Misplaced Pages

Recursion: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 14:07, 28 May 2002 view sourceBoleslav Bobcik (talk | contribs)171 edits added some information← Previous edit Latest revision as of 09:29, 14 December 2024 view source Outcome0970 (talk | contribs)64 edits Undid revision 1263036308 by Outcome0970 (talk)Tags: Undo Mobile edit Mobile web edit 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Process of repeating items in a self-similar way}}
'''Recursion''' is a way of specifying a process by means of itself. More precisely (and to dispel the appearance of circularity in the definition), "complicated" instances of the process are defined in terms of "simpler" instances, and the "simplest" instances are given explicitly.
{{Other uses}}
{{pp-vandalism|small=yes}}
<!-- Making the Recursion article link to itself will not display correctly, and is considered to break ]. The joke itself is already featured in the "Recursive humor" section. See discussion on the talk page. -->


]. The woman in this image holds an object that contains a smaller image of her holding an identical object, which in turn contains a smaller image of herself holding an identical object, and so forth. 1904 Droste ] tin, designed by Jan Misset.]]
Examples of mathematical objects often defined recursively are ]s and ]s.


'''Recursion''' occurs when the definition of a concept or process depends on a simpler or previous version of itself.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Causey |first=Robert L. |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/62093042 |title=Logic, sets, and recursion |date=2006 |publisher=Jones and Bartlett Publishers |isbn=0-7637-3784-4 |edition=2nd|location=Sudbury, Mass. |oclc=62093042}}</ref> Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from ] to ]. The most common application of recursion is in ] and ], where a ] being defined is applied within its own definition. While this apparently defines an infinite number of instances (function values), it is often done in such a way that no infinite loop or infinite chain of references can occur.
The canonical example of a recursively defined function is
the following definition of the ] function:


A process that exhibits recursion is ''recursive''. ] displays recursive images, as does an ].
:0! = 1
:''n''! = ''n'' * (''n''-1)!&nbsp;&nbsp; for any ] ''n''>0


==Formal definitions==
Therefore, given this definition, we work out 3! as follows:
], an ancient symbol depicting a serpent or dragon eating its own tail]]
In mathematics and computer science, a class of objects or methods exhibits recursive behavior when it can be defined by two properties:
* {{anchor|base case}}A simple ''base case'' (or cases) — a terminating scenario that does not use recursion to produce an answer
* {{anchor|recursive step}}A ''recursive step'' — a set of rules that reduces all successive cases toward the base case.


For example, the following is a recursive definition of a person's ''ancestor''. One's ancestor is either:
3! = 3 * (3-1)!
*One's parent (''base case''), ''or''
= 3 * 2!
*One's parent's ancestor (''recursive step'').
= 3 * 2 * (2-1)!
= 3 * 2 * 1!
= 3 * 2 * 1 * (1 - 1)!
= 3 * 2 * 1 * 1
= 6


The ] is another classic example of recursion:
Another example is the definition of ].


:{{math|1=Fib(0) = 0}} as base case 1,
In ] there is a theorem guaranteeing that such functions exist.


:{{math|1=Fib(1) = 1}} as base case 2,
'''The recursion theorem.''' Given a set ''X'', an element ''a'' of ''X'' and a function ''f'':''X''->''X'', then there is a unique function ''F'':'''N'''->''X'' such that
:''F''(0)=''a'', and
:''F''(''n''+1)=''f''(''F''(''n''))&nbsp;&nbsp; for any natural number ''n''>0.


:For all ]s {{math|''n'' > 1}}, {{math|1=Fib(''n'') = Fib(''n'' − 1) + Fib(''n'' − 2)}}.
''''


Many mathematical axioms are based upon recursive rules. For example, the formal definition of the ]s by the ] can be described as: "Zero is a natural number, and each natural number has a successor, which is also a natural number."<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/science/Peano-axioms|title=Peano axioms {{!}} mathematics|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> By this base case and recursive rule, one can generate the set of all natural numbers.
The canonical example of a recursively defined set is the ]:


Other recursively defined mathematical objects include ]s, ]s (e.g., ]s), ] (e.g., ]), and ]s.
:0 is in '''N'''
:if ''n'' is in '''N''', then ''n''+1 is in '''N'''


There are various more tongue-in-cheek definitions of recursion; see ].
The natural numbers can be defined as the smallest set satisfying the definition.


==Informal definition==
Another interesting example is the set of all true propositions in an ].
] being stirred into flour to produce sourdough: the recipe calls for some sourdough left over from the last time the same recipe was made.]]


Recursion is the process a procedure goes through when one of the steps of the procedure involves invoking the procedure itself. A procedure that goes through recursion is said to be 'recursive'.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/recursive|title=Definition of RECURSIVE|website=www.merriam-webster.com|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref>
:if a proposition is an axiom, it is true.
:if a proposition can be obtained from true propositions by means of inference rules, it is true.


To understand recursion, one must recognize the distinction between a procedure and the running of a procedure. A procedure is a set of steps based on a set of rules, while the running of a procedure involves actually following the rules and performing the steps.
''''


Recursion is related to, but not the same as, a reference within the specification of a procedure to the execution of some other procedure.
Here is another, perhaps simpler way to understand recursive processes:


When a procedure is thus defined, this immediately creates the possibility of an endless loop; recursion can only be properly used in a definition if the step in question is skipped in certain cases so that the procedure can complete.
#Are we done yet? If so, return the results.<br>
#If not, ''simplify'' the problem and send it to 1.<br>


Even if it is properly defined, a recursive procedure is not easy for humans to perform, as it requires distinguishing the new from the old, partially executed invocation of the procedure; this requires some administration as to how far various simultaneous instances of the procedures have progressed. For this reason, recursive definitions are very rare in everyday situations.
Common method of the simplification is to divide the problem into subproblems. Such programming technique is called ''divide-et-impera'' and is a fundamental part of ].


==In language==
Virtually all ] in use today allow the direct specification of recursive functions and procedures. When such a function is called, the computer keeps track of the various instances of the function by using a ]. Conversely, every recursive program can be transformed into an interative program by using a stack.
Linguist ], among many others, has argued that the lack of an upper bound on the number of grammatical sentences in a language, and the lack of an upper bound on grammatical sentence length (beyond practical constraints such as the time available to utter one), can be explained as the consequence of recursion in natural language.<ref>{{cite book|last=Pinker|first=Steven|title=The Language Instinct|year=1994|publisher=William Morrow}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | doi = 10.1016/j.cognition.2004.08.004 | title = The faculty of language: What's so special about it? | year = 2005 | last1 = Pinker | first1=Steven | last2 = Jackendoff | first2=Ray | journal = Cognition | volume = 95 | issue = 2 | pages = 201–236 | pmid=15694646| citeseerx = 10.1.1.116.7784 | s2cid = 1599505 }}</ref>


This can be understood in terms of a recursive definition of a syntactic category, such as a sentence. A sentence can have a structure in which what follows the verb is another sentence: ''Dorothy thinks witches are dangerous'', in which the sentence ''witches are dangerous'' occurs in the larger one. So a sentence can be defined recursively (very roughly) as something with a structure that includes a noun phrase, a verb, and optionally another sentence. This is really just a special case of the mathematical definition of recursion.
Any function that can be evaluated by a computer can be expressed in terms of recursive functions, without use of ].
Indeed, some languages designed for ] and ] provide recursion as the only means of repetition ''directly'' available to the programmer.
Such languages generally make ] as efficient as iteration, letting programmers express other repetition structures (such as ] <code>map</code> and <code>for</code>) in terms of recursion.


This provides a way of understanding the creativity of language—the unbounded number of grammatical sentences—because it immediately predicts that sentences can be of arbitrary length: ''Dorothy thinks that Toto suspects that Tin Man said that...''. There are many structures apart from sentences that can be defined recursively, and therefore many ways in which a sentence can embed instances of one category inside another.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.thoughtco.com/recursion-grammar-1691901|title=What Is Recursion in English Grammar?|last=Nordquist|first=Richard|website=ThoughtCo|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> Over the years, languages in general have proved amenable to this kind of analysis.
Recursion is deeply embedded in the ], with the theoretical equivalence of ]s and ]s at the foundation of ideas about the universality of the modern computer.


The generally accepted idea that recursion is an essential property of human language has been challenged by ] on the basis of his claims about the ]. Andrew Nevins, David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues are among many who have argued against this.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1353/lan.0.0140 |title=Evidence and argumentation: A reply to Everett (2009) |url=http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/Nevins_Pesetsky_Rodrigues_2_Evidence_and_Argumentation_Reply_to_Everett.pdf |year=2009 |last1=Nevins |first1=Andrew |last2=Pesetsky |first2=David |last3=Rodrigues |first3=Cilene |journal=Language |volume=85 |issue=3 |pages=671–681 |s2cid=16915455 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120106154616/http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/Nevins_Pesetsky_Rodrigues_2_Evidence_and_Argumentation_Reply_to_Everett.pdf |archive-date=2012-01-06}}</ref> Literary ] can in any case be argued to be different in kind from mathematical or logical recursion.<ref name="Drucker2008">{{cite book |last=Drucker|first=Thomas |title=Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R70M4zsVgREC&pg=PA110 |date=4 January 2008 |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |isbn=978-0-8176-4768-1 |page=110}}</ref>
See also:

* ]
Recursion plays a crucial role not only in syntax, but also in ]. The word ''and'', for example, can be construed as a function that can apply to sentence meanings to create new sentences, and likewise for noun phrase meanings, verb phrase meanings, and others. It can also apply to intransitive verbs, transitive verbs, or ditransitive verbs. In order to provide a single denotation for it that is suitably flexible, ''and'' is typically defined so that it can take any of these different types of meanings as arguments. This can be done by defining it for a simple case in which it combines sentences, and then defining the other cases recursively in terms of the simple one.<ref>Barbara Partee and Mats Rooth. 1983. In Rainer Bäuerle et al., ''Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language''. Reprinted in Paul Portner and Barbara Partee, eds. 2002. ''Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings''. Blackwell.</ref>
* ]

* ]
A ] is a ] that contains recursive ].<ref name="ns02">{{citation
| last1 = Nederhof | first1 = Mark-Jan
| last2 = Satta | first2 = Giorgio
| contribution = Parsing Non-recursive Context-free Grammars
| doi = 10.3115/1073083.1073104
| location = Stroudsburg, PA, USA
| pages = 112–119
| publisher = Association for Computational Linguistics
| title = Proceedings of the 40th Annual Meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics (ACL '02)
| year = 2002| doi-access = free
}}.</ref>

===Recursive humor===
Recursion is sometimes used humorously in computer science, programming, philosophy, or mathematics textbooks, generally by giving a ] or ], in which the putative recursive step does not get closer to a base case, but instead leads to an ]. It is not unusual for such books to include a joke entry in their glossary along the lines of:
:Recursion, ''see Recursion''.<ref name=Hunter>{{cite book|last=Hunter|first=David|title=Essentials of Discrete Mathematics|year=2011|publisher=Jones and Bartlett|pages=494|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kuwhTxCVovQC&q=recursion+joke|isbn=9781449604424}}</ref>

A variation is found on page 269 in the ] of some editions of ] and ]'s book '']''; the index entry recursively references itself ("recursion 86, 139, 141, 182, 202, 269"). Early versions of this joke can be found in ''Let's talk Lisp'' by Laurent Siklóssy (published by Prentice Hall PTR on December 1, 1975, with a copyright date of 1976) and in ''Software Tools'' by Kernighan and Plauger (published by Addison-Wesley Professional on January 11, 1976). The joke also appears in ''The UNIX Programming Environment'' by Kernighan and Pike. It did not appear in the first edition of ''The C Programming Language''. The joke is part of the ] folklore and was already widespread in the functional programming community before the publication of the aforementioned books. <ref name="Grainger College">{{cite web |last1=Shaffer |first1=Eric |title=CS 173:Discrete Structures |url=https://courses.engr.illinois.edu/cs173/sp2009/Lectures/lect_19.pdf |publisher=University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign |access-date=7 July 2023}}</ref> <ref name="Columbia University">{{cite web |title=Introduction to Computer Science and Programming in C; Session 8: September 25, 2008 |url=http://www.cs.columbia.edu/~bert/courses/1003/lecture8.pdf |publisher=Columbia University |access-date=7 July 2023}}</ref>

]

Another joke is that "To understand recursion, you must understand recursion."<ref name=Hunter/> In the English-language version of the Google web search engine, when a search for "recursion" is made, the site suggests "Did you mean: ''recursion''."<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.google.com/search?q=recursion|title=recursion - Google Search|website=www.google.com|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> An alternative form is the following, from ]: ''"If you already know what recursion is, just remember the answer. Otherwise, find someone who is standing closer to ] than you are; then ask him or her what recursion is."''

]s are other examples of recursive humor. ], for example, stands for "PHP Hypertext Preprocessor", ] stands for "WINE Is Not an Emulator", ] stands for "GNU's not Unix", and ] denotes the "SPARQL Protocol and RDF Query Language".

==In mathematics==
]—a confined recursion of triangles that form a fractal]]

===Recursively defined sets===
{{Main|Recursive definition}}

====Example: the natural numbers====
{{See also|Closure (mathematics)}}
The canonical example of a recursively defined set is given by the ]:

:0 is in <math>\mathbb{N}</math>
:if ''n'' is in <math>\mathbb{N}</math>, then ''n'' + 1 is in <math>\mathbb{N}</math>
:The set of natural numbers is the smallest set satisfying the previous two properties.

In mathematical logic, the ] (or Peano postulates or Dedekind–Peano axioms), are axioms for the natural numbers presented in the 19th century by the German mathematician ] and by the Italian mathematician ]. The Peano Axioms define the natural numbers referring to a recursive successor function and addition and multiplication as recursive functions.

====Example: Proof procedure ====
Another interesting example is the set of all "provable" propositions in an ] that are defined in terms of a ] which is inductively (or recursively) defined as follows:

*If a proposition is an axiom, it is a provable proposition.
*If a proposition can be derived from true reachable propositions by means of inference rules, it is a provable proposition.
*The set of provable propositions is the smallest set of propositions satisfying these conditions.

===Finite subdivision rules===
{{Main|Finite subdivision rule}}
Finite subdivision rules are a geometric form of recursion, which can be used to create fractal-like images. A subdivision rule starts with a collection of polygons labelled by finitely many labels, and then each polygon is subdivided into smaller labelled polygons in a way that depends only on the labels of the original polygon. This process can be iterated. The standard `middle thirds' technique for creating the ] is a subdivision rule, as is ].

===Functional recursion===
A ] may be recursively defined in terms of itself. A familiar example is the ] sequence: ''F''(''n'') = ''F''(''n'' − 1) + ''F''(''n'' − 2). For such a definition to be useful, it must be reducible to non-recursively defined values: in this case ''F''(0) = 0 and ''F''(1) = 1.

===Proofs involving recursive definitions===
Applying the standard technique of ] to recursively defined sets or functions, as in the preceding sections, yields ] — a powerful generalization of ] widely used to derive proofs in ] and computer science.

===Recursive optimization===
] is an approach to ] that restates a multiperiod or multistep optimization problem in recursive form. The key result in dynamic programming is the ], which writes the value of the optimization problem at an earlier time (or earlier step) in terms of its value at a later time (or later step).

===The recursion theorem===
In ], this is a theorem guaranteeing that recursively defined functions exist. Given a set {{mvar|X}}, an element {{mvar|a}} of {{mvar|X}} and a function {{math|''f'': ''X'' → ''X''}}, the theorem states that there is a unique function <math>F: \N \to X</math> (where <math>\N</math> denotes the set of natural numbers including zero) such that
:<math>F(0) = a</math>
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math>
for any natural number {{mvar|n}}.

Dedekind was the first to pose the problem of unique definition of set-theoretical functions on <math>\mathbb N</math> by recursion, and gave a sketch of an argument in the 1888 essay "Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?" <ref>A. Kanamori, "", pp.50--52. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 18, no. 1 (2012). Accessed 21 August 2023.</ref>

====Proof of uniqueness====
Take two functions <math>F: \N \to X</math> and <math>G: \N \to X</math> such that:

:<math>F(0) = a</math>
:<math>G(0) = a</math>
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math>
:<math>G(n + 1) = f(G(n))</math>

where {{mvar|a}} is an element of {{mvar|X}}.

It can be proved by ] that {{math|1=''F''(''n'') = ''G''(''n'')}} for all natural numbers
{{mvar|n}}:

:'''Base Case''': {{math|1=''F''(0) = ''a'' = ''G''(0)}} so the equality holds for {{math|1=''n'' = 0}}.

:'''Inductive Step''': Suppose {{math|1=''F''(''k'') = ''G''(''k'')}} for some {{nowrap|<math>k \in \N</math>.}} Then {{math|1=''F''(''k'' + 1) = ''f''(''F''(''k'')) = ''f''(''G''(''k'')) = ''G''(''k'' + 1)}}.
::Hence {{math|1=''F''(''k'') = ''G''(''k'')}} implies {{math|1=''F''(''k'' + 1) = ''G''(''k'' + 1)}}.

By induction, {{math|1=''F''(''n'') = ''G''(''n'')}} for all <math>n \in \N</math>.

==In computer science==
{{Main|Recursion (computer science)}}
A common method of simplification is to divide a problem into subproblems of the same type. As a ] technique, this is called ] and is key to the design of many important algorithms. Divide and conquer serves as a top-down approach to problem solving, where problems are solved by solving smaller and smaller instances. A contrary approach is ]. This approach serves as a bottom-up approach, where problems are solved by solving larger and larger instances, until the desired size is reached.

A classic example of recursion is the definition of the ] function, given here in ] code:

<syntaxhighlight lang="python3">def factorial(n):
if n > 0:
return n * factorial(n - 1)
else:
return 1
</syntaxhighlight>

The function calls itself recursively on a smaller version of the input {{code|(n - 1)}} and multiplies the result of the recursive call by {{code|n}}, until reaching the ], analogously to the mathematical definition of factorial.

Recursion in computer programming is exemplified when a function is defined in terms of simpler, often smaller versions of itself. The solution to the problem is then devised by combining the solutions obtained from the simpler versions of the problem. One example application of recursion is in ]s for programming languages. The great advantage of recursion is that an infinite set of possible sentences, designs or other data can be defined, parsed or produced by a finite computer program.

]s are equations which define one or more sequences recursively. Some specific kinds of recurrence relation can be "solved" to obtain a non-recursive definition (e.g., a ]).

Use of recursion in an algorithm has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is usually the simplicity of instructions. The main disadvantage is that the memory usage of recursive algorithms may grow very quickly, rendering them impractical for larger instances.

==In biology==
Shapes that seem to have been created by recursive processes sometimes appear in plants and animals, such as in branching structures in which one large part branches out into two or more similar smaller parts. One example is ].<ref>{{cite web |title=Picture of the Day: Fractal Cauliflower |date=28 December 2012 |url=https://twistedsifter.com/2012/12/fractal-cauliflower-romanesco-broccoli/ |access-date=19 April 2020}}</ref>

== In the social sciences ==
Authors use the concept of ''recursivity'' to foreground the situation in which specifically ''social'' scientists find themselves when producing knowledge about the world they are always already part of.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bourdieu |first=Pierre |year=1992 |title=Double Bind et Conversion |journal=Pour Une Anthropologie Réflexive |publisher=Le Seuil |publication-place=Paris}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Giddens |first=Anthony |title=Social Theory and Modern Sociology |publisher=Polity Press |year=1987}}</ref> According to Audrey Alejandro, “as social scientists, the recursivity of our condition deals with the fact that we are both subjects (as discourses are the medium through which we analyse) and objects of the academic discourses we produce (as we are social agents belonging to the world we analyse).”<ref name="Alejandro2021">{{Cite journal |last=Alejandro |first=Audrey |date=2021 |title=Reflexive discourse analysis: A methodology for the practice of reflexivity |journal=] |language=en |volume=27 |issue=1 |page=171 |doi=10.1177/1354066120969789 |s2cid=229461433 |issn=1354-0661|doi-access=free }}</ref> From this basis, she identifies in recursivity a fundamental challenge in the production of emancipatory knowledge which calls for the exercise of ] efforts:{{quote|we are socialised into discourses and dispositions produced by the socio-political order we aim to challenge, a socio-political order that we may, therefore, reproduce unconsciously while aiming to do the contrary. The recursivity of our situation as scholars – and, more precisely, the fact that the dispositional tools we use to produce knowledge about the world are themselves produced by this world – both evinces the vital necessity of implementing reflexivity in practice and poses the main challenge in doing so.|Audrey Alejandro| {{Harvp|Alejandro|2021}}}}

==In business==
{{Further information|Management cybernetics}}

Recursion is sometimes referred to in ] as the process of iterating through levels of abstraction in large business entities.<ref>{{cite journal |title=The Canadian Small Business–Bank Interface: A Recursive Model |date=1994 |url=https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/104225879401800401 |publisher=SAGE Journals|doi=10.1177/104225879401800401 |last1=Riding |first1=Allan |last2=Haines |first2=George H. |last3=Thomas |first3=Roland |journal=Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice |volume=18 |issue=4 |pages=5–24 }}</ref> A common example is the recursive nature of management ], ranging from ] to ] via ]. It also encompasses the larger issue of ] in ].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Beer |first1=Stafford |title=Brain Of The Firm |date=1972 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-0471948391}}</ref>

==In art==
]s by ] and ], 1892]]
]'s '']'', 1320, recursively contains an image of itself (held up by the kneeling figure in the central panel).]]
{{See also|Mathematics and art|Infinity mirror}}

The ] is a physical artistic example of the recursive concept.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Tang |first1=Daisy |title=Recursion |url=http://www.cpp.edu/~ftang/courses/CS240/lectures/recursion.htm |access-date=24 September 2015 |quote=More examples of recursion: Russian Matryoshka dolls. Each doll is made of solid wood or is hollow and contains another Matryoshka doll inside it.}}</ref>

Recursion has been used in paintings since ]'s '']'', made in 1320. Its central panel contains the kneeling figure of Cardinal Stefaneschi, holding up the triptych itself as an offering.<ref>{{cite web |title=Giotto di Bondone and assistants: Stefaneschi triptych |url=http://mv.vatican.va/3_EN/pages/PIN/PIN_Sala02_03.html |publisher=The Vatican |access-date=16 September 2015}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |title=Physical (A)Causality: Determinism, Randomness and Uncaused Events |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gxBMDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 |first=Karl |last=Svozil |year=2018 |publisher=Springer |pages=12| isbn=9783319708157 }}</ref> This practice is more generally known as the ], an example of the ] technique.

]'s '']'' (1956) is a print which depicts a distorted city containing a gallery which ]ly contains the picture, and so '']''.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Cooper |first1=Jonathan |title=Art and Mathematics |url=https://unwrappingart.com/art/art-and-mathematics/ |access-date=5 July 2020 |date=5 September 2007}}</ref>
{{Clear}}

== In culture ==
The film '']'' has colloquialized the appending of the suffix '']'' to a noun to jokingly indicate the recursion of something.<ref>{{cite web |title=-ception – The Rice University Neologisms Database |url=http://neologisms.rice.edu/index.php?a=term&d=1&t=17573 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170705153941/http://neologisms.rice.edu/index.php?a=term&d=1&t=17573 |archive-date=July 5, 2017 |access-date=December 23, 2016 |publisher=Rice University}}</ref>

==See also==
* {{Annotated link|Corecursion}}
* {{Annotated link|Course-of-values recursion}}
* {{Annotated link|Digital infinity}}
* {{Annotated link|A Dream Within a Dream (poem)}}
* {{Annotated link|Droste effect}}
* {{Annotated link|False awakening}}
* {{Annotated link|Fixed point combinator}}
* {{Annotated link|Infinite compositions of analytic functions}}
* {{Annotated link|Infinite loop}}
* {{Annotated link|Infinite regress}}
* {{Annotated link|Infinitism}}
* {{Annotated link|Infinity mirror}}
* {{Annotated link|Iterated function}}
* {{Annotated link|Mathematical induction}}
* {{Annotated link|Mise en abyme}}
<!-- {{Annotated link|Recursion}} and ] will not display correctly in this list, and including it
is considered to break ]. See discussion on the talk page.-->
* {{Annotated link|Reentrant (subroutine)}}
* {{Annotated link|Self-reference}}
* {{Annotated link|Spiegel im Spiegel}}
* {{Annotated link|Strange loop}}
* {{Annotated link|Tail recursion}}
* {{Annotated link|Tupper's self-referential formula}}
* {{Annotated link|Turtles all the way down}}

==References==
{{Reflist}}

==Bibliography==
{{refbegin}}
* {{cite journal|first=Edsger W.|last=Dijkstra|author-link=Edsger W. Dijkstra|title=Recursive Programming|journal=Numerische Mathematik|volume=2|issue=1|year=1960|pages=312–318|doi=10.1007/BF01386232|s2cid=127891023}}
*{{cite book | author=Johnsonbaugh, Richard|author-link=Richard Johnsonbaugh | title=Discrete Mathematics | publisher=Prentice Hall | year=2004 | isbn=978-0-13-117686-7 }}
*{{cite book | author=Hofstadter, Douglas | author-link=Douglas Hofstadter | title=Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid | publisher=Basic Books | year=1999 | isbn=978-0-465-02656-2 | url=https://archive.org/details/gdelescherbachet00hofs }}
*{{cite book | author=Shoenfield, Joseph R. |author-link=Joseph R. Shoenfield| title=Recursion Theory | url=https://archive.org/details/recursiontheory0000shoe | url-access=registration | publisher=A K Peters Ltd | year=2000 | isbn=978-1-56881-149-9 }}
*{{cite book | author=] | title=Logic, Sets, and Recursion | url=https://archive.org/details/logicsetsrecursi0000caus | url-access=registration | publisher=Jones & Bartlett | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-7637-1695-0 }}
*{{cite book |author1=Cori, Rene |author2=Lascar, Daniel |author3=Pelletier, Donald H. | title=Recursion Theory, Gödel's Theorems, Set Theory, Model Theory | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-19-850050-6 }}
*{{cite book | author1=Barwise, Jon| author2=Moss, Lawrence S. |author1-link=Jon Barwise| title=Vicious Circles | publisher=Stanford Univ Center for the Study of Language and Information | year=1996 | isbn=978-0-19-850050-6 }} - offers a treatment of ].
*{{cite book | author=Rosen, Kenneth H. | title=Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications | publisher=McGraw-Hill College | year=2002 | isbn=978-0-07-293033-7 }}
*{{cite book | last1=Cormen |first1=Thomas H. |first2=Charles E. |last2=Leiserson |first3=Ronald L. |last3=Rivest |first4=Clifford |last4=Stein | title=Introduction to Algorithms | publisher=Mit Pr | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-262-03293-3 }}
*{{cite book |author1=Kernighan, B. |author2=Ritchie, D. |title=The C programming Language |publisher=Prentice Hall |year=1988 |isbn=978-0-13-110362-7 |url=https://archive.org/details/cprogramminglang00bria }}
*{{cite book |author1=Stokey, Nancy |author2=Robert Lucas |author3=Edward Prescott | title=Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics | publisher=Harvard University Press | year=1989 | isbn=978-0-674-75096-8}}
*{{cite book | author=Hungerford |title=Algebra | publisher=Springer|year=1980|isbn=978-0-387-90518-1}}, first chapter on set theory.
{{refend}}

==External links==
{{Commons category}}
{{Wiktionary|recursion|recursivity}}
* - tutorial by Alan Gauld
*
*

{{Fractals}}
{{Mathematical logic}}
{{Authority control}}

]
]
]
]
]

Latest revision as of 09:29, 14 December 2024

Process of repeating items in a self-similar way For other uses, see Recursion (disambiguation).

A visual form of recursion known as the Droste effect. The woman in this image holds an object that contains a smaller image of her holding an identical object, which in turn contains a smaller image of herself holding an identical object, and so forth. 1904 Droste cocoa tin, designed by Jan Misset.

Recursion occurs when the definition of a concept or process depends on a simpler or previous version of itself. Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from linguistics to logic. The most common application of recursion is in mathematics and computer science, where a function being defined is applied within its own definition. While this apparently defines an infinite number of instances (function values), it is often done in such a way that no infinite loop or infinite chain of references can occur.

A process that exhibits recursion is recursive. Video feedback displays recursive images, as does an infinity mirror.

Formal definitions

Ouroboros, an ancient symbol depicting a serpent or dragon eating its own tail

In mathematics and computer science, a class of objects or methods exhibits recursive behavior when it can be defined by two properties:

  • A simple base case (or cases) — a terminating scenario that does not use recursion to produce an answer
  • A recursive step — a set of rules that reduces all successive cases toward the base case.

For example, the following is a recursive definition of a person's ancestor. One's ancestor is either:

  • One's parent (base case), or
  • One's parent's ancestor (recursive step).

The Fibonacci sequence is another classic example of recursion:

Fib(0) = 0 as base case 1,
Fib(1) = 1 as base case 2,
For all integers n > 1, Fib(n) = Fib(n − 1) + Fib(n − 2).

Many mathematical axioms are based upon recursive rules. For example, the formal definition of the natural numbers by the Peano axioms can be described as: "Zero is a natural number, and each natural number has a successor, which is also a natural number." By this base case and recursive rule, one can generate the set of all natural numbers.

Other recursively defined mathematical objects include factorials, functions (e.g., recurrence relations), sets (e.g., Cantor ternary set), and fractals.

There are various more tongue-in-cheek definitions of recursion; see recursive humor.

Informal definition

Sourdough starter being stirred into flour to produce sourdough: the recipe calls for some sourdough left over from the last time the same recipe was made.

Recursion is the process a procedure goes through when one of the steps of the procedure involves invoking the procedure itself. A procedure that goes through recursion is said to be 'recursive'.

To understand recursion, one must recognize the distinction between a procedure and the running of a procedure. A procedure is a set of steps based on a set of rules, while the running of a procedure involves actually following the rules and performing the steps.

Recursion is related to, but not the same as, a reference within the specification of a procedure to the execution of some other procedure.

When a procedure is thus defined, this immediately creates the possibility of an endless loop; recursion can only be properly used in a definition if the step in question is skipped in certain cases so that the procedure can complete.

Even if it is properly defined, a recursive procedure is not easy for humans to perform, as it requires distinguishing the new from the old, partially executed invocation of the procedure; this requires some administration as to how far various simultaneous instances of the procedures have progressed. For this reason, recursive definitions are very rare in everyday situations.

In language

Linguist Noam Chomsky, among many others, has argued that the lack of an upper bound on the number of grammatical sentences in a language, and the lack of an upper bound on grammatical sentence length (beyond practical constraints such as the time available to utter one), can be explained as the consequence of recursion in natural language.

This can be understood in terms of a recursive definition of a syntactic category, such as a sentence. A sentence can have a structure in which what follows the verb is another sentence: Dorothy thinks witches are dangerous, in which the sentence witches are dangerous occurs in the larger one. So a sentence can be defined recursively (very roughly) as something with a structure that includes a noun phrase, a verb, and optionally another sentence. This is really just a special case of the mathematical definition of recursion.

This provides a way of understanding the creativity of language—the unbounded number of grammatical sentences—because it immediately predicts that sentences can be of arbitrary length: Dorothy thinks that Toto suspects that Tin Man said that.... There are many structures apart from sentences that can be defined recursively, and therefore many ways in which a sentence can embed instances of one category inside another. Over the years, languages in general have proved amenable to this kind of analysis.

The generally accepted idea that recursion is an essential property of human language has been challenged by Daniel Everett on the basis of his claims about the Pirahã language. Andrew Nevins, David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues are among many who have argued against this. Literary self-reference can in any case be argued to be different in kind from mathematical or logical recursion.

Recursion plays a crucial role not only in syntax, but also in natural language semantics. The word and, for example, can be construed as a function that can apply to sentence meanings to create new sentences, and likewise for noun phrase meanings, verb phrase meanings, and others. It can also apply to intransitive verbs, transitive verbs, or ditransitive verbs. In order to provide a single denotation for it that is suitably flexible, and is typically defined so that it can take any of these different types of meanings as arguments. This can be done by defining it for a simple case in which it combines sentences, and then defining the other cases recursively in terms of the simple one.

A recursive grammar is a formal grammar that contains recursive production rules.

Recursive humor

Recursion is sometimes used humorously in computer science, programming, philosophy, or mathematics textbooks, generally by giving a circular definition or self-reference, in which the putative recursive step does not get closer to a base case, but instead leads to an infinite regress. It is not unusual for such books to include a joke entry in their glossary along the lines of:

Recursion, see Recursion.

A variation is found on page 269 in the index of some editions of Brian Kernighan and Dennis Ritchie's book The C Programming Language; the index entry recursively references itself ("recursion 86, 139, 141, 182, 202, 269"). Early versions of this joke can be found in Let's talk Lisp by Laurent Siklóssy (published by Prentice Hall PTR on December 1, 1975, with a copyright date of 1976) and in Software Tools by Kernighan and Plauger (published by Addison-Wesley Professional on January 11, 1976). The joke also appears in The UNIX Programming Environment by Kernighan and Pike. It did not appear in the first edition of The C Programming Language. The joke is part of the functional programming folklore and was already widespread in the functional programming community before the publication of the aforementioned books.

A plaque commemorates the Toronto Recursive History Project of Toronto's Recursive History.

Another joke is that "To understand recursion, you must understand recursion." In the English-language version of the Google web search engine, when a search for "recursion" is made, the site suggests "Did you mean: recursion." An alternative form is the following, from Andrew Plotkin: "If you already know what recursion is, just remember the answer. Otherwise, find someone who is standing closer to Douglas Hofstadter than you are; then ask him or her what recursion is."

Recursive acronyms are other examples of recursive humor. PHP, for example, stands for "PHP Hypertext Preprocessor", WINE stands for "WINE Is Not an Emulator", GNU stands for "GNU's not Unix", and SPARQL denotes the "SPARQL Protocol and RDF Query Language".

In mathematics

The Sierpinski triangle—a confined recursion of triangles that form a fractal

Recursively defined sets

Main article: Recursive definition

Example: the natural numbers

See also: Closure (mathematics)

The canonical example of a recursively defined set is given by the natural numbers:

0 is in N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} }
if n is in N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } , then n + 1 is in N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} }
The set of natural numbers is the smallest set satisfying the previous two properties.

In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (or Peano postulates or Dedekind–Peano axioms), are axioms for the natural numbers presented in the 19th century by the German mathematician Richard Dedekind and by the Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. The Peano Axioms define the natural numbers referring to a recursive successor function and addition and multiplication as recursive functions.

Example: Proof procedure

Another interesting example is the set of all "provable" propositions in an axiomatic system that are defined in terms of a proof procedure which is inductively (or recursively) defined as follows:

  • If a proposition is an axiom, it is a provable proposition.
  • If a proposition can be derived from true reachable propositions by means of inference rules, it is a provable proposition.
  • The set of provable propositions is the smallest set of propositions satisfying these conditions.

Finite subdivision rules

Main article: Finite subdivision rule

Finite subdivision rules are a geometric form of recursion, which can be used to create fractal-like images. A subdivision rule starts with a collection of polygons labelled by finitely many labels, and then each polygon is subdivided into smaller labelled polygons in a way that depends only on the labels of the original polygon. This process can be iterated. The standard `middle thirds' technique for creating the Cantor set is a subdivision rule, as is barycentric subdivision.

Functional recursion

A function may be recursively defined in terms of itself. A familiar example is the Fibonacci number sequence: F(n) = F(n − 1) + F(n − 2). For such a definition to be useful, it must be reducible to non-recursively defined values: in this case F(0) = 0 and F(1) = 1.

Proofs involving recursive definitions

Applying the standard technique of proof by cases to recursively defined sets or functions, as in the preceding sections, yields structural induction — a powerful generalization of mathematical induction widely used to derive proofs in mathematical logic and computer science.

Recursive optimization

Dynamic programming is an approach to optimization that restates a multiperiod or multistep optimization problem in recursive form. The key result in dynamic programming is the Bellman equation, which writes the value of the optimization problem at an earlier time (or earlier step) in terms of its value at a later time (or later step).

The recursion theorem

In set theory, this is a theorem guaranteeing that recursively defined functions exist. Given a set X, an element a of X and a function f: XX, the theorem states that there is a unique function F : N X {\displaystyle F:\mathbb {N} \to X} (where N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } denotes the set of natural numbers including zero) such that

F ( 0 ) = a {\displaystyle F(0)=a}
F ( n + 1 ) = f ( F ( n ) ) {\displaystyle F(n+1)=f(F(n))}

for any natural number n.

Dedekind was the first to pose the problem of unique definition of set-theoretical functions on N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } by recursion, and gave a sketch of an argument in the 1888 essay "Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?"

Proof of uniqueness

Take two functions F : N X {\displaystyle F:\mathbb {N} \to X} and G : N X {\displaystyle G:\mathbb {N} \to X} such that:

F ( 0 ) = a {\displaystyle F(0)=a}
G ( 0 ) = a {\displaystyle G(0)=a}
F ( n + 1 ) = f ( F ( n ) ) {\displaystyle F(n+1)=f(F(n))}
G ( n + 1 ) = f ( G ( n ) ) {\displaystyle G(n+1)=f(G(n))}

where a is an element of X.

It can be proved by mathematical induction that F(n) = G(n) for all natural numbers n:

Base Case: F(0) = a = G(0) so the equality holds for n = 0.
Inductive Step: Suppose F(k) = G(k) for some k N {\displaystyle k\in \mathbb {N} } . Then F(k + 1) = f(F(k)) = f(G(k)) = G(k + 1).
Hence F(k) = G(k) implies F(k + 1) = G(k + 1).

By induction, F(n) = G(n) for all n N {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} } .

In computer science

Main article: Recursion (computer science)

A common method of simplification is to divide a problem into subproblems of the same type. As a computer programming technique, this is called divide and conquer and is key to the design of many important algorithms. Divide and conquer serves as a top-down approach to problem solving, where problems are solved by solving smaller and smaller instances. A contrary approach is dynamic programming. This approach serves as a bottom-up approach, where problems are solved by solving larger and larger instances, until the desired size is reached.

A classic example of recursion is the definition of the factorial function, given here in Python code:

def factorial(n):
    if n > 0:
        return n * factorial(n - 1)
    else:
        return 1

The function calls itself recursively on a smaller version of the input (n - 1) and multiplies the result of the recursive call by n, until reaching the base case, analogously to the mathematical definition of factorial.

Recursion in computer programming is exemplified when a function is defined in terms of simpler, often smaller versions of itself. The solution to the problem is then devised by combining the solutions obtained from the simpler versions of the problem. One example application of recursion is in parsers for programming languages. The great advantage of recursion is that an infinite set of possible sentences, designs or other data can be defined, parsed or produced by a finite computer program.

Recurrence relations are equations which define one or more sequences recursively. Some specific kinds of recurrence relation can be "solved" to obtain a non-recursive definition (e.g., a closed-form expression).

Use of recursion in an algorithm has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is usually the simplicity of instructions. The main disadvantage is that the memory usage of recursive algorithms may grow very quickly, rendering them impractical for larger instances.

In biology

Shapes that seem to have been created by recursive processes sometimes appear in plants and animals, such as in branching structures in which one large part branches out into two or more similar smaller parts. One example is Romanesco broccoli.

In the social sciences

Authors use the concept of recursivity to foreground the situation in which specifically social scientists find themselves when producing knowledge about the world they are always already part of. According to Audrey Alejandro, “as social scientists, the recursivity of our condition deals with the fact that we are both subjects (as discourses are the medium through which we analyse) and objects of the academic discourses we produce (as we are social agents belonging to the world we analyse).” From this basis, she identifies in recursivity a fundamental challenge in the production of emancipatory knowledge which calls for the exercise of reflexive efforts:

we are socialised into discourses and dispositions produced by the socio-political order we aim to challenge, a socio-political order that we may, therefore, reproduce unconsciously while aiming to do the contrary. The recursivity of our situation as scholars – and, more precisely, the fact that the dispositional tools we use to produce knowledge about the world are themselves produced by this world – both evinces the vital necessity of implementing reflexivity in practice and poses the main challenge in doing so.

— Audrey Alejandro, Alejandro (2021)

In business

Further information: Management cybernetics

Recursion is sometimes referred to in management science as the process of iterating through levels of abstraction in large business entities. A common example is the recursive nature of management hierarchies, ranging from line management to senior management via middle management. It also encompasses the larger issue of capital structure in corporate governance.

In art

Recursive dolls: the original set of Matryoshka dolls by Zvyozdochkin and Malyutin, 1892
Front face of Giotto's Stefaneschi Triptych, 1320, recursively contains an image of itself (held up by the kneeling figure in the central panel).
See also: Mathematics and art and Infinity mirror

The Matryoshka doll is a physical artistic example of the recursive concept.

Recursion has been used in paintings since Giotto's Stefaneschi Triptych, made in 1320. Its central panel contains the kneeling figure of Cardinal Stefaneschi, holding up the triptych itself as an offering. This practice is more generally known as the Droste effect, an example of the Mise en abyme technique.

M. C. Escher's Print Gallery (1956) is a print which depicts a distorted city containing a gallery which recursively contains the picture, and so ad infinitum.

In culture

The film Inception has colloquialized the appending of the suffix -ception to a noun to jokingly indicate the recursion of something.

See also

References

  1. Causey, Robert L. (2006). Logic, sets, and recursion (2nd ed.). Sudbury, Mass.: Jones and Bartlett Publishers. ISBN 0-7637-3784-4. OCLC 62093042.
  2. "Peano axioms | mathematics". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
  3. "Definition of RECURSIVE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
  4. Pinker, Steven (1994). The Language Instinct. William Morrow.
  5. Pinker, Steven; Jackendoff, Ray (2005). "The faculty of language: What's so special about it?". Cognition. 95 (2): 201–236. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.116.7784. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2004.08.004. PMID 15694646. S2CID 1599505.
  6. Nordquist, Richard. "What Is Recursion in English Grammar?". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
  7. Nevins, Andrew; Pesetsky, David; Rodrigues, Cilene (2009). "Evidence and argumentation: A reply to Everett (2009)" (PDF). Language. 85 (3): 671–681. doi:10.1353/lan.0.0140. S2CID 16915455. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-01-06.
  8. Drucker, Thomas (4 January 2008). Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 110. ISBN 978-0-8176-4768-1.
  9. Barbara Partee and Mats Rooth. 1983. In Rainer Bäuerle et al., Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language. Reprinted in Paul Portner and Barbara Partee, eds. 2002. Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings. Blackwell.
  10. Nederhof, Mark-Jan; Satta, Giorgio (2002), "Parsing Non-recursive Context-free Grammars", Proceedings of the 40th Annual Meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics (ACL '02), Stroudsburg, PA, USA: Association for Computational Linguistics, pp. 112–119, doi:10.3115/1073083.1073104.
  11. ^ Hunter, David (2011). Essentials of Discrete Mathematics. Jones and Bartlett. p. 494. ISBN 9781449604424.
  12. Shaffer, Eric. "CS 173:Discrete Structures" (PDF). University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Retrieved 7 July 2023.
  13. "Introduction to Computer Science and Programming in C; Session 8: September 25, 2008" (PDF). Columbia University. Retrieved 7 July 2023.
  14. "recursion - Google Search". www.google.com. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
  15. A. Kanamori, "In Praise of Replacement", pp.50--52. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 18, no. 1 (2012). Accessed 21 August 2023.
  16. "Picture of the Day: Fractal Cauliflower". 28 December 2012. Retrieved 19 April 2020.
  17. Bourdieu, Pierre (1992). "Double Bind et Conversion". Pour Une Anthropologie Réflexive. Paris: Le Seuil.
  18. Giddens, Anthony (1987). Social Theory and Modern Sociology. Polity Press.
  19. Alejandro, Audrey (2021). "Reflexive discourse analysis: A methodology for the practice of reflexivity". European Journal of International Relations. 27 (1): 171. doi:10.1177/1354066120969789. ISSN 1354-0661. S2CID 229461433.
  20. Riding, Allan; Haines, George H.; Thomas, Roland (1994). "The Canadian Small Business–Bank Interface: A Recursive Model". Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice. 18 (4). SAGE Journals: 5–24. doi:10.1177/104225879401800401.
  21. Beer, Stafford (1972). Brain Of The Firm. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0471948391.
  22. Tang, Daisy. "Recursion". Retrieved 24 September 2015. More examples of recursion: Russian Matryoshka dolls. Each doll is made of solid wood or is hollow and contains another Matryoshka doll inside it.
  23. "Giotto di Bondone and assistants: Stefaneschi triptych". The Vatican. Retrieved 16 September 2015.
  24. Svozil, Karl (2018). Physical (A)Causality: Determinism, Randomness and Uncaused Events. Springer. p. 12. ISBN 9783319708157.
  25. Cooper, Jonathan (5 September 2007). "Art and Mathematics". Retrieved 5 July 2020.
  26. "-ception – The Rice University Neologisms Database". Rice University. Archived from the original on July 5, 2017. Retrieved December 23, 2016.

Bibliography

External links

Fractals
Characteristics
Iterated function
system
Strange attractor
L-system
Escape-time
fractals
Rendering techniques
Random fractals
People
Other
Mathematical logic
General
Theorems (list)
 and paradoxes
Logics
Traditional
Propositional
Predicate
Set theory
Types of sets
Maps and cardinality
Set theories
Formal systems (list),
language and syntax
Example axiomatic
systems
 (list)
Proof theory
Model theory
Computability theory
Related
icon Mathematics portal
Categories: