per dimostrare il teorema di Fermat sull'equazione indeterminata x<sup>n</sup> + y<sup>n</sup> = z<sup>n</sup> | publisher = Ferrara}}</ref> ] (1865),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1865 | title = Étude des binômes cubiques ''x''<sup>3</sup> ± ''y''<sup>3</sup> | journal = ] | volume = 61 | pages = 921–924, 961–965| authorlink=Gabriel Lamé }}</ref> ] (1872),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Tait PG | year = 1872 | title = Mathematical Notes | journal = Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh | volume = 7 | page = 144 | doi=10.1017/s0370164600041857| url = https://zenodo.org/record/1428704 | authorlink=Peter Guthrie Tait }}</ref> ] (1878),<ref>{{cite journal | last = Günther |first=S.|author-link=Siegmund Günther | year = 1878 | title = Ueber die unbestimmte Gleichung {{math|1=''x''<sup>''3''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''3''</sup> = ''a''<sup>''3''</sup>}} | journal = Sitzungsberichte der Königliche böhmische Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften in Prag |volume=jahrg. 1878-1880 | pages = 112–120|url=https://www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/111872#page/150}}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901" >{{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | year = 1901 | title = Memoria bibliographica sull'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Periodico di Matematiche | volume = 16 | pages = 145–192}}</ref> Krey (1909),<ref>{{cite journal|last=Krey|first=H.|year=1909|title=Neuer Beweis eines arithmetischen Satzes|journal=Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Blätter|volume=6|issue=12|pages=179–180|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=90Q6AQAAMAAJ&pg=RA2-PA179}}</ref> Rychlík (1910),<ref name="Rychlik_1910" >{{cite journal | author = Rychlik K | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4 and ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3 (in Bohemian) | journal = Časopis Pro Pěstování Matematiky a Fysiky | volume = 39 | pages = 65–86| authorlink=Karel Rychlík }}</ref> Stockhaus (1910),<ref>{{cite book | author = Stockhaus H | year = 1910 | title = Beitrag zum Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes | publisher = Brandstetter | location = Leipzig}}</ref> Carmichael (1915),<ref>{{cite book | author = Carmichael RD | year = 1915 | title = Diophantine Analysis | publisher = Wiley | location = New York| authorlink=Robert Daniel Carmichael }}</ref> ] (1915),<ref name="van_der_Corput_1915" >{{cite journal | author = van der Corput JG | year = 1915 | title = Quelques formes quadratiques et quelques équations indéterminées | journal = Nieuw Archief voor Wiskunde | volume = 11 | pages = 45–75| authorlink=Johannes van der Corput }}</ref> ] (1917),<ref>{{cite journal|last=Thue|first=Axel|author-link=Axel Thue|year=1917|title=Et bevis for at ligningen {{math|1=''A''<sup>3</sup> + ''B''<sup>3</sup> = ''C''<sup>3</sup>}} er unmulig i hele tal fra nul forskjellige tal ''A'', ''B'' og ''C''|journal=Archiv for Mathematik og Naturvidenskab|volume=34|issue=15|pages=3–7|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xIFEAQAAMAAJ&pg=RA13-PA1}} Reprinted in ''Selected Mathematical Papers'' (1977), Oslo: Universitetsforlaget, pp. 555–559</ref> and Duarte (1944).<ref>{{cite journal | author = Duarte FJ | year = 1944 | title = Sobre la ecuación ''x''<sup>3</sup> + ''y''<sup>3</sup> + ''z''<sup>3</sup> = 0 | journal = Boletín de la Academia de Ciencias Físicas, Matemáticas y Naturales (Caracas) | volume = 8 | pages = 971–979}}</ref>


Fermat's Last Theorem has also been proven for the exponents ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;6, 10, and 14. Proofs for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;6 have been published by Kausler,<ref name="Kausler_1802" /> Thue,<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1896 | title = Über die Auflösbarkeit einiger unbestimmter Gleichungen | journal = Det Kongel. Norske Videnskabers Selskabs Skrifter | volume = 7}} Reprinted in ''Selected Mathematical Papers'', pp. 19–30, Oslo:Universitetsforlaget (1977).</ref> Tafelmacher,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Tafelmacher WLA | year = 1897 | title = La ecuación ''x''<sup>3</sup> + ''y''<sup>3</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup>: Una demonstración nueva del teorema de fermat para el caso de las sestas potencias | journal = Ann. Univ. Chile, Santiago | volume = 97 | pages = 63–80}}</ref> Lind,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lind B | year = 1909 | title = Einige zahlentheoretische Sätze | journal = Arch. Math. Phys. | volume = 15 | pages = 368–369}}</ref> Kapferer,<ref name="Kapferer_1913" >{{cite journal | author = Kapferer H | year = 1913 | title = Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes für die Exponenten 6 und 10 | journal = Archiv Math. Phys. | volume = 21 | pages = 143–146}}</ref> Swift,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Swift E | year = 1914 | title = Solution to Problem 206 | journal = Amer. Math. Monthly | volume = 21 | pages = 238–239}}</ref> and Breusch.<ref name="Breusch_1960" >{{cite journal | doi = 10.2307/3029800 | author = Breusch R | authorlink = Robert Breusch | year = 1960 | title = A simple proof of Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;6, ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;10 | journal = Math. Mag. | volume = 33 | issue = 5 | pages = 279–281 | jstor = 3029800}}</ref> Similarly, Dirichlet<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1832 | title = Démonstration du théorème de Fermat pour le cas des 14<sup>e</sup> puissances | journal = J. Reine Angew. Math. | volume = 9 | pages = 390–393}} Reprinted in ''Werke'', vol. I, pp. 189–194, Berlin:G. Reimer (1889); reprinted New York:Chelsea (1969).</ref> and Terjanian<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1974 | title= L'équation ''x''<sup>14</sup> + ''y''<sup>14</sup> = ''z''<sup>14</sup> en nombres entiers | journal = Bull. Sci. Math. (sér. 2) | volume = 98 | pages = 91–95}}</ref> each proved the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;14, while Kapferer<ref name="Kapferer_1913" /> and Breusch<ref name="Breusch_1960" /> each proved the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;10. Strictly speaking, these proofs are unnecessary, since these cases follow from the proofs for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3, 5, and 7, respectively. Nevertheless, the reasoning of these even-exponent proofs differs from their odd-exponent counterparts. Dirichlet's proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;14 was published in 1832, before Lamé's 1839 proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;7.<ref>Edwards, pp. 73-74.</ref> The case {{nowrap|1=''p'' = 5}} was proved<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;5 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/10/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n5_28.html | access-date = 23 May 2009|date = 28 October 2005}}</ref> independently by Legendre and ] around 1825.<ref>Ribenboim, p. 49</ref>{{sfn|Mordell|1921|pp=8–9|ps=}}{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=44|ps=}}<ref name="Singh, p. 106">Singh, p. 106</ref> Alternative proofs were developed<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 55–57</ref> by ] (1875, posthumous),<ref>{{cite book | author = Gauss CF | year = 1875 | chapter = Neue Theorie der Zerlegung der Cuben | title = Zur Theorie der complexen Zahlen, Werke, vol. II | edition = 2nd | publisher = Königl. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen | pages = 387–391| authorlink=Carl Friedrich Gauss }} (Published posthumously)</ref> Lebesgue (1843),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1843 | title = Théorèmes nouveaux sur l'équation indéterminée ''x''<sup>5</sup> + ''y''<sup>5</sup> = ''az''<sup>5</sup> | journal = ] | volume = 8 | pages = 49–70| authorlink=Victor Lebesgue }}</ref> Lamé (1847),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1847 | title = Mémoire sur la résolution en nombres complexes de l'équation ''A''<sup>5</sup> + ''B''<sup>5</sup> + ''C''<sup>5</sup> = 0 | journal = ] | volume = 12 | pages = 137–171| authorlink=Gabriel Lamé }}</ref> Gambioli (1901),<ref name="Gambioli_1901"/><ref>{{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | date = 1903{{ndash}}1904 | title = Intorno all'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Il Pitagora | volume = 10 | pages = 11–13, 41–42}}</ref> Werebrusow (1905),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Werebrusow AS | year = 1905 | title = On the equation ''x''<sup>5</sup> + ''y''<sup>5</sup> = ''Az''<sup>5</sup> ''(in Russian)'' | journal = Moskov. Math. Samml. | volume = 25 | pages = 466–473}}</ref>{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} Rychlík (1910),<ref>{{cite journal | author = Rychlik K | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;5 ''(in Bohemian)'' | journal = Časopis Pěst. Mat. | volume = 39 | pages = 185–195, 305–317| authorlink=Karel Rychlík }}</ref>{{dubious|date=October 2017|reason=it is unlikely that this article was published in the Bohemian language}}{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} van der Corput (1915),<ref name="van_der_Corput_1915"/> and ] (1987).<ref>{{cite journal | author = Terjanian G | year = 1987 | title = Sur une question de V. A. Lebesgue | journal = Annales de l'Institut Fourier | volume = 37 | issue = 3 | pages = 19–37 | doi=10.5802/aif.1096| authorlink=Guy Terjanian | doi-access = free }}</ref>


The case {{nowrap|1=''p'' = 7}} was proved<ref>Ribenboim, pp. 57–63</ref>{{sfn|Mordell|1921|p=8|ps=}}{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=44|ps=}}<ref name="Singh, p. 106"/> by Lamé in 1839.<ref name="Lame_1839" >{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1839 | title = Mémoire sur le dernier théorème de Fermat | journal = ] | volume = 9 | pages = 45–46| authorlink=Gabriel Lamé }}<br/>{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1840 | title = Mémoire d'analyse indéterminée démontrant que l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> = ''z''<sup>7</sup> est impossible en nombres entiers | journal = ] | volume = 5 | pages = 195–211| authorlink=Gabriel Lamé }}</ref> His rather complicated proof was simplified in 1840 by Lebesgue,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1840 | title = Démonstration de l'impossibilité de résoudre l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 en nombres entiers | journal = ] | volume = 5 | pages = 276–279, 348–349| authorlink=Victor Lebesgue }}</ref> and still simpler proofs<ref>{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;7 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2006/01/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n7.html | access-date = 23 May 2009|date = 18 January 2006}}</ref> were published by ] in 1864, 1874 and 1876.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1864 | title = Intorno all'equazioni ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = ] | volume = 6 | pages = 287–288 | doi=10.1007/bf03198884| s2cid = 124916552 | authorlink=Angelo Genocchi | url = https://zenodo.org/record/1428472 }}<br/>{{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1874 | title = Sur l'impossibilité de quelques égalités doubles | journal = ] | volume = 78 | pages = 433–436| authorlink=Angelo Genocchi }}<br/>{{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1876 | title = Généralisation du théorème de Lamé sur l'impossibilité de l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = ] | volume = 82 | pages = 910–913| authorlink=Angelo Genocchi }}</ref> Alternative proofs were developed by Théophile Pépin (1876)<ref>{{cite journal | author = Pepin T | year = 1876 | title = Impossibilité de l'équation ''x''<sup>7</sup> + ''y''<sup>7</sup> + ''z''<sup>7</sup> = 0 | journal = ] | volume = 82 | pages = 676–679, 743–747| authorlink=Théophile Pépin }}</ref> and Edmond Maillet (1897).<ref>{{cite journal | author = Maillet E | year = 1897 | title = Sur l'équation indéterminée ''ax''<sup>''λ''<sup>''t''</sup></sup> + ''by''<sup>''λ''<sup>''t''</sup></sup> = ''cz''<sup>''λ''<sup>''t''</sup></sup> | journal = Association française pour l'avancement des sciences, St. Etienne, Compte Rendu de la 26me Session, deuxième partie | volume = 26 | pages = 156–168 |url=http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k201187c/f159.image| authorlink=Edmond Maillet }}</ref>
Many proofs for specific exponents use Fermat's technique of ], which Fermat used to prove the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;4, but many do not. However, the details and auxiliary arguments are often ''ad hoc'' and tied to the individual exponent under consideration.<ref name="Edwards, p. 74">Edwards, p. 74.</ref> Since they became ever more complicated as ''p'' increased, it seemed unlikely that the general case of Fermat's Last Theorem could be proven by building upon the proofs for individual exponents.<ref name="Edwards, p. 74"/> Although some general results on Fermat's Last Theorem were published in the early 19th century by ] and ],<ref>Dickson, p. 733.</ref><ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | pages = 51–54}}</ref> the first significant work on the general theorem was done by ].<ref>Singh, pp. 97–109.</ref>


Fermat's Last Theorem was also proved for the exponents ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;6, 10, and 14. Proofs for {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 6}} were published by Kausler,<ref name="Kausler_1802"/> Thue,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Thue A | year = 1896 | title = Über die Auflösbarkeit einiger unbestimmter Gleichungen | journal = Det Kongelige Norske Videnskabers Selskabs Skrifter | volume = 7| authorlink=Axel Thue }} Reprinted in ''Selected Mathematical Papers'', pp. 19–30, Oslo: Universitetsforlaget (1977).</ref> Tafelmacher,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Tafelmacher WLA | year = 1897 | title = La ecuación ''x''<sup>3</sup> + ''y''<sup>3</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup>: Una demonstración nueva del teorema de fermat para el caso de las sestas potencias | journal = ] | volume = 97 | pages = 63–80}}</ref> Lind,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lind B | year = 1909 | title = Einige zahlentheoretische Sätze | journal = Archiv der Mathematik und Physik | volume = 15 | pages = 368–369}}</ref> Kapferer,<ref name="Kapferer_1913" >{{cite journal | author = Kapferer H | year = 1913 | title = Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes für die Exponenten 6 und 10 | journal = Archiv der Mathematik und Physik | volume = 21 | pages = 143–146}}</ref> Swift,<ref>{{cite journal | author = Swift E | year = 1914 | title = Solution to Problem 206 | journal = ] | volume = 21 | issue = 7 | pages = 238–239 | doi = 10.2307/2972379 | jstor = 2972379 }}</ref> and Breusch.<ref name="Breusch_1960" >{{cite journal | doi = 10.2307/3029800 | author = Breusch R | authorlink=Robert Breusch | year = 1960 | title = A simple proof of Fermat's last theorem for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;6, ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;10 | journal = ] | volume = 33 | issue = 5 | pages = 279–281 | jstor = 3029800}}</ref> Similarly, Dirichlet<ref>{{cite journal | author = Dirichlet PGL | year = 1832 | title = Démonstration du théorème de Fermat pour le cas des 14<sup>e</sup> puissances | journal = ] | volume = 9 | pages = 390–393| authorlink=Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet }} Reprinted in ''Werke'', vol. I, pp. 189–194, Berlin: G. Reimer (1889); reprinted New York:Chelsea (1969).</ref> and Terjanian<ref>{{cite journal | author = Terjanian G | year = 1974 | title= L'équation ''x''<sup>14</sup> + ''y''<sup>14</sup> = ''z''<sup>14</sup> en nombres entiers | journal = Bulletin des Sciences Mathématiques |series=Série 2 | volume = 98 | pages = 91–95| authorlink=Guy Terjanian }}</ref> each proved the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;14, while Kapferer<ref name="Kapferer_1913"/> and Breusch<ref name="Breusch_1960"/> each proved the case ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;10. Strictly speaking, these proofs are unnecessary, since these cases follow from the proofs for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;3, 5, and 7, respectively. Nevertheless, the reasoning of these even-exponent proofs differs from their odd-exponent counterparts. Dirichlet's proof for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;14 was published in 1832, before Lamé's 1839 proof for {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 7}}.{{sfn|Edwards|1996|pp=73–74|ps=}}
==Sophie Germain==
{{Main|Sophie Germain}}


All proofs for specific exponents used Fermat's technique of ],{{citation needed|reason=this assertion requires a thorough review of all the existing literature, or a reliable source making the assertion|date=January 2015}} either in its original form, or in the form of descent on elliptic curves or abelian varieties. The details and auxiliary arguments, however, were often ''ad hoc'' and tied to the individual exponent under consideration.{{sfn|Edwards|1996|p=74|ps=}} Since they became ever more complicated as ''p'' increased, it seemed unlikely that the general case of Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved by building upon the proofs for individual exponents.{{sfn|Edwards|1996|p=74|ps=}} Although some general results on Fermat's Last Theorem were published in the early 19th century by ] and ],{{sfn|Dickson|1919|p=733|ps=}}<ref>{{cite book | author = Ribenboim P | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | pages = 51–54| authorlink=Paulo Ribenboim }}</ref> the first significant work on the general theorem was done by ].<ref>Singh, pp. 97–109</ref>
In the early 19th century, ] developed several novel approaches to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all exponents.<ref name="Laubenbacher_2007" >{{cite web | author = Laubenbacher R, Pengelley D | year = 2007 | title = Voici ce que j'ai trouvé: Sophie Germain's grand plan to prove Fermat's Last Theorem | url = http://www.math.nmsu.edu/%7Edavidp/germain.pdf | accessdate = 19 May 2009}}</ref> First, she defined a set of auxiliary primes θ constructed from the prime exponent ''p'' by the equation θ&nbsp;=&nbsp;2''hp''+1, where ''h'' is any integer not divisible by three. She showed that if no integers raised to the ''p''<sup>th</sup> power were adjacent modulo θ (the ''non-consecutivity condition''), then θ must divide the product ''xyz''. Her goal was to use ] to prove that, for any given ''p'', infinitely many auxiliary primes θ satisfied the non-consecutivity condition and thus divided ''xyz''; since the product ''xyz'' can have at most a finite number of prime factors, such a proof would have established Fermat's Last Theorem. Although she developed many techniques for establishing the non-consecutivity condition, she did not succeed in her strategic goal. She also worked to set lower limits on the size of solutions to Fermat's equation for a given exponent ''p'', a modified version of which was published by ]. As a byproduct of this latter work, she proved ], which verified the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem (namely, the case in which ''p'' does not divide ''xyz'') for every odd prime exponent less than 100.<ref name="Laubenbacher_2007" /><ref>Aczel, p. 57.</ref> Germain tried unsuccessfully to prove the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem for all even exponents, specifically for ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;2''p'', which was proven by ] in 1977.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Terjanian|first=G.|year=1977|title=Sur l'équation ''x''<sup>2''p''</sup> + ''y''<sup>2''p''</sup> = ''z''<sup>2''p''</sup> |journal=Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des sciences. Série a et B|volume=285|pages=973–975}}</ref> In 1985, ], ] and Étienne Fouvry proved that the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem holds for infinitely many odd primes ''p''.<ref>{{cite journal |author = Adleman LM, Heath-Brown DR | year = 1985 | month = June |title = The first case of Fermat's last theorem | journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 79 | issue = 2 |pages = 409–416 | publisher = Springer | location = Berlin | doi=10.1007/BF01388981}}</ref>


=== Early modern breakthroughs ===
==Ernst Kummer and the theory of ideals==
==== Sophie Germain ====
In the early 19th century, ] developed several novel approaches to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all exponents.<ref name="Laubenbacher_2007" >{{cite web | vauthors = Laubenbacher R, Pengelley D | year = 2007 | title = Voici ce que j'ai trouvé: Sophie Germain's grand plan to prove Fermat's Last Theorem | url = http://www.math.nmsu.edu/%7Edavidp/germain.pdf | access-date = 19 May 2009 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20130405163013/http://www.math.nmsu.edu/%7Edavidp/germain.pdf | archive-date = 5 April 2013 | url-status = dead }}</ref> First, she defined a set of auxiliary primes ''θ'' constructed from the prime exponent ''p'' by the equation {{nowrap|1=''θ'' = 2''hp'' + 1}}, where ''h'' is any integer not divisible by three. She showed that, if no integers raised to the ''p''th power were adjacent modulo ''θ'' (the ''non-consecutivity condition''), then ''θ'' must divide the product ''xyz''. Her goal was to use ] to prove that, for any given ''p'', infinitely many auxiliary primes ''θ'' satisfied the non-consecutivity condition and thus divided ''xyz''; since the product ''xyz'' can have at most a finite number of prime factors, such a proof would have established Fermat's Last Theorem. Although she developed many techniques for establishing the non-consecutivity condition, she did not succeed in her strategic goal. She also worked to set lower limits on the size of solutions to Fermat's equation for a given exponent ''p'', a modified version of which was published by ]. As a byproduct of this latter work, she proved ], which verified the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem (namely, the case in which ''p'' does not divide ''xyz'') for every odd prime exponent less than 270,<ref name="Laubenbacher_2007"/>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=57|ps=}} and for all primes ''p'' such that at least one of {{nowrap|2''p'' + 1}}, {{nowrap|4''p'' + 1}}, {{nowrap|8''p'' + 1}}, {{nowrap|10''p'' + 1}}, {{nowrap|14''p'' + 1}} and {{nowrap|16''p'' + 1}} is prime (specially, the primes ''p'' such that {{nowrap|2''p'' + 1}} is prime are called ]s). Germain tried unsuccessfully to prove the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem for all even exponents, specifically for {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 2''p''}}, which was proved by ] in 1977.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Terjanian|first=G.|year=1977|title=Sur l'équation ''x''<sup>2''p''</sup> + ''y''<sup>2''p''</sup> = ''z''<sup>2''p''</sup> |journal=Comptes Rendus de l'Académie des Sciences, Série A-B|volume=285|pages=973–975}}</ref> In 1985, ], ] and ] proved that the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem holds for infinitely many odd primes ''p''.<ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Adleman LM, Heath-Brown DR |date=June 1985 |title = The first case of Fermat's last theorem | journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 79 | issue = 2 |pages = 409–416 | publisher = Springer | location = Berlin | doi=10.1007/BF01388981 | bibcode=1985InMat..79..409A|s2cid=122537472 }}</ref>


==== Ernst Kummer and the theory of ideals ====
In 1847, ] outlined a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem based on factoring the equation ''x''<sup>''p''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''p''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''p''</sup> in complex numbers, specifically the ] based on the ]. His proof failed, however, because it assumed incorrectly that such complex numbers can be ] into primes, similar to integers. This gap was pointed out immediately by ], who later read a paper that demonstrated this failure of unique factorisation, written by ].
In 1847, ] outlined a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem based on factoring the equation {{math|1={{itco|''x''}}{{sup|''p''}} + {{itco|''y''}}{{sup|''p''}} = {{itco|''z''}}{{sup|''p''}}}} in ]s, specifically the ] based on the ]. His proof failed, however, because it assumed incorrectly that such complex numbers can be ] into primes, similar to integers. This gap was pointed out immediately by ], who later read a paper that demonstrated this failure of unique factorisation, written by ].


Kummer set himself the task of determining whether the ] could be generalized to include new prime numbers such that unique factorisation was restored. He succeeded in that task by developing the ]s. Using the general approach outlined by Lamé, Kummer proved both cases of Fermat's Last Theorem for all ]. However, he could not prove the theorem for the exceptional primes (]) which conjecturally occur approximately 39% of the time; the only irregular primes below 100 are 37, 59 and 67. Kummer set himself the task of determining whether the ] could be generalized to include new prime numbers such that unique factorisation was restored. He succeeded in that task by developing the ]s.


(It is often stated that Kummer was led to his "ideal complex numbers" by his interest in Fermat's Last Theorem; there is even a story often told that Kummer, like ], believed he had proven Fermat's Last Theorem until ] told him his argument relied on unique factorization; but the story was first told by ] in 1910 and the evidence indicates it likely derives from a confusion by one of Hensel's sources. ] said the belief that Kummer was mainly interested in Fermat's Last Theorem "is surely mistaken".{{sfn|Edwards|1996|p=79|ps=}} See ].)
==Mordell conjecture==


Using the general approach outlined by Lamé, Kummer proved both cases of Fermat's Last Theorem for all ]. However, he could not prove the theorem for the exceptional primes (irregular primes) that ]; the only irregular primes below 270 are 37, 59, 67, 101, 103, 131, 149, 157, 233, 257 and 263.
In the 1920s, ] posed a conjecture that implied that Fermat's equation has at most a finite number of nontrivial primitive integer solutions if the exponent ''n'' is greater than two.<ref>Aczel, pp. 84–88; Singh, pp. 232–234.</ref> This conjecture was proven in 1983 by ],<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1983 | title = Endlichkeitssätze für abelsche Varietäten über Zahlkörpern |journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 73 | issue = 3 |pages = 349–366 |doi=10.1007/BF01388432}}</ref> and is now known as ].


==== Mordell conjecture ====
==Computational studies==
In the 1920s, ] posed a conjecture that implied that Fermat's equation has at most a finite number of nontrivial primitive integer solutions, if the exponent ''n'' is greater than two.{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=84–88|ps=}}<ref>Singh, pp. 232–234</ref> This conjecture was proved in 1983 by ],<ref>{{cite journal | author = Faltings G | year = 1983 | title = Endlichkeitssätze für abelsche Varietäten über Zahlkörpern |journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 73 | issue = 3 |pages = 349–366 |doi=10.1007/BF01388432|bibcode = 1983InMat..73..349F | s2cid = 121049418 | authorlink=Gerd Faltings }}</ref> and is now known as ].


==== Computational studies ====
In the latter half of the 20th century, computational methods were used to extend Kummer's approach to the irregular primes. In 1954, ] used a ] to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all primes up to 2521.<ref>{{cite book | author = ] | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | page = 202}}</ref> By 1978, ] had extended this to all primes less than 125,000.<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1978 | title = The irregular primes to 125000 | journal = Math. Comp. | volume = 32 | pages = 583–591 | doi = 10.2307/2006167 | issue = 142 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | jstor = 2006167}} </ref> By 1993, Fermat's Last Theorem had been proven for all primes less than four million.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Buhler J, Crandell R, Ernvall R, Metsänkylä T | year = 1993 | title = Irregular primes and cyclotomic invariants to four million | journal = Math. Comp. | volume = 61 | pages = 151–153 | doi = 10.2307/2152942 | issue = 203 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | jstor = 2152942}}</ref>
In the latter half of the 20th century, computational methods were used to extend Kummer's approach to the irregular primes. In 1954, ] used a ] to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all primes up to 2521.<ref>{{cite book | author = Ribenboim P | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | page = 202| authorlink=Paulo Ribenboim }}</ref> By 1978, ] had extended this to all primes less than 125,000.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Wagstaff SS Jr. | year = 1978 | title = The irregular primes to 125000 | journal = Mathematics of Computation | volume = 32 | pages = 583–591 | doi = 10.2307/2006167 | issue = 142 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | jstor = 2006167| authorlink=Samuel S. Wagstaff, Jr }} {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20121024112422/http://www.ams.org/journals/mcom/1978-32-142/S0025-5718-1978-0491465-4/S0025-5718-1978-0491465-4.pdf |date=24 October 2012 }}</ref> By 1993, Fermat's Last Theorem had been proved for all primes less than four million.<ref name=":0">{{cite journal|vauthors=Buhler J, Crandell R, Ernvall R, Metsänkylä T|year=1993|title=Irregular primes and cyclotomic invariants to four million|url=https://www.ams.org/journals/mcom/1993-61-203/S0025-5718-1993-1197511-5/home.html|journal=Mathematics of Computation|publisher=American Mathematical Society|volume=61|issue=203|pages=151–153|bibcode=1993MaCom..61..151B|doi=10.2307/2152942|jstor=2152942|doi-access=free}}</ref>


However, despite these efforts and their results, no proof existed of Fermat's Last Theorem. Proofs of individual exponents by their nature could never prove the ''general'' case: even if all exponents were verified up to an extremely large number X, a higher exponent beyond X might still exist for which the claim was not true. (This had been the case with some other past conjectures, such as with ], and it could not be ruled out in this conjecture.)
==Connection with elliptic curves==


=== Connection with elliptic curves ===
The ultimately successful strategy for proving Fermat's Last Theorem was by proving the ]. The strategy was first described by ] in 1984.<ref>Singh, pp. 194–198; Aczel, pp. 109–114.</ref> Frey noted that if Fermat's equation had a solution (''a'', ''b'', ''c'') for exponent ''p''&nbsp;>&nbsp;2, the corresponding ]<ref group=note>This elliptic curve was first suggested in the 1960s by Yves Hellegouarch, but he did not call attention to its non-modularity. For more details, see {{Cite book | last=Hellegouarch | first=Yves | title=Invitation to the Mathematics of Fermat-Wiles | publisher=Academic Press | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-12-339251-0 }}</ref>
The strategy that ultimately led to a successful proof of Fermat's Last Theorem arose from the "astounding"<ref name="Singh">Fermat's Last Theorem, Simon Singh, 1997, {{isbn|1-85702-521-0}}</ref>{{rp|211}} ], proposed around 1955—which many mathematicians believed would be near to impossible to prove,<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|223}} and was linked in the 1980s by ], ] and ] to Fermat's equation. By accomplishing a partial proof of this conjecture in 1994, ] ultimately succeeded in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, as well as leading the way to a full proof by others of what is now known as the ].


==== Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture ====
:''y''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''&nbsp;(''x''&nbsp;−&nbsp;''a''<sup>''p''</sup>)(''x''&nbsp;+&nbsp;''b''<sup>''p''</sup>)
{{main|Modularity theorem}}


would have such unusual properties that the curve would likely violate the modularity theorem.<ref>{{cite journal | author = ] | year = 1986 |title = Links between stable elliptic curves and certain diophantine equations | journal = Ann. Univ. Sarav. Ser. Math. | volume = 1 | pages = 1–40}}</ref> This theorem, first conjectured in the mid-1950s and gradually refined through the 1960s, states that every elliptic curve is ], meaning that it can be associated with a unique ]. Around 1955, Japanese mathematicians ] and ] observed a possible link between two apparently completely distinct branches of mathematics, ]s and ]s. The resulting ] (at the time known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) states that every elliptic curve is ], meaning that it can be associated with a unique ].


The link was initially dismissed as unlikely or highly speculative, but was taken more seriously when number theorist ] found evidence supporting it, though not proving it; as a result the conjecture was often known as the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|211–215}}
Following this strategy, the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem required two steps. First, it was necessary to show that Frey's intuition was correct: that the above elliptic curve, if it exists, is always non-modular. Frey did not succeed in proving this rigorously; the missing piece was identified by ]. This missing piece, the so-called "]", was proven by ] in 1986. Second, it was necessary to prove a special case of the modularity theorem. This special case (for ]s) was proven by Andrew Wiles in 1995.


Even after gaining serious attention, the conjecture was seen by contemporary mathematicians as extraordinarily difficult or perhaps inaccessible to proof.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|203–205, 223, 226}} For example, Wiles's doctoral supervisor ] states that it seemed "impossible to actually prove",<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|226}} and Ken Ribet considered himself "one of the vast majority of people who believed was completely inaccessible", adding that "Andrew Wiles was probably one of the few people on earth who had the audacity to dream that you can actually go and prove ."<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|223}}
Thus, the epsilon conjecture showed that any solution to Fermat's equation could be used to generate a non-modular semistable elliptic curve, whereas Wiles' proof showed that all such elliptic curves must be modular. This contradiction implies that there can be no solutions to Fermat's equation, thus proving Fermat's Last Theorem.


==== Ribet's theorem for Frey curves ====
==Wiles's general proof==
{{main|Frey curve|Ribet's theorem}}
]]]
{{Main|Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem}}


In 1984, ] noted a link between Fermat's equation and the modularity theorem, then still a conjecture. If Fermat's equation had any solution {{nowrap|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'')}} for exponent {{nowrap|''p'' > 2}}, then it could be shown that the semi-stable ] (now known as a ]<ref group=note>This elliptic curve was first suggested in the 1960s by {{Interlanguage link|Yves Hellegouarch|de}}, but he did not call attention to its non-modularity. For more details, see {{Cite book | last=Hellegouarch | first=Yves | title=Invitation to the Mathematics of Fermat-Wiles | publisher=Academic Press | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-12-339251-0 }}</ref>)
Ribet's proof of the ] in 1986 accomplished the first half of Frey's strategy for proving Fermat's Last Theorem. Upon hearing of Ribet's proof, Andrew Wiles decided to commit himself to accomplishing the second half: proving a special case of the ] (then known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) for semistable elliptic curves.<ref>Singh, p. 205; Aczel, pp. 117–118.</ref> Wiles worked on that task for six years in almost complete secrecy. He based his initial approach on his area of expertise, ], but by the summer of 1991, this approach seemed inadequate to the task.<ref>Singh, pp. 237–238; Aczel, pp. 121–122.</ref> In response, he exploited an ] recently developed by ] and ]. Since Wiles was unfamiliar with such methods, he asked his Princeton colleague, ], to check his reasoning over the spring semester of 1993.<ref>Singh, pp. 239–243; Aczel, pp. 122–125.</ref>
: ''y''<sup>2</sup> = {{nowrap|''x''(''x'' − ''a''<sup>''p''</sup>)(''x'' + ''b''<sup>''p''</sup>)}}
would have such unusual properties that it was unlikely to be modular.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Frey G | year = 1986 |title = Links between stable elliptic curves and certain diophantine equations | journal = Annales Universitatis Saraviensis. Series Mathematicae. | volume = 1 | pages = 1–40| authorlink=Gerhard Frey }}</ref> This would conflict with the modularity theorem, which asserted that all elliptic curves are modular. As such, Frey observed that a proof of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture might also simultaneously prove Fermat's Last Theorem.<ref>Singh, pp. 194–198</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996||pp=109–114|ps=}} By ], a ''disproof'' or refutation of Fermat's Last Theorem would disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture.


In plain English, Frey had shown that, if this intuition about his equation was correct, then any set of four numbers (''a'', ''b'', ''c'', ''n'') capable of disproving Fermat's Last Theorem, could also be used to disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture. Therefore, if the latter were true, the former could not be disproven, and would also have to be true.
By mid-1993, Wiles was sufficiently confident of his results that he presented them in three lectures delivered on June 21–23, 1993 at the ].<ref>Singh, pp. 244–253; Aczel, pp. 1–4, 126–128.</ref> Specifically, Wiles presented his proof of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture for semistable elliptic curves; together with Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture, this implied Fermat's Last Theorem. However, it soon became apparent that Wiles's initial proof was incorrect. A critical portion of the proof contained an error in a bound on the order of a particular ]. The error was caught by several mathematicians refereeing Wiles's manuscript including Katz,<ref>Aczel, pp. 128–130.</ref> who alerted Wiles on 23 August 1993.<ref>Singh, p. 257.</ref>


Following this strategy, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem required two steps. First, it was necessary to prove the modularity theorem, or at least to prove it for the types of elliptical curves that included Frey's equation (known as ]s). This was widely believed inaccessible to proof by contemporary mathematicians.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|203–205, 223, 226}} Second, it was necessary to show that Frey's intuition was correct: that if an elliptic curve were constructed in this way, using a set of numbers that were a solution of Fermat's equation, the resulting elliptic curve could not be modular. Frey showed that this was ''plausible'' but did not go as far as giving a full proof. The missing piece (the so-called "]", now known as ]) was identified by ] who also gave an almost-complete proof<!-- see introduction of Ribet's paper --> and the link suggested by Frey was finally proved in 1986 by ].<ref name="ribet90">{{cite journal|last=Ribet|first=Ken|authorlink=Ken Ribet|title=On modular representations of Gal({{overline|'''Q'''}}/'''Q''') arising from modular forms|journal=Inventiones Mathematicae|volume=100|year=1990|issue=2|pages=431–476|doi=10.1007/BF01231195|mr=1047143|url=http://math.berkeley.edu/~ribet/Articles/invent_100.pdf|bibcode=1990InMat.100..431R|hdl=10338.dmlcz/147454|s2cid=120614740}}</ref>
Wiles and his former student ] spent almost a year trying to repair the proof, without success.<ref>Singh, pp. 269–274.</ref> On 19 September 1994, Wiles had a flash of insight that the proof could be saved by returning to his original Horizontal Iwasawa theory approach, which he had abandoned in favour of the Kolyvagin–Flach approach.<ref>Singh, pp. 275–277; Aczel, pp. 132–134.</ref> On 24 October 1994, Wiles submitted two manuscripts, "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem"<ref>{{cite journal|last=Wiles|first=Andrew|authorlink=Andrew Wiles|year=1995|title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem|url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf|journal=Annals of Mathematics|volume=141|issue=3|pages=443–551|oclc=37032255|format=PDF|doi=10.2307/2118559|jstor=2118559|publisher=Annals of Mathematics}}</ref> and "Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras",<ref>{{cite journal | author = ], ] | year = 1995 | journal = Annals of Mathematics | title = Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras | volume = 141 | issue = 3| pages = 553–572 | oclc = 37032255 | url = http://www.math.harvard.edu/~rtaylor/hecke.ps | doi = 10.2307/2118560 | jstor = 2118560 | publisher = Annals of Mathematics}}</ref> the second of which was co-authored with Taylor. The two papers were vetted and published as the entirety of the May 1995 issue of the '']''. These papers established the modularity theorem for semistable elliptic curves, the last step in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, 358 years after it was conjectured.


Following Frey, Serre and Ribet's work, this was where matters stood:
==Exponents other than positive integers==
===Rational exponents===


* Fermat's Last Theorem needed to be proven for all exponents ''n'' that were prime numbers.
All solutions of the Diophantine equation <math>a^{n/m} + b^{n/m} = c^{n/m}</math> when ''n''=1 were computed by Lenstra in 1992.<ref>] (1992). ''On the inverse Fermat equation.'' Discrete Mathematics, '''106-107''', pp. 329-331.</ref> In the case in which the ''m''<sup>th</sup> roots are required to be real and positive, all solutions are given by<ref>Newton, M., "A radical diophantine equation", '']'' 13 (1981), 495-498.</ref>
* The modularity theorem—if proved for semi-stable elliptic curves—would mean that all semistable elliptic curves ''must'' be modular.
* Ribet's theorem showed that any solution to Fermat's equation for a prime number could be used to create a semistable elliptic curve that ''could not'' be modular;
* The only way that both of these statements could be true, was if ''no'' solutions existed to Fermat's equation (because then no such curve could be created), which was what Fermat's Last Theorem said. As Ribet's Theorem was already proved, this meant that a proof of the modularity theorem would automatically prove Fermat's Last theorem was true as well.


=== Wiles's general proof ===
:<math>a=rs^m</math>
{{Main|Andrew Wiles|Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem}}
:<math>b=rt^m</math>
]]]
:<math>c=r(s+t)^m</math>


Ribet's proof of the ] in 1986 accomplished the first of the two goals proposed by Frey. Upon hearing of Ribet's success, ], an English mathematician with a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem, and who had worked on elliptic curves, decided to commit himself to accomplishing the second half: proving a special case of the ] (then known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) for semistable elliptic curves.<ref>Singh, p. 205</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=117–118|ps=}}
for positive integers ''r, s, t'' with ''s'' and ''t'' coprime.


Wiles worked on that task for six years in near-total secrecy, covering up his efforts by releasing prior work in small segments as separate papers and confiding only in his wife.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|229–230}} His initial study suggested ] by ],<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|230–232, 249–252}} and he based his initial work and first significant breakthrough on ]<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|251–253, 259}} before switching to an attempt to extend ] for the inductive argument around 1990–91 when it seemed that there was no existing approach adequate to the problem.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|258–259}} However, by mid-1991, Iwasawa theory also seemed to not be reaching the central issues in the problem.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|259–260}}<ref>Singh, pp. 237–238</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=121–122|ps=}} In response, he approached colleagues to seek out any hints of cutting-edge research and new techniques, and discovered an ] recently developed by ] and ] that seemed "tailor made" for the inductive part of his proof.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|260–261}} Wiles studied and extended this approach, which worked. Since his work relied extensively on this approach, which was new to mathematics and to Wiles, in January 1993 he asked his Princeton colleague, ], to help him check his reasoning for subtle errors. Their conclusion at the time was that the techniques Wiles used seemed to work correctly.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|261–265}}<ref>Singh, pp. 239–243</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=122–125|ps=}}
In 2004, for ''n''>2, Bennett, Glass, and Szekely proved that if gcd(''n'',''m'')=1, then there are integer solutions if and only if 6 divides ''m'', and <math>a^{1/m}</math>, <math>b^{1/m},</math> and <math>c^{1/m}</math> are different complex 6th roots of the same real number.<ref>Bennett, Curt D., Glass, Andrew M.W., and ] (2004). ''Fermat’s last theorem for rational exponents.'' The American Mathematical Monthly, '''111''', no. 4, pp. 322-329.</ref>


By mid-May 1993, Wiles was ready to tell his wife he thought he had solved the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem,<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|265}} and by June he felt sufficiently confident to present his results in three lectures delivered on 21–23 June 1993 at the ].<ref>Singh, pp. 244–253</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=1–4,126–128|ps=}} Specifically, Wiles presented his proof of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture for semistable elliptic curves; together with Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture, this implied Fermat's Last Theorem. However, it became apparent during ] that a critical point in the proof was incorrect. It contained an error in a bound on the order of a particular ]. The error was caught by several mathematicians refereeing Wiles's manuscript including Katz (in his role as reviewer),{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=128–130|ps=}} who alerted Wiles on 23 August 1993.<ref>Singh, p. 257</ref>
===Negative exponents===
====''n'' =&nbsp;–1====


The error would not have rendered his work worthless: each part of Wiles's work was highly significant and innovative by itself, as were the many developments and techniques he had created in the course of his work, and only one part was affected.<ref name="Singh"/>{{rp|289, 296–297}} However, without this part proved, there was no actual proof of Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles spent almost a year trying to repair his proof, initially by himself and then in collaboration with his former student ], without success.<ref name="sept1994">Singh, pp. 269–277</ref><ref> 28 June 1994</ref><ref> 3 July 1994</ref> By the end of 1993, rumours had spread that under scrutiny, Wiles's proof had failed, but how seriously was not known. Mathematicians were beginning to pressure Wiles to disclose his work whether it was complete or not, so that the wider community could explore and use whatever he had managed to accomplish. But instead of being fixed, the problem, which had originally seemed minor, now seemed very significant, far more serious, and less easy to resolve.<ref>Singh, pp. 175–185</ref>
All primitive (pairwise coprime) integer solutions to <math>a^{-1}+b^{-1}=c^{-1}</math> can be written as<ref>Dickson, pp. 688-691</ref>


Wiles states that on the morning of 19 September 1994, he was on the verge of giving up and was almost resigned to accepting that he had failed, and to publishing his work so that others could build on it and fix the error. He adds that he was having a final look to try and understand the fundamental reasons why his approach could not be made to work, when he had a sudden insight: that the specific reason why the Kolyvagin–Flach approach would not work directly {{em|also}} meant that his original attempts using ] could be made to work, if he strengthened it using his experience gained from the Kolyvagin–Flach approach. Fixing one approach with tools from the other approach would resolve the issue for all the cases that were not already proven by his refereed paper.<ref name="sept1994"/>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|pp=132–134|ps=}} He described later that Iwasawa theory and the Kolyvagin–Flach approach were each inadequate on their own, but together they could be made powerful enough to overcome this final hurdle.<ref name="sept1994"/>
:<math>a=mn+m^2,</math>
:<math>b=mn+n^2,</math>
:<math>c=mn</math>


{{blockquote|I was sitting at my desk examining the Kolyvagin–Flach method. It wasn't that I believed I could make it work, but I thought that at least I could explain why it didn't work. Suddenly I had this incredible revelation. I realised that, the Kolyvagin–Flach method wasn't working, but it was all I needed to make my original Iwasawa theory work from three years earlier. So out of the ashes of Kolyvagin–Flach seemed to rise the true answer to the problem. It was so indescribably beautiful; it was so simple and so elegant. I couldn't understand how I'd missed it and I just stared at it in disbelief for twenty minutes. Then during the day I walked around the department, and I'd keep coming back to my desk looking to see if it was still there. It was still there. I couldn't contain myself, I was so excited. It was the most important moment of my working life. Nothing I ever do again will mean as much.|Andrew Wiles, as quoted by Simon Singh<ref>Singh p. 186–187 (text condensed)</ref>}}
for positive, coprime integers ''m, n''.


On 24 October 1994, Wiles submitted two manuscripts, "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem"<ref>{{cite journal|last=Wiles|first=Andrew|authorlink=Andrew Wiles|year=1995|title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem|url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf|url-status=dead|journal=]|volume=141|issue=3|pages=443–551|doi=10.2307/2118559|jstor=2118559|oclc=37032255|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20030628220453/http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf|archive-date=28 June 2003}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|url=http://scienzamedia.uniroma2.it/~eal/Wiles-Fermat.pdf|title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem}}</ref> and "Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras",<ref>{{cite journal|author=], ] |year=1995 |journal=] |title=Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras |volume=141 |issue=3 |pages=553–572 |oclc=37032255 |url=http://www.math.harvard.edu/~rtaylor/hecke.ps |doi=10.2307/2118560 |jstor=2118560 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20011127181043/http://www.math.harvard.edu/~rtaylor/hecke.ps |archive-date=27 November 2001 }}</ref> the second of which was co-authored with Taylor and proved that certain conditions were met that were needed to justify the corrected step in the main paper. The two papers were vetted and published as the entirety of the May 1995 issue of the '']''. The proof's method of identification of a deformation ring with a Hecke algebra (now referred to as an ''R=T theorem'') to prove modularity lifting theorems has been an influential development in ].
====''n'' =&nbsp;–2====


These papers established the modularity theorem for semistable elliptic curves, the last step in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, 358 years after it was conjectured.
The case ''n'' =&nbsp;–2 also has an infinitude of solutions, and these have a geometric interpretation in terms of ].<ref>Voles, Roger, "Integer solutions of <math>a^{-2}+b^{-2}=d^{-2}</math>," '']'' 83, July 1999, 269–271.</ref><ref>Richinick, Jennifer, "The upside-down Pythagorean Theorem," ''Mathematical Gazette'' 92, July 2008, 313–317.</ref> All primitive solutions to <math>a^{-2}+b^{-2}=d^{-2}</math> are given by


=== Subsequent developments ===
:<math>a=(v^2-u^2)(v^2+u^2), \,</math>
The full Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture was finally proved by Diamond (1996),<ref name="Diamond-1996"/> Conrad et al. (1999),<ref name="Conrad-etal-1999"/> and Breuil et al. (2001)<ref name="Breuil-etal-2001"/> who, building on Wiles's work, incrementally chipped away at the remaining cases until the full result was proved. The now fully proved conjecture became known as the ].
:<math>b=2uv(v^2+u^2), \,</math>
:<math>d=2uv(v^2-u^2), \,</math>


Several other theorems in number theory similar to Fermat's Last Theorem also follow from the same reasoning, using the modularity theorem. For example: no cube can be written as a sum of two coprime ''n''th powers, {{nowrap|''n'' ≥ 3}}. (The case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = 3}} was already known by ].)
for coprime integers ''u'', ''v'' with ''v''&nbsp;>&nbsp;''u''. The geometric interpretation is that ''a'' and ''b'' are the integer legs of a right triangle and ''d'' is the integer altitude to the hypotenuse. Then the hypotenuse itself is the integer


== Relationship to other problems and generalizations ==
:<math>c=(v^2+u^2)^2, \,</math>
Fermat's Last Theorem considers solutions to the Fermat equation: {{math|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} with positive integers {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}}, and {{math|''c''}} and an integer {{math|''n''}} greater than 2. There are several generalizations of the Fermat equation to more general equations that allow the exponent {{math|''n''}} to be a negative integer or rational, or to consider three different exponents.


=== Generalized Fermat equation ===
so (''a, b, c'') is a ].
The generalized Fermat equation generalizes the statement of Fermat's last theorem by considering positive integer solutions ''a'', ''b'', ''c'', ''m'', ''n'', ''k'' satisfying<ref name="princeton-companion">{{cite book |title=The Princeton Companion to Mathematics |url=https://archive.org/details/princetoncompanio00gowe |last1=Barrow-Green |first1=June |last2=Leader |first2=Imre |last3=Gowers |first3=Timothy |pages=361–362 |year=2008 |publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=9781400830398 }}</ref>
{{NumBlk|:|<math>a^m + b^n = c^k.</math>|{{EquationRef|1}}}}
In particular, the exponents ''m'', ''n'', ''k'' need not be equal, whereas Fermat's last theorem considers the case {{math|1=''m'' = ''n'' = ''k''.}}


The ], also known as the Mauldin conjecture<ref>{{cite web |url = http://www.primepuzzles.net/puzzles/puzz_559.htm | title = Mauldin / Tijdeman-Zagier Conjecture | publisher = Prime Puzzles | access-date = 1 October 2016}}</ref> and the Tijdeman-Zagier conjecture,<ref name=Elkies>{{cite journal |last=Elkies| first = Noam D. | title=The ABC's of Number Theory | journal = The Harvard College Mathematics Review | year=2007 | volume=1 | issue = 1 | url=http://dash.harvard.edu/bitstream/handle/1/2793857/Elkies%20-%20ABCs%20of%20Number%20Theory.pdf?sequence=2}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |journal= Moscow Mathematical Journal|volume=4 |year=2004 |title=Open Diophantine Problems |pages=245–305 |author=Michel Waldschmidt |doi=10.17323/1609-4514-2004-4-1-245-305 |arxiv=math/0312440|s2cid=11845578 }}</ref><ref name="PrimeNumbers">{{cite book |title=Prime Numbers: A Computational Perspective |last1=Crandall |first1=Richard |last2=Pomerance |first2=Carl |year=2000 |isbn=978-0387-25282-7 |publisher=Springer |page=417}}</ref> states that there are no solutions to the generalized Fermat equation in positive integers ''a'', ''b'', ''c'', ''m'', ''n'', ''k'' with ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' being pairwise coprime and all of ''m'', ''n'', ''k'' being greater than 2.<ref>{{cite web| url=https://www.ams.org/profession/prizes-awards/ams-supported/beal-conjecture | title=Beal Conjecture | publisher=American Mathematical Society | access-date=21 August 2016}}</ref>
====Integer ''n'' <&nbsp;–2====


The ] generalizes Fermat's last theorem with the ideas of the ].<ref>{{cite journal |title=A new generalization of Fermat's Last Theorem |last1=Cai |first1=Tianxin |last2=Chen |first2=Deyi |last3=Zhang |first3=Yong |journal=Journal of Number Theory |volume=149 |year=2015 |pages=33–45|doi=10.1016/j.jnt.2014.09.014 |arxiv=1310.0897 |s2cid=119732583 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=A Cyclotomic Investigation of the Catalan–Fermat Conjecture |last=Mihailescu |first=Preda |journal=Mathematica Gottingensis |year=2007}}</ref> The conjecture states that the generalized Fermat equation has only ''finitely many'' solutions (''a'', ''b'', ''c'', ''m'', ''n'', ''k'') with distinct triplets of values (''a''<sup>''m''</sup>, ''b''<sup>''n''</sup>, ''c''<sup>''k''</sup>), where ''a'', ''b'', ''c'' are positive coprime integers and ''m'', ''n'', ''k'' are positive integers satisfying
There are no solutions in integers for <math>a^n+b^n=c^n</math> for integer ''n'' <&nbsp;–2. If there were, the equation could be multiplied through by <math>a^{|n|}b^{|n|}c^{|n|}</math> to obtain <math>(bc)^{|n|}+(ac)^{|n|}=(ab)^{|n|}</math>, which is impossible by Fermat's Last Theorem.


{{NumBlk|:|<math>\frac{1}{m} + \frac{1}{n} + \frac{1}{k} < 1.</math>|{{EquationRef|2}}}}
==Did Fermat possess a general proof?==


The statement is about the finiteness of the set of solutions because there are 10 ].<ref name="princeton-companion"/>
The mathematical techniques used in Fermat's "marvelous" proof are unknown. Only one detailed proof of Fermat has survived, the above proof that no three coprime integers (''x'', ''y'', ''z'') satisfy the equation ''x''<sup>4</sup> − ''y''<sup>4</sup> = ''z''<sup>2</sup>.


=== Inverse Fermat equation ===
Taylor and Wiles's proof relies on mathematical techniques developed in the twentieth century, which would be alien to mathematicians who had worked on Fermat's Last Theorem even a century earlier. Fermat's alleged "marvellous proof", by comparison, would have had to be elementary, given mathematical knowledge of the time, and so could not have been the same as Wiles' proof. Most mathematicians and science historians doubt that Fermat had a valid proof of his theorem for all exponents ''n''.{{Citation needed|date=August 2011}}
When we allow the exponent {{math|''n''}} to be the reciprocal of an integer, i.e. {{math|1=''n'' = 1/''m''}} for some integer {{math|''m''}}, we have the inverse Fermat equation {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>1/''m''</sup> + ''b''<sup>1/''m''</sup> = ''c''<sup>1/''m''</sup>}}.
All solutions of this equation were computed by ] in 1992.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Lenstra Jr. H.W. | authorlink=Hendrik Lenstra | year = 1992 | title = On the inverse Fermat equation | journal = Discrete Mathematics | volume = 106–107 | pages = 329–331 | doi = 10.1016/0012-365x(92)90561-s | doi-access = }}</ref> In the case in which the ''m''th roots are required to be real and positive, all solutions are given by<ref>{{cite journal | author = Newman M | year = 1981 | title = A radical diophantine equation | doi = 10.1016/0022-314x(81)90040-8 | journal = ] | volume = 13 | issue = 4| pages = 495–498 | doi-access = free }}</ref>
: <math>a=rs^m</math>
: <math>b=rt^m</math>
: <math>c=r(s+t)^m</math>
for positive integers ''r'', ''s'', ''t'' with ''s'' and ''t'' coprime.


=== Rational exponents ===
]'s ] implies that Fermat's last theorem can be proved in elementary arithmetic, a rather weak form of arithmetic with addition, multiplication, exponentiation, and a limited form of induction for formulas with bounded quantifiers.<ref>{{Cite journal | last1=Avigad | first1=Jeremy | title=Number theory and elementary arithmetic | doi=10.1093/philmat/11.3.257 | mr=2006194 | year=2003 | journal=Philosophia Mathematica. Philosophy of Mathematics, its Learning, and its Application. Series III | issn=0031-8019 | volume=11 | issue=3 | pages=257–284 | id = {{citeseerx|10.1.1.105.6509}} }}</ref> Any such proof would be elementary but possibly too long to write down.
For the Diophantine equation {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>''n''/''m''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''/''m''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''/''m''</sup>}} with ''n'' not equal to 1, Bennett, Glass, and Székely proved in 2004 for {{nowrap|''n'' > 2}}, that if ''n'' and ''m'' are coprime, then there are integer solutions if and only if 6 divides ''m'', and {{nowrap|''a''<sup>1/''m''</sup>}}, {{nowrap|''b''<sup>1/''m''</sup>}}, and {{nowrap|''c''<sup>1/''m''</sup>}} are different complex 6th roots of the same real number.<ref>
{{cite journal
| last1 = Bennett | first1 = Curtis D.
| last2 = Glass | first2 = A. M. W.
| last3 = Székely | first3 = Gábor J.
| doi = 10.2307/4145241
| issue = 4
| journal = American Mathematical Monthly
| mr = 2057186
| pages = 322–329
| title = Fermat's last theorem for rational exponents
| volume = 111
| year = 2004| jstor = 4145241
}}</ref>


=== Negative integer exponents ===
==Monetary prizes==
==== ''n'' = −1 ====
All primitive integer solutions (i.e., those with no prime factor common to all of ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'') to the ] {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>−1</sup> + ''b''<sup>−1</sup> = ''c''<sup>−1</sup>}} can be written as{{sfn|Dickson|1919|pp=688–691|ps=}}
: <math>a = mk + m^2,</math>
: <math>b = mk + k^2,</math>
: <math>c = mk</math>
for positive, coprime integers ''m'', ''k''.


==== ''n'' = −2 ====
In 1816 and again in 1850, the ] offered a prize for a general proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.<ref>Aczel, p. 69; Singh, p. 105.</ref> In 1857, the Academy awarded 3000 francs and a gold medal to Kummer for his research on ideal numbers, although he had not submitted an entry for the prize.<ref>Aczel, p. 69.</ref> Another prize was offered in 1883 by the Academy of Brussels.<ref name="Koshy_2001" >{{cite book | author = Koshy T | year = 2001 | title = Elementary number theory with applications | publisher = Academic Press | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-12-421171-1 | page = 544}}</ref>
The case {{nowrap|1=''n'' = −2}} also has an infinitude of solutions, and these have a geometric interpretation in terms of ].<ref>{{cite journal |last=Voles |first=Roger |title=Integer solutions of ''a''<sup>−2</sup>&nbsp;+&nbsp;''b''<sup>−2</sup>&nbsp;=&nbsp;''d''<sup>−2</sup> |journal=] |volume=83 |issue=497 |date=July 1999 |pages=269–271|doi=10.2307/3619056 |jstor=3619056 |s2cid=123267065 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Richinick |first=Jennifer |title=The upside-down Pythagorean Theorem |journal=] |volume=92 |date=July 2008 |pages=313–317|doi=10.1017/S0025557200183275 |s2cid=125989951 }}</ref> All primitive solutions to {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>−2</sup> + ''b''<sup>−2</sup> = ''d''<sup>−2</sup>}} are given by
: <math>a = (v^2 - u^2)(v^2 + u^2),</math>
: <math>b = 2uv(v^2 + u^2),</math>
: <math>d = 2uv(v^2 - u^2),</math>
for coprime integers ''u'', ''v'' with {{nowrap|''v'' > ''u''}}. The geometric interpretation is that ''a'' and ''b'' are the integer legs of a right triangle and ''d'' is the integer altitude to the hypotenuse. Then the hypotenuse itself is the integer
: <math>c = (v^2 + u^2)^2,</math>
so {{nowrap|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'')}} is a ].


==== ''n'' < −2 ====
In 1908, the German industrialist and amateur mathematician ] bequeathed 100,000 ] to the Göttingen Academy of Sciences to be offered as a prize for a complete proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.<ref>Singh, pp. 120–125, 131–133, 295–296; Aczel, p. 70.</ref> On 27 June 1908, the Academy published nine rules for awarding the prize. Among other things, these rules required that the proof be published in a peer-reviewed journal; the prize would not be awarded until two years after the publication; and that no prize would be given after 13 September 2007, roughly a century after the competition was begun.<ref>Singh, pp. 120–125.</ref> Wiles collected the Wolfskehl prize money, then worth $50,000, on 27 June 1997.<ref>Singh, p. 284</ref>
There are no solutions in integers for {{nowrap|1=''a''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''b''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''c''<sup>''n''</sup>}} for integers {{nowrap|''n'' < −2}}. If there were, the equation could be multiplied through by {{nowrap|''a''<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup>''b''<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup>''c''<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup>}} to obtain {{nowrap|1=(''bc'')<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup> + (''ac'')<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup> = (''ab'')<sup>{{abs|''n''}}</sup>}}, which is impossible by Fermat's Last Theorem.


=== abc conjecture ===
Prior to Wiles' proof, thousands of incorrect proofs were submitted to the Wolfskehl committee, amounting to roughly 10 feet (3 meters) of correspondence.<ref>Singh, p. 295.</ref> In the first year alone (1907–1908), 621 attempted proofs were submitted, although by the 1970s, the rate of submission had decreased to roughly 3–4 attempted proofs per month. According to F. Schlichting, a Wolfskehl reviewer, most of the proofs were based on elementary methods taught in schools, and often submitted by "people with a technical education but a failed career".<ref>Singh, pp. 295–296.</ref> In the words of mathematical historian ], "Fermat's Last Theorem has the peculiar distinction of being the mathematical problem for which the greatest number of incorrect proofs have been published."<ref name="Koshy_2001" />
{{Main|abc conjecture#Some consequences}}


The ] roughly states that if three positive integers ''a'', ''b'' and ''c'' (hence the name) are coprime and satisfy {{nowrap|1=''a'' + ''b'' = ''c''}}, then the ] ''d'' of ''abc'' is usually not much smaller than ''c''. In particular, the abc conjecture in its most standard formulation implies Fermat's last theorem for ''n'' that are sufficiently large.<ref>{{cite book |title=Algebra |last=Lang |first=Serge |authorlink=Serge Lang |publisher=Springer-Verlag New York |series=Graduate Texts in Mathematics |volume=211 |year=2002 |page=196}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1155/S1073792891000144 |title=ABC implies Mordell |first=Noam |last=Elkies |authorlink=Noam Elkies |journal=] |volume=1991 |issue=7 |year=1991 |pages=99–109 |quote=Our proof generalizes the known implication "effective ABC eventual Fermat" which was the original motivation for the ABC conjecture|doi-access= free}}</ref><ref name="Granville-Tucker"/> The ] is equivalent to the abc conjecture and therefore has the same implication.<ref>{{cite journal | last=Oesterlé | first=Joseph | authorlink=Joseph Oesterlé | title=Nouvelles approches du "théorème" de Fermat | url= http://www.numdam.org/item?id=SB_1987-1988__30__165_0 | series=Séminaire Bourbaki exp 694 |mr=992208 | year=1988 | journal=Astérisque | issn=0303-1179 | issue=161 | pages=165–186}}</ref><ref name="Granville-Tucker"/> An effective version of the abc conjecture, or an effective version of the modified Szpiro conjecture, implies Fermat's Last Theorem outright.<ref name="Granville-Tucker">{{cite journal | last1 = Granville | first1 = Andrew | authorlink1=Andrew Granville | last2 = Tucker | first2 = Thomas | year = 2002 | title = It's As Easy As abc | url = https://www.ams.org/notices/200210/fea-granville.pdf | journal = Notices of the AMS | volume = 49 | issue = 10| pages = 1224–1231 }}</ref>
==In popular culture==

== Prizes and incorrect proofs ==
In 1816, and again in 1850, the ] offered a prize for a general proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=69|ps=}}<ref>Singh, p. 105</ref> In 1857, the academy awarded 3,000 francs and a gold medal to Kummer for his research on ideal numbers, although he had not submitted an entry for the prize.{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=69|ps=}} Another prize was offered in 1883 by the Academy of Brussels.<ref name="Koshy_2001" >{{cite book | author = Koshy T | year = 2001 | title = Elementary number theory with applications | publisher = Academic Press | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-12-421171-1 | page = 544}}</ref>

In 1908, the German industrialist and amateur mathematician ] bequeathed 100,000 ]—a large sum at the time—to the Göttingen Academy of Sciences to offer as a prize for a complete proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.<ref>Singh, pp. 120–125, 131–133, 295–296</ref>{{sfn|Aczel|1996|p=70|ps=}} On 27 June 1908, the academy published nine rules for awarding the prize. Among other things, these rules required that the proof be published in a peer-reviewed journal; the prize would not be awarded until two years after the publication; and that no prize would be given after 13 September 2007, roughly a century after the competition was begun.<ref>Singh, pp. 120–125</ref> Wiles collected the Wolfskehl prize money, then worth $50,000, on 27 June 1997.<ref>Singh, p. 284</ref> In March 2016, Wiles was awarded the Norwegian government's ] worth €600,000 for "his stunning proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by way of the modularity conjecture for semistable elliptic curves, opening a new era in number theory".<ref>{{cite web
| url = http://www.abelprize.no/c67107/binfil/download.php?tid=67059
| title = The Abel Prize citation 2016
| date = March 2016
| website = The Abel Prize
| publisher = The Abel Prize Committee
| access-date = 16 March 2016
| archive-date = 20 May 2020
| archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20200520195920/https://www.abelprize.no/c67107/binfil/download.php?tid=67059
| url-status = dead
}}</ref>

Prior to Wiles's proof, thousands of incorrect proofs were submitted to the Wolfskehl committee, amounting to roughly {{convert|10|ft|m|abbr=off|sp=us}} of correspondence.<ref>Singh, p. 295</ref> In the first year alone (1907–1908), 621 attempted proofs were submitted, although by the 1970s, the rate of submission had decreased to roughly 3–4 attempted proofs per month. According to some claims, ] tended to use a special preprinted form for such proofs, where the location of the first mistake was left blank to be filled by one of his graduate students.<ref>'''', Martin Gardner</ref> According to F. Schlichting, a Wolfskehl reviewer, most of the proofs were based on elementary methods taught in schools, and often submitted by "people with a technical education but a failed career".<ref>Singh, pp. 295–296</ref> In the words of mathematical historian ], "Fermat's Last Theorem has the peculiar distinction of being the mathematical problem for which the greatest number of incorrect proofs have been published."<ref name="Koshy_2001"/>

== In popular culture ==
{{Main|Fermat's Last Theorem in fiction}} {{Main|Fermat's Last Theorem in fiction}}


The popularity of the theorem outside science has led to it being described as achieving "that rarest of mathematical accolades: A niche role in ]."<ref>{{Cite web |last=Garmon |first=Jay |date=2006-02-21 |title=Geek Trivia: The math behind the myth |url=https://www.techrepublic.com/article/geek-trivia-the-math-behind-the-myth/ |access-date=2022-05-21 |website=TechRepublic |language=en-US }}</ref>]
* An episode in the television series '']'', titled "]", refers to the theorem in the first act. Riker visits Captain Jean-Luc Picard in his ready room to report only to find Picard puzzling over Fermat's last theorem. Picard's interest in this theorem goes beyond the difficulty of the puzzle; he also feels humbled that despite their advanced technology, they are still unable to solve a problem set forth by a man who had no computer.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://memory-alpha.org/The_Royale_(episode) |title=The Royale (episode) - Memory Alpha, the Star Trek Wiki |publisher=Memory-alpha.org |date=2012-05-10 |accessdate=2012-08-15}}</ref> An episode in '']'', titled "]", refers to the theorem as well. In a scene involving O'Brien, Tobin Dax mentions continuing work on his own attempt to solve Fermat's last theorem.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://memory-alpha.org/Facets_(episode) |title=Facets (episode) - Memory Alpha, the Star Trek Wiki |publisher=Memory-alpha.org |date= |accessdate=2012-08-15}}</ref>

* "The Proof" – ''Nova'' (]) documentary about Andrew Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.
]' 1954 short story "]" features a ] who bargains with the ] that the latter cannot produce a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem within twenty-four hours.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Kasman|first=Alex|date=January 2003|title=Mathematics in Fiction: An Interdisciplinary Course|journal=]|language=en|volume=13|issue=1|pages=1–16|doi=10.1080/10511970308984042|s2cid=122365046 |issn=1051-1970}}</ref>
* On August 17, 2011, a ] was shown on the Google homepage, showing a blackboard with the theorem on it. When hovered over, it displays the text "I have discovered a truly marvelous proof of this theorem, which this doodle is too small to contain." This is a reference to the note made by Fermat in the margins of ''Arithmetica''. It commemorated the 410th birth anniversary of de Fermat.<ref></ref>

* In the book ''],'' main character Lisbeth Salander becomes obsessed with the theorem in the opening chapters of the book. Her continuing effort to come up with a proof on her own is a running sub-plot throughout the story, and is used as a way to demonstrate her exceptional intelligence. In the end she comes up with a proof (the actual proof is not featured in the book). But after being shot in the head and surviving, she has lost the proof.
In '']'' episode "]", ] writes the equation {{nowrap|1=3987<sup>12</sup> + 4365<sup>12</sup> = 4472<sup>12</sup>}} on a blackboard, which appears to be a ] to Fermat's Last Theorem. The equation is wrong, but it appears to be correct if entered in a calculator with 10 ].<ref name=SinghSimpsons>{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=feg_AQAAQBAJ&pg=PA35 |title=The Simpsons and Their Mathematical Secrets |last=Singh |first=Simon |authorlink=Simon Singh |pages=35–36 |year=2013 |publisher=A&C Black |isbn=978-1-4088-3530-2 |language=en}}</ref>
* In the ] re-make of the movie '']'', starring Brendan Fraser and Elizabeth Hurley, Fermat's Last Theorem appears written on the chalkboard in the classroom that the protagonist Elliot finds himself teleported to after he aborts his failed fourth wish. In the director's commentary for the DVD release, director Ramis comments that nobody has seemed to notice that the equation on the board is Fermat's Last Theorem.
* In '']'', Season 5 Episode 1 "]", the Doctor transmits a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by typing it in just a few seconds on Jeff's laptop to prove his genius to a collection of world leaders discussing the latest threat to the human race. This implies that the Doctor knew a proof which was quite short and easy for others to comprehend.
* In '']'', Series 3 Episode 6 "]" Fermat's Last Theorem is referenced during a photo shoot for a calendar about geeks and achievements in Science and Mathematics.
* The song "Bizarro Genius Baby" by ] contains the lyrics "And no dust had settled when she’d disproved Fermat by finding A^3 + B^3 that = C^3".


In the '']'' episode "]", ] states that the theorem is still unproven in the 24th century. The proof was released five years after the episode originally aired.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Moseman |first=Andrew |date=2017-09-01 |title=Here's a Fun Math Goof in 'Star Trek: The Next Generation' |url=https://www.popularmechanics.com/science/math/news/a28040/fermats-last-theorem-star-trek-the-next-generation/ |access-date=2023-06-09 |website=Popular Mechanics |language=en-US}}</ref>
==See also==


== See also ==
{{Portal|Mathematics}}
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ], a list of related conjectures and theorems
* ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ]


==Notes== == Footnotes ==
{{reflist|group="note"|30em}} {{reflist|group="note"|30em}}


==References== == References ==
{{Reflist|30em}} {{reflist}}


==Bibliography== == Bibliography ==
{{refbegin|30em}} {{refbegin|30em}}
* {{cite book
* {{Cite book|last=Aczel|first=Amir|authorlink=Amir Aczel|title=Fermat's Last Theorem: Unlocking the Secret of an Ancient Mathematical Problem|date=30 September 1996|publisher=Four Walls Eight Windows|isbn=978-1-56858-077-7}}
| last=Aczel | first=Amir | authorlink=Amir Aczel
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 1919 | title = ]. Volume II. Diophantine Analysis | publisher = Chelsea Publishing | location = New York | pages = 545–550, 615–621, 688–691, 731–776}}
| date=1996
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 1997 | title = Fermat's Last Theorem. A Genetic Introduction to Algebraic Number Theory | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | series = Graduate Texts in Mathematics | volume = 50}}
| title=Fermat's Last Theorem: Unlocking the Secret of an Ancient Mathematical Problem
* {{Cite book | last = Friberg | first = Joran | year = 2007 | title = Amazing Traces of a Babylonian Origin in Greek Mathematics | publisher =World Scientific Publishing Company | isbn = 978-981-270-452-8}}
| publisher=Four Walls Eight Windows
* {{Cite journal | author = Kleiner I | year = 2000 | title = From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat's Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem | journal = Elem. Math. | volume = 55 | pages = 19–37 | url = http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/kleiner.pdf | doi = 10.1007/PL00000079}}
| isbn=978-1-56858-077-7
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 1921 | title = Three Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Cambridge University Press | location = Cambridge}}
| url=https://archive.org/details/fermatslasttheor00acz_pep
* {{Cite book | last = Panchishkin | first = Alekseĭ Alekseevich | year = 2007 | title = Introduction to Modern Number Theory (Encyclopedia of Mathematical Sciences | publisher =Springer Berlin Heidelberg New York | isbn = 978-3-540-20364-3}}
}}
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 2000 | title = Fermat's Last Theorem for Amateurs | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-98508-4}}
* {{cite book
* {{Cite book | author = ] | title = Fermat's Enigma | year = 1998 | month = October | publisher = Anchor Books | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-385-49362-8}}
| last1 = Dickson | first1 = LE | authorlink = Leonard Eugene Dickson
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 1978 | title = An Introduction to Number Theory | publisher = MIT Press | isbn = 0-262-69060-8}}
| year = 1919
| title = History of the Theory of Numbers
| volume = II
| series = Diophantine Analysis
| publisher = Chelsea Publishing | location = New York
| pages = 545–550, 615–621, 688–691, 731–776
}}
* {{cite book
| last1 = Edwards | first1 = HM | authorlink = Harold Edwards (mathematician)
| year = 1996 | orig-year=1977
| title = Fermat's Last Theorem. A Genetic Introduction to Algebraic Number Theory
| series = Graduate Texts in Mathematics
| volume = 50
| publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York
| isbn = 978-0-387-90230-2
}}
* {{cite book
| last = Friberg | first = Joran
| year = 2007
| title = Amazing Traces of a Babylonian Origin in Greek Mathematics
| publisher = World Scientific Publishing Company
| isbn = 978-981-270-452-8
}}
* {{cite journal
| last1 = Kleiner | first1 = I
| year = 2000
| title = From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat's Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem
| journal = ]
| volume = 55
| pages = 19–37
| url = http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/kleiner.pdf
| doi = 10.1007/PL00000079
| s2cid = 53319514
| url-status = dead
| archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20110608052614/http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/kleiner.pdf
| archive-date = 8 June 2011
}}
* {{cite book
| last1 = Mordell | first1 = LJ | authorlink=Louis Mordell
| year = 1921
| title = Three Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem
| publisher = Cambridge University Press | location = Cambridge
}}
* {{cite book
| last1 = Manin | first1 = Yuri Ivanovic
| last2 = Panchishkin | first2 = Alekseĭ Alekseevich
| year = 2007
| title = Introduction to Modern Number Theory
| chapter = Fundamental problems, Ideas and Theories
| series = Encyclopedia of Mathematical Sciences
| volume = 49
| edition = 2nd
| publisher=Springer | location=Berlin Hedelberg
| isbn = 978-3-540-20364-3
}}
* {{cite book
| last1 = Ribenboim | first1=P | authorlink=Paulo Ribenboim
| year = 2000
| title = Fermat's Last Theorem for Amateurs
| publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York
| isbn = 978-0-387-98508-4
}}
* {{cite book
| last1 = Singh | first1 = S | authorlink = Simon Singh
| year = 1998
| title = Fermat's Enigma
| publisher = Anchor Books | location = New York
| isbn = 978-0-385-49362-8
| title-link = Fermat's Enigma
}}
* {{cite book
| last1=Stark | first1=H | authorlink=Harold Stark
| year = 1978
| title = An Introduction to Number Theory
| publisher = MIT Press
| isbn = 0-262-69060-8
| url = https://archive.org/details/introductiontonu00star_0
}}
{{refend}} {{refend}}


==Further reading== == Further reading ==
{{refbegin|30em}} {{refbegin|30em}}
* {{Cite book|last=Bell|first=Eric T.|title=The Last Problem|location=New York|isbn=978-0-88385-451-8|date=6 August 1998|publisher=The Mathematical Association of America|origyear=1961}} * {{cite book | last=Bell | first=Eric T. | title=The Last Problem | location=New York | isbn=978-0-88385-451-8 | date=1998 | publisher=The Mathematical Association of America | orig-year=1961 }}
* {{Cite book|last=Benson|first=Donald C.|title=The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-513919-8|date=5 April 2001}} * {{cite book | last=Benson | first=Donald C. | title=The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies | publisher=Oxford University Press | isbn=978-0-19-513919-8 | date=2001}}
* {{Cite book|last=Brudner|first=Harvey J.|authorlink=Harvey J. Brudner|title=Fermat and the Missing Numbers|publisher=WLC, Inc|isbn=978-0-9644785-0-3|year=1994}} * {{cite book | last=Brudner | first=Harvey J. | authorlink=Harvey J. Brudner | title=Fermat and the Missing Numbers | publisher=WLC, Inc | isbn=978-0-9644785-0-3 | year=1994 }}
* {{cite journal | author = Faltings G |date=July 1995 | url = https://www.ams.org/notices/199507/faltings.pdf | title=The Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by R. Taylor and A. Wiles | journal=] | volume=42 | issue=7 | pages=743–746 | issn=0002-9920 | authorlink=Gerd Faltings }}
* {{Cite book | last=Edwards|first=H. M. | title=Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher=Springer-Verlag | origyear=1977|year=1996|month=March| isbn=978-0-387-90230-2|location=New York }}
* {{cite book | last=Mozzochi | first=Charles | title=The Fermat Diary | date=2000 | isbn=978-0-8218-2670-6 | publisher=American Mathematical Society }}
* {{Cite journal | author = ] | year = 1995 | month = July | url = http://www.ams.org/notices/199507/faltings.pdf|format=PDF|title=The Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by R. Taylor and A. Wiles|journal=Notices of the AMS|volume=42|issue=7|pages=743–746|issn=0002-9920}}
* {{Cite book|last=Mozzochi|first=Charles | title=The Fermat Diary | date=7 December 2000 | isbn=978-0-8218-2670-6|publisher=American Mathematical Society}} * {{cite book | author = Ribenboim P | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0| authorlink=Paulo Ribenboim }}
* {{cite journal | last = Saikia | first = Manjil P | date = July 2011 | url = http://www.manjilsaikia.in/publ/projects/kummerFLT.pdf | title = A Study of Kummer's Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for Regular Primes | journal = IISER Mohali (India) Summer Project Report | bibcode = 2013arXiv1307.3459S | arxiv = 1307.3459 | access-date = 9 March 2014 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20150922030715/http://www.manjilsaikia.in/publ/projects/kummerFLT.pdf | archive-date = 22 September 2015 | url-status = dead }}
* {{Cite book | author = ] | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0}}
* {{Cite book|last=van der Poorten|first=Alf|title=Notes on Fermat's Last Theorem|date=6 March 1996|publisher=WileyBlackwell |isbn=978-0-471-06261-5}} * {{cite book | last=Stevens | first=Glenn | authorlink=Glenn H. Stevens | chapter=An Overview of the Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem | title=Modular Forms and Fermat's Last Theorem | location=New York | publisher=Springer | year=1997 | isbn=0-387-94609-8 | pages=1–16 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Va-quzVwtMsC&pg=PA1 }}
* {{cite book | last=van der Poorten | first=Alf | title=Notes on Fermat's Last Theorem | date=1996 | publisher=WileyBlackwell | isbn=978-0-471-06261-5 | url-access=registration | url=https://archive.org/details/notesonfermatsla0000vand }}
* {{Cite journal | last = Saikia| first = Manjil P | year = 2011 | month = July | url = http://www.thequantizedquark.com/papers/kummerFLT.pdf|format=PDF|title=A Study of Kummer's Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for Regular Primes|journal=IISER Mohali Report}}
{{refend}} {{refend}}


==External links== == External links ==
{{Wikibooks}} {{Wikibooks}}
{{Wikiquote}}
* {{cite web|author=Daney, Charles|year=2003 | url=http://cgd.best.vwh.net/home/flt/flt01.htm| title=The Mathematics of Fermat's Last Theorem|accessdate=5 August 2004}}
{{Commons category}}
*
{{refbegin}}
* {{cite web|author=Elkies, Noam D.| url=http://www.math.harvard.edu/~elkies/ferm.html| title=Tables of Fermat "near-misses" &mdash; approximate solutions of x<sup>n</sup> + y<sup>n</sup> = z<sup>n</sup>}}
* {{cite web|author=Freeman, Larry| year=2005|url=http://www.fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com| title=Fermat's Last Theorem Blog}} Blog that covers the history of Fermat's Last Theorem from Fermat to Wiles. * {{cite web | last1=Daney | first1=Charles | year=2003 | url=http://cgd.best.vwh.net/home/flt/flt01.htm | title=The Mathematics of Fermat's Last Theorem | access-date=5 August 2004 | url-status=dead | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20040803221632/http://cgd.best.vwh.net/home/flt/flt01.htm | archive-date=3 August 2004 }}
* {{cite web | last1=Elkies | first1=Noam D. | url=http://www.math.harvard.edu/~elkies/ferm.html | title=Tables of Fermat "near-misses" – approximate solutions of ''x''<sup>''n''</sup> + ''y''<sup>''n''</sup> = ''z''<sup>''n''</sup> }}
* {{springer|title=Fermat's last theorem|id=p/f110070}}
* {{cite web|author=Ribet, Ken| year=1995| url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/ribet.pdf |title=Galois representations and modular forms|format=PDF}} Discusses various material which is related to the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem: elliptic curves, modular forms, Galois representations and their deformations, Frey's construction, and the conjectures of Serre and of Taniyama–Shimura. * {{cite web | last1=Freeman | first1=Larry | year=2005 |url=http://www.fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com | title=Fermat's Last Theorem Blog}} Blog that covers the history of Fermat's Last Theorem from Fermat to Wiles.
* {{SpringerEOM | title=Fermat's last theorem | id=p/f110070|mode=cs1 }}
* {{cite web|author=Shay, David|year=2003| url=http://shayfam.com/David/flt/index.htm| title=Fermat's Last Theorem| accessdate=5 August 2004}} The story, the history and the mystery.
* {{cite journal
* {{MathWorld | urlname=FermatsLastTheorem| title=Fermat's Last Theorem}}
| last1 = Ribet | first1 = Kenneth A.
* {{cite web| author = O'Connor JJ, Robertson EF | year = 1996 | url = http://www-gap.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/HistTopics/Fermat's_last_theorem.html | title = Fermat's last theorem | accessdate = 5 August 2004}}
| year = 1995
* {{cite web |url=http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/proof/| title=The Proof}} The title of one edition of the PBS television series NOVA, discusses Andrew Wiles's effort to prove Fermat's Last Theorem.
| arxiv = math/9503219
* {{cite web |url=http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=7FnXgprKgSE| title= Documentary Movie on Fermat's Last Theorem (1996) }} Simon Singh and John Lynch's film tells the story of Andrew Wiles.
| doi = 10.1090/S0273-0979-1995-00616-6
{{Use dmy dates|date=August 2010}}
| issue = 4
*
| journal = Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society
| mr = 1322785
| pages = 375–402
| series = New Series
| title = Galois representations and modular forms
| volume = 32
| s2cid = 16786407
}} Discusses various material that is related to the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem: elliptic curves, modular forms, Galois representations and their deformations, Frey's construction, and the conjectures of Serre and of Taniyama–Shimura.
* {{cite web|author=Shay, David|year=2003| url=http://shayfam.freevar.com/david/flt/index.htm| title=Fermat's Last Theorem| access-date=14 January 2017}} The story, the history and the mystery.
* {{MathWorld | urlname=FermatsLastTheorem | title=Fermat's Last Theorem}}
* {{cite web | vauthors = O'Connor JJ, Robertson EF | year = 1996 | url = http://www-gap.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/HistTopics/Fermat's_last_theorem.html | title = Fermat's last theorem | access-date = 5 August 2004 | url-status = dead | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20040804045854/http://www-gap.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/HistTopics/Fermat%27s_last_theorem.html | archive-date = 4 August 2004 }}
* {{cite web | url=https://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/proof/ | title=The Proof | publisher=]}} The title of one edition of the PBS television series NOVA, discusses Andrew Wiles's effort to prove Fermat's Last Theorem.
* {{cite web | url=http://vimeo.com/18216532 | title= Documentary Movie on Fermat's Last Theorem (1996) }} Simon Singh and John Lynch's film tells the story of Andrew Wiles.
{{refend}}


{{Pierre de Fermat}}
]
{{Authority control}}
]


] ]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]

Latest revision as of 13:37, 19 November 2024

17th-century conjecture proved by Andrew Wiles in 1994 For other theorems named after Pierre de Fermat, see Fermat's theorem. For the book by Simon Singh, see Fermat's Last Theorem (book).
This article's use of external links may not follow Misplaced Pages's policies or guidelines. Please improve this article by removing excessive or inappropriate external links, and converting useful links where appropriate into footnote references. (June 2021) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Fermat's Last Theorem
The 1670 edition of Diophantus's Arithmetica includes Fermat's commentary, referred to as his "Last Theorem" (Observatio Domini Petri de Fermat), posthumously published by his son.
FieldNumber theory
StatementFor any integer n > 2, the equation a + b = c has no positive integer solutions.
First stated byPierre de Fermat
First stated inc. 1637
First proof byAndrew Wiles
First proof inReleased 1994
Published 1995
Implied by
Generalizations

In number theory, Fermat's Last Theorem (sometimes called Fermat's conjecture, especially in older texts) states that no three positive integers a, b, and c satisfy the equation a + b = c for any integer value of n greater than 2. The cases n = 1 and n = 2 have been known since antiquity to have infinitely many solutions.

The proposition was first stated as a theorem by Pierre de Fermat around 1637 in the margin of a copy of Arithmetica. Fermat added that he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin. Although other statements claimed by Fermat without proof were subsequently proven by others and credited as theorems of Fermat (for example, Fermat's theorem on sums of two squares), Fermat's Last Theorem resisted proof, leading to doubt that Fermat ever had a correct proof. Consequently, the proposition became known as a conjecture rather than a theorem. After 358 years of effort by mathematicians, the first successful proof was released in 1994 by Andrew Wiles and formally published in 1995. It was described as a "stunning advance" in the citation for Wiles's Abel Prize award in 2016. It also proved much of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture, subsequently known as the modularity theorem, and opened up entire new approaches to numerous other problems and mathematically powerful modularity lifting techniques.

The unsolved problem stimulated the development of algebraic number theory in the 19th and 20th centuries. It is among the most notable theorems in the history of mathematics and prior to its proof was in the Guinness Book of World Records as the "most difficult mathematical problem", in part because the theorem has the largest number of unsuccessful proofs.

Overview

Pythagorean origins

The Pythagorean equation, x + y = z, has an infinite number of positive integer solutions for x, y, and z; these solutions are known as Pythagorean triples (with the simplest example being 3, 4, 5). Around 1637, Fermat wrote in the margin of a book that the more general equation a + b = c had no solutions in positive integers if n is an integer greater than 2. Although he claimed to have a general proof of his conjecture, Fermat left no details of his proof, and none has ever been found. His claim was discovered some 30 years later, after his death. This claim, which came to be known as Fermat's Last Theorem, stood unsolved for the next three and a half centuries.

The claim eventually became one of the most notable unsolved problems of mathematics. Attempts to prove it prompted substantial development in number theory, and over time Fermat's Last Theorem gained prominence as an unsolved problem in mathematics.

Subsequent developments and solution

This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Fermat's Last Theorem" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (August 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

The special case n = 4, proved by Fermat himself, is sufficient to establish that if the theorem is false for some exponent n that is not a prime number, it must also be false for some smaller n, so only prime values of n need further investigation. Over the next two centuries (1637–1839), the conjecture was proved for only the primes 3, 5, and 7, although Sophie Germain innovated and proved an approach that was relevant to an entire class of primes. In the mid-19th century, Ernst Kummer extended this and proved the theorem for all regular primes, leaving irregular primes to be analyzed individually. Building on Kummer's work and using sophisticated computer studies, other mathematicians were able to extend the proof to cover all prime exponents up to four million, but a proof for all exponents was inaccessible (meaning that mathematicians generally considered a proof impossible, exceedingly difficult, or unachievable with current knowledge).

Separately, around 1955, Japanese mathematicians Goro Shimura and Yutaka Taniyama suspected a link might exist between elliptic curves and modular forms, two completely different areas of mathematics. Known at the time as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture (eventually as the modularity theorem), it stood on its own, with no apparent connection to Fermat's Last Theorem. It was widely seen as significant and important in its own right, but was (like Fermat's theorem) widely considered completely inaccessible to proof.

In 1984, Gerhard Frey noticed an apparent link between these two previously unrelated and unsolved problems. An outline suggesting this could be proved was given by Frey. The full proof that the two problems were closely linked was accomplished in 1986 by Ken Ribet, building on a partial proof by Jean-Pierre Serre, who proved all but one part known as the "epsilon conjecture" (see: Ribet's Theorem and Frey curve). These papers by Frey, Serre and Ribet showed that if the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture could be proven for at least the semi-stable class of elliptic curves, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem would also follow automatically. The connection is described below: any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then by definition, no solution contradicting Fermat's Last Theorem could exist, meaning that Fermat's Last Theorem must also be true.

Although both problems were daunting and widely considered to be "completely inaccessible" to proof at the time, this was the first suggestion of a route by which Fermat's Last Theorem could be extended and proved for all numbers, not just some numbers. Unlike Fermat's Last Theorem, the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture was a major active research area and viewed as more within reach of contemporary mathematics. However, general opinion was that this simply showed the impracticality of proving the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. Mathematician John Coates' quoted reaction was a common one:

I myself was very sceptical that the beautiful link between Fermat's Last Theorem and the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture would actually lead to anything, because I must confess I did not think that the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture was accessible to proof. Beautiful though this problem was, it seemed impossible to actually prove. I must confess I thought I probably wouldn't see it proved in my lifetime.

On hearing that Ribet had proven Frey's link to be correct, English mathematician Andrew Wiles, who had a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem and had a background of working with elliptic curves and related fields, decided to try to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture as a way to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. In 1993, after six years of working secretly on the problem, Wiles succeeded in proving enough of the conjecture to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles's paper was massive in size and scope. A flaw was discovered in one part of his original paper during peer review and required a further year and collaboration with a past student, Richard Taylor, to resolve. As a result, the final proof in 1995 was accompanied by a smaller joint paper showing that the fixed steps were valid. Wiles's achievement was reported widely in the popular press, and was popularized in books and television programs. The remaining parts of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, now proven and known as the modularity theorem, were subsequently proved by other mathematicians, who built on Wiles's work between 1996 and 2001. For his proof, Wiles was honoured and received numerous awards, including the 2016 Abel Prize.

Equivalent statements of the theorem

There are several alternative ways to state Fermat's Last Theorem that are mathematically equivalent to the original statement of the problem.

In order to state them, we use the following notations: let N be the set of natural numbers 1, 2, 3, ..., let Z be the set of integers 0, ±1, ±2, ..., and let Q be the set of rational numbers a/b, where a and b are in Z with b ≠ 0. In what follows we will call a solution to x + y = z where one or more of x, y, or z is zero a trivial solution. A solution where all three are nonzero will be called a non-trivial solution.

For comparison's sake we start with the original formulation.

  • Original statement. With n, x, y, z ∈ N (meaning that n, x, y, z are all positive whole numbers) and n > 2, the equation x + y = z has no solutions.

Most popular treatments of the subject state it this way. It is also commonly stated over Z:

  • Equivalent statement 1: x + y = z, where integer n ≥ 3, has no non-trivial solutions x, y, z ∈ Z.

The equivalence is clear if n is even. If n is odd and all three of x, y, z are negative, then we can replace x, y, z with −x, −y, −z to obtain a solution in N. If two of them are negative, it must be x and z or y and z. If x, z are negative and y is positive, then we can rearrange to get (−z) + y = (−x) resulting in a solution in N; the other case is dealt with analogously. Now if just one is negative, it must be x or y. If x is negative, and y and z are positive, then it can be rearranged to get (−x) + z = y again resulting in a solution in N; if y is negative, the result follows symmetrically. Thus in all cases a nontrivial solution in Z would also mean a solution exists in N, the original formulation of the problem.

  • Equivalent statement 2: x + y = z, where integer n ≥ 3, has no non-trivial solutions x, y, zQ.

This is because the exponents of x, y, and z are equal (to n), so if there is a solution in Q, then it can be multiplied through by an appropriate common denominator to get a solution in Z, and hence in N.

  • Equivalent statement 3: x + y = 1, where integer n ≥ 3, has no non-trivial solutions x, yQ.

A non-trivial solution a, b, c ∈ Z to x + y = z yields the non-trivial solution a/c, b/cQ for v + w = 1. Conversely, a solution a/b, c/dQ to v + w = 1 yields the non-trivial solution ad, cb, bd for x + y = z.

This last formulation is particularly fruitful, because it reduces the problem from a problem about surfaces in three dimensions to a problem about curves in two dimensions. Furthermore, it allows working over the field Q, rather than over the ring Z; fields exhibit more structure than rings, which allows for deeper analysis of their elements.

  • Equivalent statement 4 – connection to elliptic curves: If a, b, c is a non-trivial solution to a + b = c, p odd prime, then y = x(xa)(x + b) (Frey curve) will be an elliptic curve without a modular form.

Examining this elliptic curve with Ribet's theorem shows that it does not have a modular form. However, the proof by Andrew Wiles proves that any equation of the form y = x(xa)(x + b) does have a modular form. Any non-trivial solution to x + y = z (with p an odd prime) would therefore create a contradiction, which in turn proves that no non-trivial solutions exist.

In other words, any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the modularity theorem. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then it would follow that no contradiction to Fermat's Last Theorem could exist either. As described above, the discovery of this equivalent statement was crucial to the eventual solution of Fermat's Last Theorem, as it provided a means by which it could be "attacked" for all numbers at once.

Mathematical history

Pythagoras and Diophantus

Pythagorean triples

Main article: Pythagorean triple

In ancient times it was known that a triangle whose sides were in the ratio 3:4:5 would have a right angle as one of its angles. This was used in construction and later in early geometry. It was also known to be one example of a general rule that any triangle where the length of two sides, each squared and then added together (3 + 4 = 9 + 16 = 25), equals the square of the length of the third side (5 = 25), would also be a right angle triangle. This is now known as the Pythagorean theorem, and a triple of numbers that meets this condition is called a Pythagorean triple; both are named after the ancient Greek Pythagoras. Examples include (3, 4, 5) and (5, 12, 13). There are infinitely many such triples, and methods for generating such triples have been studied in many cultures, beginning with the Babylonians and later ancient Greek, Chinese, and Indian mathematicians. Mathematically, the definition of a Pythagorean triple is a set of three integers (a, b, c) that satisfy the equation a + b = c.

Diophantine equations

Main article: Diophantine equation

Fermat's equation, x + y = z with positive integer solutions, is an example of a Diophantine equation, named for the 3rd-century Alexandrian mathematician, Diophantus, who studied them and developed methods for the solution of some kinds of Diophantine equations. A typical Diophantine problem is to find two integers x and y such that their sum, and the sum of their squares, equal two given numbers A and B, respectively:

A = x + y {\displaystyle A=x+y}
B = x 2 + y 2 . {\displaystyle B=x^{2}+y^{2}.}

Diophantus's major work is the Arithmetica, of which only a portion has survived. Fermat's conjecture of his Last Theorem was inspired while reading a new edition of the Arithmetica, that was translated into Latin and published in 1621 by Claude Bachet.

Diophantine equations have been studied for thousands of years. For example, the solutions to the quadratic Diophantine equation x + y = z are given by the Pythagorean triples, originally solved by the Babylonians (c. 1800 BC). Solutions to linear Diophantine equations, such as 26x + 65y = 13, may be found using the Euclidean algorithm (c. 5th century BC). Many Diophantine equations have a form similar to the equation of Fermat's Last Theorem from the point of view of algebra, in that they have no cross terms mixing two letters, without sharing its particular properties. For example, it is known that there are infinitely many positive integers x, y, and z such that x + y = z, where n and m are relatively prime natural numbers.

Fermat's conjecture

Problem II.8 in the 1621 edition of the Arithmetica of Diophantus. On the right is the margin that was too small to contain Fermat's alleged proof of his "last theorem".

Problem II.8 of the Arithmetica asks how a given square number is split into two other squares; in other words, for a given rational number k, find rational numbers u and v such that k = u + v. Diophantus shows how to solve this sum-of-squares problem for k = 4 (the solutions being u = 16/5 and v = 12/5).

Around 1637, Fermat wrote his Last Theorem in the margin of his copy of the Arithmetica next to Diophantus's sum-of-squares problem:

Cubum autem in duos cubos, aut quadratoquadratum in duos quadratoquadratos & generaliter nullam in infinitum ultra quadratum potestatem in duos eiusdem nominis fas est dividere cuius rei demonstrationem mirabilem sane detexi. Hanc marginis exiguitas non caperet.

It is impossible to separate a cube into two cubes, or a fourth power into two fourth powers, or in general, any power higher than the second, into two like powers. I have discovered a truly marvelous proof of this, which this margin is too narrow to contain.

After Fermat's death in 1665, his son Clément-Samuel Fermat produced a new edition of the book (1670) augmented with his father's comments. Although not actually a theorem at the time (meaning a mathematical statement for which proof exists), the marginal note became known over time as Fermat's Last Theorem, as it was the last of Fermat's asserted theorems to remain unproved.

It is not known whether Fermat had actually found a valid proof for all exponents n, but it appears unlikely. Only one related proof by him has survived, namely for the case n = 4, as described in the section § Proofs for specific exponents.

While Fermat posed the cases of n = 4 and of n = 3 as challenges to his mathematical correspondents, such as Marin Mersenne, Blaise Pascal, and John Wallis, he never posed the general case. Moreover, in the last thirty years of his life, Fermat never again wrote of his "truly marvelous proof" of the general case, and never published it. Van der Poorten suggests that while the absence of a proof is insignificant, the lack of challenges means Fermat realised he did not have a proof; he quotes Weil as saying Fermat must have briefly deluded himself with an irretrievable idea. The techniques Fermat might have used in such a "marvelous proof" are unknown.

Wiles and Taylor's proof relies on 20th-century techniques. Fermat's proof would have had to be elementary by comparison, given the mathematical knowledge of his time.

While Harvey Friedman's grand conjecture implies that any provable theorem (including Fermat's last theorem) can be proved using only 'elementary function arithmetic', such a proof need be 'elementary' only in a technical sense and could involve millions of steps, and thus be far too long to have been Fermat's proof.

Proofs for specific exponents

Main article: Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for specific exponents
Fermat's infinite descent for Fermat's Last Theorem case n=4 in the 1670 edition of the Arithmetica of Diophantus (pp. 338–339).

Exponent = 4

Only one relevant proof by Fermat has survived, in which he uses the technique of infinite descent to show that the area of a right triangle with integer sides can never equal the square of an integer. His proof is equivalent to demonstrating that the equation

x 4 y 4 = z 2 {\displaystyle x^{4}-y^{4}=z^{2}}

has no primitive solutions in integers (no pairwise coprime solutions). In turn, this proves Fermat's Last Theorem for the case n = 4, since the equation a + b = c can be written as cb = (a).

Alternative proofs of the case n = 4 were developed later by Frénicle de Bessy (1676), Leonhard Euler (1738), Kausler (1802), Peter Barlow (1811), Adrien-Marie Legendre (1830), Schopis (1825), Olry Terquem (1846), Joseph Bertrand (1851), Victor Lebesgue (1853, 1859, 1862), Théophile Pépin (1883), Tafelmacher (1893), David Hilbert (1897), Bendz (1901), Gambioli (1901), Leopold Kronecker (1901), Bang (1905), Sommer (1907), Bottari (1908), Karel Rychlík (1910), Nutzhorn (1912), Robert Carmichael (1913), Hancock (1931), Gheorghe Vrănceanu (1966), Grant and Perella (1999), Barbara (2007), and Dolan (2011).

Other exponents

After Fermat proved the special case n = 4, the general proof for all n required only that the theorem be established for all odd prime exponents. In other words, it was necessary to prove only that the equation a + b = c has no positive integer solutions (a, b, c) when n is an odd prime number. This follows because a solution (a, b, c) for a given n is equivalent to a solution for all the factors of n. For illustration, let n be factored into d and e, n = de. The general equation

a + b = c

implies that (a, b, c) is a solution for the exponent e

(a) + (b) = (c).

Thus, to prove that Fermat's equation has no solutions for n > 2, it would suffice to prove that it has no solutions for at least one prime factor of every n. Each integer n > 2 is divisible by 4 or by an odd prime number (or both). Therefore, Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved for all n if it could be proved for n = 4 and for all odd primes p.

In the two centuries following its conjecture (1637–1839), Fermat's Last Theorem was proved for three odd prime exponents p = 3, 5 and 7. The case p = 3 was first stated by Abu-Mahmud Khojandi (10th century), but his attempted proof of the theorem was incorrect. In 1770, Leonhard Euler gave a proof of p = 3, but his proof by infinite descent contained a major gap. However, since Euler himself had proved the lemma necessary to complete the proof in other work, he is generally credited with the first proof. Independent proofs were published by Kausler (1802), Legendre (1823, 1830), Calzolari (1855), Gabriel Lamé (1865), Peter Guthrie Tait (1872), Siegmund Günther (1878), Gambioli (1901), Krey (1909), Rychlík (1910), Stockhaus (1910), Carmichael (1915), Johannes van der Corput (1915), Axel Thue (1917), and Duarte (1944).

The case p = 5 was proved independently by Legendre and Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet around 1825. Alternative proofs were developed by Carl Friedrich Gauss (1875, posthumous), Lebesgue (1843), Lamé (1847), Gambioli (1901), Werebrusow (1905), Rychlík (1910), van der Corput (1915), and Guy Terjanian (1987).

The case p = 7 was proved by Lamé in 1839. His rather complicated proof was simplified in 1840 by Lebesgue, and still simpler proofs were published by Angelo Genocchi in 1864, 1874 and 1876. Alternative proofs were developed by Théophile Pépin (1876) and Edmond Maillet (1897).

Fermat's Last Theorem was also proved for the exponents n = 6, 10, and 14. Proofs for n = 6 were published by Kausler, Thue, Tafelmacher, Lind, Kapferer, Swift, and Breusch. Similarly, Dirichlet and Terjanian each proved the case n = 14, while Kapferer and Breusch each proved the case n = 10. Strictly speaking, these proofs are unnecessary, since these cases follow from the proofs for n = 3, 5, and 7, respectively. Nevertheless, the reasoning of these even-exponent proofs differs from their odd-exponent counterparts. Dirichlet's proof for n = 14 was published in 1832, before Lamé's 1839 proof for n = 7.

All proofs for specific exponents used Fermat's technique of infinite descent, either in its original form, or in the form of descent on elliptic curves or abelian varieties. The details and auxiliary arguments, however, were often ad hoc and tied to the individual exponent under consideration. Since they became ever more complicated as p increased, it seemed unlikely that the general case of Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved by building upon the proofs for individual exponents. Although some general results on Fermat's Last Theorem were published in the early 19th century by Niels Henrik Abel and Peter Barlow, the first significant work on the general theorem was done by Sophie Germain.

Early modern breakthroughs

Sophie Germain

In the early 19th century, Sophie Germain developed several novel approaches to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all exponents. First, she defined a set of auxiliary primes θ constructed from the prime exponent p by the equation θ = 2hp + 1, where h is any integer not divisible by three. She showed that, if no integers raised to the pth power were adjacent modulo θ (the non-consecutivity condition), then θ must divide the product xyz. Her goal was to use mathematical induction to prove that, for any given p, infinitely many auxiliary primes θ satisfied the non-consecutivity condition and thus divided xyz; since the product xyz can have at most a finite number of prime factors, such a proof would have established Fermat's Last Theorem. Although she developed many techniques for establishing the non-consecutivity condition, she did not succeed in her strategic goal. She also worked to set lower limits on the size of solutions to Fermat's equation for a given exponent p, a modified version of which was published by Adrien-Marie Legendre. As a byproduct of this latter work, she proved Sophie Germain's theorem, which verified the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem (namely, the case in which p does not divide xyz) for every odd prime exponent less than 270, and for all primes p such that at least one of 2p + 1, 4p + 1, 8p + 1, 10p + 1, 14p + 1 and 16p + 1 is prime (specially, the primes p such that 2p + 1 is prime are called Sophie Germain primes). Germain tried unsuccessfully to prove the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem for all even exponents, specifically for n = 2p, which was proved by Guy Terjanian in 1977. In 1985, Leonard Adleman, Roger Heath-Brown and Étienne Fouvry proved that the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem holds for infinitely many odd primes p.

Ernst Kummer and the theory of ideals

In 1847, Gabriel Lamé outlined a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem based on factoring the equation x + y = z in complex numbers, specifically the cyclotomic field based on the roots of the number 1. His proof failed, however, because it assumed incorrectly that such complex numbers can be factored uniquely into primes, similar to integers. This gap was pointed out immediately by Joseph Liouville, who later read a paper that demonstrated this failure of unique factorisation, written by Ernst Kummer.

Kummer set himself the task of determining whether the cyclotomic field could be generalized to include new prime numbers such that unique factorisation was restored. He succeeded in that task by developing the ideal numbers.

(It is often stated that Kummer was led to his "ideal complex numbers" by his interest in Fermat's Last Theorem; there is even a story often told that Kummer, like Lamé, believed he had proven Fermat's Last Theorem until Lejeune Dirichlet told him his argument relied on unique factorization; but the story was first told by Kurt Hensel in 1910 and the evidence indicates it likely derives from a confusion by one of Hensel's sources. Harold Edwards said the belief that Kummer was mainly interested in Fermat's Last Theorem "is surely mistaken". See the history of ideal numbers.)

Using the general approach outlined by Lamé, Kummer proved both cases of Fermat's Last Theorem for all regular prime numbers. However, he could not prove the theorem for the exceptional primes (irregular primes) that conjecturally occur approximately 39% of the time; the only irregular primes below 270 are 37, 59, 67, 101, 103, 131, 149, 157, 233, 257 and 263.

Mordell conjecture

In the 1920s, Louis Mordell posed a conjecture that implied that Fermat's equation has at most a finite number of nontrivial primitive integer solutions, if the exponent n is greater than two. This conjecture was proved in 1983 by Gerd Faltings, and is now known as Faltings's theorem.

Computational studies

In the latter half of the 20th century, computational methods were used to extend Kummer's approach to the irregular primes. In 1954, Harry Vandiver used a SWAC computer to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all primes up to 2521. By 1978, Samuel Wagstaff had extended this to all primes less than 125,000. By 1993, Fermat's Last Theorem had been proved for all primes less than four million.

However, despite these efforts and their results, no proof existed of Fermat's Last Theorem. Proofs of individual exponents by their nature could never prove the general case: even if all exponents were verified up to an extremely large number X, a higher exponent beyond X might still exist for which the claim was not true. (This had been the case with some other past conjectures, such as with Skewes' number, and it could not be ruled out in this conjecture.)

Connection with elliptic curves

The strategy that ultimately led to a successful proof of Fermat's Last Theorem arose from the "astounding" Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, proposed around 1955—which many mathematicians believed would be near to impossible to prove, and was linked in the 1980s by Gerhard Frey, Jean-Pierre Serre and Ken Ribet to Fermat's equation. By accomplishing a partial proof of this conjecture in 1994, Andrew Wiles ultimately succeeded in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, as well as leading the way to a full proof by others of what is now known as the modularity theorem.

Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture

Main article: Modularity theorem

Around 1955, Japanese mathematicians Goro Shimura and Yutaka Taniyama observed a possible link between two apparently completely distinct branches of mathematics, elliptic curves and modular forms. The resulting modularity theorem (at the time known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) states that every elliptic curve is modular, meaning that it can be associated with a unique modular form.

The link was initially dismissed as unlikely or highly speculative, but was taken more seriously when number theorist André Weil found evidence supporting it, though not proving it; as a result the conjecture was often known as the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture.

Even after gaining serious attention, the conjecture was seen by contemporary mathematicians as extraordinarily difficult or perhaps inaccessible to proof. For example, Wiles's doctoral supervisor John Coates states that it seemed "impossible to actually prove", and Ken Ribet considered himself "one of the vast majority of people who believed was completely inaccessible", adding that "Andrew Wiles was probably one of the few people on earth who had the audacity to dream that you can actually go and prove ."

Ribet's theorem for Frey curves

Main articles: Frey curve and Ribet's theorem

In 1984, Gerhard Frey noted a link between Fermat's equation and the modularity theorem, then still a conjecture. If Fermat's equation had any solution (a, b, c) for exponent p > 2, then it could be shown that the semi-stable elliptic curve (now known as a Frey-Hellegouarch)

y = x(xa)(x + b)

would have such unusual properties that it was unlikely to be modular. This would conflict with the modularity theorem, which asserted that all elliptic curves are modular. As such, Frey observed that a proof of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture might also simultaneously prove Fermat's Last Theorem. By contraposition, a disproof or refutation of Fermat's Last Theorem would disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture.

In plain English, Frey had shown that, if this intuition about his equation was correct, then any set of four numbers (a, b, c, n) capable of disproving Fermat's Last Theorem, could also be used to disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture. Therefore, if the latter were true, the former could not be disproven, and would also have to be true.

Following this strategy, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem required two steps. First, it was necessary to prove the modularity theorem, or at least to prove it for the types of elliptical curves that included Frey's equation (known as semistable elliptic curves). This was widely believed inaccessible to proof by contemporary mathematicians. Second, it was necessary to show that Frey's intuition was correct: that if an elliptic curve were constructed in this way, using a set of numbers that were a solution of Fermat's equation, the resulting elliptic curve could not be modular. Frey showed that this was plausible but did not go as far as giving a full proof. The missing piece (the so-called "epsilon conjecture", now known as Ribet's theorem) was identified by Jean-Pierre Serre who also gave an almost-complete proof and the link suggested by Frey was finally proved in 1986 by Ken Ribet.

Following Frey, Serre and Ribet's work, this was where matters stood:

  • Fermat's Last Theorem needed to be proven for all exponents n that were prime numbers.
  • The modularity theorem—if proved for semi-stable elliptic curves—would mean that all semistable elliptic curves must be modular.
  • Ribet's theorem showed that any solution to Fermat's equation for a prime number could be used to create a semistable elliptic curve that could not be modular;
  • The only way that both of these statements could be true, was if no solutions existed to Fermat's equation (because then no such curve could be created), which was what Fermat's Last Theorem said. As Ribet's Theorem was already proved, this meant that a proof of the modularity theorem would automatically prove Fermat's Last theorem was true as well.

Wiles's general proof

Main articles: Andrew Wiles and Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem
British mathematician Andrew Wiles

Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture in 1986 accomplished the first of the two goals proposed by Frey. Upon hearing of Ribet's success, Andrew Wiles, an English mathematician with a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem, and who had worked on elliptic curves, decided to commit himself to accomplishing the second half: proving a special case of the modularity theorem (then known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) for semistable elliptic curves.

Wiles worked on that task for six years in near-total secrecy, covering up his efforts by releasing prior work in small segments as separate papers and confiding only in his wife. His initial study suggested proof by induction, and he based his initial work and first significant breakthrough on Galois theory before switching to an attempt to extend horizontal Iwasawa theory for the inductive argument around 1990–91 when it seemed that there was no existing approach adequate to the problem. However, by mid-1991, Iwasawa theory also seemed to not be reaching the central issues in the problem. In response, he approached colleagues to seek out any hints of cutting-edge research and new techniques, and discovered an Euler system recently developed by Victor Kolyvagin and Matthias Flach that seemed "tailor made" for the inductive part of his proof. Wiles studied and extended this approach, which worked. Since his work relied extensively on this approach, which was new to mathematics and to Wiles, in January 1993 he asked his Princeton colleague, Nick Katz, to help him check his reasoning for subtle errors. Their conclusion at the time was that the techniques Wiles used seemed to work correctly.

By mid-May 1993, Wiles was ready to tell his wife he thought he had solved the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem, and by June he felt sufficiently confident to present his results in three lectures delivered on 21–23 June 1993 at the Isaac Newton Institute for Mathematical Sciences. Specifically, Wiles presented his proof of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture for semistable elliptic curves; together with Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture, this implied Fermat's Last Theorem. However, it became apparent during peer review that a critical point in the proof was incorrect. It contained an error in a bound on the order of a particular group. The error was caught by several mathematicians refereeing Wiles's manuscript including Katz (in his role as reviewer), who alerted Wiles on 23 August 1993.

The error would not have rendered his work worthless: each part of Wiles's work was highly significant and innovative by itself, as were the many developments and techniques he had created in the course of his work, and only one part was affected. However, without this part proved, there was no actual proof of Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles spent almost a year trying to repair his proof, initially by himself and then in collaboration with his former student Richard Taylor, without success. By the end of 1993, rumours had spread that under scrutiny, Wiles's proof had failed, but how seriously was not known. Mathematicians were beginning to pressure Wiles to disclose his work whether it was complete or not, so that the wider community could explore and use whatever he had managed to accomplish. But instead of being fixed, the problem, which had originally seemed minor, now seemed very significant, far more serious, and less easy to resolve.

Wiles states that on the morning of 19 September 1994, he was on the verge of giving up and was almost resigned to accepting that he had failed, and to publishing his work so that others could build on it and fix the error. He adds that he was having a final look to try and understand the fundamental reasons why his approach could not be made to work, when he had a sudden insight: that the specific reason why the Kolyvagin–Flach approach would not work directly also meant that his original attempts using Iwasawa theory could be made to work, if he strengthened it using his experience gained from the Kolyvagin–Flach approach. Fixing one approach with tools from the other approach would resolve the issue for all the cases that were not already proven by his refereed paper. He described later that Iwasawa theory and the Kolyvagin–Flach approach were each inadequate on their own, but together they could be made powerful enough to overcome this final hurdle.

I was sitting at my desk examining the Kolyvagin–Flach method. It wasn't that I believed I could make it work, but I thought that at least I could explain why it didn't work. Suddenly I had this incredible revelation. I realised that, the Kolyvagin–Flach method wasn't working, but it was all I needed to make my original Iwasawa theory work from three years earlier. So out of the ashes of Kolyvagin–Flach seemed to rise the true answer to the problem. It was so indescribably beautiful; it was so simple and so elegant. I couldn't understand how I'd missed it and I just stared at it in disbelief for twenty minutes. Then during the day I walked around the department, and I'd keep coming back to my desk looking to see if it was still there. It was still there. I couldn't contain myself, I was so excited. It was the most important moment of my working life. Nothing I ever do again will mean as much.

— Andrew Wiles, as quoted by Simon Singh

On 24 October 1994, Wiles submitted two manuscripts, "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem" and "Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras", the second of which was co-authored with Taylor and proved that certain conditions were met that were needed to justify the corrected step in the main paper. The two papers were vetted and published as the entirety of the May 1995 issue of the Annals of Mathematics. The proof's method of identification of a deformation ring with a Hecke algebra (now referred to as an R=T theorem) to prove modularity lifting theorems has been an influential development in algebraic number theory.

These papers established the modularity theorem for semistable elliptic curves, the last step in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, 358 years after it was conjectured.

Subsequent developments

The full Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture was finally proved by Diamond (1996), Conrad et al. (1999), and Breuil et al. (2001) who, building on Wiles's work, incrementally chipped away at the remaining cases until the full result was proved. The now fully proved conjecture became known as the modularity theorem.

Several other theorems in number theory similar to Fermat's Last Theorem also follow from the same reasoning, using the modularity theorem. For example: no cube can be written as a sum of two coprime nth powers, n ≥ 3. (The case n = 3 was already known by Euler.)

Relationship to other problems and generalizations

Fermat's Last Theorem considers solutions to the Fermat equation: a + b = c with positive integers a, b, and c and an integer n greater than 2. There are several generalizations of the Fermat equation to more general equations that allow the exponent n to be a negative integer or rational, or to consider three different exponents.

Generalized Fermat equation

The generalized Fermat equation generalizes the statement of Fermat's last theorem by considering positive integer solutions a, b, c, m, n, k satisfying

a m + b n = c k . {\displaystyle a^{m}+b^{n}=c^{k}.} 1

In particular, the exponents m, n, k need not be equal, whereas Fermat's last theorem considers the case m = n = k.

The Beal conjecture, also known as the Mauldin conjecture and the Tijdeman-Zagier conjecture, states that there are no solutions to the generalized Fermat equation in positive integers a, b, c, m, n, k with a, b, and c being pairwise coprime and all of m, n, k being greater than 2.

The Fermat–Catalan conjecture generalizes Fermat's last theorem with the ideas of the Catalan conjecture. The conjecture states that the generalized Fermat equation has only finitely many solutions (a, b, c, m, n, k) with distinct triplets of values (a, b, c), where a, b, c are positive coprime integers and m, n, k are positive integers satisfying

1 m + 1 n + 1 k < 1. {\displaystyle {\frac {1}{m}}+{\frac {1}{n}}+{\frac {1}{k}}<1.} 2

The statement is about the finiteness of the set of solutions because there are 10 known solutions.

Inverse Fermat equation

When we allow the exponent n to be the reciprocal of an integer, i.e. n = 1/m for some integer m, we have the inverse Fermat equation a + b = c. All solutions of this equation were computed by Hendrik Lenstra in 1992. In the case in which the mth roots are required to be real and positive, all solutions are given by

a = r s m {\displaystyle a=rs^{m}}
b = r t m {\displaystyle b=rt^{m}}
c = r ( s + t ) m {\displaystyle c=r(s+t)^{m}}

for positive integers r, s, t with s and t coprime.

Rational exponents

For the Diophantine equation a + b = c with n not equal to 1, Bennett, Glass, and Székely proved in 2004 for n > 2, that if n and m are coprime, then there are integer solutions if and only if 6 divides m, and a, b, and c are different complex 6th roots of the same real number.

Negative integer exponents

n = −1

All primitive integer solutions (i.e., those with no prime factor common to all of a, b, and c) to the optic equation a + b = c can be written as

a = m k + m 2 , {\displaystyle a=mk+m^{2},}
b = m k + k 2 , {\displaystyle b=mk+k^{2},}
c = m k {\displaystyle c=mk}

for positive, coprime integers m, k.

n = −2

The case n = −2 also has an infinitude of solutions, and these have a geometric interpretation in terms of right triangles with integer sides and an integer altitude to the hypotenuse. All primitive solutions to a + b = d are given by

a = ( v 2 u 2 ) ( v 2 + u 2 ) , {\displaystyle a=(v^{2}-u^{2})(v^{2}+u^{2}),}
b = 2 u v ( v 2 + u 2 ) , {\displaystyle b=2uv(v^{2}+u^{2}),}
d = 2 u v ( v 2 u 2 ) , {\displaystyle d=2uv(v^{2}-u^{2}),}

for coprime integers u, v with v > u. The geometric interpretation is that a and b are the integer legs of a right triangle and d is the integer altitude to the hypotenuse. Then the hypotenuse itself is the integer

c = ( v 2 + u 2 ) 2 , {\displaystyle c=(v^{2}+u^{2})^{2},}

so (a, b, c) is a Pythagorean triple.

n < −2

There are no solutions in integers for a + b = c for integers n < −2. If there were, the equation could be multiplied through by abc to obtain (bc) + (ac) = (ab), which is impossible by Fermat's Last Theorem.

abc conjecture

Main article: abc conjecture § Some consequences

The abc conjecture roughly states that if three positive integers a, b and c (hence the name) are coprime and satisfy a + b = c, then the radical d of abc is usually not much smaller than c. In particular, the abc conjecture in its most standard formulation implies Fermat's last theorem for n that are sufficiently large. The modified Szpiro conjecture is equivalent to the abc conjecture and therefore has the same implication. An effective version of the abc conjecture, or an effective version of the modified Szpiro conjecture, implies Fermat's Last Theorem outright.

Prizes and incorrect proofs

In 1816, and again in 1850, the French Academy of Sciences offered a prize for a general proof of Fermat's Last Theorem. In 1857, the academy awarded 3,000 francs and a gold medal to Kummer for his research on ideal numbers, although he had not submitted an entry for the prize. Another prize was offered in 1883 by the Academy of Brussels.

In 1908, the German industrialist and amateur mathematician Paul Wolfskehl bequeathed 100,000 gold marks—a large sum at the time—to the Göttingen Academy of Sciences to offer as a prize for a complete proof of Fermat's Last Theorem. On 27 June 1908, the academy published nine rules for awarding the prize. Among other things, these rules required that the proof be published in a peer-reviewed journal; the prize would not be awarded until two years after the publication; and that no prize would be given after 13 September 2007, roughly a century after the competition was begun. Wiles collected the Wolfskehl prize money, then worth $50,000, on 27 June 1997. In March 2016, Wiles was awarded the Norwegian government's Abel prize worth €600,000 for "his stunning proof of Fermat's Last Theorem by way of the modularity conjecture for semistable elliptic curves, opening a new era in number theory".

Prior to Wiles's proof, thousands of incorrect proofs were submitted to the Wolfskehl committee, amounting to roughly 10 feet (3.0 meters) of correspondence. In the first year alone (1907–1908), 621 attempted proofs were submitted, although by the 1970s, the rate of submission had decreased to roughly 3–4 attempted proofs per month. According to some claims, Edmund Landau tended to use a special preprinted form for such proofs, where the location of the first mistake was left blank to be filled by one of his graduate students. According to F. Schlichting, a Wolfskehl reviewer, most of the proofs were based on elementary methods taught in schools, and often submitted by "people with a technical education but a failed career". In the words of mathematical historian Howard Eves, "Fermat's Last Theorem has the peculiar distinction of being the mathematical problem for which the greatest number of incorrect proofs have been published."

In popular culture

Main article: Fermat's Last Theorem in fiction

The popularity of the theorem outside science has led to it being described as achieving "that rarest of mathematical accolades: A niche role in pop culture."

Czech postage stamp commemorating Wiles' proof

Arthur Porges' 1954 short story "The Devil and Simon Flagg" features a mathematician who bargains with the Devil that the latter cannot produce a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem within twenty-four hours.

In The Simpsons episode "The Wizard of Evergreen Terrace", Homer Simpson writes the equation 3987 + 4365 = 4472 on a blackboard, which appears to be a counterexample to Fermat's Last Theorem. The equation is wrong, but it appears to be correct if entered in a calculator with 10 significant figures.

In the Star Trek: The Next Generation episode "The Royale", Captain Picard states that the theorem is still unproven in the 24th century. The proof was released five years after the episode originally aired.

See also

Footnotes

  1. If the exponent n were not prime or 4, then it would be possible to write n either as a product of two smaller integers (n = PQ), in which P is a prime number greater than 2, and then a = a = (a) for each of a, b, and c. That is, an equivalent solution would also have to exist for the prime power P that is smaller than n; or else as n would be a power of 2 greater than 4, and writing n = 4Q, the same argument would hold.
  2. For example, ((j + 1)) + (j(j + 1)) = (j + 1).
  3. This elliptic curve was first suggested in the 1960s by Yves Hellegouarch [de], but he did not call attention to its non-modularity. For more details, see Hellegouarch, Yves (2001). Invitation to the Mathematics of Fermat-Wiles. Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-339251-0.

References

  1. ^ Singh, pp. 18–20
  2. ^ "Abel prize 2016 – full citation". Archived from the original on 20 May 2020. Retrieved 16 March 2016.
  3. "Science and Technology". The Guinness Book of World Records. Guinness Publishing Ltd. 1995. ISBN 9780965238304.
  4. Nigel Boston. "The Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem" (PDF). p. 5.
  5. ^ Buhler J, Crandell R, Ernvall R, Metsänkylä T (1993). "Irregular primes and cyclotomic invariants to four million". Mathematics of Computation. 61 (203). American Mathematical Society: 151–153. Bibcode:1993MaCom..61..151B. doi:10.2307/2152942. JSTOR 2152942.
  6. Singh, p. 223
  7. Singh 1997, pp. 203–205, 223, 226
  8. Singh, p. 144 quotes Wiles's reaction to this news: "I was electrified. I knew that moment that the course of my life was changing because this meant that to prove Fermat's Last Theorem all I had to do was to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. It meant that my childhood dream was now a respectable thing to work on."
  9. ^ Singh, p. 144
  10. ^ Diamond, Fred (July 1996). "On Deformation Rings and Hecke Rings". The Annals of Mathematics. 144 (1): 137–166. doi:10.2307/2118586. JSTOR 2118586.
  11. ^ Conrad, Brian; Diamond, Fred; Taylor, Richard (1999). "Modularity of certain potentially Barsotti-Tate Galois representations". Journal of the American Mathematical Society. 12 (2): 521–567. doi:10.1090/S0894-0347-99-00287-8. ISSN 0894-0347.
  12. ^ Breuil, Christophe; Conrad, Brian; Diamond, Fred; Taylor, Richard (15 May 2001). "On the modularity of elliptic curves over Q: Wild 3-adic exercises". Journal of the American Mathematical Society. 14 (4): 843–939. doi:10.1090/S0894-0347-01-00370-8. ISSN 0894-0347.
  13. Castelvecchi, Davide (15 March 2016). "Fermat's last theorem earns Andrew Wiles the Abel Prize". Nature. 531 (7594): 287. Bibcode:2016Natur.531..287C. doi:10.1038/nature.2016.19552. PMID 26983518. S2CID 4383161.
  14. British mathematician Sir Andrew Wiles gets Abel math prize – The Washington Post.
  15. 300-year-old math question solved, professor wins $700k – CNN.com.
  16. Weisstein, Eric W. "Fermat's Last Theorem". MathWorld – A Wolfram Web Resource. Retrieved 7 May 2021.
  17. Wiles, Andrew (1995). "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem" (PDF). Annals of Mathematics. 141 (3): 448. doi:10.2307/2118559. JSTOR 2118559. OCLC 37032255. Archived from the original (PDF) on 10 May 2011. Retrieved 11 August 2003. Frey's suggestion, in the notation of the following theorem, was to show that the (hypothetical) elliptic curve y = x(x + u)(xv) could not be modular.
  18. Ribet, Ken (1990). "On modular representations of Gal(Q/Q) arising from modular forms" (PDF). Inventiones Mathematicae. 100 (2): 432. Bibcode:1990InMat.100..431R. doi:10.1007/BF01231195. hdl:10338.dmlcz/147454. MR 1047143. S2CID 120614740.
  19. Stillwell J (2003). Elements of Number Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 110–112. ISBN 0-387-95587-9. Retrieved 17 March 2016.
  20. Aczel 1996, pp. 13–15
  21. Stark 1978, pp. 151–155
  22. Stark 1978, pp. 145–146
  23. Singh, pp. 50–51
  24. Stark 1978, p. 145
  25. Aczel 1996, pp. 44–45
  26. Singh, pp. 56–58
  27. Aczel 1996, pp. 14–15
  28. Stark 1978, pp. 44–47
  29. Friberg 2007, pp. 333–334
  30. ^ Dickson 1919, p. 731
  31. Singh, pp. 60–62
  32. Aczel 1996, p. 9
  33. T. Heath, Diophantus of Alexandria Second Edition, Cambridge University Press, 1910, reprinted by Dover, NY, 1964, pp. 144–145
  34. Manin & Panchishkin 2007, p. 341
  35. Singh, pp. 62–66
  36. Singh, p. 67
  37. Aczel 1996, p. 10
  38. Ribenboim, pp. 13, 24
  39. ^ van der Poorten, Notes and Remarks 1.2, p. 5
  40. André Weil (1984). Number Theory: An approach through history. From Hammurapi to Legendre. Basel, Switzerland: Birkhäuser. p. 104.
  41. BBC Documentary.
  42. Freeman L (12 May 2005). "Fermat's One Proof". Retrieved 23 May 2009.
  43. Dickson 1919, pp. 615–616
  44. ^ Aczel 1996, p. 44
  45. Ribenboim, pp. 15–24
  46. Frénicle de Bessy, Traité des Triangles Rectangles en Nombres, vol. I, 1676, Paris. Reprinted in Mém. Acad. Roy. Sci., 5, 1666–1699 (1729)
  47. Euler L (1738). "Theorematum quorundam arithmeticorum demonstrationes". Novi Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Petropolitanae. 10: 125–146.. Reprinted Opera omnia, ser. I, "Commentationes Arithmeticae", vol. I, pp. 38–58, Leipzig:Teubner (1915)
  48. ^ Kausler CF (1802). "Nova demonstratio theorematis nec summam, nec differentiam duorum cuborum cubum esse posse". Novi Acta Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae. 13: 245–253.
  49. Barlow P (1811). An Elementary Investigation of Theory of Numbers. St. Paul's Church-Yard, London: J. Johnson. pp. 144–145.
  50. ^ Legendre AM (1830). Théorie des Nombres (Volume II) (3rd ed.). Paris: Firmin Didot Frères. Reprinted in 1955 by A. Blanchard (Paris).
  51. Schopis (1825). Einige Sätze aus der unbestimmten Analytik. Gummbinnen: Programm.
  52. Terquem O (1846). "Théorèmes sur les puissances des nombres". Nouvelles Annales de Mathématiques. 5: 70–87.
  53. Bertrand J (1851). Traité Élémentaire d'Algèbre. Paris: Hachette. pp. 217–230, 395.
  54. Lebesgue VA (1853). "Résolution des équations biquadratiques z = x ± 2y, z = 2xy, 2z = x ± y". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 18: 73–86.
    Lebesgue VA (1859). Exercices d'Analyse Numérique. Paris: Leiber et Faraguet. pp. 83–84, 89.
    Lebesgue VA (1862). Introduction à la Théorie des Nombres. Paris: Mallet-Bachelier. pp. 71–73.
  55. Pepin T (1883). "Étude sur l'équation indéterminée ax + by = cz". Atti della Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei. Classe di Scienze Fisiche, Matematiche e Naturali. Rendiconti Lincei. Serie IX. Matematica e Applicazioni. 36: 34–70.
  56. A. Tafelmacher (1893). "Sobre la ecuación x + y = z". Anales de la Universidad de Chile. 84: 307–320.
  57. Hilbert D (1897). "Die Theorie der algebraischen Zahlkörper". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 4: 175–546. Reprinted in 1965 in Gesammelte Abhandlungen, vol. I by New York:Chelsea.
  58. Bendz TR (1901). Öfver diophantiska ekvationen x + y = z (Thesis). Uppsala: Almqvist & Wiksells Boktrycken.
  59. ^ Gambioli D (1901). "Memoria bibliographica sull'ultimo teorema di Fermat". Periodico di Matematiche. 16: 145–192.
  60. Kronecker L (1901). Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie, vol. I. Leipzig: Teubner. pp. 35–38. Reprinted by New York:Springer-Verlag in 1978.
  61. Bang A (1905). "Nyt Bevis for at Ligningen xy = z, ikke kan have rationale Løsinger". Nyt Tidsskrift for Matematik. 16B: 31–35. JSTOR 24528323.
  62. Sommer J (1907). Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie. Leipzig: Teubner.
  63. Bottari A (1908). "Soluzione intere dell'equazione pitagorica e applicazione alla dimostrazione di alcune teoremi della teoria dei numeri". Periodico di Matematiche. 23: 104–110.
  64. ^ Rychlik K (1910). "On Fermat's last theorem for n = 4 and n = 3 (in Bohemian)". Časopis Pro Pěstování Matematiky a Fysiky. 39: 65–86.
  65. Nutzhorn F (1912). "Den ubestemte Ligning x + y = z". Nyt Tidsskrift for Matematik. 23B: 33–38.
  66. Carmichael RD (1913). "On the impossibility of certain Diophantine equations and systems of equations". American Mathematical Monthly. 20 (7). Mathematical Association of America: 213–221. doi:10.2307/2974106. JSTOR 2974106.
  67. Hancock H (1931). Foundations of the Theory of Algebraic Numbers, vol. I. New York: Macmillan.
  68. Gheorghe Vrănceanu (1966). "Asupra teorema lui Fermat pentru n = 4". Gazeta Matematică Seria A. 71: 334–335. Reprinted in 1977 in Opera matematica, vol. 4, pp. 202–205, București: Editura Academiei Republicii Socialiste România.
  69. Grant, Mike, and Perella, Malcolm, "Descending to the irrational", Mathematical Gazette 83, July 1999, pp. 263–267.
  70. Barbara, Roy, "Fermat's last theorem in the case n = 4", Mathematical Gazette 91, July 2007, 260–262.
  71. Dolan, Stan, "Fermat's method of descente infinie", Mathematical Gazette 95, July 2011, 269–271.
  72. Ribenboim, pp. 1–2
  73. Dickson 1919, p. 545
  74. O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F. "Abu Mahmud Hamid ibn al-Khidr Al-Khujandi". MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. University of St Andrews.
  75. Euler L (1770) Vollständige Anleitung zur Algebra, Roy. Acad. Sci., St. Petersburg.
  76. Freeman L (22 May 2005). "Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 3". Retrieved 23 May 2009.
  77. Ribenboim, pp. 24–25
  78. Mordell 1921, pp. 6–8
  79. Edwards 1996, pp. 39–40
  80. Edwards 1996, pp. 40, 52–54
  81. J. J. Mačys (2007). "On Euler's hypothetical proof". Mathematical Notes. 82 (3–4): 352–356. doi:10.1134/S0001434607090088. MR 2364600. S2CID 121798358.
  82. Ribenboim, pp. 33, 37–41
  83. Legendre AM (1823). "Recherches sur quelques objets d'analyse indéterminée, et particulièrement sur le théorème de Fermat". Mémoires de l'Académie royale des sciences. 6: 1–60. Reprinted in 1825 as the "Second Supplément" for a printing of the 2nd edition of Essai sur la Théorie des Nombres, Courcier (Paris). Also reprinted in 1909 in Sphinx-Oedipe, 4, 97–128.
  84. Calzolari L (1855). Tentativo per dimostrare il teorema di Fermat sull'equazione indeterminata x + y = z. Ferrara.
  85. Lamé G (1865). "Étude des binômes cubiques x ± y". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 61: 921–924, 961–965.
  86. Tait PG (1872). "Mathematical Notes". Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. 7: 144. doi:10.1017/s0370164600041857.
  87. Günther, S. (1878). "Ueber die unbestimmte Gleichung x + y = a". Sitzungsberichte der Königliche böhmische Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften in Prag. jahrg. 1878-1880: 112–120.
  88. Krey, H. (1909). "Neuer Beweis eines arithmetischen Satzes". Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Blätter. 6 (12): 179–180.
  89. Stockhaus H (1910). Beitrag zum Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes. Leipzig: Brandstetter.
  90. Carmichael RD (1915). Diophantine Analysis. New York: Wiley.
  91. ^ van der Corput JG (1915). "Quelques formes quadratiques et quelques équations indéterminées". Nieuw Archief voor Wiskunde. 11: 45–75.
  92. Thue, Axel (1917). "Et bevis for at ligningen A + B = C er unmulig i hele tal fra nul forskjellige tal A, B og C". Archiv for Mathematik og Naturvidenskab. 34 (15): 3–7. Reprinted in Selected Mathematical Papers (1977), Oslo: Universitetsforlaget, pp. 555–559
  93. Duarte FJ (1944). "Sobre la ecuación x + y + z = 0". Boletín de la Academia de Ciencias Físicas, Matemáticas y Naturales (Caracas). 8: 971–979.
  94. Freeman L (28 October 2005). "Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 5". Retrieved 23 May 2009.
  95. Ribenboim, p. 49
  96. Mordell 1921, pp. 8–9
  97. ^ Singh, p. 106
  98. Ribenboim, pp. 55–57
  99. Gauss CF (1875). "Neue Theorie der Zerlegung der Cuben". Zur Theorie der complexen Zahlen, Werke, vol. II (2nd ed.). Königl. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen. pp. 387–391. (Published posthumously)
  100. Lebesgue VA (1843). "Théorèmes nouveaux sur l'équation indéterminée x + y = az". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 8: 49–70.
  101. Lamé G (1847). "Mémoire sur la résolution en nombres complexes de l'équation A + B + C = 0". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 12: 137–171.
  102. Gambioli D (1903–1904). "Intorno all'ultimo teorema di Fermat". Il Pitagora. 10: 11–13, 41–42.
  103. Werebrusow AS (1905). "On the equation x + y = Az (in Russian)". Moskov. Math. Samml. 25: 466–473.
  104. Rychlik K (1910). "On Fermat's last theorem for n = 5 (in Bohemian)". Časopis Pěst. Mat. 39: 185–195, 305–317.
  105. Terjanian G (1987). "Sur une question de V. A. Lebesgue". Annales de l'Institut Fourier. 37 (3): 19–37. doi:10.5802/aif.1096.
  106. Ribenboim, pp. 57–63
  107. Mordell 1921, p. 8
  108. Lamé G (1839). "Mémoire sur le dernier théorème de Fermat". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 9: 45–46.
    Lamé G (1840). "Mémoire d'analyse indéterminée démontrant que l'équation x + y = z est impossible en nombres entiers". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 5: 195–211.
  109. Lebesgue VA (1840). "Démonstration de l'impossibilité de résoudre l'équation x + y + z = 0 en nombres entiers". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 5: 276–279, 348–349.
  110. Freeman L (18 January 2006). "Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 7". Retrieved 23 May 2009.
  111. Genocchi A (1864). "Intorno all'equazioni x + y + z = 0". Annali di Matematica Pura ed Applicata. 6: 287–288. doi:10.1007/bf03198884. S2CID 124916552.
    Genocchi A (1874). "Sur l'impossibilité de quelques égalités doubles". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 78: 433–436.
    Genocchi A (1876). "Généralisation du théorème de Lamé sur l'impossibilité de l'équation x + y + z = 0". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 82: 910–913.
  112. Pepin T (1876). "Impossibilité de l'équation x + y + z = 0". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 82: 676–679, 743–747.
  113. Maillet E (1897). "Sur l'équation indéterminée ax + by = cz". Association française pour l'avancement des sciences, St. Etienne, Compte Rendu de la 26me Session, deuxième partie. 26: 156–168.
  114. Thue A (1896). "Über die Auflösbarkeit einiger unbestimmter Gleichungen". Det Kongelige Norske Videnskabers Selskabs Skrifter. 7. Reprinted in Selected Mathematical Papers, pp. 19–30, Oslo: Universitetsforlaget (1977).
  115. Tafelmacher WLA (1897). "La ecuación x + y = z: Una demonstración nueva del teorema de fermat para el caso de las sestas potencias". Anales de la Universidad de Chile. 97: 63–80.
  116. Lind B (1909). "Einige zahlentheoretische Sätze". Archiv der Mathematik und Physik. 15: 368–369.
  117. ^ Kapferer H (1913). "Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes für die Exponenten 6 und 10". Archiv der Mathematik und Physik. 21: 143–146.
  118. Swift E (1914). "Solution to Problem 206". American Mathematical Monthly. 21 (7): 238–239. doi:10.2307/2972379. JSTOR 2972379.
  119. ^ Breusch R (1960). "A simple proof of Fermat's last theorem for n = 6, n = 10". Mathematics Magazine. 33 (5): 279–281. doi:10.2307/3029800. JSTOR 3029800.
  120. Dirichlet PGL (1832). "Démonstration du théorème de Fermat pour le cas des 14 puissances". Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik. 9: 390–393. Reprinted in Werke, vol. I, pp. 189–194, Berlin: G. Reimer (1889); reprinted New York:Chelsea (1969).
  121. Terjanian G (1974). "L'équation x + y = z en nombres entiers". Bulletin des Sciences Mathématiques. Série 2. 98: 91–95.
  122. Edwards 1996, pp. 73–74
  123. ^ Edwards 1996, p. 74
  124. Dickson 1919, p. 733
  125. Ribenboim P (1979). 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem. New York: Springer Verlag. pp. 51–54. ISBN 978-0-387-90432-0.
  126. Singh, pp. 97–109
  127. ^ Laubenbacher R, Pengelley D (2007). "Voici ce que j'ai trouvé: Sophie Germain's grand plan to prove Fermat's Last Theorem" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 5 April 2013. Retrieved 19 May 2009.
  128. Aczel 1996, p. 57
  129. Terjanian, G. (1977). "Sur l'équation x + y = z". Comptes Rendus de l'Académie des Sciences, Série A-B. 285: 973–975.
  130. Adleman LM, Heath-Brown DR (June 1985). "The first case of Fermat's last theorem". Inventiones Mathematicae. 79 (2). Berlin: Springer: 409–416. Bibcode:1985InMat..79..409A. doi:10.1007/BF01388981. S2CID 122537472.
  131. Edwards 1996, p. 79
  132. Aczel 1996, pp. 84–88
  133. Singh, pp. 232–234
  134. Faltings G (1983). "Endlichkeitssätze für abelsche Varietäten über Zahlkörpern". Inventiones Mathematicae. 73 (3): 349–366. Bibcode:1983InMat..73..349F. doi:10.1007/BF01388432. S2CID 121049418.
  135. Ribenboim P (1979). 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem. New York: Springer Verlag. p. 202. ISBN 978-0-387-90432-0.
  136. Wagstaff SS Jr. (1978). "The irregular primes to 125000". Mathematics of Computation. 32 (142). American Mathematical Society: 583–591. doi:10.2307/2006167. JSTOR 2006167. (PDF) Archived 24 October 2012 at the Wayback Machine
  137. ^ Fermat's Last Theorem, Simon Singh, 1997, ISBN 1-85702-521-0
  138. Frey G (1986). "Links between stable elliptic curves and certain diophantine equations". Annales Universitatis Saraviensis. Series Mathematicae. 1: 1–40.
  139. Singh, pp. 194–198
  140. Aczel 1996, pp. 109–114
  141. Ribet, Ken (1990). "On modular representations of Gal(Q/Q) arising from modular forms" (PDF). Inventiones Mathematicae. 100 (2): 431–476. Bibcode:1990InMat.100..431R. doi:10.1007/BF01231195. hdl:10338.dmlcz/147454. MR 1047143. S2CID 120614740.
  142. Singh, p. 205
  143. Aczel 1996, pp. 117–118
  144. Singh, pp. 237–238
  145. Aczel 1996, pp. 121–122
  146. Singh, pp. 239–243
  147. Aczel 1996, pp. 122–125
  148. Singh, pp. 244–253
  149. Aczel 1996, pp. 1–4, 126–128
  150. Aczel 1996, pp. 128–130
  151. Singh, p. 257
  152. ^ Singh, pp. 269–277
  153. A Year Later, Snag Persists In Math Proof 28 June 1994
  154. 26 June – 2 July; A Year Later Fermat's Puzzle Is Still Not Quite Q.E.D. 3 July 1994
  155. Singh, pp. 175–185
  156. Aczel 1996, pp. 132–134
  157. Singh p. 186–187 (text condensed)
  158. Wiles, Andrew (1995). "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem" (PDF). Annals of Mathematics. 141 (3): 443–551. doi:10.2307/2118559. JSTOR 2118559. OCLC 37032255. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 June 2003.
  159. "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem" (PDF).
  160. Taylor R, Wiles A (1995). "Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras". Annals of Mathematics. 141 (3): 553–572. doi:10.2307/2118560. JSTOR 2118560. OCLC 37032255. Archived from the original on 27 November 2001.
  161. ^ Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre; Gowers, Timothy (2008). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 361–362. ISBN 9781400830398.
  162. "Mauldin / Tijdeman-Zagier Conjecture". Prime Puzzles. Retrieved 1 October 2016.
  163. Elkies, Noam D. (2007). "The ABC's of Number Theory" (PDF). The Harvard College Mathematics Review. 1 (1).
  164. Michel Waldschmidt (2004). "Open Diophantine Problems". Moscow Mathematical Journal. 4: 245–305. arXiv:math/0312440. doi:10.17323/1609-4514-2004-4-1-245-305. S2CID 11845578.
  165. Crandall, Richard; Pomerance, Carl (2000). Prime Numbers: A Computational Perspective. Springer. p. 417. ISBN 978-0387-25282-7.
  166. "Beal Conjecture". American Mathematical Society. Retrieved 21 August 2016.
  167. Cai, Tianxin; Chen, Deyi; Zhang, Yong (2015). "A new generalization of Fermat's Last Theorem". Journal of Number Theory. 149: 33–45. arXiv:1310.0897. doi:10.1016/j.jnt.2014.09.014. S2CID 119732583.
  168. Mihailescu, Preda (2007). "A Cyclotomic Investigation of the Catalan–Fermat Conjecture". Mathematica Gottingensis.
  169. Lenstra Jr. H.W. (1992). "On the inverse Fermat equation". Discrete Mathematics. 106–107: 329–331. doi:10.1016/0012-365x(92)90561-s.
  170. Newman M (1981). "A radical diophantine equation". Journal of Number Theory. 13 (4): 495–498. doi:10.1016/0022-314x(81)90040-8.
  171. Bennett, Curtis D.; Glass, A. M. W.; Székely, Gábor J. (2004). "Fermat's last theorem for rational exponents". American Mathematical Monthly. 111 (4): 322–329. doi:10.2307/4145241. JSTOR 4145241. MR 2057186.
  172. Dickson 1919, pp. 688–691
  173. Voles, Roger (July 1999). "Integer solutions of a + b = d". Mathematical Gazette. 83 (497): 269–271. doi:10.2307/3619056. JSTOR 3619056. S2CID 123267065.
  174. Richinick, Jennifer (July 2008). "The upside-down Pythagorean Theorem". Mathematical Gazette. 92: 313–317. doi:10.1017/S0025557200183275. S2CID 125989951.
  175. Lang, Serge (2002). Algebra. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Vol. 211. Springer-Verlag New York. p. 196.
  176. Elkies, Noam (1991). "ABC implies Mordell". International Mathematics Research Notices. 1991 (7): 99–109. doi:10.1155/S1073792891000144. Our proof generalizes the known implication "effective ABC eventual Fermat" which was the original motivation for the ABC conjecture
  177. ^ Granville, Andrew; Tucker, Thomas (2002). "It's As Easy As abc" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 49 (10): 1224–1231.
  178. Oesterlé, Joseph (1988). "Nouvelles approches du "théorème" de Fermat". Astérisque. Séminaire Bourbaki exp 694 (161): 165–186. ISSN 0303-1179. MR 0992208.
  179. ^ Aczel 1996, p. 69
  180. Singh, p. 105
  181. ^ Koshy T (2001). Elementary number theory with applications. New York: Academic Press. p. 544. ISBN 978-0-12-421171-1.
  182. Singh, pp. 120–125, 131–133, 295–296
  183. Aczel 1996, p. 70
  184. Singh, pp. 120–125
  185. Singh, p. 284
  186. "The Abel Prize citation 2016". The Abel Prize. The Abel Prize Committee. March 2016. Archived from the original on 20 May 2020. Retrieved 16 March 2016.
  187. Singh, p. 295
  188. Wheels, Life and Other Mathematical Amusements, Martin Gardner
  189. Singh, pp. 295–296
  190. Garmon, Jay (21 February 2006). "Geek Trivia: The math behind the myth". TechRepublic. Retrieved 21 May 2022.
  191. Kasman, Alex (January 2003). "Mathematics in Fiction: An Interdisciplinary Course". PRIMUS. 13 (1): 1–16. doi:10.1080/10511970308984042. ISSN 1051-1970. S2CID 122365046.
  192. Singh, Simon (2013). The Simpsons and Their Mathematical Secrets. A&C Black. pp. 35–36. ISBN 978-1-4088-3530-2.
  193. Moseman, Andrew (1 September 2017). "Here's a Fun Math Goof in 'Star Trek: The Next Generation'". Popular Mechanics. Retrieved 9 June 2023.

Bibliography

Further reading

External links

Pierre de Fermat
Work
Related
Categories: