Revision as of 19:35, 2 March 2010 editUncle Dick (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers40,529 editsm Reverted edits by AlfredJAyer to last revision by Snowded (HG)← Previous edit | Revision as of 04:39, 16 December 2024 edit undoBardRapt (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users1,886 edits →Influences: Gillespie 1984, p. 148 dlNext edit → | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|German philosopher (1889–1976)}} | |||
{{pp-semi-protect|small=yes}} | |||
{{ |
{{Redirect|Heidegger}} | ||
{{Use dmy dates|date=August 2020}} | |||
{{Infobox Philosopher | | |||
{{Infobox philosopher | |||
<!-- Scroll down to edit this page --> | |||
|region = ] | |||
<!-- Philosopher Category --> | |||
|era = ] | |||
region = Western Philosophy | | |||
|image = Heidegger 3 (1960).jpg | |||
era = ] | | |||
|caption = Heidegger in 1960 | |||
color = #B0C4DE | | |||
|name = Martin Heidegger | |||
|birth_date = {{Birth date|1889|09|26|df=y}} | |||
image_name = Mheidegger.jpg| | |||
|birth_place = ], ], ] | |||
image_size = 200px | | |||
|death_date = {{Death date and age|df=yes|1976|5|26|1889|9|26}} | |||
|death_place = ], ],<br />]<ref name=yrt1>{{Cite web|date=12 October 2011|title=Martin Heidegger|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/heidegger/|access-date=20 July 2024|website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref><ref name=yrt2>{{Cite web|title=Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) - Universitätbibliothek Freiburg|url=https://www.ub.uni-freiburg.de/recherche/personenportale/martin-heidegger/|access-date=20 July 2024|website=University Library Freiburg}}</ref> | |||
<!-- Information --> | |||
|education = {{ill|Collegium Borromaeum|de|3=Collegium Borromaeum (Freiburg im Breisgau)|lt=Collegium Borromaeum}}<br />(1909–1911)<br />]<br />(PhD, 1914; ] 1916) | |||
name = Martin Heidegger | | |||
|institutions = ]<br />] | |||
birth_date = 26 September 1889 | |||
|school_tradition = ]<br />]<br />]<br />]<br /> | |||
|birth_place = ], Germany | |||
|main_interests = {{hlist |] |] |] |] |] |] |]}} | |||
|death_date = {{dda|df=yes|1976|05|26|1889|09|26}} | |||
| signature = Heidegger signature.svg | |||
|death_place = ], Germany | | |||
| thesis1_title = The Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism: A Critical-theoretical Contribution to Logic | |||
school_tradition = ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ] | | |||
| thesis1_url = https://ophen.org/pub-105956 | |||
main_interests = ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ] {{·}} ] | | |||
| thesis1_year = 1914 | |||
influences = ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ] {{·}} ]<!-- {{·}} ]-->| | |||
| thesis2_title = Duns Scotus's Doctrine of Categories and Meaning | |||
influenced = ]{{·}}]{{·}} ]{{·}}]{{·}}]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}}]{{·}} ]{{·}}]{{·}}]{{·}}]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}}]{{·}}]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]{{·}}]| | |||
| thesis2_url = https://ophen.org/pub-106038 | |||
notable_ideas = ]{{·}} ]{{·}} ]| | |||
| thesis2_year = 1916 | |||
| doctoral_advisor = Arthur Schneider (PhD advisor)<br />] (Dr. phil. hab. advisor) | |||
| spouse = {{marriage|Elfride Petri|1917}} | |||
| partner = {{plainlist| | |||
* ]<br />(1918–1969) | |||
* ]<br />(1924–1928) | |||
}} | |||
| module = {{Infobox person|embed=yes | |||
| party = ] (1933–1945) | |||
}} | |||
}} | }} | ||
'''Martin Heidegger''' (26 September 1889 – 26 May 1976) |
'''Martin Heidegger''' ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|h|aɪ|d|ɛ|ɡ|ər|,_|ˈ|h|aɪ|d|ɪ|ɡ|ər}};{{sfn|Wells|2008}} {{IPA|de|ˈmaʁtiːn ˈhaɪdɛɡɐ|lang}};{{sfn|Wells|2008}} 26 September 1889 – 26 May 1976) was a German philosopher best known for contributions to ], ], and ]. His work covers a wide range of topics including ], ], ], ], ], ] and ]. He is often considered to be among the most important and influential philosophers of the 20th century, especially in the ]. | ||
In April 1933, Heidegger was elected as ] at the ] and was widely criticized for his membership and support for the ] during his tenure. After ] he was dismissed from Freiburg and banned from teaching after ] hearings at Freiburg. There has been controversy about the relationship between ]. | |||
== Introduction == | |||
Heidegger claimed that ] has, since ], misunderstood what it means for something "to be", tending to approach this question in terms of ''a'' being, rather than asking about being itself. In other words, Heidegger believed all investigations of being have historically focused on particular entities and their properties, or have treated being itself as an entity, or ], with properties. A more authentic analysis of being would, for Heidegger, investigate "that on the basis of which beings are already understood", or that which underlies all particular entities and allows them to show up ''as'' entities in the first place.<ref> Martin Heidegger, ''Being and Time'', pp. 25–26.</ref> But since philosophers and scientists have overlooked the more basic, pre-theoretical ways of being from which their theories derive, and since they have incorrectly applied those theories universally, they have confused our understanding of being and human existence. To avoid these deep-rooted misconceptions, Heidegger believed philosophical inquiry must be conducted in a new way, through a process of retracing the steps of the history of philosophy. | |||
In Heidegger's first major text, '']'' (1927), '']'' is introduced as a term for the type of being that humans possess. Heidegger believed that Dasein already has a "pre-ontological" and concrete understanding that shapes how it lives, which he analyzed in terms of the unitary structure of "being-in-the-world". Heidegger used this analysis to approach the question of the meaning of being; that is, the question of how entities appear as the specific entities they are. In other words, Heidegger's governing "question of being" is concerned with what makes beings intelligible as beings. | |||
Heidegger argued that this misunderstanding, commencing from Plato, has left its traces in every stage of Western thought. All that we understand, from the way we speak to our notions of "]", is susceptible to error, to fundamental mistakes about the nature of being. These mistakes filter into the terms through which being is articulated in the history of philosophy—reality, logic, God, consciousness, presence, et cetera. In his later philosophy, Heidegger argues that this profoundly affects the way in which human beings relate to modern technology. | |||
==Life== | |||
Heidegger's work has strongly influenced philosophy, theology and the humanities. Within philosophy it played a crucial role in the development of ], ], ], ], and ] in general. Well-known philosophers such as ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ] have all analyzed Heidegger's work. | |||
===Early years=== | |||
Heidegger supported ] and was a member of the ] from May 1933 until May 1945<ref>Source: Hannah Arendt / Martin Heidegger by Elzbieta Ettinger, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1995, page 10</ref>. His defenders, notably Hannah Arendt, see this support as arguably a personal " 'error' " (a word which Arendt placed in quotation marks when referring to Heidegger's Nazi-era politics.)<ref>Hannah Arendt, ''Martin Heidegger At 80'', New York Review of Books, 17/6, (Oct. 21, 1971), 50-54; repr. in ''Heidegger and Modern Philosophy'' ed. M. Murray (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1978), 293-303</ref> Defenders think this error was largely irrelevant to Heidegger's philosophy. Critics, such as his former students Emmanuel Lévinas<ref> by David J. Gauthier, Ph.D dissertation, Louisiana State University, 2004, page 156</ref> and ]<ref name="Karl Löwith 1986 p. 57">Karl Löwith, ''Mein Leben in Deutschland vor und nach 1933: ein Bericht'' (Stuttgart: Metzler, 1986), p. 57, translated by Paula Wissing as cited by Maurice Blanchot in "Thinking the Apocalypse: a Letter from Maurice Blanchot to Catherine David", in ''Critical Inquiry'' 15:2, pp. 476-477.</ref>, claim that Heidegger's support for National Socialism revealed flaws inherent in his thought.<ref>"Emmanuel Faye, argues fascist and racist ideas are so woven into the fabric of Heidegger’s theo-ries that they no longer deserve to be called philosophy. . . . Richard Wolin, the author of several books on Heidegger and a close reader of the Faye book, said he is not convinced Heidegger’s thought is as thoroughly tainted by Nazism as Mr. Faye argues. Nonetheless he recognizes how far Heidegger’s ideas have spilled into the larger culture." ''An Ethical Question: Does a Nazi Deserve a Place Among Philosophers?'' by Patricia Cohen. New York Times. Published: November 8, 2009. </ref> | |||
], where Heidegger grew up]] | |||
Heidegger was born on 26 September 1889 in rural ], ], the son of Johanna (Kempf) and Friedrich Heidegger. His father was the ] of the village church, and the young Martin was raised ].{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
In 1903, Heidegger began to train for the ]. He entered a ] ] in 1909, but was discharged within weeks because of heart trouble. It was during this time that he first encountered the work of ]. From here he went on to study theology and ] at the ].{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
== Biography == | |||
=== Early years === | |||
], where Heidegger grew up.]] | |||
Heidegger was born in rural ], Germany. Raised a ], he was the son of the ] of the village church, Friedrich Heidegger, and his wife Johanna, née Kempf. In their faith, his parents adhered to the ] of 1870, which was observed mainly by the poorer class of Meßkirch. The religious controversy between the wealthy ''Altkatholiken'' and the working class led to the temporary use of a converted barn for the Roman Catholics. At the festive reunion of the congregation in 1895, the Old Catholic sexton handed the key to six year old Martin. | |||
In 1911 he broke off training for the priesthood and turned his attention to recent philosophy, in particular, ]'s ''Logical Investigations''. He graduated with a thesis on ], ''The Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism: A Critical-theoretical Contribution to Logic'', in 1914. The following year, he completed his ] on ], which was directed by ], a ], and influenced by Husserl's ].{{sfn|Alfieri|2015|page=6}}{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}}{{sfn|Luft|2015|page=461}} The title has been published in several languages and in English is "Duns Scotus's doctrine of categories and meaning".<ref> {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231201213753/https://search.worldcat.org/en/title/1330198203 |date=1 December 2023 }} Retrieved 27 November 2023.</ref> | |||
Heidegger's family could not afford to send him to university, so he entered a Jesuit seminary, though he was turned away within weeks because of the health requirement, and what he described as a ] heart condition.<ref>Hermann Philipse, ''Heidegger's Philosophy of Being'' p. 173, Notes to Chapter One, Martin Heidegger, ''Supplements'', trans. John Van Buren p. 183.</ref> After studying theology at the ] from 1909 to 1911, he switched to philosophy, in part again because of his heart condition. Heidegger completed his doctoral thesis on ] in 1914 influenced by ] and ]<ref>''Die Lehre vom Urteil im Psychologismus. Ein kritisch-theoretischer Beitrag zur Logik'' (1914). Source: Annemarie Gethmann-Siefert, "Martin Heidegger", ''Theologische Realenzyklopädie'', XIV, 1982, p. 562</ref>, and in 1916 finished his '']'' with a thesis on ] influenced by ] and ].<ref>Note, however, that it was discovered later that one of the two main sources used by Heidegger was not by Scotus, but by ]. Thus Heidegger's 1916 doctoral thesis, ''Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus'', should have been entitled, ''Die Kategorienlehre des Duns Scotus und die Bedeutungslehre des Thomas von Erfurt''. Source: .</ref> In the two years following, he worked first as an unsalaried ], then served as a soldier during the final year of ], working behind a desk and never leaving Germany. After the war, he served as a salaried senior assistant to ] at the ] from 1919 until 1923. | |||
He attempted to get the (Catholic) philosophy post at the University of Freiburg on 23 June 1916 but failed despite the support of {{Interlanguage link|Heinrich Finke|de|lt=Heinrich Finke}}.{{sfn|Altman|2012|page=79}} Instead, he worked first as an unsalaried ] then served as a soldier during the final year of ]. His service was in the last ten months of the war, most of which he spent in meteorological unit on the ] upon being deemed unfit for combat.{{sfn|Korab-Karpowicz|loc=§1}}{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
=== Marburg === | |||
In 1923, Heidegger was elected to an ] in Philosophy at the ]. His colleagues there included ], Ernst Friedländer, ], and ]. Heidegger's students at Marburg included ], ], ], ], Irene Strauss Paley, ], ], ], and ]. Through a confrontation with ] he began to develop in his lectures the main theme of his philosophy: the question of the sense of being. He extended the concept of subject to the dimension of ] and concrete ] which he found prefigured in such Christian thinkers as ], ], ], and ]. He also read the works of ], ] and ]<ref>Gethmann-Siefert, 1982, p. 563</ref>. | |||
Heidegger married Elfride Petri on 21 March 1917 in a ] ceremony officiated by his friend {{Interlanguage link|Engelbert Krebs|de|lt=Engelbert Krebs}}, and a week later in a ] ceremony in the presence of her parents.{{sfn|Heidegger|2009|page=xxxvi}} Their first son, Jörg, was born in 1919.{{sfn|Schalow|Denker|2010|page=135}} Elfride then gave birth to {{Interlanguage link|Hermann Heidegger|de|lt=Hermann}} in August 1920. Heidegger knew that he was not Hermann's biological father, but raised him as his son. Hermann's biological father, who became godfather to his son, was family friend and doctor Friedel Caesar. Hermann was told of this at the age of 14; Hermann grew up to become a historian and would later serve as the executor of Heidegger's will.{{sfn|Cammann|Soboczynski|2014}} | |||
=== Freiburg === | |||
In 1927, Heidegger published his main work ''Sein und Zeit'' (Being and Time). When ] retired as Professor of Philosophy in 1928, Heidegger accepted Freiburg's election to be his successor, in spite of a counter-offer by Marburg. Heidegger remained at ] for the rest of his life, declining a number of later offers including one from ], the most prestigious German university of the day. Among his students at Freiburg were ], ] and ]. ] attended his lecture courses during his stay in Freiburg in 1928. | |||
In the same year that he married his wife, Heidegger began a decades-long correspondence with her friend ]. Their letters are suggestive from the beginning, and it is certain they were romantically involved in the summer of 1929.{{sfn|Safranski|1998|pages=85-88, 108-81}} Blochmann was ], which raises questions in light of ].{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 10}} | |||
Heidegger was elected rector of the University on April 21, 1933, and joined the National Socialist Party on May 1.<ref>Charles Bambach, Heidegger’s Roots (Cornell University Press, 2003, page 82)</ref> In his inaugural address as rector on May 27, and in political speeches and articles from the same year, he expressed his support for the Nazi cause and its leader Adolf Hitler,<ref>Julian Young, Heidegger, Philosophy, Nazism (Cambridge University Press, 1997, page 3, page 11).</ref> He resigned the rectorate in April 1934, but remained a member of the party until 1945.<ref>Ibid. page 3</ref> | |||
From 1919 to 1923, Heidegger taught courses at the ].{{efn|See his published courses in '']. Early Freiburg lecture courses, 1919–1923.''}}{{Full citation needed|date=September 2024}} At this time he also became an assistant to Husserl, who had been a professor there since 1916.{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
{{seealso|Martin_Heidegger#Heidegger_and_National_Socialism}} | |||
=== |
===Marburg=== | ||
In 1923, Heidegger was elected to an ] in philosophy at the ]. His colleagues there included ], ], ], and ].{{sfn|Gross|Kemmann|2005|page=65}} Heidegger's students at Marburg included ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ]. Following ], he began to develop in his lectures the main theme of his philosophy: the question of the sense of being. He extended the concept of subject to the dimension of history and concrete ], which he found prefigured in such Christian thinkers as ], ], ], and ]. He also read the works of ], Husserl, ], and ].{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§1}} | |||
In late 1946, the French military authorities determined that Heidegger would be forbidden from teaching or participating in any university activities.<ref>Provisional ruling October 5, 1946; final ruling December 28, 1946; Hugo Ott, Marti Heidegger: A Political Life, (Harper Collins, 1993, page 348)</ref> The denazification procedures against Heidegger continued until March 1949, when he was finally pronounced a "Mitläufer" or fellow-traveler of National Socialism, and no punitive measures against him were proposed. This opened the way for his readmission to teaching at Freiburg University in the winter semester of 1950/51.<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil (Harvard University Press, 1998, page 373)</ref> He was granted emeritus status and then taught regularly from 1951 until 1958, and by invitation until 1967. | |||
In 1925, a 35-year-old Heidegger began what would be a four-year affair with Hannah Arendt, who was then 19 years old and his student. Like Blochmann, Arendt was Jewish. Heidegger and Arendt agreed to keep the details of the relationship a secret, preserving their letters, but keeping them unavailable.{{sfn|Young-Bruehl|2004|p=50}}<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.themarginalian.org/2016/04/25/hannah-arendt-martin-heidegger-love-letters/|title=The Remarkable Love Letters of Hannah Arendt and Martin Heidegger|first=Maria|last=Popova|date=25 April 2016|access-date=24 January 2024|archive-date=24 January 2024|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240124183352/https://www.themarginalian.org/2016/04/25/hannah-arendt-martin-heidegger-love-letters/|url-status=live}}</ref> The affair was not widely known until 1995, when ] gained access to the sealed correspondence. Nevertheless, Arendt faced criticism for her association with Heidegger after his election as ] at the University of Freiburg in 1933. | |||
=== Personal life === | |||
] | |||
In 1927 Heidegger published his main work, '']'' (''Being and Time''). He was primarily concerned to qualify to be a full professor.{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} The book, however, did more than this: it raised him to "a position of international intellectual visibility."{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§1}} | |||
] | |||
Heidegger married Elfriede Petri on March 21, 1917, in a Catholic ceremony officiated by his friend Engelbert Krebs, and a week later in a Protestant ceremony in the presence of her parents. Their first son Jörg was born in 1919. According to the recently published correspondence between the spouses<ref>{{citation | |||
|last1=Heidegger | |||
|first1=Martin | |||
|last2=Heidegger | |||
|first2=Gertrud | |||
|title=Mein liebes Seelchen! Briefe von Martin Heidegger an seine Frau Elfride: 1915-1970 | |||
|publisher=DVA | |||
|place=Munich | |||
|isbn=978-3421058492 | |||
|date=September 2005 | |||
}}</ref>, Hermann (born 1920) is the son of Elfriede and Friedel Caesar. Martin Heidegger had extramarital affairs with ] and ], both students of his. Arendt was ] and Blochmann had one Jewish parent, making them subject to severe persecution by the Nazi authorities. He helped Blochmann emigrate from Germany prior to World War II and resumed contact with both of them after the war.<ref>''Martin Heidegger / Elisabeth Blochmann. Briefwechsel 1918–1969''. Joachim W. Storck, ed. Marbach am Neckar: Deutsches Literatur-Archiv, 1989, 2nd edn. 1990.</ref> | |||
===Freiburg=== | |||
Heidegger spent much time at his vacation home at ], on the edge of the ]. He considered the seclusion provided by the forest to be the best environment in which to engage in philosophical thought.<ref>, a Spring 2007 article on Heidegger's vacation home for '']'' magazine.</ref> | |||
When Husserl retired as professor of philosophy in 1928, Heidegger accepted Freiburg's election to be his successor, in spite of a counter-offer by Marburg. The title of his 1929 inaugural lecture was "What is Metaphysics?" In this year he also published '']''.{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
Heidegger remained at ] for the rest of his life, declining later offers including one from ]. His students at Freiburg included Hannah Arendt, ], ], ], ], ], and ].{{sfn|Wolin|2015}}{{sfn|Fleischacker|2008}} ] attended his lecture courses during his stay in Freiburg in 1928, as did ] in 1933; Patočka in particular was deeply influenced by him.{{sfn|Steinfels|1995}}{{sfn|Findlay|2002|page=32}} | |||
Heidegger died on May 26, 1976 and was burried in the Meßkirch cemetery. | |||
Heidegger was elected rector of the university on 21 April 1933, and joined the ] on 1 May, just three months after ] was appointed chancellor.{{sfn|Bambach|2003|page=82}}{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} During his time as rector he was a member and an enthusiastic supporter of the party.{{sfn|Hemming|2013|loc=chapter 7}}{{sfn|Farin|2016}} There is continuing controversy as to ].{{sfn|Sheehan|1988}} He wanted to position himself as the philosopher of the party, but the highly abstract nature of his work and the opposition of ], who himself aspired to act in that position, limited Heidegger's role. His withdrawal from his position as rector owed more to his frustration as an administrator than to any principled opposition to the Nazis, according to historians.{{sfn|Evans|2005|pages=419–22}} In his inaugural address as rector on 27 May he expressed his support of a German revolution, and in an article and a speech to the students from the same year he also supported Adolf Hitler.{{sfn|Young|1998|pages=3, 11}} In November 1933, Heidegger signed the '']''. Heidegger resigned from the rectorate in April 1934, but remained a member of the Nazi Party until 1945 even though the Nazis eventually prevented him from publishing.{{sfn|Young|1998|page=3}} | |||
== Philosophy == | |||
=== Being, time, and ''Dasein'' === | |||
In 1935, he gave the talk "]". The next year, while in Rome, Heidegger gave his first lecture on ]. In the years 1936{{ndash}}1937, Heidegger wrote what some commentators consider his second greatest work, '']''; it would not be published, however, until 1989, 13 years after his death.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§1}} | |||
Heidegger's philosophy is founded on the attempt to conjoin what he considers two fundamental insights: | |||
From 1936 to 1940, Heidegger also delivered a series of lectures on ] at Freiburg that presented much of the raw material incorporated in his more established work and thought from this time. These would appear in published form in 1961. This period also marks the beginning of his interest in the "].{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
*The first of these is Heidegger's observation that, in the course of over two thousand years of history, philosophy has attended to all the beings that can be found in the world (including the "world" itself), but has forgotten to ask what "being" itself is. This is Heidegger's "question of being", and it is Heidegger's fundamental concern throughout his work from the beginning of his career until its end. One crucial source of this insight was Heidegger's reading of ] treatise on ] manifold uses of the word "being", a work which provoked Heidegger to ask what kind of unity underlies this multiplicity of uses. Heidegger opens his ''magnum opus'', '']'', with a citation from ] ] <ref> For a recent study on Heidegger's reading of the ''Sophist'' and his less central interest in Plato's ''Timaeus'' and its conception of ''space'' qua ''khôra'': see: Nader El-Bizri, "''On Kai khôra'': Situating Heidegger between the ''Sophist'' and the ''Timaeus''", ''Studia Phaenomenologica'', Vol. IV, Issue 1-2 (2004), pp. 73-98</ref> indicating that Western philosophy has neglected "being" because it was considered obvious, rather than as worthy of question. Heidegger's intuition about the question of being is thus a historical argument, which in his later work becomes his concern with the "history of being", that is, the history of the forgetting of being, which according to Heidegger requires that philosophy retrace its footsteps through a productive "]" of the history of philosophy. | |||
*The second intuition animating Heidegger's philosophy derives from the influence of ], a philosopher largely uninterested in questions of philosophical history. Rather, Husserl argued that all that philosophy could and should be is a description of experience (hence the phenomenological slogan, "to the things themselves"). But for Heidegger, this meant understanding that experience is ] and in ways of being. Thus Husserl's understanding that all consciousness is "]" (in the sense that it is always intended ''toward'' something, and is always "about" something) is transformed in Heidegger's philosophy, becoming the thought that all experience is grounded in "care." This is the basis of Heidegger's "existential analytic", as he develops it in ''Being and Time''. Heidegger argues that to be able to describe experience properly means finding the being for whom such a description might matter. Heidegger thus conducts his description of experience with reference to "'']''", the being for whom being is a question.<ref>In everyday German, "''Dasein''" means "existence." It is composed of "''Da''" (here/there) and "''Sein''" (being). ''Dasein'' is transformed in Heidegger's usage from its everyday meaning to refer, rather, to that being that is ''there'' in its world, that is, the being for whom being matters. In later publications Heidegger writes the term in hyphenated form as ''Da-sein'', thus emphasizing the distance from the word's ordinary usage.</ref> In ''Being and Time'', Heidegger criticized the abstract and metaphysical character of traditional ways of grasping human existence as rational animal, person, man, soul, spirit, or subject. ''Dasein'', then, is not intended as a way of conducting a "]", but is rather understood by Heidegger to be the condition of possibility for anything like a "philosophical anthropology."<ref>Jacques Derrida describes this in the following terms: "We can see then that Dasein, though ''not'' man, is nevertheless ''nothing other'' than man." Jacques Derrida, "The Ends of Man", ''Margins of Philosophy'' (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 127.</ref> ''Dasein'', according to Heidegger, ''is'' care. In the course of his existential analytic, Heidegger argues that ''Dasein'', who finds itself thrown into the world amidst things and with others, is thrown into its possibilities, including the possibility and inevitability of one's own mortality. The need for ''Dasein'' to assume these possibilities, that is, the need to be responsible for one's own existence, is the basis of Heidegger's notions of authenticity and resoluteness—that is, of those specific possibilities for ''Dasein'' which depend on escaping the "vulgar" temporality of calculation and of public life. | |||
In the autumn of 1944, Heidegger was drafted into the '']'' and assigned to dig anti-tank ditches along the ].{{sfn|Inwood|2014}} | |||
The marriage of these two observations depends on the fact that each of them is essentially concerned with time. That ''Dasein'' is thrown into an already existing world and thus into its mortal possibilities does not only mean that ''Dasein'' is an essentially temporal being; it also implies that the description of ''Dasein'' can only be carried out in terms inherited from the Western tradition itself. For Heidegger, unlike for Husserl, philosophical terminology could not be divorced from the history of the use of that terminology, and thus genuine philosophy could not avoid confronting questions of language and meaning. The existential analytic of ''Being and Time'' was thus always only a first step in Heidegger's philosophy, to be followed by the "dismantling" (''Destruktion'') of the history of philosophy, that is, a transformation of its language and meaning, that would have made of the existential analytic only a kind of "limit case" (in the sense in which special relativity is a limit case of general relativity). | |||
===Post-war=== | |||
That Heidegger did not write this second part of ''Being and Time'', and that the existential analytic was left behind in the course of Heidegger's subsequent writings on the history of being, might be interpreted as a failure to conjugate his account of ''individual'' experience with his account of the vicissitudes of the ''collective'' human adventure that he understands the Western philosophical tradition to be. And this would in turn raise the question of whether this failure is due to a flaw in Heidegger's account of temporality, that is, of whether Heidegger was correct to oppose vulgar and authentic time.<ref>Cf. ], "Technics of Decision: An Interview", ''Angelaki'' 8 (2003), pp. 154–67, and cf. the discussion of Stiegler's reading of Heidegger in the sub-section "Bernard Stiegler" below.</ref> | |||
In late 1946, as France engaged in '']'' in its ], the French military authorities determined that Heidegger should be blocked from teaching or participating in any university activities because of his association with the Nazi Party.{{efn|Provisional ruling October 5, 1946; final ruling December 28, 1946; Hugo Ott, Martin Heidegger: A Political Life, (Harper Collins, 1993, page 348).}} Nevertheless, he presented the talk "What are Poets for?" in memory of ]. He also published "On Humanism" in 1947 to clarify his differences with ] and French ]. The ] procedures against Heidegger continued until March 1949 when he was finally pronounced a '']'' (the second lowest of five categories of "incrimination" by association with the Nazi regime). No punitive measures against him were proposed.{{sfn|Safranski|1998}} This opened the way for his readmission to teaching at Freiburg University in the winter semester of 1950–51.{{sfn|Safranski|1998|page=373}} He was granted emeritus status and then taught regularly from 1951 until 1958, and by invitation until 1967. | |||
] | |||
=== ''Being and Time'' === | |||
In 1966 he gave an interview to '']'' attempting to justify his support of the Nazi Party. Per their agreement, it was not published until five days after his death in 1976, under the title "]" after a reference to Hölderlin that Heidegger makes during the interview.{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
] | |||
{{Main|Being and Time}} | |||
Heidegger's publications during this time were mostly reworked versions of his lectures. In his last days, he also arranged for a complete edition of his works to be compiled and published. Its first volume appeared in 1975. As of 2019,{{Update inline|date=September 2024}} the edition is almost complete at over 100 volumes.{{sfn|Inwood|2019|loc=chapter 1}} | |||
''Being and Time'' (German title: ''Sein und Zeit''), published in 1927, is Heidegger's first academic book. He had been under pressure to publish in order to qualify for Husserl's chair at ] and the success of this work ensured his appointment to the post. | |||
=== Death === | |||
It investigates the question of ] by asking about the being for whom being is a question. Heidegger names this being ''Dasein'' (see above), and the book pursues its investigation through themes such as mortality, anxiety, temporality, and historicity. It was Heidegger's original intention to write a second half of the book, consisting of a "''Destruktion''" of the history of philosophy — that is, the transformation of philosophy by re-tracing its history — but he never completed this project. | |||
Heidegger died on 26 May 1976 in ].<ref name=yrt1/><ref name=yrt2/> A few months before his death, he met with Bernhard Welte, a Catholic priest, Freiburg University professor and earlier correspondent. The exact nature of their conversation is not known, but what is known is that it included talk of Heidegger's relationship to the Catholic Church and subsequent Christian burial at which the priest officiated. Heidegger was buried in the Meßkirch cemetery.{{sfn|Lambert|2007|pages=157–69}}{{sfn|Safranski|1998|page=432}}{{sfn|Fiske|1976}} | |||
==Early influences== | |||
''Being and Time'' influenced many thinkers, including such existentialist thinkers as ] (although Heidegger distanced himself from ]—see below). | |||
], the founder of ], was Heidegger's teacher and a major influence on his thought. While the specific lines of influence remain a matter of scholarly dispute,{{sfn|Gadamer|1994|page=18}}{{sfn|Dostal|1993|page=142}}{{sfn|Kisiel|Buren|1994|page=244}} one thing is clear: Heidegger's early work on ''Being and Time'' moved away from Husserl's theory of ] to focus on the pre-theoretical conditions that enable consciousness to grasp objects.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.1}} | |||
] influenced Heidegger from an early age. This influence was mediated through Catholic ], ], and ].{{sfn|Krell|1975}}{{sfn|Moran|2000}} | |||
=== ''Die Kehre'' === | |||
According to scholar Michael Wheeler, it is by way of a "radical rethinking" of Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'' that Heidegger supplants Husserl's notion of intentionality with his unitary notion of being-in-the-world. According to this reinterpretation, the various modes of being are united in more basic capacity of taking-as or making-present-to.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.1}} | |||
] | |||
Some scholars have argued that Heidegger's thought after ''Being and Time'' exhibits a "turn" in his thinking (''die Kehre''). Heidegger denied this in a letter—published by ] in ''Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought'' (1963)—which stated that, if there had been a turn at all, it was simply a matter of going deeper into the same matters. In his later work, Heidegger largely abandons the account of ''Dasein'' as a pragmatic, engaged, worldly agent, and instead discusses other elements necessary to an understanding of being, notably language, the earth (as the almost ineffable foundation of world) and the presence of the gods. Nevertheless, ''Dasein'' (or "mortals", as he later prefers to say) remains a crucial part of the coming-about or event (''Ereignis'') of being. | |||
The works of ] shaped Heidegger's very early project of developing a "hermeneutics of ] life", and his hermeneutical transformation of phenomenology.{{sfn|Rockmore|2003|pages=477–494}}{{efn|In ''The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time'', Theodor Kisiel designates the first version of the project that culminates in ''Being and Time'', "the Dilthey draft".{{sfn|Kisiel|1993|page=313}} }} There is little doubt that Heidegger seized upon Dilthey's concept of hermeneutics.{{sfn|Ormiston|Schrift|1990|pages=32–33}} Heidegger's novel ideas about ontology required a ''gestalt'' formation, not merely a series of logical arguments, in order to demonstrate his fundamentally new paradigm of thinking, and the ] offered a new and powerful tool for the articulation and realization of these ideas.{{sfn|Nelson|2014|pages=109–28}} | |||
] contributed much to Heidegger's treatment of the existentialist aspects of his thought located in Division II of ''Being and Time''.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|loc=Appendix}} Heidegger's concepts of anxiety ('']'') and mortality draw on Kierkegaard and are indebted to the way in which the latter lays out the importance of our subjective relation to truth, our existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world. | |||
=== Later works === | |||
==Philosophy== | |||
] Nr. 13]] | |||
{{See also|Heideggerian terminology}} | |||
Heidegger's later works, following the so-called "turn" and after the Second World War, seem to many commentators to at least reflect a shift of focus, if not indeed a major change in his philosophical outlook. One way this has been understood is as a shift from "doing" to "dwelling", although others feel that this is to overstate the difference. Heidegger focuses less on the way in which the structures of being are revealed in everyday behavior, and more on the way in which behavior itself depends on a prior "openness to being." The essence of being human is the maintenance of this openness. Heidegger contrasts this openness to the "will to power" of the modern human subject, which is one way of forgetting this originary openness. | |||
] | |||
=== Fundamental ontology<!--Ontological difference redirects here--> === | |||
Heidegger understands the commencement of the history of Western philosophy as a brief period of authentic openness to being, during the time of the ], especially ], ], and ]. This was followed, according to Heidegger, by a long period increasingly dominated by the forgetting of this initial openness, a period which commences with ], but a forgetting or abandonment which occurs in different ways throughout Western history. | |||
{{See also|Fundamental ontology}} | |||
According to scholar ], traditional ontology asks "Why is there anything?", whereas Heidegger's fundamental ontology asks "What does it mean for something to be?" Heidegger's ontology "is fundamental relative to traditional ontology in that it concerns what any understanding of entities necessarily presupposes, namely, our understanding of that by virtue of which entities are entities".{{sfn|Carman|2003|pages=8-52}} | |||
Two recurring themes of Heidegger's later writings are poetry and technology. Heidegger sees poetry and technology as two contrasting ways of "revealing." Poetry reveals being in the way in which, if it is genuine poetry, it commences something new. Technology, on the other hand, when it gets going, inaugurates the world of the dichotomous subject and object, which modern philosophy commencing with Descartes also reveals. But with ''modern'' technology a new stage of revealing is reached, in which the subject-object distinction is overcome even in the "material" world of technology. The essence of modern technology is the conversion of the whole universe of beings into an undifferentiated "standing reserve" (''Bestand'') of energy available for any use to which humans choose to put it. Heidegger described the essence of modern technology as '']'', or "enframing." Heidegger does not unequivocally condemn technology: while he acknowledges that modern technology contains grave dangers, Heidegger nevertheless also argues that it may constitute a chance for human beings to enter a new epoch in their relation to being. Despite this, some commentators have insisted that an agrarian nostalgia permeates his later work. | |||
This line of inquiry is "central to Heidegger's philosophy". He accuses the Western philosophical tradition of mistakenly trying to understand ''being as such'' as if it were an ultimate entity.{{sfn|Dahlstrom|2004}} Heidegger modifies traditional ontology by focusing instead on the ''meaning of being''. This kind of ontological inquiry, he claims, is required to understand the basis of our understanding, scientific and otherwise.{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|loc=§3}} | |||
Heidegger's important later works include ''Vom Wesen der Wahrheit'' ("On the Essence of Truth", 1930), ''Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes'' ("]", 1935), ''Einführung in die Metaphysik'' ("An Introduction to Metaphysics", 1935), ''Bauen Wohnen Denken'' ("Building Dwelling Thinking", 1951), and ''Die Frage nach der Technik'' ("]", 1954) and ''Was heisst Denken?'' ("What Is Called Thinking?" 1954). Also important is ''Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis)'' ('']]), composed in the years 1936–38 but not published until 1989, on the centennial of Heidegger's birth. | |||
In short, before asking what exists, Heidegger contends that people must first examine what "to exist" even means.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.2.1}} | |||
=== Influences === | |||
====Aristotle and the Greeks==== | |||
Heidegger was influenced at an early age by ], mediated through Catholic ], ], and ]. Aristotle's ethical, logical, and metaphysical works were crucial to the development of his thought in the crucial period of the 1920s. Although he later worked less on Aristotle, Heidegger recommended postponing reading Nietzsche, and to "first study Aristotle for ten to fifteen years."<ref>Heidegger, ''What is Called Thinking?'' (New York: Harper & Row, 1968), p. 73.</ref> In reading Aristotle, Heidegger increasingly contested the traditional Latin translation and scholastic interpretation of his thought. Particularly important (not least for its influence upon others, both in their interpretation of Aristotle and in rehabilitating a neo-Aristotelian "practical philosophy"<ref>Kelvin Knight, ''Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre'' (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007).</ref>) was his radical reinterpretation of Book Six of Aristotle's '']'' and several books of the '']''. Both informed the argument of ''Being and Time''. | |||
===''Being and Time''=== | |||
The idea of asking about ] may be traced back via Aristotle to ]. Heidegger claimed to have revived the question of being, the question having been largely forgotten by the ] tradition extending from ] to ], a forgetfulness extending to the ] and then to modern science and technology. In pursuit of the retrieval of this question, Heidegger spent considerable time reflecting on ], in particular on ], ], ], and ], as well as on the tragic playwright ]. | |||
{{See also|Being and Time}} | |||
In his first major work, ''Being and Time'', Heidegger pursues this ontological inquiry by way of an analysis of the kind of being that people have, namely, that humans are the sort of beings able to pose the question of the meaning of being. According to Canadian philosopher ] Heidegger was probably influenced by Scotus in this approach.<ref>{{cite journal |last=McGrath |first=Sean J. |author-link=Sean McGrath (philosopher) |title=Heidegger and Duns Scotus on Truth and Language |journal=] |volume=57 |number=2 |year=2003 |pages=339–358 |jstor=20131978 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/20131978 |access-date=28 November 2023 |archive-date=1 December 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231201195241/https://www.jstor.org/stable/20131978 |url-status=live }}</ref> His term for us, in this phenomenological context, is ].{{sfn|Sandkühler|2010}} | |||
] | |||
====Dilthey==== | |||
Heidegger's very early project of developing a "hermeneutics of ] life" and his hermeneutical transformation of phenomenology was influenced in part by his reading of the works of ]. Heidegger's portrayal of history, historicity, and generation need to be interpreted in this context and, in particular, the correspondence between ] and ]. | |||
This procedure works because Dasein's ''pre-ontological'' understanding of being shapes experience. Dasein's ordinary and even mundane experience of "being-in-the-world" provides "access to the meaning" or "sense of being"; that is, the terms in which "something becomes intelligible as something."{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=151}} Heidegger proposes that this ordinary "prescientific" understanding precedes abstract ways of knowing, such as logic or theory.{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=12}} ''Being and Time'' is designed to show how this implicit understanding can be made progressively explicit through ] and ].{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|pages=1–27}}{{sfn|Whittingham|2018}}{{sfn|Inwood|1999}} | |||
Of the influence of Dilthey, ] writes the following: "As far as Dilthey is concerned, we all know today what I have known for a long time: namely that it is a mistake to conclude on the basis of the citation in ''Being and Time'' that Dilthey was especially influential in the development of Heidegger's thinking in the mid-1920s. This dating of the influence is much too late." He adds that by the fall of 1923 it was plain that Heidegger felt "the clear superiority of Count Yorck over the famous scholar, Dilthey." Gadamer nevertheless makes clear that Dilthey's influence was important in helping the youthful Heidegger "in distancing himself from the systematic ideal of Neo-Kantianism, as Heidegger acknowledges in ''Being and Time''."<ref>Hans-Georg Gadamer, "Martin Heidegger's One Path", in Theodore Kisiel & John van Buren (eds.), ''Reading Heidegger from the Start: Essays in His Earliest Thought'' (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), pp. 22–4.</ref> Based on Heidegger's earliest lecture courses, in which Heidegger already engages Dilthey's thought prior to the period Gadamer mentions as "too late", recent scholars as diverse as ] and ] have argued for the importance of Diltheyan concepts and strategies in the formation of Heidegger's thought.<ref>In ''The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time'' (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), Theodor Kisiel designates the first version of the project that culminates in ''Being and Time'', "the Dilthey draft" (p. 313). David Farrell Krell comments in ''Daimon Life: Heidegger and Life-Philosophy'' (Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1992) that "Heidegger's project sprouts (in part, but in ''good'' part) from the soil of Dilthey's philosophy of factical-historical life" (p. 35).</ref> | |||
====Being-in-the-world==== | |||
Even though Gadamer's interpretation of Heidegger has been questioned, there is little doubt that Heidegger seized upon Dilthey's concept of hermeneutics. Heidegger's novel ideas about ontology required a ''gestalt'' formation, not merely a series of logical arguments, in order to demonstrate his fundamentally new paradigm of thinking, and the hermeneutic circle offered a new and powerful tool for the articulation and realization of these ideas. | |||
Heidegger introduces the term ] to denote a "living being" through its activity of "being there".{{sfn|Horrigan-Kelly|Millar|Dowling|2016}} Understood as a unitary phenomenon rather than a contingent, additive combination, it is characterized by Heidegger as "being-in-the-world".{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.2.3}} | |||
Heidegger insists that the 'in' of Dasein's being-in-the-world is an 'in' of involvement or of engagement, not of objective, physical enclosedness. The sense in which Dasein is 'in' the world is the sense of "residing" or "dwelling" in the world.{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=54}} Heidegger provides a few examples: "having to do with something, producing something, attending to something and looking after it, making use of something".{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=56}}{{sfn|Polt|1999|pages=46–49}} | |||
====Husserl==== | |||
There is disagreement over the degree of influence that Husserl had on Heidegger's philosophical development, just as there is disagreement about the degree to which Heidegger's philosophy is grounded in phenomenology. These disagreements centre around how much of Husserlian phenomenology is contested by Heidegger, and how much this phenomenology in fact informs Heidegger's own understanding. | |||
Just as 'being-in' does not denote objective, physical enclosedness, so 'world', as Heidegger uses the term, does not denote a universe of physical objects. The world, in Heidegger's sense, is to be understood according to our sense of our possibilities: things present themselves to people in terms of their projects, the uses to which they can put them. The 'sight' with which people grasp equipment is not a mentalistic intentionality, but what Heidegger calls 'circumspection'.{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=69}} This is to say that equipment reveals itself in terms of its 'towards-which,' in terms of the work it is good for. In the everyday world, people are absorbed within the equipmental totality of their work-world.{{sfn|Polt|1999|loc=pp. 46–61, esp. diagram on p.61}}{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=88–100}} Moreover, on Heidegger's analysis, this entails a radical holism.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.2.3}} In his own words, "there 'is' no such thing as ''an'' equipment".{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|loc=p. 97, qtd. in translators' fn. 1}} | |||
On the relation between the two figures, Gadamer wrote the following: "When asked about phenomenology, Husserl was quite right to answer as he used to in the period directly after World War I: 'Phenomenology, that is me and Heidegger'." Nevertheless, Gadamer noted that Heidegger was no patient collaborator with Husserl, and that Heidegger's "rash ascent to the top, the incomparable fascination he aroused, and his stormy temperament surely must have made Husserl, the patient one, as suspicious of Heidegger as he always had been of ] volcanic fire."<ref>Hans-Georg Gadamer, "Martin Heidegger—75 Years", ''Heidegger's Ways'' (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), p. 18.</ref> | |||
For example, when someone sits down to dinner and picks up their fork, they are not picking up an object with good stabbing properties: they are non-reflectively engaging an 'in-order-to-eat'. When it works as expected, equipment is transparent; when it is used, it is subsumed under the work toward which it is employed. Heidegger calls this structure of practically ordered reference relations the 'worldhood of the world'.{{sfn|Polt|1999|loc=pp. 46–61, esp. diagram on p.61}}{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=88–100}} | |||
Robert J. Dostal understands the importance of Husserl to be profound: | |||
:Heidegger himself, who is supposed to have broken with Husserl, bases his hermeneutics on an account of time that not only parallels Husserl's account in many ways but seems to have been arrived at through the same phenomenological method as was used by Husserl. The differences between Husserl and Heidegger are significant, but if we do not see how much it is the case that Husserlian phenomenology provides the framework for Heidegger's approach, we will not be able to appreciate the exact nature of Heidegger's project in ''Being and Time'' or why he let it unfinished.<ref>Robert J. Dostal, "Time and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger", in Charles Guignon (ed.), ''The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger'' (Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 142.</ref> | |||
Heidegger calls the mode of being of such entities "ready-to-hand", for they are understood only in being handled.{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=50}} If the fork is made of plastic, however, and it snaps in the course of using it, then it assumes the mode of being that Heidegger calls "present-at-hand." For now the fork needs to be made the object of focal awareness, considering it in terms of its properties. Is it too broken to use? If so, could the diner possibly get by with another utensil or just with their fingers? This kind of equipmental breakdown is not the only way that objects become present-at-hand for us, but Heidegger considers it typical of the way that this shift occurs in the course of ordinary goings-on.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=71-72}} | |||
Daniel O. Dahlstrom sees Heidegger's presentation of his work as a departure from Husserl as unfairly misrepresenting Husserl's own work. Dahlstrom concludes his consideration of the relation between Heidegger and Husserl as follows: | |||
:Heidegger's silence about the stark similarities between his account of temporality and Husserl's investigation of internal time-consciousness contributes to a ''misrepresentation'' of Husserl's account of intentionality. Contrary to the criticisms Heidegger advances in his lectures, intentionality (and, by implication, the meaning of 'to be') in the final analysis is not construed by Husserl as sheer presence (be it the presence of a fact or object, act or event). Yet for all its "dangerous closeness" to what Heidegger understands by temporality, Husserl's account of internal time-consciousness does differ fundamentally. In Husserl's account the structure of protentions is accorded neither the finitude nor the primacy that Heidegger claims are central to the original future of ecstatic-horizonal temporality.<ref>Daniel O. Dahlstrom, "Heidegger's Critique of Husserl", in Theodore Kisiel & John van Buren (eds.), ''Reading Heidegger from the Start: Essays in His Earliest Thought'' (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), p. 244.</ref> | |||
In this way, Heidegger creates a theoretical space for the categories of subject and object, while at the same time denying that they apply to our most basic way of moving about in the world, of which they are instead presented as derivative.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.2.2}} | |||
====Kierkegaard==== | |||
Contemporary Heideggerians regard ] as, by far, the greatest philosophical contributor to Heidegger's own existentialist concepts.<ref>Dreyfus, Hubert. ''Being-in-the-world: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I.'' (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), Sec. Appendix.</ref>. Heidegger's concepts of anxiety ('']'') and mortality draw on Kierkegaard and are indebted to the way in which the latter lays out the importance of our subjective relation to truth, our existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world. Nonetheless, it is important to notice the difference between the Danish philosopher, whose thought was both individualistic and Christian, and Heidegger, who conceived of human existence as thoroughly social and sharply distinguished philosophy itself from all personal, scientific, and religious commitments. | |||
Heidegger presents three primary structural features of being-in-the-world: understanding, attunement, and discourse. He calls these features "existentiales" or "existentialia" (''Existenzialien'') to distinguish their ontological status, as distinct from the "categories" of metaphysics.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=40–42}}{{sfn|Inwood|1999|pages=61–62}} | |||
====Hölderlin and Nietzsche==== | |||
] and ] were both important influences on Heidegger, and many of his lecture courses were devoted to one or other of these figures, especially in the 1930s and 1940s. The lectures on Nietzsche focused on fragments posthumously published under the title '']'', rather than on Nietzsche's published works. Heidegger read ''The Will to Power'' as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics, and the lectures are a kind of dialogue between the two thinkers. | |||
* ''Understanding'' is "our fundamental ability to be someone, to do things, to get around in the world". It is the basic "know-how" in terms of which Dasein goes about pursuing the usually humdrum tasks that make up daily life. Heidegger argues that this mode of understanding is more fundamental than theoretical understanding.{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=65}} | |||
This is also the case for the lecture courses devoted to the poetry of Friedrich Hölderlin, which became an increasingly central focus of Heidegger's work and thought. Heidegger grants to Hölderlin a singular place within the history of being and the history of Germany, as a herald whose thought is yet to be "heard" in Germany or the West. Many of Heidegger's works from the 1930s onwards include meditations on lines from Hölderlin's poetry, and several of the lecture courses are devoted to the reading of a single poem (see, for example, '']''). | |||
* ''Attunement'' is "our way of finding ourselves thrust into the world".{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=65}} It can also be translated as "disposition" or "affectedness". (The standard translation of Macquarrie and Robinson uses "state-of-mind", but this misleadingly suggests a private mental state.) There is no perfect equivalent for Heidegger's ''Befindlichkeit'', which is not even an ordinary German word.{{sfn|Heidegger|1996a|page=xv}}{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=168}}{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=65}} What needs to be conveyed, however, is "being found in a situation where things and opinions already matter".{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=168}} | |||
* ''Discourse'' (sometimes: ''talk'' or ''telling'' ) is "the articulation of the world into recognizable, communicable patterns of meaning." It is implicated in both understanding attunement: "The world that is opened up by moods and grasped by understanding gets organized by discourse. Discourse makes language possible."{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=65}} According to Heidegger, "Discourse is the articulation of intelligibility."{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=161}} In its most basic form, this referential whole manifests itself in the way things are told apart just in the course of using them.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=214}} | |||
Heidegger unifies these three existential features of Dasein in a composite structure he terms "care":{{efn|] provides a brief discussion of this term to illustrate Heidegger's use of language more generally: "The word 'care', which corresponds closely, if not exactly, to the German ''Sorge'', has a range of senses. We can see this from the adjectives it forms and the words they contrast with: 'careworn' and 'carefree'; 'careful' and 'careless'; 'caring' and 'uncaring'. These oppositions are not the same: one can be, for example, both careworn and careless. In ordinary usage not everyone is careworn, careful and caring all the time. Some of us are carefree, careless or uncaring. Heidegger makes two innovations. First, he uses 'care' in a broad sense which underlies its diversification into the careworn, the careful and the caring. Second, in this sense of 'care', he insists, everyone cares; no one is wholly carefree, careless or uncaring. It is only because everyone is, in this fundamental sense, care-ful, that we can ever be carefree, careless or uncaring in the ordinary, or as he has it, the 'ontical', senses of these words. In the 'ontological' sense of 'care', everyone cares. All human beings, again, are 'ahead of themselves' (''sich vorweg''), roughly 'up to something' or on the look out for what to do. What about those mired in hopeless despair? Even those, Heidegger insists, are 'ahead of themselves': 'Hopelessness does not tear Dasein away from its possibilities; it is only a particular mode of being toward these possibilities' (BT, 236)."{{sfn|Inwood|1999|pages=2–3}} }} "ahead-of-itself-being-already-in-(the-world) as being-amidst (entities encountered within-the-world)."{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=192}}{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=238–39}} What unifies this formula is ''temporality''. Understanding is oriented towards future possibilities, attunement is shaped by the past, and discourse discloses the present in those terms.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|pages=244–45}}{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§2.2.7}} In this way, the investigation into the being of Dasein leads to time. Much of Division II of ''Being and Time'' is devoted to a more fundamental reinterpretation of the findings of Division I in terms of Dasein's temporality.{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=85}} | |||
=== Heidegger and Eastern thought === | |||
====''Das Man''==== | |||
Some writers on Heidegger's work see possibilities within it for dialogue with traditions of thought outside of Western philosophy, particularly East Asian thinking. Despite perceived differences between Eastern and Western philosophy, some of Heidegger's later work, particularly "A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer", does show an interest in initiating such a dialogue.<ref>Heidegger, "A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer", in ''On the Way to Language'' (New York: Harper & Row, 1971).</ref> Heidegger himself had contact with a number of leading Japanese intellectuals, including members of the ], notably ], ] and Kyoshi Miki. | |||
As implied in the analysis of both attunement and discourse, Dasein is "always already", or ], a social being. In Heidegger's technical idiom, Dasein is "Dasein-with" (''Mitsein''), which he presents as equally primordial with "being-one's self" (''Selbstsein'').{{sfn|Inwood|1999|page=31}} | |||
Heidegger's term for this existential feature of Dasein is ''das Man'', which is a German pronoun, ''man'', that Heidegger turns into a noun.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|page=212}} In English it is usually translated as either "the they" or "the one" (sometimes also capitalized); for, as Heidegger puts it, "By 'others' we do not mean everyone else but me.... They are rather those from whom for the most part, one does ''not'' distinguish oneself—those among whom one is too".{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|page=118}} Quite frequently the term is just left in the German. | |||
Furthermore, it has also been claimed that a number of elements within Heidegger's thought bear a close parallel to Eastern philosophical ideas, particularly with ] and ]. An account given by Paul Hsao (in ''Heidegger and Asian Thought'') records a remark by Chang Chung-Yuan claiming that "Heidegger is the only Western Philosopher who not only intellectually understands but has intuitively grasped Taoist thought." | |||
According to philosopher ], part of Heidegger's aim is to show that, contrary to Husserl, individuals do not generate an intersubjective world from their separate activities; rather, "these activities ''presuppose'' the disclosure of one shared world." This is one way in which Heidegger breaks from the ] tradition of beginning from the perspective of individual subjectivity.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=142}} | |||
According to ], the concept of ''Dasein'' was inspired—although Heidegger remains silent on this—by ] concept of ''das-in-der-Welt-sein'' (being in the world) expressed in '']'' to describe ] philosophy, which Imamichi's teacher had offered to Heidegger in 1919, after having studied with him the year before.<ref name=Imamichi> Tomonubu Imamichi, ''In Search of Wisdom. One Philosopher's Journey'', Tokyo, International House of Japan, 2004 (quoted by Anne Fagot-Largeau during her at the ] on December 7, 2006).</ref> | |||
Dreyfus argues that the chapter on ''das Man'' is "the most confused" in ''Being and Time'' and so is often misinterpreted. The problem, he says, is that Heidegger's presentation conflates two opposing influences. The first is Dilthey's account of the role that public and historical contexts have in the production of significance. The second is Kierkegaard's insistence that truth is never to be found in the crowd.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=143}} | |||
Some scholars interested in the relationships between Western philosophy and the history of ideas in ] and Arabic philosophical medieval sources may have been influenced by Heidegger's work.<ref> See for instance: Nader El-Bizri, ''The Phenomenological Quest between ] and Heidegger'' (Binghamton, N.Y.: Global Publications SUNY, 2000)</ref> | |||
The Diltheyian dimension of Heidegger's analysis positions ''das Man'' as ontologically existential in the same way as understanding, affectedness, and discourse. This dimension of Heidegger's analysis captures the way that a socio-historical "background" makes possible the specific significance that entities and activities can have.{{sfn|Dreyfus|1991|page=143}} Philosopher ] expands upon the term: "It is that of which I am not simply unaware... but at the same time I cannot be said to be explicitly or focally aware of it, because that status is already occupied by what it is making intelligible".{{sfn|Taylor|1993|page=325}} For this reason, background non-representationally informs and enables engaged agency in the world, but is something that people can never make fully explicit to themselves.{{sfn|Taylor|1993|page=327}} | |||
==Heidegger and National Socialism== | |||
{{main|Heidegger and Nazism}} | |||
The Kierkegaardian influence on Heidegger's analysis introduces a more ] dimension to ''Being and Time''. (] is a broad philosophical movement largely defined by ] and is not to be confused with Heidegger's technical analysis of the specific existential features of Dasein.) Its central notion is ''authenticity'', which emerges as a problem from the "publicness" built into the existential role of ''das Man''. In Heidegger's own words: | |||
=== The rectorate === | |||
<blockquote>In this inconspicuousness and unascertainability, the real dictatorship of the 'they' is unfolded. We take pleasure and enjoy ourselves as ''they'' take pleasure; we read, see and judge about literature and art as ''they'' see and judge; likewise we shrink back from the 'great mass' as ''they'' shrink back; we find 'shocking' what they find shocking. The 'they', which is nothing definite, and which we all are, through not as the sum, prescribes the kind of being of everydayness.{{sfn|Heidegger|1962|pages=126–27}}</blockquote> | |||
] | |||
] was named ] on January 30, 1933. Heidegger was elected ] of the ] on April 21, 1933, assuming the position the following day, and on May 1 he joined the ]. Heidegger delivered his inaugural address, the , on May 27. It was entitled "The Self-Assertion of the German University", and became notorious for its praise of National Socialism. Heidegger wrote, for example that "The German people must choose its future, and this future is bound to the ]."<ref>Source: "German Men and Women!", Freiburger Studentenzeitung,, November 10, 1933, as quoted in //Introducing Heidegger// by Jeff Collins et al., Icon Books, Thriplow, Cambridge, page 96</ref> | |||
This "dictatorship of ''das Man''" threatens to undermine Heidegger's entire project of uncovering the meaning of being because it does not seem possible, from such a condition, to even raise the question of being that Heidegger claims to pursue. He responds to this challenge with his account of ]. | |||
His tenure as rector was, however, fraught with difficulties from the outset. Some National Socialist education officials viewed him as a rival, while others saw his efforts as comical. Some of Heidegger's fellow National Socialists also ridiculed his philosophical writings as gibberish. He finally offered his resignation on April 23, 1934, and it was accepted on April 27. Heidegger remained a member of both the academic faculty and of the Nazi party until the end of the war. | |||
====Authenticity==== | |||
Philosophical historian ] places Heidegger's embrace of National Socialism during this period within the context of its similar and often even more enthusiastic acceptance by many other German philosophers. He characterises Heidegger's stance while rector in the following way: | |||
Heidegger's term ''Eigentlichkeit'' is a neologism, in which Heidegger stresses the root ''eigen'', meaning "own." So this word, usually translated "authenticity", could just as well be translated "ownedness" or "being one's own".{{sfn|Varga|Guignon|2014|loc=§3.1}}{{sfn|Inwood|1999|pages=22–23}} Authenticity, according to Heidegger, is a matter of taking responsibility for being, that is, the stand that people take with respect to their ultimate projects. It is, in his terms, a matter of taking a properly "resolute" stand on "for-the-sake-of-which". Put differently, the "self" to which one is true in authenticity is not something just "there" to be discovered, but instead is a matter of "on-going narrative construction".{{sfn|Varga|Guignon|2014|loc=§3.1}} | |||
Scholars Somogy Varga and ] describe three ways by which Dasein might attain an authentic relation to itself from out of its "fallen" condition as "they"-self. First, a powerful mood such as ] can disclose Dasein to itself as an ultimately isolated individual. Second, direct confrontation with Dasein's "ownmost" potential for death can similarly disclose to Dasein its own irreducible finitude. Third, experiencing "the call of conscience" can disclose to Dasein its own "guilt" (''Schuld'') as the debt it has to itself in virtue of having taken over pre-given possibilities that it is now Dasein's own responsibility to maintain.{{sfn|Varga|Guignon|2014|loc=§3.1}} | |||
:Though as rector he prevented students from displaying an anti-Semitic poster at the entrance to the university and from holding a book burning, he kept in close contact with the Nazi student leaders and clearly signaled to them his sympathy with their activism.<ref>Hans Sluga, ''Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in Nazi Germany'' (Cambridge, Massachusetts, & London: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 149.</ref> | |||
Philosopher ] describes authenticity as "resolving to accept the openness which, paradoxically, one already is".{{sfn|Zimmerman|1981|page=xx}} He emphasizes that this is a matter, not of "intellectual comprehension", but of "hard-won insight".{{sfn|Zimmerman|1981|page=xix}} Authenticity is ultimately a matter of allowing the ego to be "eclipsed by the manifestation of one's finitude".{{sfn|Zimmerman|1981|page=xxvii}} | |||
In 1945 Heidegger wrote a defence of his term as rector, which he gave to his son Hermann, and which was published in 1983. In it Heidegger referred to his 1933–34 involvement in the following terms: | |||
Although the term "authenticity" disappears from Heidegger's writing after ''Being and Time'', Zimmerman argues that it is supplanted in his later thought by the less subjective or ] notion of ''Ereignis''. This ordinary German term for "event" or "happening" is theorized by Heidegger as the appropriation of Dasein into a cosmic play of concealment and appearance.{{sfn|Zimmerman|1981|pages=xxiv–xxviii}} | |||
:The rectorate was an attempt to see something in the movement that had come to power, beyond all its failings and crudeness, that was much more far-reaching and that could perhaps one day bring a concentration on the Germans' Western historical essence. It will in no way be denied that at the time I believed in such possibilities and for that reason renounced the actual vocation of thinking in favor of being effective in an official capacity. In no way will what was caused by my own inadequacy in office be played down. But these points of view do not capture what is essential and what moved me to accept the rectorate.<ref>Heidegger, "The Rectorate 1933/34: Facts and Thoughts", in Günther Neske & Emil Kettering (eds.), ''Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers'' (New York: Paragon House, 1990), p. 29.</ref> | |||
=== |
===Later works: The Turn=== | ||
{{see also|Kehre}} | |||
Heidegger's "Turn", which is sometimes referred to by the German ''die Kehre'', refers to a change in his work as early as 1930 that became clearly established by the 1940s, according to some commentators, who variously describe a shift of focus or a major change in outlook.{{sfn|Korab-Karpowicz|loc=§1}}{{sfn|Richardson|1963}}{{efn|"In a 1947 piece, in which Heidegger distances his views from Sartre's existentialism, he links the turn to his own failure to produce the missing divisions of ''Being and Time'' . ... At root Heidegger's later philosophy shares the deep concerns of ''Being and Time'', in that it is driven by the same preoccupation with ] and our relationship with it that propelled the earlier work. ... he later Heidegger does seem to think that his earlier focus on Dasein bears the stain of a ] that ultimately blocks the path to an understanding of Being. This is not to say that the later thinking turns away altogether from the project of transcendental hermeneutic phenomenology. The project of illuminating the a priori conditions on the basis of which entities show up as intelligible to us is still at the heart of things."{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§3.1}} }} | |||
Heidegger himself frequently used the term to refer to the shift announced at the end of ''Being and Time'' from "being and time" to "time and being". However, he rejected the existence of the "sharp 'about turn{{'"}} posited by some interpreters.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|page=8}} Scholar ] also calls attention to the fact that many of the ideas from ''Being and Time'' are retained in a different vocabulary in his later work—and also that, in other cases, a word or expression common throughout his career comes to acquire a different meaning in the later works.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|page=8}} | |||
Beginning in 1917 Edmund Husserl championed Heidegger's work and helped him secure the retiring Husserl's chair in Philosophy at the University of Freiburg.<ref> (Rowman and Littlefield, 2003, p. 120.)</ref> | |||
This supposed shift—applied here to cover about 30 years of Heidegger's 40-year writing career—has been described by commentators from widely varied viewpoints, for instance, from ''dwelling'' (being) in the world to ''doing'' (temporality) in the world.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§3.1}}{{sfn|Heidegger|2002}} This aspect, in particular the 1951 essay "Building Dwelling Thinking", has influenced several architectural theorists.{{sfn|Davies|2017}} | |||
On April 6, 1933, the Reichskommissar of Baden province, Robert Wagner, suspended all Jewish government employees, including present and retired faculty at the University of Freiburg. Heidegger's predecessor as rector formally notified Edmund Husserl of his "enforced leave of absence" on April 14, 1933. | |||
Other interpreters believe the Turn can be overstated or doesn't exist at all. For instance, ] believes this supposed change is "far less dramatic than usually suggested", and entails merely a change in focus and method.{{sfn|Polt|Fried|2001|page=15}} ] argued that the Turn isn't found in Heidegger's writings, but is simply a misconception.{{sfn|Wrathall|2010}} | |||
Heidegger became rector of the University of Freiburg on April 22, 1933. The following week the national Reich law of April 28, 1933 replaced Reichskommissar Wagner's decree. The Reich law required the firing of Jewish professors from German universities, including those, such as Husserl, who had previously converted to Christianity. The termination of the retired professor Husserl's academic privileges thus involved no specific action on Heidegger's part.<ref> (October/November 1999 issue of Boston Review.)</ref> | |||
Some notable later works are "]" (1935), '']'' (1937), "]" (1946), "Building Dwelling Thinking" (1951), "]" (1954), and "]" (1954). | |||
Heidegger had by then broken off contact with Husserl other than through intermediaries. Heidegger later claimed that the relationship with Husserl had already become strained after Husserl publicly "settled accounts" with Heidegger and ] in the early 1930s.<ref>Martin Heidegger, "Der Spiegel Interview", in Günther Neske & Emil Kettering (eds.), ''Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers'' (New York: Paragon House, 1990), p. 48.</ref> | |||
===The history of being=== | |||
Heidegger did not attend his former mentor's cremation in 1938. In 1941, under pressure from publisher Max Niemeyer, Heidegger agreed to remove the dedication to Husserl from ''Being and Time'' (restored in post-war editions).<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil'' (Cambridge, Mass., & London: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 253-8.</ref> | |||
The idea of asking about being may be traced back via Aristotle to ]. Heidegger claims to revive this question of being that had been largely forgotten by the ] tradition extending from ] to ], a forgetfulness extending into the ], as well as modern science and technology. In pursuit of the retrieval of the question, Heidegger spends considerable time reflecting on ], in particular on Plato, ], ], and ]. | |||
In his later philosophy, Heidegger attempts to reconstruct the "history of being" in order to show how the different epochs in the history of philosophy were dominated by different conceptions of being.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|loc= §History of being}} His goal is to retrieve the original experience of being present in the ] that was covered up by later philosophers.{{sfn|Korab-Karpowicz|loc=§4}} | |||
Heidegger's behavior towards Husserl has evoked controversy. Hannah Arendt had initially suggested that Heidegger's behavior precipitated Husserl's death. She called him a "potential murderer." However, she later recanted this accusation.<ref>Elzbieta Ettinger,''Hannah Arendt – Martin Heidegger'', (New Haven, Conn., & London: Yale University Press, 1995), p. 37.</ref> | |||
According to ], Heidegger believed "the thinking of ] and ], which lies at the origin of philosophy, was falsified and misinterpreted" by Plato and Aristotle, thus tainting all of subsequent Western philosophy.{{sfn|Korab-Karpowicz|2016|page=58}} In his '']'', Heidegger states, "Among the most ancient Greek thinkers, it is Heraclitus who was subjected to the most fundamentally un-Greek misinterpretation in the course of Western history, and who nevertheless in more recent times has provided the strongest impulses toward redisclosing what is authentically Greek."{{sfn|Heidegger|2014}} | |||
=== Post-rectorate National Socialist period === | |||
] writes that Heidegger aims to correct this misunderstanding by reviving Presocratic notions of being with an emphasis on "understanding the way beings show up in (and as) an unfolding ''happening or event''." Guignon adds that "we might call this alternative outlook 'event ontology.{{'"}}{{sfn|Polt|Fried|2001|page=36}} | |||
After the spectacular failure of Heidegger's rectorship, he withdrew from most political activity, without canceling his membership in the NSDAP. Nevertheless, references to National Socialism continued to appear in his work, usually in ambiguous ways. | |||
===Language=== | |||
In the course of his 1935 lectures, Heidegger referred to the "inner truth and greatness of this movement" (''die innere Wahrheit und Größe dieser Bewegung''), that is, of ]. This phrase remained when the lectures were published in 1953 under the title, ''An Introduction to Metaphysics''; however, Heidegger added a parenthetical qualification, without mentioning this change at the time of publication: "(namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity) (''nämlich die Begegnung der planetarisch bestimmten Technik und des neuzeitlichen Menschen'')."<ref>Rainer Marten, letter to Jürgen Habermas, January 28, 1988, cited by Habermas in "Work and ''Weltanschauung'': the Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective", ''Critical Inquiry'' 15 (1989), pp. 452–54.</ref> | |||
In ''Being and Time'', language is presented as logically secondary to Dasein's understanding of the world and its significance. On this conception of worldhood, language can develop from prelinguistic significance.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|p=208}} | |||
Post-turn, Heidegger refines his position to present some basic words (e.g., ''phusis'', the Greek term that roughly translates to "nature") as world-disclosive, that is, as establishing the foundational parameters in terms of which Dasein's understanding can occur in the specific ways that it does. It is in this context that Heidegger proclaims that "Language is the house of being."{{sfn|Inwood|1999|p=209}} | |||
In the lectures of 1942, published posthumously as '']'', Heidegger makes the following remark: | |||
In the present age, he says, the language of "technology", or instrumental reason, flatten the significance of our world. For salvation, he turns to poetry.{{sfn|Inwood|1999|p=209}} | |||
:Today—if one still reads such books at all—one can scarcely read a treatise or book on the Greeks without everywhere being assured that here, with the Greeks, "everything" is "politically" determined. In the majority of "research results", the Greeks appear as the pure National Socialists. This overenthusiasm on the part of academics seems not even to notice that with such "results" it does National Socialism and its historical uniqueness no service at all, not that it needs this anyhow.<ref>Heidegger, '']'' (Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996), pp. 79-80.</ref> | |||
Heidegger rejected the notion of language being purely a means of communication. Language construed us such, he believed, would form the basis of an age of technology, the digital thought processes of which would only use language to organise and communicate the coverage of that which exists. Thinking in terms of calculation and digital processing would put man at odds with language, at the centre of everything that exists. If man would believe that they would have language at their disposal, that they would be the one to use it, then, Heidegger believed, man would completely miss the core tenet of language itself:<ref>''Wegmarken.'' GA 9, S. 75.</ref> "It is language that speaks, not man. Man only speaks if they neatly correspond to language."<ref>''Der Satz vom Grund.'' GA 10, S. 143.</ref> In this way, Heidegger wanted to point out that man is only a ''participant'' of language that they have not themselves created. Man is bound within a sort of process of transfer and may only ''act'' with respect to anything the language conveys. | |||
] met Heidegger in 1936 while the latter was visiting Rome to lecture on Hölderlin. In an account set down in 1940 and not intended for publication, Löwith recounted an exchange with Heidegger over editorials published in the '']'': | |||
In this, however, Heidegger does not think in terms of ]: The ] of the formulation ''language speaks'' (originally in German "die Sprache spricht") is his way of trying to prevent the phenomenon of language to be used with respect to anything else than language itself. In line with his unique thinking, he is seeking to avoid having to justify the language by anything else. In this way, language could for instance never be explained by the sheer transmission of acoustic sounds, or speaking. According to Heidegger, language is rather difficult to fathom because we are too close to it, hence we need to speak about that which usually remains unmentioned because it is just to close to us. His work "Unterwegs zur Sprache" (''On the way to language'') is an attempt to reach "a place we already are in."<ref>''Unterwegs zur Sprache.'' GA 12, S. 199.</ref> | |||
: told him that I did not agree either with the way in which ] was attacking him or in the way Staiger]] was defending him, because my opinion was that his taking the side of National Socialism was in agreement with the essence of his philosophy. Heidegger told me unreservedly that I was right and developed his idea by saying that his idea of historicity was the foundation for his political involvement.<ref name="Karl Löwith 1986 p. 57"/> | |||
=== Influences === | |||
Löwith went on to say: | |||
{{multiple image | |||
| width = 140 | |||
| image1 = Nietzsche187a.jpg | |||
| alt1 = Friedrich Nietzsche | |||
| image2 = FK Hiemer - Friedrich Hölderlin (Pastell 1792).jpg | |||
| alt2 = Friedrich Hölderlin, | |||
| footer = Heidegger dedicated many of his lectures to both Nietzsche and Hölderlin. | |||
}} | |||
] and ] were both important influences on Heidegger, and many of his lecture courses were devoted to one or the other, especially in the 1930s and 1940s.{{sfn|Raffoul|Nelson|2013|page=224}} The lectures on Nietzsche focused on fragments posthumously published under the title '']'', rather than on Nietzsche's published works. Heidegger reads ''The Will to Power'' as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics, and the lectures are a kind of dialogue between the two thinkers. | |||
:In response to my remark that I could understand many things about his attitude, with one exception, which was that he would permit himself to be seated at the same table with a figure such as ] (at the German Academy of Law), he was silent at first. At last he uttered this well-known rationalisation (which Karl Barth saw so clearly), which amounted to saying that "it all would have been much worse if some men of knowledge had not been involved." And with a bitter resentment towards people of culture, he concluded his statement: "If these gentlemen had not considered themselves too refined to become involved, things would have been different, but I had to stay in there alone." To my reply that one did not have to be very refined to refuse to work with a Streicher, he answered that it was useless to discuss Streicher; the ''Stürmer'' was nothing more than "pornography." Why didn't Hitler get rid of this sinister individual? He didn't understand it.<ref>ibid, p. 477</ref> | |||
] says that Heidegger's theoretical acceptance of "destiny" has much in common with the ] of Marxism. But Marxists believe Heidegger's "theoretical acceptance is antagonistic to practical political activity and implies fascism". Gillespie, however, says "the real danger" from Heidegger isn't ] but ]. Modernity has cast mankind toward a new goal "on the brink of profound ]" that is "so alien it requires the construction of a new tradition to make it comprehensible."{{sfn|Gillespie|1984|page=133}} | |||
For commentators such as Habermas who credit Löwith's account, there are a number of generally shared implications: one is that Heidegger did not turn away from National Socialism ''per se'' but became deeply disaffected with the official philosophy and ideology of the party, as embodied by ] or ], whose biologistic racist doctrines he never accepted. | |||
Gillespie extrapolates from Heidegger's writings that humankind may degenerate into "scientists, workers, and brutes".{{sfn|Gillespie|1984|page=}} According to Gillespie, Heidegger envisaged this abyss to be the greatest event in the history of the West because it might enable humanity to comprehend being more profoundly and primordially than the ].{{sfn|Gillespie|1984|page=151}} | |||
=== Post-war period === | |||
The poetry of Friedrich Hölderlin became an increasingly central focus of Heidegger's later work and thought. Heidegger grants Hölderlin a singular place within the history of being and the history of Germany, as a herald whose thought is yet to be "heard" in Germany or the West more generally. Many of Heidegger's works from the 1930s onwards include meditations on lines from Hölderlin's poetry, and several of the lecture courses are devoted to the reading of a single poem; for example, '']''. | |||
Heidegger's affair with Hannah Arendt occurred some time before Heidegger's involvement in National Socialism, but her friendship with Heidegger did not end when she moved to ] to continue her studies under ]. Arendt later spoke on his behalf at his ] hearings. Jaspers spoke against him at the same hearings, suggesting he would have a detrimental influence on German students because of his powerful teaching presence. Arendt cautiously resumed their friendship after the war, despite or even because of the widespread contempt for Heidegger and his political sympathies. The denazification hearings resulted in Heidegger being forbidden to teach between 1945 and 1951. One consequence of his disfavour in Germany was that Heidegger began to engage far more in the French philosophical scene. | |||
==Heidegger and the Nazi Party== | |||
In a lecture on technology delivered at Bremen in 1949, Heidegger made the following controversial remark: | |||
{{Main|Martin Heidegger and Nazism|l1=Heidegger and Nazism}} | |||
{{Conservatism in Germany|Intellectuals}} | |||
===The rectorate=== | |||
:Agriculture is now a motorized food industry, the same thing in its essence as the production of corpses in the gas chambers and the extermination camps, the same thing as blockades and the reduction of countries to famine, the same thing as the manufacture of hydrogen bombs.<ref>Cited in Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, ''Heidegger, Art and Politics: The Fiction of the Political'' (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), p. 34.</ref> | |||
], where Heidegger was Rector from 21 April 1933 to 23 April 1934]] | |||
] was sworn in as ] on 30 January 1933. Heidegger was elected ] of the ] on 21 April 1933, and assumed the position the following day. On 1 May, he joined the ]. | |||
On 27 May 1933, Heidegger delivered his inaugural address, the ''Rektoratsrede'' (titled "The Self-assertion of the German University"), in a hall decorated with swastikas, with members of the ] (SA) and prominent Nazi Party officials present.{{sfn|Sharpe|2018}} | |||
This quotation has been the subject of widespread criticism and interpretation. ], for example, described it as "scandalously inadequate."<ref>Lacoue-Labarthe, ''Heidegger, Art and Politics'', p. 34.</ref> | |||
That summer he delivered a lecture on a fragment of ] (usually translated in English: "War is the father of all"). His notes on this lecture appear under the heading "Struggle as the essence of Beings."<ref name=":0">{{Cite book |last=Heidegger |first=Martin |title=Being & Truth |publisher=Indiana University Press |year=1933 |isbn=978-0253355119 |publication-date=2010 |pages=124 |chapter=The Saying of Hearaclitus: Struggle as the essence of Beings}}</ref> In this lecture he suggests that if an enemy cannot be found for the people then one must be invented, and once conceptualized and identified, then the 'beings' who have discovered or invented this enemy must strive for the total annihilation of the enemy.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
In 1967 Heidegger had an encounter with the poet ], a Jew who had survived concentration camps operated by the Nazis' Romanian allies. While admiring aspects of Heidegger's writings, Celan had long been aware of Heidegger's involvement with National Socialism. | |||
His tenure as rector was fraught with difficulties from the outset. Some ] education officials viewed him as a rival, while others saw his efforts as comical. Some of Heidegger's fellow Nazis also ridiculed his philosophical writings as gibberish. He finally offered his resignation as rector on 23 April 1934, and it was accepted on 27 April. Heidegger remained a member of both the academic faculty and of the Nazi Party until the end of the war.{{sfn|Sheehan|1988}} | |||
On July 24 Celan gave a reading at the University of Freiburg, attended by Heidegger. Heidegger there presented Celan with a copy of ''What is Called Thinking?'', and invited him to visit him at his hut at '']'', an invitation which Celan accepted. On July 25 Celan visited Heidegger at his retreat, signing the guestbook and spending some time walking and talking with Heidegger. The details of their conversation are not known, but the meeting was the subject of a subsequent poem by Celan, entitled "Todtnauberg" (dated August 1, 1967). | |||
Philosophical historian ] wrote, "Though as rector he prevented students from displaying an anti-Semitic poster at the entrance to the university and from holding a book burning, he kept in close contact with the Nazi student leaders and clearly signaled to them his sympathy with their activism."{{sfn|Sluga|2013|page=149}} | |||
The enigmatic poem and the encounter have been discussed by numerous writers on Heidegger and Celan, notably Lacoue-Labarthe. A common interpretation of the poem is that it concerns, in part, Celan's wish for Heidegger to apologize for Heidegger's behavior during the Nazi era. | |||
In 1945, Heidegger wrote of his term as rector, giving the writing to his son Hermann; it was published in 1983: | |||
=== The ''Der Spiegel'' interview === | |||
<blockquote>The rectorate was an attempt to see something in the movement that had come to power, beyond all its failings and crudeness, that was much more far-reaching and that could perhaps one day bring a concentration on the Germans' Western historical essence. It will in no way be denied that at the time I believed in such possibilities and for that reason renounced the actual vocation of thinking in favor of being effective in an official capacity. In no way will what was caused by my own inadequacy in office be played down. But these points of view do not capture what is essential and what moved me to accept the rectorate.{{sfn|Neske|Kettering|1990|page=29}}</blockquote> | |||
On September 23, 1966, Heidegger gave an interview to '']'' magazine, in which he agreed to discuss his political past provided that the interview be published posthumously (it was published on May 31, 1976). In the interview, Heidegger defended his entanglement with National Socialism in two ways: first, he argued that there was no alternative, saying that he was trying to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and thus had to compromise with the Nazi administration. Second, he admitted that he saw an "awakening" ("''Aufbruch''") which might help to find a "new national and social approach" but stated that he changed his mind about this in 1934, largely prompted by the violence of the ]. | |||
===Treatment of Husserl=== | |||
Thus, in his ''Der Spiegel'' interview Heidegger defended as double-speak his 1935 lecture describing the "inner truth and greatness of this movement." He affirmed that Nazi informants who observed his lectures would understand that by "movement" he meant National Socialism. However, Heidegger asserted that his dedicated students would know this statement was no elegy for the NSDAP. Rather, he meant it as he expressed it in the parenthetical clarification later added to ''An Introduction to Metaphysics'' (1953), namely, "the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity." | |||
Beginning in 1917, German-Jewish philosopher ] championed Heidegger's work, and helped Heidegger become his successor for the chair in philosophy at the University of Freiburg in 1928.{{sfn|Benhabib|2003|page=120}} | |||
On 6 April 1933, the Gauleiter of ] Province, Robert Wagner, suspended all Jewish government employees, including present and retired faculty at the University of Freiburg. Heidegger's predecessor as rector formally notified Husserl of his "enforced leave of absence" on 14 April 1933. | |||
The Löwith account from 1936 has been cited to contradict the account given in the ''Spiegel'' interview in two ways: that there was no decisive break with National Socialism in 1934 and that Heidegger was willing to entertain more profound relations between his philosophy and political involvement. The ''Der Spiegel'' interviewers did not bring up Heidegger's 1949 quotation comparing the industrialization of agriculture to the extermination camps. In fact, the ''Der Spiegel'' interviewers were not in possession of much of the evidence now known for Heidegger's Nazi sympathies.<ref>For critical readings of the interview (published in 1966 as "Only a God Can Save Us", ''Der Spiegel''), see the "Special Feature on Heidegger and Nazism" in ''Critical Inquiry'' 15:2 (Winter 1989), particularly the contributions by ] and ]. The issue includes partial translations of Derrida's ''Of Spirit'' and Lacoue-Labarthe's ''Of Spirit'' and ''Heidegger, Art, and Politics: the Fiction of the Political''.</ref> | |||
Heidegger became Rector of the University of Freiburg on 22 April 1933. The following week the national Reich law of 28 April 1933 replaced Reichskommissar Wagner's decree. The Reich law required the firing of Jewish professors from German universities, including those, such as Husserl, who had converted to Christianity. The termination of the retired professor Husserl's academic privileges thus did not involve any specific action on Heidegger's part. | |||
== Influence and reception in France == | |||
Heidegger had by then broken off contact with Husserl, other than through intermediaries. Heidegger later claimed that his relationship with Husserl had already become strained after Husserl publicly "settled accounts" with Heidegger and ] in the early 1930s.{{sfn|Heidegger|1990|page=48}} | |||
Heidegger was one of the most influential philosophers of the 20th century, and his ideas have penetrated into many areas, but in France there is a very long and particular history of reading and interpreting his work. | |||
Heidegger did not attend his former mentor's cremation in 1938, for which he later declared himself regretful: "That I failed to express again to Husserl my gratitude and respect for him upon the occasion of his final illness and death is a human failure that I apologized for in a letter to Mrs. Husserl".{{sfn|Augstein|Wolff|Heidegger|1976|pages=193–219}} In 1941, under pressure from publisher Max Niemeyer, Heidegger agreed to remove the dedication to Husserl from ''Being and Time'' (restored in post-war editions).{{sfn|Safranski|1998|pages=258–58}} | |||
=== Existentialism and pre-war influence === | |||
Heidegger's behavior towards Husserl has provoked controversy. Hannah Arendt initially suggested that Heidegger's behavior precipitated Husserl's death. She called Heidegger a "potential murderer". However, she later recanted her accusation.{{sfn|Ettinger|1997|page=37}} | |||
Heidegger's influence on French philosophy began in the 1930s, when ''Being and Time'', "What is Metaphysics?" and other Heideggerian texts were read by ] and other existentialists, as well as by thinkers such as Emmanuel Lévinas, ] and ].<ref>On the history of the French translation of Heidegger's "What is Metaphysics?", and on its importance to the French intellectual scene, cf. Denis Hollier, "Plenty of Nothing", in Hollier (ed.), ''A New History of French Literature'' (Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1989), pp. 894–900.</ref> Because Heidegger's discussion of ontology (the study of being) is rooted in an analysis of the mode of existence of individual human beings (''Dasein'', or being-there), his work has often been associated with existentialism. The influence of Heidegger on Sartre's '']'' is marked, but Heidegger felt that Sartre had misread his work, as he argued in later texts such as the "Letter on 'Humanism'." In that text, intended for a French audience, Heidegger explained this misreading in the following terms: | |||
:Sartre's key proposition about the priority of ''existentia'' over ''essentia'' does, however, justify using the name "existentialism" as an appropriate title for a philosophy of this sort. But the basic tenet of "existentialism" has nothing at all in common with the statement from ''Being and Time'' —apart from the fact that in ''Being and Time'' no statement about the relation of ''essentia'' and ''existentia'' can yet be expressed, since there it is still a question of preparing something precursory.<ref>Heidegger, "Letter on 'Humanism'", ''Pathmarks'' (Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 250–1.</ref> | |||
===Post-rectorate period=== | |||
"Letter on 'Humanism'" is often seen as a direct response to Sartre's 1945 lecture "Existentialism is a Humanism." Aside from merely disputing readings of his own work, however, in "Letter on 'Humanism,'" Heidegger asserts that "Every humanism is either grounded in a metaphysics or is itself made to be the ground of one." Heidegger's largest issue with Sartre's existential humanism is that, while it does make a humanistic 'move' in privileging existence over essence, "the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement." From this point onward in his thought, Heidegger attempted to think beyond metaphysics to a place where the articulation of the fundamental questions of ontology were fundamentally possible. | |||
After the failure of Heidegger's rectorship, he withdrew from most political activity, but remained a member of the ]. In May 1934 he accepted a position on the Committee for the Philosophy of Law in the ], where he remained active until at least 1936. The academy had official consultant status in preparing Nazi legislation such as the ] that came into effect in 1935. In addition to Heidegger, such Nazi notables as ], ], ], and ] belonged to the Academy and served on this committee. | |||
In a 1935 lecture, later published in 1953 as part of the book '']'', Heidegger refers to the "inner truth and greatness" of the Nazi movement, but he then adds a qualifying statement in parentheses: "namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity". However, it subsequently transpired that this qualification had not been made during the original lecture, although Heidegger claimed that it had been. This has led scholars to argue that Heidegger still supported the Nazi party in 1935 but that he did not want to admit this after the war, and so he attempted to silently correct his earlier statement.{{sfn|Habermas|1989|pages=452–54}}{{efn|See also ], "Martin Heidegger: on the publication of the lectures of 1935", in ], ed., ''The Heidegger Controversy'' (], 1993). The controversial page of the 1935 manuscript is missing from the Heidegger Archives in ]; however, Habermas's scholarship leaves little doubt about the original wording.}} | |||
=== Post-war forays into France === | |||
In private notes written in 1939, Heidegger took a strongly critical view of Hitler's ideology;{{sfn|Heidegger|2016|loc=§47}} however, in public lectures, he seems to have continued to make ambiguous comments which, if they expressed criticism of the regime, did so only in the context of praising its ideals. For instance, in a 1942 lecture, published posthumously, Heidegger said of recent German classics scholarship, "In the majority of "research results," the Greeks appear as pure National Socialists. This overenthusiasm on the part of academics seems not even to notice that with such "results" it does National Socialism and its historical uniqueness no service at all, not that it needs this anyhow."{{sfn|Heidegger|1996b|pages=79–80}} | |||
After the war, Heidegger was banned from university teaching for a period on account of his activities as Rector of Freiburg University. He developed a number of contacts in France, where his work continued to be taught, and a number of French students visited him at ] (see, for example, ] brief account in ''Heidegger and "the jews"'', which discusses a Franco-German conference held in Freiburg in 1947, one step toward bringing together French and German students). Heidegger subsequently made several visits to France, and made efforts to keep abreast of developments in French philosophy by way of correspondence with ], an early French translator of Heidegger, and with Lucien Braun. | |||
An important witness to Heidegger's continued allegiance to Nazism during the post-rectorship period is his former student ], who met Heidegger in 1936 while Heidegger was visiting Rome. In an account set down in 1940 (though not intended for publication), Löwith recalled that Heidegger wore a swastika pin to their meeting, though Heidegger knew that Löwith was Jewish. Löwith also recalled that Heidegger "left no doubt about his faith in ]", and stated that his support for Nazism was in agreement with the essence of his philosophy.{{sfn|Wolin|1991}} | |||
=== Derrida and deconstruction === | |||
Heidegger rejected the "biologically grounded racism" of the Nazis, replacing it with linguistic-historical heritage.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§3.5}}by living according to the principle of race had themselves promoted the very reasoning by which they were now being attacked and so they had no right to complain when it was being used against them by the Germans promoting their own racial purity." | |||
] came to Heidegger's attention in 1967 by way of Lucien Braun's recommendation of ] work (] was present at an initial discussion and indicated to Heidegger that Derrida's work came to his attention by way of an assistant). Heidegger expressed interest in meeting Derrida personally after the latter sent him some of his work. There was discussion of a meeting in 1972, but this failed to take place. Heidegger's interest in Derrida is said by Braun to have been considerable (as is evident in two letters, of September 29, 1967 and May 16, 1972, from Heidegger to Braun). Braun also brought to Heidegger's attention the work of ]. Foucault's relation to Heidegger is a matter of considerable difficulty; Foucault acknowledged Heidegger as a philosopher whom he read but never wrote about. (For more on this see ''Penser à Strasbourg,'' Jacques Derrida, et al., which includes reproductions of both letters and an account by Braun, "À mi-chemin entre Heidegger et Derrida"). | |||
===Post-war period=== | |||
Jacques Derrida made emphatic efforts to displace the understanding of Heidegger's work that had been prevalent in France from the period of the ban against Heidegger teaching in German universities, which amounted to an almost wholesale rejection of the influence of ] and existentialist terms. In Derrida's view, deconstruction is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term "déconstruction" is a term coined to translate Heidegger's use of the words "Destruktion"—literally "destruction"-and "Abbau"-more literally "de-building"). According to Derrida, Sartre's interpretation of Dasein and other key Heideggerian concerns is overly psychologistic, anthropocentric, and misses the historicality central to ''Dasein'' in ''Being and Time''. Because of Derrida's vehement attempts to "rescue" Heidegger from his existentialist interpreters (and also from Heidegger's "orthodox" followers), Derrida has at times been represented as a "French Heidegger", to the extent that he, his colleagues, and his former students are made to go proxy for Heidegger's worst (political) mistakes, despite ample evidence that the reception of Heidegger's work by later practitioners of deconstruction is anything but doctrinaire. | |||
After the end of World War II, Heidegger was summoned to appear at a ] hearing. Heidegger's former student and lover ] spoke on his behalf at this hearing, while ] spoke against him.{{sfn|Maier-Katkin|2010|page=249}} He was charged on four counts, dismissed from the university and declared a "follower" ('']'') of Nazism. Heidegger was forbidden to teach between 1945 and 1951. One consequence of this teaching ban was that Heidegger began to engage far more in the French philosophical scene.{{sfn|Janicaud|2015}} | |||
In his postwar thinking, Heidegger distanced himself from Nazism, but his critical comments about Nazism seem scandalous to some since they tend to equate the Nazi war atrocities with other inhumane practices related to ] and ], including the treatment of animals by ]. For instance in a lecture delivered at Bremen in 1949, Heidegger said: "Agriculture is now a motorized food industry, the same thing in its essence as the production of corpses in the gas chambers and the extermination camps, the same thing as blockades and the reduction of countries to famine, the same thing as the manufacture of hydrogen bombs." | |||
=== The Farías debate === | |||
In 1967 Heidegger met with the Jewish poet ], a concentration camp survivor. Having corresponded since 1956,{{sfn|Lyon|2006|page=66}} Celan visited Heidegger at his country retreat and wrote an enigmatic poem about the meeting, which some interpret as Celan's wish for Heidegger to apologize for his behavior during the Nazi era.{{sfn|Anderson|1991}} | |||
Derrida, Lacoue-Labarthe, and ], among others, all engaged in debate and disagreement about the relation between Heidegger's philosophy and his politics. These debates included the question of whether it was possible to do without Heidegger's philosophy, a position which Derrida in particular rejected. Forums where these debates took place include the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as "Les Fins de l'homme à partir du travail de Jacques Derrida: colloque de Cerisy, 23 juillet-2 août 1980", Derrida's "Feu la cendre/cio' che resta del fuoco", and the studies on ] by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987. | |||
Heidegger's defenders, notably Arendt, see his support for Nazism as arguably a personal " 'error' " (a word which Arendt placed in quotation marks when referring to Heidegger's Nazi-era politics).{{sfn|Murray|1978|pages=293–303}} Defenders think this error was irrelevant to Heidegger's philosophy. Critics such as Levinas, ],{{sfn|Löwith|1989|page=57}} and Theodor Adorno claim that Heidegger's support for Nazism revealed flaws inherent in his thought. | |||
When in 1987 ] published his book ''Heidegger et le nazisme'', this debate was taken up by many others, some of whom were inclined to disparage so-called "deconstructionists" for their association with Heidegger's philosophy. Derrida and others not only continued to defend the importance of reading Heidegger, but attacked Farías, on the grounds of poor scholarship and for what they saw as the sensationalism of his approach. Not all scholars agreed with this negative assessment: ], for example, declared that " book includes more concrete information relevant to Heidegger's relations with the Nazis than anything else available, and it is an excellent antidote to the evasive apologetics that are still being published."<ref></ref> | |||
====''Der Spiegel'' interview==== | |||
=== Bernard Stiegler === | |||
On 23 September 1966, Heidegger was interviewed by ], a former Nazi, and ] for '']'' magazine, in which he agreed to discuss his political past provided that the interview be published posthumously. ("]" was published five days after his death, on 31 May 1976.){{sfn|Augstein|Wolff|Heidegger|1976|pages=193–219}} In the interview, Heidegger defended his entanglement with Nazism in two ways. First, he claimed that there was no alternative, saying that with his acceptance of the position of rector of the ] he was trying to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and thus had to compromise with the Nazi administration. Second, he admitted that he saw an "awakening" (''Aufbruch'') which might help to find a "new national and social approach," but said that he changed his mind about this in 1934, when he refused, under threat of dismissal, to remove from the position of dean of the faculty those who were not acceptable to the Nazi party, and he consequently decided to resign as rector.{{sfn|Augstein|Wolff|Heidegger|1976|pages=193–219}} | |||
In his interview Heidegger defended as ] his 1935 lecture describing the "inner truth and greatness of this movement." He affirmed that Nazi informants who observed his lectures would understand that by "movement" he meant Nazism. However, Heidegger asserted that his dedicated students would know this statement wasn't praise for the ]. Rather, he meant it as he expressed it in the parenthetical clarification later added to ''Introduction to Metaphysics'' (1953), namely, "the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity."{{sfn|McGrath|2008|page=92}} | |||
More recently, Heidegger's thought has considerably influenced the work of the French philosopher ]. This is evident even from the title of Stiegler's multi-volume ''magnum opus'', ''La technique et le temps'' (volume one translated into English as '']'').<ref>Bernard Stiegler,'' Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus'' (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), part 2.</ref> Stiegler offers an original reading of Heidegger, arguing that there can be no access to "originary temporality" other than via material, that is, technical, supports, and that Heidegger recognised this in the form of his account of world historicality, yet in the end suppressed that fact. Stiegler understands the existential analytic of ''Being and Time'' as an account of psychic ], and his later "history of being" as an account of collective individuation. He understands many of the problems of Heidegger's philosophy and politics as the consequence of Heidegger's inability to integrate the two. | |||
The eyewitness account of Löwith from 1940, contradicts the account given in the ''Der Spiegel'' interview in two ways: that he did not make any decisive break with Nazism in 1934, and that Heidegger was willing to entertain more profound relations between his philosophy and political involvement. The ''Der Spiegel'' interviewers did not bring up Heidegger's 1949 quotation comparing the industrialization of agriculture to the extermination camps. In fact, the interviewers were not in possession of much of the evidence now known for Heidegger's Nazi sympathies.{{efn|The 1966 interview published in 1976 after Heidegger's death as {{cite magazine |title=Only a God Can Save Us |url=https://archive.org/stream/MartinHeidegger-DerSpiegelInterviewenglishTranslationonlyAGodCan/Heidegger-derSpiegelInterview1966 |magazine=] |date=1976-05-31 |pages=193–219 |translator=William J. Richardson}} For critical readings, see the {{Citation |title=Special Feature on Heidegger and Nazism |url=https://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/past_issues/issue/winter_1989_v15_n2/ |journal=Critical Inquiry |year=1989 |volume=15 |issue=2 |edition=Winter 1989 |doi=10.1086/ci.15.2.1343581}}, particularly the contributions by ] and ]. The issue includes partial translations of ]'s ''Of Spirit'' and ]'s ''Heidegger, Art, and Politics: the Fiction of the Political''.}} Furthermore, ''Der Spiegel'' journalist Georg Wolff had been an ] with the ], stationed in Oslo during World War II, and had been writing articles with antisemitic and racist overtones in ''Der Spiegel'' since the end of the war.{{sfn|Janich|2013|page=178}} | |||
== Criticism == | |||
====The Farías debate==== | |||
Heidegger's influence upon 20th century ] is unquestioned and has produced a variety of critical responses. | |||
], ], and ], among others, all engaged in debate and disagreement about the relation between Heidegger's philosophy and his Nazi politics. These debates included the question of whether it was possible to do without Heidegger's philosophy, a position which Derrida in particular rejected. Forums where these debates took place include the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as "''Les Fins de l'homme à partir du travail de Jacques Derrida: colloque de Cerisy, 23 juillet-2 août 1980''", Derrida's "''Feu la cendre/cio' che resta del fuoco''", and the studies on ] by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida, which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987. | |||
=== |
==== The Black Notebooks ==== | ||
In 2014, Heidegger's '']'' were published although he had written in them between 1931 and the early 1970s. The notebooks contain several examples of ] sentiments, which have led to reevaluation of ].{{sfn|Inwood|2014}}{{sfn|Assheuer|2014}} An example of Heidegger using anti-Semitic language he once wrote "world ] is ungraspable everywhere and doesn't need to get involved in military action while continuing to unfurl its influence, whereas we are left to sacrifice the best blood of the best of our people". The term and notion of "world Judaism" was first promoted by the anti-Semitic text ] and later appeared in Hitler's infamous book '']''.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Oltermann |first=Philip |date=2014-03-13 |title=Heidegger's 'black notebooks' reveal antisemitism at core of his philosophy |language=en-GB |work=The Guardian |url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/13/martin-heidegger-black-notebooks-reveal-nazi-ideology-antisemitism |access-date=2023-11-07 |issn=0261-3077 |archive-date=30 November 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231130063910/https://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/13/martin-heidegger-black-notebooks-reveal-nazi-ideology-antisemitism |url-status=live }}</ref> In another instance Heidegger wrote "by living according to the principle of race had themselves promoted the very reasoning by which they were now being attacked and so they had no right to complain when it was being used against them by the Germans promoting their own racial purity".<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Mitchell |first1=Andrew J. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=aUUyDwAAQBAJ&dq=by+living+according+to+the+principle+of+race+%5Bthe+Jews%5D+had+themselves+promoted+the+very+reasoning+by+which+they+were+now+being+attacked+and+so+they+had+no+right+to+complain+when+it+was+being+used+against+them+by+the+Germans+promoting+their+own+racial+purity.%E2%80%9D&pg=PT218 |title=Heidegger's Black Notebooks: Responses to Anti-Semitism |last2=Trawny |first2=Peter |date=2017-09-05 |publisher=Columbia University Press |isbn=978-0-231-54438-2 |language=en |access-date=26 November 2023 |archive-date=28 November 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231128001246/https://books.google.com/books?id=aUUyDwAAQBAJ&dq=by+living+according+to+the+principle+of+race+[the+Jews]+had+themselves+promoted+the+very+reasoning+by+which+they+were+now+being+attacked+and+so+they+had+no+right+to+complain+when+it+was+being+used+against+them+by+the+Germans+promoting+their+own+racial+purity.%E2%80%9D&pg=PT218 |url-status=live }}</ref> However, in the notebooks there are instances of Heidegger writing critically of ] and biological oppression.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Escudero |first=Jesús Adrián |date=2015 |title=Heidegger's Black Notebooks and the Question of Anti-Semitism |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/ESCHBN |access-date=2023-11-07 |journal=Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual |volume=5 |pages=21–49 |doi=10.5840/gatherings201552 |language=en |archive-date=13 May 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230513095146/https://philpapers.org/rec/ESCHBN |url-status=live }}</ref>{{sfn|Wheeler|2020}} | |||
A notable entry in the notebooks are his writings about his mentor and former friend Edmund Husserl specifically relating to Husserl Jewish heritage. In 1939, only a year after Husserl's death, Heidegger wrote in his '']'': | |||
The content of ''Being and Time'', according to Husserl, claimed to deal with ontology, but from Husserl's perspective only did so in the first few pages of the book. Having nothing further to contribute to an ontology independent of human existence, Heidegger changed the topic to ''Dasein''. Whereas Heidegger argued that the question of human existence is central to the pursuit of the question of being, Husserl criticized this as reducing phenomenology to "philosophical anthropology" and offering an abstract and incorrect portrait of the human being.<ref>See Edmund Husserl, ''Psychological and transcendental phenomenology and the confrontation with Heidegger (1927-1931)'' (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997).</ref> | |||
<blockquote>the occasional increase in the power of Judaism is grounded in the fact that Western metaphysics, especially in | |||
The ] ] and Heidegger engaged in an influential debate located in ] in 1929, concerning the significance of Kantian notions of freedom and rationality. Whereas Cassirer defended the role of rationality in Kant, Heidegger argued for the priority of the imagination. Dilthey's student ] wrote the first extended critical appropriation of Heidegger in ''Lebensphilosophie und Phänomenologie. Eine Auseinandersetzung der Diltheyschen Richtung mit Heidegger und Husserl'', Leipzig 1930 (3. ed. Stuttgart 1964). | |||
its modern evolution, offered the point of attachment for the expansion of an otherwise empty rationality and calculative capacity, and these thereby created for themselves an abode in the "spirit" without ever being able, on their own, to grasp the concealed decisive domains. The more originary and inceptual the future decisions and questions become, all the more inaccessible will they remain to this 'race.' (Thus Husserl's step to the phenomenological attitude, taken in explicit opposition to psychological explanation and to the historiological calculation of opinions, will be of lasting importance—and yet this attitude never reaches into the domains of the essential decisions.){{sfn|Heidegger|2017|pages=67–68}}</blockquote> | |||
This would seem to imply that Heidegger considered Husserl to be philosophically limited by his Jewishness.{{Original research inline|date=September 2024}} | |||
=== Left-Hegelianism and critical theory === | |||
== Reception == | |||
Hegel-influenced Marxist thinkers, especially ] and the ], associated the style and content of Heidegger's thought with German irrationalism and criticized its political implications. | |||
===Influence=== | |||
Initially members of the Frankfurt School were positively disposed to Heidegger, becoming more critical at the beginning of the 1930s. Heidegger's student ] became associated with the Frankfurt School. Initially striving for a synthesis between Hegelian-Marxism and Heidegger's phenomenology, Marcuse later rejected Heidegger's thought for its "false concreteness" and "revolutionary conservativism." ] wrote an extended critique of the ideological character of Heidegger's early and later use of language in the ''Jargon of Authenticity''. Contemporary social theorists associated with the Frankfurt School have remained largely critical of Heidegger's works and influence. In particular, ] admonishes the influence of Heidegger on recent French philosophy in his polemic against "postmodernism" in ''The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity'' (1985). However, recent work by philosopher and critical theorist Nikolas Kompridis tries to show that Heidegger's insights into ] are badly misunderstood and mishandled by Habermas, and are of vital importance for critical theory, offering an important way of ].<ref>Nikolas Kompridis, <i>Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory between Past and Future</i> MIT Press, 2006.</ref><ref></ref> | |||
Heidegger is often considered to be among the most important and influential philosophers of the 20th century by many observers.{{sfn|Fiske|1976}} American Philosopher ] has ranked Heidegger as among the most important philosophers along with ] and ].<ref>{{Citation |title=Preface |date=2011 |work=The Philosophy of Heidegger |pages=vii–ix |editor-last=Watts |editor-first=Michael |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/philosophy-of-heidegger/preface/AD50ABABCA3E65485CE85F587BB31211 |access-date=2024-06-22 |series=Continental European Philosophy |publisher=Acumen Publishing |doi=10.1017/UPO9781844652655.001 |isbn=978-1-84465-263-1}}</ref> ] has praised Heidegger as the "most important and influential philosopher in the continental tradition in the 20th century".<ref>{{Cite news |last=Critchley |first=Simon |date=2009-06-08 |title=Being and Time, part 1: Why Heidegger matters |url=https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/belief/2009/jun/05/heidegger-philosophy |access-date=2024-06-22 |work=The Guardian |language=en-GB |issn=0261-3077}}</ref> | |||
Slovenian philosopher ] has referred to Heidegger as a "great philosopher" and rejected the notion that his alleged anti-semitism against him tainted his philosophy.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Žižek |first=Slavoj |date=2015-05-13 |title=Slavoj Žižek: Why Heidegger should not be criminalised |url=https://www.newstatesman.com/culture/2015/05/slavoj-zizek-why-heidegger-should-not-be-criminalised |access-date=2024-07-02 |website=New Statesman |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
=== Reception by Analytic and Anglo-American philosophy === | |||
In France, there is a very long and particular history of reading and interpreting Heidegger's work. Because Heidegger's discussion of ontology is sometimes interpreted as rooted in an analysis of the mode of existence of individual human beings (Dasein), his work has often been associated with existentialism. Derrida sees ] is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term "''déconstruction''" is a term coined to translate Heidegger's use of the words "''Destruktion''"—literally "destruction"—and "''Abbau''"—more literally "de-building").{{sfn|Zuckert|1991}} The influence of Heidegger on Sartre's 1943 '']'' is marked. Heidegger himself, however, argued that Sartre had misread his work.{{sfn|Wheeler|2020|loc=§3.1}}{{sfn|Heidegger|1998|pages=250–51}} | |||
Criticism of Heidegger's philosophy has also come from ], beginning with ]. Accusing Heidegger of offering an "illusory" ontology, ] criticized him, in "The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language" (1932), of committing the fallacy of ] and of wrongly dismissing the logical treatment of language, which, according to Carnap, can only lead to writing "nonsensical pseudo-propositions." | |||
] introduced Heidegger's notion of "being-in-the-world" to research in ]. According to Dreyfus, long-standing research questions such as the ] can be only dissolved within an Heideggerian framework.<ref>(Eds.): {{cite book |last1=Husbands P. |title=Why Heideggerian AI Failed and How Fixing It Would Require Making It More Heideggerian (in: The Mechanical Mind in History) |last2=Holland O. |last3=Wheeler M. |date=2008 |publisher=MIT Press |pages=331–371}}</ref> Heidegger also profoundly influenced ] and ]. Former Trump chief strategist ] has expressed admiration for Heidegger and has praised his philosophy.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Scheuermann |first=Christoph |date=2018-10-29 |title=Stephen Bannon Tries Rightwing Revolution in Europe |url=https://www.spiegel.de/international/world/stephen-bannon-tries-rightwing-revolution-in-europe-a-1235297.html |access-date=2024-04-21 |work=Der Spiegel |language=en |issn=2195-1349}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |last=Stonebridge |first=Lyndsey |date=2023-04-08 |title=Who is afraid of Martin Heidegger? |url=https://www.newstatesman.com/the-weekend-essay/2023/04/philosopher-martin-heidegger-nazi-legacy-influence-right-wing-ideology |access-date=2024-04-21 |website=New Statesman |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
A strong critic of Heidegger's philosophy was the British logical positivist ]. In Ayer's view, Heidegger proposed vast, overarching theories regarding existence, which are completely unverifiable through empirical demonstration and logical analysis. For Ayer, this sort of philosophy was a poisonous strain in modern thought. He considered Heidegger to be the worst example of such philosophy, which Ayer believed to be entirely useless. | |||
Some writers on Heidegger's work see possibilities within it for dialogue with traditions of thought outside of Western philosophy, particularly East Asian thinking.{{sfn|Ma|2007}}{{sfn|Oldmeadow|2004|pages=351–54}} Despite perceived differences between Eastern and Western philosophy, some of Heidegger's later work, particularly "A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer", does show an interest in initiating such a dialogue. Heidegger himself had contact with a number of leading Japanese intellectuals, including members of the ], notably ] and ]. The scholar Chang Chung-Yuan stated, "Heidegger is the only Western Philosopher who not only intellectually understands ], but has intuitively experienced the essence of it as well."{{sfn|Laozi|2013|page=8}} Philosopher Reinhard May sees great influence of Taoism and Japanese scholars in Heidegger's work, although this influence is not acknowledged by the author. He asserts it can be shown that Heidegger sometimes "appropriated wholesale and almost verbatim major ideas from the German translations of Daoist and Zen Buddhist classics." To this he adds, "This clandestine textual appropriation of non-Western spirituality, the extent of which has gone undiscovered for so long, seems quite unparalleled, with far-reaching implications for our future interpretation of Heidegger's work."{{sfn|May|1996|page=xv}} | |||
] commented, expressing the sentiments of many mid-20th-century English-speaking philosophers, that: | |||
:Highly eccentric in its terminology, his philosophy is extremely obscure. One cannot help suspecting that language is here running riot. An interesting point in his speculations is the insistence that nothingness is something positive. As with much else in Existentialism, this is a psychological observation made to pass for logic.<ref>Bertrand Russell, ''Wisdom of the West'' (New York: Crescent Books, 1989), p. 303.</ref> | |||
Notable figures known to be influenced by Heidegger's work today include ], a prominent Russian far-right political philosopher.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Sharpe |first=Matthew |date=2020-04-02 |title=In the Crosshairs of the Fourfold: Critical Thoughts on Aleksandr Dugin's Heidegger |url=https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/14409917.2020.1759284 |journal=Critical Horizons |language=en |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=167–187 |doi=10.1080/14409917.2020.1759284 |issn=1440-9917}}</ref> | |||
] stated that: | |||
:His major work Being and Time is formidably difficult—unless it is utter nonsense, in which case it is laughably easy. I am not sure how to judge it, and have read no commentator who even begins to make sense of it<ref>Jeff Collins, ''Introducing Heidegger'' (Thriplow, Cambridge: Icon Books, 1998), p. 7.</ref>. | |||
=== Criticism === | |||
The analytic tradition values clarity of expression. Heidegger, however, has on occasion appeared to take an opposing view, stating for example that "those in the crossing must in the end know what is mistaken by all urging for intelligibility: that every thinking of being, all philosophy, can ''never'' be confirmed by 'facts,' i.e., by beings. Making itself intelligible is suicide for philosophy. Those who idolize 'facts' never notice that their idols only shine in a borrowed light. They are also meant not to notice this; for thereupon they would have to be at a loss and therefore useless. But idolizers and idols are used wherever gods are in flight and so announce ''their'' nearness."<ref>Martin Heidegger, ''Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning)'' (Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1999), p. 307.</ref> Apart from the charge of ], other analytic philosophers considered the actual content of Heidegger's work to be either faulty and meaningless, vapid or uninteresting. | |||
According to Husserl, ''Being and Time'' claimed to deal with ontology, but only did so in the first few pages of the book. Having nothing further to contribute to an ontology independent of human existence, Heidegger changed the topic to Dasein. Whereas Heidegger argued that the question of human existence is central to the pursuit of the question of being, Husserl criticized this as reducing phenomenology to "philosophical anthropology" and offering an abstract and incorrect portrait of the human being.{{sfn|Husserl|1997}} Aspects of his work have been criticized by those who acknowledge his influence. Some questions raised about Heidegger's philosophy include the priority of ontology, the status of animals, the nature of the religious, Heidegger's supposed neglect of ethics (]), the body (]), sexual difference (]), and space (]).{{sfn|Holland|2018|pages=139–43}}{{sfn|Elden|2012|pages=85–88}} ] objected that Heidegger proposed vast, overarching theories regarding existence that were completely unverifiable through empirical demonstration and logical analysis.{{sfn|Gorner|2000|page=90}} | |||
In France, there is a very long and particular history of reading and interpreting Heidegger. In 1929 the ] ] and Heidegger engaged in ], during the Second ] in ], concerning the significance of ] notions of freedom and rationality. Whereas Cassirer defended the role of rationality in Kant, Heidegger argued for the priority of the imagination.{{sfn|Nirenberg|2011}}The reception of Heidegger's philosophy by Anglo-American ], beginning with the ], was almost uniformly negative. ] accused Heidegger of offering an "illusory" ontology, criticizing him for committing the fallacy of ] and for wrongly dismissing the logical treatment of language which, according to Carnap, can only lead to writing "nonsensical pseudo-propositions".{{sfn|Carnap|1931}}{{sfn|Carnap|1966}} | |||
Not all analytic philosophers, however, have been as hostile. ] wrote a critical yet positive review of ''Being and Time'' and ] made a remark recorded by Friedrich Waismann: "To be sure, I can imagine what Heidegger means by being and anxiety"<ref>''Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations Recorded by Friedrich Waismann'', Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1979, p.68</ref> which has been construed by some commentators{{Who|date=June 2009}} as sympathetic to Heidegger's philosophical approach. These positive and negative analytic evaluations have been collected in Michael Murray (ed.), ''Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays'' (Yale University Press, 1978). Heidegger's reputation within English-language philosophy has slightly improved in philosophical terms in some part through the efforts of ], ], and a recent generation of analytically-oriented phenomenology scholars. Pragmatist Rorty claimed that Heidegger's approach to philosophy in the first half of his career has much in common with that of the latter-day Ludwig Wittgenstein, a significant figure in analytic philosophy. Nevertheless, Rorty asserted that what Heidegger had constructed in his writings was a myth of being rather than an account of it<ref>Jeff Collins, ''Introducing Heidegger'' (Thriplow, Cambridge: Icon Books, 1998), p. 170.</ref>. | |||
]ian-]ist thinkers, especially ] and the ], associated the style and content of Heidegger's thought with irrationalism and criticized its political implications. For instance, ] wrote an extended critique of the ideological character of Heidegger's early and later use of language in the ''Jargon of Authenticity'', and ] admonishes the influence of Heidegger on recent French philosophy in his polemic against "postmodernism" in '']''.{{sfn|Rockmore|1992|pages=57, 75, 149, 258}}{{sfn|Adorno|1973}}{{sfn|Habermas|1990|loc=chapter VI}} | |||
=== Contemporary European reception === | |||
] considered Heidegger an ], writing, "Highly eccentric in its terminology, his philosophy is extremely obscure. One cannot help suspecting that language is here running riot. An interesting point in his speculations is the insistence that nothingness is something positive. As with much else in Existentialism, this is a psychological observation made to pass for logic."{{sfn|Russell|1959 |page=303}} According to ], this quote expresses the sentiments of many 20th-century analytic philosophers concerning Heidegger.{{sfn|Polt|1999|page=123}} | |||
Even though Heidegger is considered by many observers to be the most influential philosopher of the 20th century in continental philosophy, aspects of his work have been criticised by those who nevertheless acknowledge this influence, such as ] and ]. Some questions raised about Heidegger's philosophy include the priority of ontology, the status of animals, the nature of the religious, Heidegger's supposed neglect of ethics (]), the body (]), or sexual difference (]). | |||
==In film== | |||
Emmanuel Lévinas was deeply influenced by Heidegger yet became one of his fiercest critics, contrasting the infinity of the good beyond being with the immanence and totality of ontology. Lévinas also condemned Heidegger's involvement with National Socialism, stating "One can forgive many Germans, but there are some Germans it is difficult to forgive. It is difficult to forgive Heidegger."<ref>Emmanuel Levinas, ''Nine Talmudic Readings'' (Indiana University Press, 1990), p. xxv, translated by Annette Aronowicz</ref> | |||
* '']'' (1989) is a German TV documentary about Heidegger, co-directed by Ulrich Boehm and ].<ref>{{cite news |last=Boy |first=Christof |date=23 January 1989 |url=https://taz.de/Nebuloese-Schwaermerei-fuer-Heidegger/!1824768/ |title=Nebulöse Schwärmerei für Heidegger |newspaper=] |language=de |access-date=1 July 2024 }}</ref> | |||
* The film director ] translated Heidegger's 1929 essay ''Vom Wesen des Grundes'' into English. It was published under the title ''The Essence of Reasons'' (1969). It is also frequently said of Malick that his cinema has Heideggerian sensibilities.{{sfn|Patterson|2003|pages=179–91}}{{sfn|Cavell|1979|page=xv}} | |||
* '']'' (2004) is a film based on Heidegger's ] on ], and features ], ], Bernard Stiegler, and ]. | |||
* '']'' (2010) draws on Heidegger's work to explore what it means to be human in a technological age. A number of Heidegger scholars are interviewed, including ], ], ], ], and ]. | |||
== |
==See also== | ||
{{div col}} | |||
* ] | |||
* '']'' | |||
* ] | |||
* '']'' | |||
* '']'' | |||
* ] | |||
* '']'' | |||
{{div col end}} | |||
==Notes== | |||
* '']'' (2004) is a film based on Heidegger's ] on ], and features ], ], Bernard Stiegler, and ]. <ref>http://www.theister.com/</ref> | |||
{{reflist|30em|group=lower-alpha}} | |||
* The film director ] translated Heidegger's 1929 essay "''Vom Wesen des Grundes''" into English. It was published under the title ''The Essence of Reasons'' (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1969, bilingual edition). | |||
== |
==Bibliography== | ||
=== ''Gesamtausgabe'' === | |||
Heidegger's collected works are published by The ''Gesamtausgabe'' was begun during Heidegger's lifetime. He defined the order of publication and controversially dictated that the principle of editing should be "ways not works." Publication has not yet been completed. | |||
===References=== | |||
The contents are listed here: ]. | |||
{{reflist|colwidth=15em}} | |||
=== |
===Works cited=== | ||
''For ease of reference, citations of ''Being and Time'' should always cite to the pagination of the standard German edition, which is included in the margins of both of the English translations, each of which has its virtues.'' | |||
A complete list of English translations of Heidegger's work is available | |||
{| border="1" cellpadding="2" cellspacing="0" align="center" | |||
! style="background:silver" | Year | |||
! style="background:silver" | Original German | |||
! style="background:silver" | English Translation | |||
|- | |||
| 1927 | |||
| ''Sein und Zeit'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 2 | |||
| '']'', trans. by ] and Edward Robinson (London: SCM Press, 1962); re-translated by Joan Stambaugh (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996) | |||
|- | |||
| 1929 | |||
| ''Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 3 | |||
| ''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics'', trans. by Richard Taft (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990) | |||
|- | |||
| 1935 | |||
| ''Einführung in die Metaphysik'' (1935, published 1953), Gesamtausgabe Volume 40 | |||
| ''An Introduction to Metaphysics'', trans. by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000) | |||
|- | |||
| 1936–8 | |||
| ''Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis)'' (1936–1938, published 1989), Gesamtausgabe Volume 65 | |||
| '']'', trans. by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999) | |||
|- | |||
| 1942 | |||
| ''Hölderlins Hymne »Der Ister«'' (1942, published 1984), Gesamtausgabe Volume 53 | |||
| '']'', trans. by ] and Julia Davis (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996) | |||
|- | |||
| 1949 | |||
| "Die Frage nach der Technik", in Gesamtausgabe Volume 7 | |||
| "]" , in Heidegger, Martin, ''Basic Writings'': Second Edition, Revised and Expanded, ed. David Farrell Krell (New York: Harper Collins, 1993) | |||
|- | |||
| 1950 | |||
| ''Holzwege'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 5. This collection includes "Der Ursprung der Kunstwerkes" (1935–1936) | |||
| ''Off the Beaten Track''. This collection includes "]" | |||
|- | |||
| 1955–56 | |||
| ''Der Satz vom Grund'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 10 | |||
| ''The Principle of Reason'', trans. Reginald Lilly (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1991) | |||
|- | |||
| 1955–57 | |||
| ''Identität und Differenz'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 11 | |||
| ''Identity and Difference'', trans. by Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1969) | |||
|- | |||
| 1959 | |||
| ''Gelassenheit'', in Gesamtausgabe Volume 16 | |||
| ''Discourse On Thinking'' | |||
|- | |||
| 1959 | |||
| ''Unterwegs zur Sprache'', Gesamtausgabe Volume 12 | |||
| ''On the Way To Language'', published without the essay "''Die Sprache''" ("Language") by arrangement with Heidegger | |||
|- | |||
|} | |||
===Primary sources=== | |||
{{academia | |||
Heidegger's collected writings are published by ].{{sfn|Georgakis|Ennis|2015|pages=ix–xiii}} The '']'' was begun during Heidegger's lifetime. He defined the order of publication and dictated that the principle of editing should be "ways not works". Publication has not yet been completed. The current executor of Martin Heidegger's Literary Estate is his grandson and a lawyer, Arnulf Heidegger (1969– ).{{sfn|Herrmann|Alfieri|2021|page=xv}} | |||
| | students=]</br>]</br>]</br>]</br>]</br>]</br>]</br>]</br>] | |||
| | teachers=]</br>]</br>] | |||
}} | |||
{{refbegin|30em|refs=}} | |||
== Further reading == | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |year= 1962|title=Being and Time |translator=John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson |publisher=Harper Collins}} | |||
{{Further Reading}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Peter D. Hertz |year=1971a |chapter=A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer |title=On the Way to Language |editor= |publisher=Harper & Row }} | |||
=== On ''Being and Time'' === | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Albert Hofstadter |year=1971b |title=Poetry, Language, Thought |publisher=Albert Hofstadter }} | |||
* William Blattner, ''Heidegger's Temporal Idealism'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=J. Glenn Gray |year=1976 |title=What is Called Thinking? |publisher=Harper Perennial }} | |||
* Taylor Carman, ''Heidegger's Analytic: Interpretation, Discourse, and Authenticity in "Being and Time"'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator= |year=1990 |chapter=Der Spiegel Interview |title=Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers |editor=Günther Neske and Emil Kettering |publisher=Paragon House }} | |||
* ], ''Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |editor=David Farrell Krell|translator-first1=Joan|translator-last1=Stambaugh|translator-first2=David Farrell|translator-last2=Krell|translator-first3=Frank A.|translator-last3=Capuzzi |year=1991 |title=Nietzsche |publisher=HarperOne |isbn= 0-06-063841-9 |oclc= 22492313}} | |||
* ], ''Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |year=1996a |title=Being and Time |translator=Joan Stambaugh|publisher=SUNY Press}} | |||
* ], ''A Commentary on Heidegger's ''Being and Time'', Revised Edition'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator= William McNeill and Julia Davis |year=1996b |title=Hölderlin's Hymn "The Ister" |publisher=Indiana University Press }} | |||
* E.F. Kaelin, "Heidegger's Being & Time: A Reading for Readers" | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=William McNeil |year=1998 |chapter=Letter on Humanism |title=Pathmarks |editor=William McNeil |publisher=Cambridge University Press }} | |||
* Magda King, ''A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Joan Stambaugh |year=2002 |chapter=Time and Being |title=On Time and Being |editor= |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=0-226-32375-7 }} | |||
* ], ''The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |year=2009 |title=Becoming Heidegger: On the Trail of his Early Occasional Writings, 1910-1927 |edition=2nd |publisher= Routledge|editor=Theodore Kisiel and Thomas Sheehan |isbn=978-0-9701679-9-6}} | |||
* ], ''Heidegger and Being and Time'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Richard Rojcewicz |year=2012 |title=Contributions to Philosophy: (Of the Event) |publisher=Indiana University Press |isbn=9780253001276 }} | |||
* James Luchte, ''Heidegger's Early Philosophy: The Phenomenology of Ecstatic Temporality'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator= Gregory Fried and Richard Polt |year=2014 |title=Introduction to Metaphysics |edition=2nd |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn= 978-0-300-18612-3}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Parvis Emad and Thomas Kalary |year=2016 |title=Mindfulness |publisher=Bloomsbury Academic }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Heidegger |first1=Martin |translator=Richard Rojcewicz |year=2017 |title=Ponderings XII–XV: Black Notebooks 1939–1941 |publisher=Indiana University Press |isbn=9780253029317 }} | |||
{{Refend}} | |||
=== |
===Secondary sources=== | ||
<!-- PLEASE MAINTAIN ALPHABETICAL ORDER WITH ANY ADDITIONS YOU MAKE. THANK YOU!--> | |||
* ], ''Heidegger and Nazism'', ed. by ] and Tom Rockmore | |||
{{refbegin|30em|refs=}} | |||
* ], ''Martin Heidegger: A Political Life'' | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Adorno |first1=Theodor W. |translator=Knut Tarnowski and Frederic Will|title=The Jargon of Authenticity |date=1973 |publisher=Northwestern University Press}} | |||
* ], ''Martin Heidegger's Path of Thinking'', trans. by D. Magurshak and S. Barber, Humanities Press, 1987. | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=978-3319156620 |title=The Presence of Duns Scotus in the Thought of Edith Stein: The question of Individuality |last1=Alfieri |first1=Francesco |year=2015| publisher=Springer }} | |||
* ], ''Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil'' | |||
* {{cite book| isbn=978-0739171684 | title=Martin Heidegger and the First World War: Being and Time as Funeral Oration | last1=Altman |first1=William H. F. | year=2012 |publisher=Lexington Books }} | |||
* John van Buren, ''The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King'' | |||
* {{cite news|title=Das vergiftete Erbe|last=Assheuer|first=Thomas|author-link=:de:Thomas Assheuer|url=https://www.zeit.de/2014/12/heidegger-schwarze-hefte-veroeffentlicht|newspaper=]|date=21 March 2014|language=de|trans-title=The poisoned heritage|access-date=18 June 2022|archive-date=4 April 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230404104433/https://www.zeit.de/2014/12/heidegger-schwarze-hefte-veroeffentlicht|url-status=live}} | |||
* {{Cite journal| doi = 10.2307/488241| issn = 0094-033X|issue = 53| pages = 3–18| last = Anderson|first = Mark M.|title = The 'Impossibility of Poetry': Celan and Heidegger in France|journal = ]| date = 1991-04-01| jstor = 488241}} | |||
* {{cite journal |first1=Rudolf|last1=Augstein |first2=Georg |last2=Wolff|first3=Martin |last3=Heidegger|title=''Nur noch ein Gott kann uns retten''|url=https://www.spiegel.de/politik/datum-31-mai-1976-heidegger-a-56699e74-0002-0001-0000-000041238349?context=issue |journal=] |year=1976 |pages=193–219 |access-date=2013-06-14 |archive-date=6 February 2013 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130206225835/http://www.spiegel.de/spiegel/print/d-41238349.html |url-status=live }} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131016094800/http://www.ditext.com/heidegger/interview.html |date=16 October 2013 }} by ] in {{cite book|title=Heidegger. The Man and the Thinker|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qIrWZajVZuwC&pg=PA45&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false|editor-first=Thomas|editor-last=Sheehan|year=1981|publisher=]|location=]|pages=45–67|isbn=978-1-412-81537-6}} | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=978-0801472664 |title=Heidegger's Roots: Nietzsche, National Socialism, and the Greeks | last1=Bambach |first1=Charles R. | year=2003 |publisher=Cornell University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=f3l7S-ZTK4YC&pg=PA120 | title=The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt | isbn=9780742521513 | last1=Benhabib | first1=Seyla | year=2003 | publisher=Rowman & Littlefield }} | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=9781139441995 |title=Heidegger's Analytic: Interpretation, Discourse and Authenticity in Being and Time |last1=Carman |first1=Taylor |date=2003 |publisher=Cambridge University Press }} | |||
* {{cite journal | url=https://www.philosophie.hu-berlin.de/de/lehrbereiche/logik/lehre/carnap-metaphysik.pdf | archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221009/https://www.philosophie.hu-berlin.de/de/lehrbereiche/logik/lehre/carnap-metaphysik.pdf | archive-date=2022-10-09 | url-status=live | last1=Carnap | first1=Rudolf | title=Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache | journal=Erkenntnis | volume=2 | number= | pages=219–241 | year=1931 | doi=10.1007/BF02028153 | s2cid=144658746 }} | |||
* {{cite book | contribution-url=https://eclass.uoa.gr/modules/document/file.php/PHS269/The%20Elimination%20of%20Metaphysics%20through%20the%20Logical%20Analysis%20of%20Language.pdf | archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221009/https://eclass.uoa.gr/modules/document/file.php/PHS269/The%20Elimination%20of%20Metaphysics%20through%20the%20Logical%20Analysis%20of%20Language.pdf | archive-date=2022-10-09 | url-status=live | last1=Carnap | first1=Rudolf | contribution=The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language | pages=60–81 | isbn=978-0029011300 | editor=A.J. Ayer | title=Logical Positivism | location=New York | publisher=The Free Press | series=The Library of Philosophical Movements | volume= | edition= | year=1966 }} | |||
* {{cite news |title=Es ist wieder da |url=https://www.zeit.de/2014/05/martin-heidegger-schwarze-hefte/komplettansicht |last1=Cammann |first1=Alexander |last2=Soboczynski |first2=Adam |newspaper=Die Zeit |date=30 January 2014 |access-date=14 April 2015 |archive-date=6 May 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150506125637/http://www.zeit.de/2014/05/martin-heidegger-schwarze-hefte/komplettansicht |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book| isbn=978-0674961968 | title=The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film, Enlarged Edition | last1=Cavell | first1=Stanley | year=1979 |publisher=Harvard University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Dahlstrom |first1=D. O. |title=New Catholic Encyclopedia |date=2004 |publisher=Gale |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/ontology |chapter=Ontology |access-date=25 December 2020 |archive-date=29 January 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210129034430/https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/ontology |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{Cite web|url=https://www.architectural-review.com/essays/reputations/martin-heidegger-1889-1976|title=Martin Heidegger (1889–1976)|last1=Davies|first1=Paul|date=11 April 2017|access-date=9 October 2020|archive-date=26 January 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210126041136/https://www.architectural-review.com/essays/reputations/martin-heidegger-1889-1976|url-status=live}} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=0-521-38597-0 | chapter=Time and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger |title=The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger | author-last=Dostal |author-first=Robert J. |editor=Charles Guignon | date=1993 | publisher=Cambridge University Press |pages=141–69}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Dreyfus |first1=Hubert L. |year=1991 |title=Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's ''Being and Time'', Division I |publisher=MIT Press }} | |||
* {{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AU5_Vd-O4e4C&pg=PA85&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Sloterdijk Now|isbn=9780745651361|last1=Elden|first1=Stuart|date=2012|publisher=Polity|access-date=14 March 2023 | archive-date=21 June 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230621205206/https://books.google.com/books?id=AU5_Vd-O4e4C&pg=PA85|url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0300072549 | title=Hannah Arendt/Martin Heidegger |last1=Ettinger | first1=Elzbieta | date= 1997 | publisher=Yale University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book |last= Evans |first=Richard J.|author-link=Richard J. Evans |title=The Coming of the Third Reich|publisher=Penguin Books|date=2005 |pages=419–422 |isbn=978-0143034698}} | |||
* {{cite book | last = Farin | first = Ingo | title = Reading Heidegger's "Black notebooks 1931--1941 | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=m2OkCwAAQBAJ | publisher = The MIT Press | location = Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England | year = 2016 | isbn = 978-0262034012 | access-date = 18 June 2022 | archive-date = 1 March 2024 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20240301000127/https://books.google.com/books?id=m2OkCwAAQBAJ | url-status = live }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=IHLgtD-1tv8C&pg=PA32&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=Caring for the Soul in a Postmodern Age: Politics and Phenomenology in the Thought of Jan Patočka | isbn=9780791454855 | last1=Findlay | first1=Edward F. | year=2002 | publisher=SUNY Press | access-date=14 March 2023 | archive-date=21 June 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230621205202/https://books.google.com/books?id=IHLgtD-1tv8C&pg=PA32 | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book |editor-last= Fleischacker |editor-first= Samuel |title=Heidegger's Jewish Followers: Essays on Hannah Arendt, Leo Strauss, Hans Jonas, and Emmanuel Levinas |publisher=] Press |date=August 2008 |isbn=978-0820704128}} | |||
* {{cite web |last=Fiske |first=Edward B. |date=May 27, 1976 |title=Martin Heidegger, a Philosopher Who Affected Many Fields, Dies |url=https://www.nytimes.com/1976/05/27/archives/martin-heidegger-a-philosopher-who-affected-many-fields-dies-martin.html |work=] |access-date=18 September 2019 |archive-date=13 December 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221213181015/https://www.nytimes.com/1976/05/27/archives/martin-heidegger-a-philosopher-who-affected-many-fields-dies-martin.html |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0791417379 | title=Heidegger's Ways | last1=Gadamer | first1=Hans Georg | date=1994 | publisher=SUNY Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-9401796781 | title=Heidegger in the Twenty-First Century |last1=Georgakis | first1=Tziovanis | last2=Ennis | first2=Paul J. | date=2015 | publisher=Springer }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Gillespie |first1=Michael Allen |year=1984 |title=Hegel, Heidegger, and the Ground of History |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=9780226293769 }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hjicAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA90&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=Twentieth Century German Philosophy | isbn=978-0-19-289309-3 | last1=Gorner | first1=Paul | year=2000 | publisher=Oxford University Press | access-date=13 November 2022 | archive-date=13 November 2022 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221113143146/https://books.google.com/books?id=hjicAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA90 | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_UdNAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA65&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=Heidegger and Rhetoric | isbn=9780791465516 | editor1-last=Gross | editor1-first=Daniel M. | editor2-last=Kemmann | editor2-first=Ansgar | year=2005 | publisher=SUNY Press | access-date=18 June 2022 | archive-date=29 February 2024 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240229235911/https://books.google.com/books?id=_UdNAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA65#v=onepage&q&f=false | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite journal | last1 = Habermas | first1 = Jürgen | author-link = Jürgen Habermas | year = 1989 | title = Work and ''Weltanschauung'': the Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective | journal = ] | volume = 15 | issue = 2| pages = 452–54 | doi = 10.1086/448492 | s2cid = 143394757 }} | |||
* {{cite book | last1 = Habermas | first1 = Jürgen |translator=Frederick Lawrence | title = The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures | publisher = MIT Press | year = 1990}} | |||
* {{cite book | last = Hemming | first = Laurence | title = Heidegger and Marx : a productive dialogue over the language of humanism | publisher = Northwestern University Press |location = Evanston, Ill | year = 2013 | isbn = 978-0810128750 }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-3030694951 | title=Martin Heidegger and the Truth About the Black Notebooks | last1=Herrmann | first1=Friedrich-Wilhelm von | last2=Alfieri | first2=Francesco | date=2021 | publisher=Springer }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dNlmDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT139 | title=Heidegger and the Problem of Consciousness | isbn=9780253035981 | last1=Holland | first1=Nancy J. | year=2018 | publisher=Indiana University Press | access-date=22 June 2020 | archive-date=29 February 2024 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240229235911/https://books.google.com/books?id=dNlmDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT139#v=onepage&q&f=false | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Horrigan-Kelly|first1=Marcella |first2=Michelle |last2=Millar |first3=Maura |last3=Dowling |title=Understanding the Key Tenets of Heidegger's Philosophy for Interpretive Phenomenological Research |journal=International Journal of Qualitative Methods |year=2016 |volume=15 |issue=January–December 2016: 1–8 |doi=10.1177/1609406916680634 |s2cid=152252826 |doi-access=free |hdl=10379/7166 |hdl-access=free }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Husserl |first1=Edmund |title=Psychological and transcendental phenomenology and the confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931) |year=1997 |publisher=Kluwer}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Inwood |first1=Michael |year=1999 |title=A Heidegger Dictionary |publisher=Blackwell}} | |||
* {{cite news |last=Inwood |first=Michael |date=12 April 2014 |title=Martin Heidegger: the philosopher who fell for Hitler |url=https://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/books/10739165/Martin-Heidegger-the-philosopher-who-fell-for-Hitler.html |work=] |access-date=27 September 2018 |archive-date=24 February 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230224233752/https://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/books/10739165/Martin-Heidegger-the-philosopher-who-fell-for-Hitler.html |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book|isbn=978-0-19-256380-4 |title=Heidegger: A Very Short Introduction |last1=Inwood |first1=Michael |date=2019 |edition=2nd, ebook|publisher=Oxford University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0AIorc_ytnQC&pg=PT178 | title=Die Vereinigten Staaten von Europa: Geheimdokumente enthüllen: Die dunklen Pläne der Elite | isbn=9783862484713 | last1=Janich | first1=Oliver | year=2013 | publisher=FinanzBuch Verlag | access-date=25 August 2020 | archive-date=29 February 2024 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240229235914/https://books.google.com/books?id=0AIorc_ytnQC&pg=PT178 | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0253017734 | title=Heidegger in France | last1=Janicaud | first1=Dominique | date= 2015 | publisher=Indiana University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Kisiel |first1=Theodore |year=1993 |title=The Genesis of ''Being and Time'' |publisher=California University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0791420683 | title=Reading Heidegger from the Start: Essays in His Earliest Thought | last1=Kisiel | first1=Theodore J. | last2=Buren | first2=John Van | date=1994 | publisher=State University of New York Press }} | |||
* {{cite journal | doi=10.1163/156916475x00114 | title=On the Manifold Meaning of Aletheia: Brentano, Aristotle, Heidegger | date=1975 | last1=Krell | first1=David Farrell | journal=Research in Phenomenology | volume=5 | pages=77–94}} | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia |last=Korab-Karpowicz |first=W. J. |title=Martin Heidegger (1889—1976) |publisher=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/heidegge/ |access-date=25 December 2020 |archive-date=27 January 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230127171137/https://iep.utm.edu/heidegge/ |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=978-3631712917 |title=The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger |last1=Korab-Karpowicz |first1=Julian W. | year=2016 |publisher=Peter Lang }} | |||
* {{cite journal | last1 = Lambert | first1 = Cesar | year = 2007 | title = Some considerations about the correspondence between Martin Heidegger and Bernhard Welte | journal = Revista de Filosofía | volume = 63 | pages = 157–169 | doi = 10.4067/S0718-43602007000100012 | doi-access = free }} | |||
* {{cite book| isbn=978-1848192010 |title=Tao - a New Way of Thinking: A Translation of the Tao Tê Ching with an Introduction and Commentaries | author1=Laozi |year=2013 |publisher=Jessica Kingsley Publishers }} | |||
* {{cite book|last1=Löwith|first1=Karl|title=Mein Leben in Deutschland vor und nach 1933: Ein Bericht|year=1989|url=https://archive.org/details/meinlebenindeuts0000karl/page/56/mode/2up|publisher=Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag|location=Frankfurt am Main|isbn=3-596-25677-1}} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0415452526 | title=The Neo-Kantian Reader | last1=Luft | first1=Sebastian | date=2015 | publisher=Routledge }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0801883026 | title=Paul Celan and Martin Heidegger: An Unresolved Conversation, 1951–1970 | last1=Lyon | first1=James K. | date=2006 | publisher=JHU Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kyTAgAAQBAJ | title=Heidegger on East-West Dialogue: Anticipating the Event | isbn=9781135908690 | last1=Ma | first1=Lin | date=2007 | publisher=Routledge | access-date=11 April 2020 | archive-date=22 August 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230822140238/https://books.google.com/books?id=2kyTAgAAQBAJ | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book| isbn=978-0393068337 | title=Stranger from Abroad: Hannah Arendt, Martin Heidegger, Friendship and Forgiveness |last1=Maier-Katkin |first1=Daniel |year=2010 | publisher=W. W. Norton & Company }} | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=978-0415140386 | title=Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East Asian Influences on His Work | last1=May | first1=Reinhard | year=1996 | publisher=Psychology Press }} | |||
* {{cite book |isbn=978-0802860071 | title=Heidegger: A (Very) Critical Introduction |last1=McGrath |first1=S. J.| year=2008 |publisher=Wm. B. Eerdmans }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0300022360 | title=Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays |last1=Murray | first1=Michael | date=1978 | publisher=Yale University Press }} | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Moran |first1=Dermot |title=Heidegger's Critique of Husserl's and Brentano's Accounts of Intentionality |journal=Inquiry |date=2000 |volume= 43|issue=1 |pages=39–65 |doi=10.1080/002017400321361 |s2cid=54834191 }} | |||
* {{cite book|last1=Nelson|first1=Eric S.|title="Heidegger and Dilthey: Language, History, and Hermeneutics", in Horizons of Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology, edited by Hans Pedersen and Megan Altman|date=2014 |publisher=Springer |location=Dordrecht |isbn=978-9401794411 |pages=109–28}} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-1557783103 | title=Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers | last1=Neske | first1=Gunther | last2=Kettering | first2=Emil | date=1990 | publisher=Paragon House }} | |||
* {{cite web |last1=Nirenberg |first1=David |title=When Philosophy Mattered |url=https://newrepublic.com/article/81380/heidegger-cassirer-davos-kant |date=13 January 2011 |publisher=] |access-date=23 July 2020 |archive-date=23 July 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200723085745/https://newrepublic.com/article/81380/heidegger-cassirer-davos-kant |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vC1qAj6RbRQC&pg=PA351&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=Journeys East: 20th Century Western Encounters with Eastern Religious Traditions | isbn=9780941532570 | last1=Oldmeadow | first1=Harry | date=2004 | publisher=World Wisdom | access-date=11 April 2020 | archive-date=29 February 2024 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240229235912/https://books.google.com/books?id=vC1qAj6RbRQC&pg=PA351#v=onepage&q&f=false | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LNrkHmE5xfkC&pg=PA33&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=Transforming the Hermeneutic Context: From Nietzsche to Nancy | isbn=9780791401347 | last1=Ormiston | first1=Gayle L. | last2=Schrift | first2=Alan D. | date=January 1990 | publisher=SUNY Press | access-date=29 November 2022 | archive-date=29 November 2022 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221129122727/https://books.google.com/books?id=LNrkHmE5xfkC&pg=PA33 | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-1903364765 | title=The Cinema of Terrence Malick: Poetic Visions of America | editor1-last=Patterson | editor1-first=Hannah | date=2003 | publisher=Wallflower }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Polt |first1=Richard F. H. |year=1999 |title=Heidegger: An Introduction |publisher=Cornell University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0300085235 | title=A Companion to Heidegger's Introduction to Metaphysics | last1=Polt | first1=Richard | last2=Fried | first2=Gregory |year=2001 | publisher=Yale University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eSZMAQAAQBAJ&pg=PT224&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false | title=The Bloomsbury Companion to Heidegger | isbn=9781441199850 | last1=Raffoul | first1=Francois | last2=Nelson | first2=Eric S. | year=2013 | publisher=A&C Black | access-date=5 July 2023 | archive-date=5 July 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230705121450/https://books.google.com/books?id=eSZMAQAAQBAJ&pg=PT224 | url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book|last=Richardson|first=William J.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5y4QAQAAIAAJ|title=Heidegger. Through Phenomenology to Thought|others=Preface by Martin Heidegger|publisher=]|location=]|year=1963}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230621205201/https://books.google.com/books?id=C0cf3q3NJuwC |date=21 June 2023 }} (2003). The Bronx: ]. {{ISBN|0-823-22255-1}}; {{ISBN|978-08-2322-255-1}}. | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0520077119 | title=On Heidegger's Nazism and Philosophy | last1=Rockmore | first1=Tom | date= 1992 | publisher=University of California Press }} | |||
*{{cite journal |jstor=23955847 |title=Dilthey and Historical Reason |last1=Rockmore |first1=Tom |journal=Revue Internationale de Philosophie |date=2003 |volume=226 |issue=4 |pages=477–494 |doi=10.3917/rip.226.0477 |s2cid=170687756 }} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Russell |first=Bertrand |url=https://archive.org/details/wisdomofwesthis00russ/page/303/mode/1up |title=Wisdom of the West; a historical survey of Western philosophy in its social and political setting |publisher=] |year=1959 |isbn=978-0-517-69041-3 |location=Garden City, N.Y. |page=303 |author-link=Bertrand Russell }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Safranski |first1=Rüdiger |translator=Ewald Osers |year=1998 |title=] |publisher=Harvard University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Sandkühler |first1=Hans Jörg |title=Enzyklopädie Philosophie |date=2010 |publisher=Meiner |url=https://meiner.de/enzyklopadie-philosophie.html |chapter=Ontologie |access-date=25 December 2020 |archive-date=11 March 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210311040207/https://meiner.de/enzyklopadie-philosophie.html |url-status=dead }} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Schalow |first1=Frank |last2=Denker |first2=Alfred |year=2010 |title= Historical Dictionary of Heidegger's Philosophy|publisher=Scarecrow Press }} | |||
* {{cite journal | doi=10.5325/philrhet.51.2.0176 | title=Rhetorical Action in ''Rektoratsrede'': Calling Heidegger's ''Gefolgschaft'' | date=2018 | last1=Sharpe | first1=Matthew | journal=Philosophy & Rhetoric | volume=51 | issue=2 | pages=176–201 | s2cid=149519358}} | |||
* {{cite news |last1=Sheehan |first1=Thomas |title=Heidegger and the Nazis |url=http://www.stanford.edu/dept/relstud/faculty/sheehan/pdf/88-nazi.PDF |work=] |date=16 June 1988 |volume=35 |issue=10 |pages=38–47 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111107062318/http://www.stanford.edu/dept/relstud/faculty/sheehan/pdf/88-nazi.PDF |access-date=27 April 2017 |archive-date=7 November 2011 }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0674365070 | title=Heidegger's Crisis | last1=Sluga | first1=Hans | date= 2013 | publisher=Harvard University Press }} | |||
* {{cite news |last=Steinfels |first=Peter |date=27 December 1995 |title=Emmanuel Levinas, 90, French Ethical Philosopher |url=https://www.nytimes.com/1995/12/27/world/emmanuel-levinas-90-french-ethical-philosopher.html |work=] |access-date=27 September 2018 |archive-date=21 June 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230621205157/https://www.nytimes.com/1995/12/27/world/emmanuel-levinas-90-french-ethical-philosopher.html |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=0-521-38597-0 | chapter=Engaged Agency and Background |title=The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger | author-last=Taylor |author-first=Charles |editor= Charles Guignon | date=1993 | publisher=Cambridge University Press |pages=317–36}} | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/authenticity/ |title=Authenticity |date=11 September 2014 |last1=Varga |first1=Somogy |last2=Guignon |first2=Charles |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=2020 |editor=Edward N. Zalta |access-date=11 September 2023 |archive-date=1 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240301000140/https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/authenticity/ |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/heidegger/ |title=Martin Heidegger |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=2020 |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2020 |last=Wheeler |first=Michael |access-date=14 October 2020 |archive-date=30 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220630205544/https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/heidegger/ |url-status=live }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=9781405881180| title=Longman Pronunciation Dictionary| last1=Wells| first1=John| date=23 May 2008| edition=3rd |publisher=Pearson}} | |||
*{{cite book |isbn=978-3-319-77246-2 |title=The Self and Social Relations |last1=Whittingham |first1=Matthew |date=2018 |publisher=Springer }} | |||
* {{cite book | isbn=978-0231075961 | title=The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader | last1=Wolin | first1=Richard | date=1991 | publisher=Columbia University Press }} | |||
*{{cite book |last=Wolin|first=Richard|author-link= Richard Wolin|title=Heidegger's Children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Hans Jonas, and Herbert Marcuse |publisher=] Press |date=2015 |isbn=9780691168616}} | |||
* {{cite book | first1=Mark |last1= Wrathall |title=Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, and History |publisher=Cambridge University Press|year= 2010}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Young|first=Julian |author-link=Julian Young|title=Heidegger, Philosophy, Nazism |publisher=Cambridge University Press |date=1998|isbn=978-0521644945}} | |||
* {{cite book|isbn=978-0300105889 |title=Hannah Arendt: For Love of the World |last1=Young-Bruehl |first1=Elisabeth |date=January 2004 |publisher=Yale University Press }} | |||
* {{cite book|isbn=978-0821405703 |title=Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger's Concept of Authenticity |last1=Zimmerman |first1=Michael E. |date=1981 |publisher=Ohio University Press }} | |||
* {{cite journal |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/3235130 |jstor=3235130 |title=The Politics of Derridean Deconstruction |last1=Zuckert |first1=Catherine |journal=Polity |date=1991 |volume=23 |issue=3 |pages=335–356 |doi=10.2307/3235130 |s2cid=147001554 |access-date=6 September 2023 |archive-date=6 September 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230906104257/https://www.jstor.org/stable/3235130 |url-status=live }} | |||
{{Refend}} | |||
==External links== | |||
=== Politics and National Socialism === | |||
{{commons}} | |||
* ], ''The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger'' | |||
{{wikiquote}} | |||
* Miguel de Beistegui, ''Heidegger and the Political: Dystopias'' | |||
{{Library resources box|by=yes|onlinebooks=no|about=yes|wikititle=Martin Heidegger}} | |||
* ], ''Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger and nazism'', Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 1989. | |||
* ], ''Heidegger, l'introduction du nazisme dans la philosophie : autour des séminaires inédits de 1933-1935'', Paris, Albin Michel, 2005. ISBN 2-226-14252-5 <small>in French language</small> | |||
* ] & Otto Pöggeler (eds.), ''Heidegger und die praktische Philosophie'', Frankfurt a. M., ], 1989. <small>in German language</small> | |||
* ], ''The Shadow of That Thought'' | |||
* ], "Transcendence Ends in Politics", in ''Typography: Mimesis, Philosophy, Politics'' | |||
* Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, ''Heidegger, Art, and Politics: The Fiction of the Political'' | |||
* George Leaman, ''Heidegger im Kontext: Gesamtüberblick zum NS-Engagement der Universitätsphilosophen'', Argument Verlag, Hamburg, 1993. ISBN 3-88619-205-9 | |||
* ], ''Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism'' | |||
* Karl Löwith | |||
* ], ''Heidegger and "the jews"'' | |||
* Günther Neske & Emil Kettering (eds.), ''Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers'' | |||
* | |||
* Tom Rockmore and ] (ed.), ''The Heidegger Case'' | |||
* ], | |||
* ], ''Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in Nazi Germany'' | |||
* Iain Thomson, ''Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education'' | |||
* Dana Villa, ''Arendt and Heidegger: the Fate of the Political'' | |||
* ] (ed.), ''The Heidegger Controversy'' ISBN 0-262-23166-2. | |||
===Archival collections=== | |||
=== Other secondary literature === | |||
* are kept at the ] archives. See also "The transcripts and photocopies of Martin Heidegger's writings were given to Barbara Fiand, SNDdeN, Ph.D., by Fritz Heidegger in 1978". | |||
* ], ''Heidegger in Question: The Art of Existing'' | |||
* | |||
* Walter A. Brogan, ''Heidegger and Aristotle: The Twofoldness of Being'' | |||
* . Special Collections and Archives, The UC Irvine Libraries, Irvine, California. | |||
* Gabriel Cercel / ] (eds), ''The Early Heidegger'' (''Studia Phaenomenologica'' I, 3-4), Bucharest: Humanitas, 2001, 506 p., including letters by Heidegger and Pöggeler, and articles by Walter Biemel, Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, ], Marion Heinz, Alfred Denker | |||
* | |||
* Steven Galt Crowell, ''Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning: Paths toward Transcendental Phenomenology'' | |||
* {{Helveticat}} | |||
* Jacques Derrida, "''Ousia'' and ''Gramme'': Note on a Note from ''Being and Time''", in ''Margins of Philosophy'' | |||
* Majority of Heidegger Archives. Online: in the town of Marbach am Neckar, Germany. Also known as: . Most of Martin Heidegger's manuscripts are in the DLA's collection. Search for Heidegger in their | |||
* ], ''Heidegger's Confusions'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger: Thought and Historicity'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger Explained'' | |||
* Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, ''Poetry as Experience'' | |||
* Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, ''Heidegger and the Politics of Poetry'' | |||
* ], ''The Glance of the Eye: Heidegger, Aristotle, and the Ends of Theory'' | |||
* William McNeill, ''The Time of Life: Heidegger and Ethos'' | |||
* ], "The Decision of Existence", in ''The Birth to Presence'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger's Philosophy of Being: A Critical Interpretation'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger: An Introduction'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger and the Subject'' | |||
* François Raffoul & David Pettigrew (ed), ''Heidegger and Practical Philosophy'' | |||
* ], ''Echoes: After Heidegger'' | |||
* John Sallis (ed), ''Reading Heidegger: Commemorations'', including articles by Robert Bernasconi, Jacques Derrida, ], and John Sallis, among others. | |||
* ], ''Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles to Anarchy'' | |||
* Tony See, ''Community without Identity: The Ontology and Politics of Heidegger'' | |||
* Adam Sharr, ''Heidegger's Hut'' | |||
* ], '']'' | |||
* ], "An Introduction to Heideggerian Existentialism," in '']'' (University of Chicago: 1989). | |||
* Andrzej Warminski, ''Readings in Interpretation: Hölderlin, Hegel, Heidegger'' | |||
=== |
===General information=== | ||
* | |||
* ], ''Dialogue avec Heidegger'', 4 vols. | |||
* ], in '']'' | |||
* ], ''Heidegger en France'', 2 vols. | |||
* ], , Rome 1936 | |||
* ], ''Heidegger - Pensée de l'être et origine de la subjectivité'', 1760 pages, first and only book on Heidegger awarded by the ]. | |||
* {{in lang|de}} | |||
* ], ''Generation Existential: Heidegger's Philosophy in France, 1927–1961'' | |||
* Arne D. Naess Jr., in '']'' | |||
* Martin Heidegger, | |||
* | |||
* {{PM20|FID=pe/007408}} | |||
* | |||
===Works by Heidegger=== | |||
=== Influence on Japanese philosophy === | |||
* Mayeda, Graham. 2006. ''Time, space and ethics in the philosophy of Watsuji Tetsurō, Kuki Shūzō, and Martin Heidegger'' (New York: Routledge, 2006). ISBN 0415976731 (alk. paper). | |||
=== Influence on Asian philosophy === | |||
* Parkes, Graham. 1987. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 0824810643. | |||
== See also == | |||
* '']'' | |||
* ] | |||
* '']'' | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
==References== | |||
{{reflist|colwidth=30em}} | |||
== External links == | |||
{{sisterlinks|Martin Heidegger}} | |||
=== General information === | |||
* {{de icon}} | |||
* | |||
=== Works by Heidegger === | |||
* | * | ||
* {{Internet Archive author |sname=Martin Heidegger}} | |||
* | |||
{{Martin Heidegger}} | |||
{{navboxes | |||
|list= | |||
{{continental philosophy}} | {{continental philosophy}} | ||
{{Existentialism}} | |||
{{metaphysics}} | {{metaphysics}} | ||
{{Philosophy of mind}} |
{{Philosophy of mind}} | ||
{{Aesthetics |
{{Aesthetics}} | ||
{{Conservative Revolution}} | |||
{{Social and political philosophy}} | |||
}} | |||
{{Authority control}} | |||
{{Persondata | |||
|NAME=Heidegger, Martin | |||
|ALTERNATIVE NAMES= | |||
|SHORT DESCRIPTION=German ] | |||
|DATE OF BIRTH=26 September 1889 | |||
|PLACE OF BIRTH=], Germany | |||
|DATE OF DEATH=26 May 1976 | |||
|PLACE OF DEATH=], Germany | |||
}} | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Heidegger, Martin}} | {{DEFAULTSORT:Heidegger, Martin}} | ||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
{{Link FA|de}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Revision as of 04:39, 16 December 2024
German philosopher (1889–1976) "Heidegger" redirects here. For other uses, see Heidegger (disambiguation).
Martin Heidegger | |
---|---|
Heidegger in 1960 | |
Born | (1889-09-26)26 September 1889 Meßkirch, Grand Duchy of Baden, German Empire |
Died | 26 May 1976(1976-05-26) (aged 86) Freiburg, Baden-Württemberg, West Germany |
Education | Collegium Borromaeum [de] (1909–1911) University of Freiburg (PhD, 1914; Dr. phil. hab. 1916) |
Spouse |
Elfride Petri (m. 1917) |
Partners |
|
Era | 20th-century philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | Continental philosophy Existentialism Hermeneutics Phenomenology |
Institutions | University of Marburg University of Freiburg |
Theses | |
Doctoral advisor | Arthur Schneider (PhD advisor) Heinrich Rickert (Dr. phil. hab. advisor) |
Main interests | |
Political party | Nazi Party (1933–1945) |
Signature | |
Martin Heidegger (/ˈhaɪdɛɡər, ˈhaɪdɪɡər/; German: [ˈmaʁtiːn ˈhaɪdɛɡɐ]; 26 September 1889 – 26 May 1976) was a German philosopher best known for contributions to phenomenology, hermeneutics, and existentialism. His work covers a wide range of topics including ontology, technology, art, metaphysics, humanism, language and history of philosophy. He is often considered to be among the most important and influential philosophers of the 20th century, especially in the continental tradition.
In April 1933, Heidegger was elected as rector at the University of Freiburg and was widely criticized for his membership and support for the Nazi Party during his tenure. After World War II he was dismissed from Freiburg and banned from teaching after denazification hearings at Freiburg. There has been controversy about the relationship between his philosophy and Nazism.
In Heidegger's first major text, Being and Time (1927), Dasein is introduced as a term for the type of being that humans possess. Heidegger believed that Dasein already has a "pre-ontological" and concrete understanding that shapes how it lives, which he analyzed in terms of the unitary structure of "being-in-the-world". Heidegger used this analysis to approach the question of the meaning of being; that is, the question of how entities appear as the specific entities they are. In other words, Heidegger's governing "question of being" is concerned with what makes beings intelligible as beings.
Life
Early years
Heidegger was born on 26 September 1889 in rural Meßkirch, Baden, the son of Johanna (Kempf) and Friedrich Heidegger. His father was the sexton of the village church, and the young Martin was raised Roman Catholic.
In 1903, Heidegger began to train for the priesthood. He entered a Jesuit seminary in 1909, but was discharged within weeks because of heart trouble. It was during this time that he first encountered the work of Franz Brentano. From here he went on to study theology and scholastic philosophy at the University of Freiburg.
In 1911 he broke off training for the priesthood and turned his attention to recent philosophy, in particular, Edmund Husserl's Logical Investigations. He graduated with a thesis on psychologism, The Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism: A Critical-theoretical Contribution to Logic, in 1914. The following year, he completed his habilitation thesis on Duns Scotus, which was directed by Heinrich Rickert, a Neo-Kantian, and influenced by Husserl's phenomenology. The title has been published in several languages and in English is "Duns Scotus's doctrine of categories and meaning".
He attempted to get the (Catholic) philosophy post at the University of Freiburg on 23 June 1916 but failed despite the support of Heinrich Finke [de]. Instead, he worked first as an unsalaried Privatdozent then served as a soldier during the final year of World War I. His service was in the last ten months of the war, most of which he spent in meteorological unit on the western front upon being deemed unfit for combat.
Heidegger married Elfride Petri on 21 March 1917 in a Catholic ceremony officiated by his friend Engelbert Krebs [de], and a week later in a Protestant ceremony in the presence of her parents. Their first son, Jörg, was born in 1919. Elfride then gave birth to Hermann [de] in August 1920. Heidegger knew that he was not Hermann's biological father, but raised him as his son. Hermann's biological father, who became godfather to his son, was family friend and doctor Friedel Caesar. Hermann was told of this at the age of 14; Hermann grew up to become a historian and would later serve as the executor of Heidegger's will.
In the same year that he married his wife, Heidegger began a decades-long correspondence with her friend Elisabeth Blochmann. Their letters are suggestive from the beginning, and it is certain they were romantically involved in the summer of 1929. Blochmann was Jewish, which raises questions in light of Heidegger's later membership in the Nazi Party.
From 1919 to 1923, Heidegger taught courses at the University of Freiburg. At this time he also became an assistant to Husserl, who had been a professor there since 1916.
Marburg
In 1923, Heidegger was elected to an extraordinary professorship in philosophy at the University of Marburg. His colleagues there included Rudolf Bultmann, Nicolai Hartmann, Paul Tillich, and Paul Natorp. Heidegger's students at Marburg included Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Gerhard Krüger, Leo Strauss, Jacob Klein, Günther Anders, and Hans Jonas. Following Aristotle, he began to develop in his lectures the main theme of his philosophy: the question of the sense of being. He extended the concept of subject to the dimension of history and concrete existence, which he found prefigured in such Christian thinkers as Paul of Tarsus, Augustine of Hippo, Martin Luther, and Søren Kierkegaard. He also read the works of Wilhelm Dilthey, Husserl, Max Scheler, and Friedrich Nietzsche.
In 1925, a 35-year-old Heidegger began what would be a four-year affair with Hannah Arendt, who was then 19 years old and his student. Like Blochmann, Arendt was Jewish. Heidegger and Arendt agreed to keep the details of the relationship a secret, preserving their letters, but keeping them unavailable. The affair was not widely known until 1995, when Elzbieta Ettinger gained access to the sealed correspondence. Nevertheless, Arendt faced criticism for her association with Heidegger after his election as rector at the University of Freiburg in 1933.
In 1927 Heidegger published his main work, Sein und Zeit (Being and Time). He was primarily concerned to qualify to be a full professor. The book, however, did more than this: it raised him to "a position of international intellectual visibility."
Freiburg
When Husserl retired as professor of philosophy in 1928, Heidegger accepted Freiburg's election to be his successor, in spite of a counter-offer by Marburg. The title of his 1929 inaugural lecture was "What is Metaphysics?" In this year he also published Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics.
Heidegger remained at Freiburg im Breisgau for the rest of his life, declining later offers including one from Humboldt University of Berlin. His students at Freiburg included Hannah Arendt, Günther Anders, Hans Jonas, Karl Löwith, Charles Malik, Herbert Marcuse, and Ernst Nolte. Emmanuel Levinas attended his lecture courses during his stay in Freiburg in 1928, as did Jan Patočka in 1933; Patočka in particular was deeply influenced by him.
Heidegger was elected rector of the university on 21 April 1933, and joined the Nazi Party on 1 May, just three months after Adolf Hitler was appointed chancellor. During his time as rector he was a member and an enthusiastic supporter of the party. There is continuing controversy as to the relationship between his philosophy and his political allegiance to Nazism. He wanted to position himself as the philosopher of the party, but the highly abstract nature of his work and the opposition of Alfred Rosenberg, who himself aspired to act in that position, limited Heidegger's role. His withdrawal from his position as rector owed more to his frustration as an administrator than to any principled opposition to the Nazis, according to historians. In his inaugural address as rector on 27 May he expressed his support of a German revolution, and in an article and a speech to the students from the same year he also supported Adolf Hitler. In November 1933, Heidegger signed the Vow of allegiance of the Professors of the German Universities and High-Schools to Adolf Hitler and the National Socialistic State. Heidegger resigned from the rectorate in April 1934, but remained a member of the Nazi Party until 1945 even though the Nazis eventually prevented him from publishing.
In 1935, he gave the talk "The Origin of the Work of Art". The next year, while in Rome, Heidegger gave his first lecture on Friedrich Hölderlin. In the years 1936–1937, Heidegger wrote what some commentators consider his second greatest work, Contributions to Philosophy; it would not be published, however, until 1989, 13 years after his death.
From 1936 to 1940, Heidegger also delivered a series of lectures on Friedrich Nietzsche at Freiburg that presented much of the raw material incorporated in his more established work and thought from this time. These would appear in published form in 1961. This period also marks the beginning of his interest in the "essence of technology".
In the autumn of 1944, Heidegger was drafted into the Volkssturm and assigned to dig anti-tank ditches along the Rhine.
Post-war
In late 1946, as France engaged in épuration légale in its occupation zone, the French military authorities determined that Heidegger should be blocked from teaching or participating in any university activities because of his association with the Nazi Party. Nevertheless, he presented the talk "What are Poets for?" in memory of Rilke. He also published "On Humanism" in 1947 to clarify his differences with Jean-Paul Sartre and French existentialism. The denazification procedures against Heidegger continued until March 1949 when he was finally pronounced a Mitläufer (the second lowest of five categories of "incrimination" by association with the Nazi regime). No punitive measures against him were proposed. This opened the way for his readmission to teaching at Freiburg University in the winter semester of 1950–51. He was granted emeritus status and then taught regularly from 1951 until 1958, and by invitation until 1967.
In 1966 he gave an interview to Der Spiegel attempting to justify his support of the Nazi Party. Per their agreement, it was not published until five days after his death in 1976, under the title "Only a God Can Save Us" after a reference to Hölderlin that Heidegger makes during the interview.
Heidegger's publications during this time were mostly reworked versions of his lectures. In his last days, he also arranged for a complete edition of his works to be compiled and published. Its first volume appeared in 1975. As of 2019, the edition is almost complete at over 100 volumes.
Death
Heidegger died on 26 May 1976 in Freiburg. A few months before his death, he met with Bernhard Welte, a Catholic priest, Freiburg University professor and earlier correspondent. The exact nature of their conversation is not known, but what is known is that it included talk of Heidegger's relationship to the Catholic Church and subsequent Christian burial at which the priest officiated. Heidegger was buried in the Meßkirch cemetery.
Early influences
Edmund Husserl, the founder of phenomenology, was Heidegger's teacher and a major influence on his thought. While the specific lines of influence remain a matter of scholarly dispute, one thing is clear: Heidegger's early work on Being and Time moved away from Husserl's theory of intentionality to focus on the pre-theoretical conditions that enable consciousness to grasp objects.
Aristotle influenced Heidegger from an early age. This influence was mediated through Catholic theology, medieval philosophy, and Franz Brentano. According to scholar Michael Wheeler, it is by way of a "radical rethinking" of Aristotle's Metaphysics that Heidegger supplants Husserl's notion of intentionality with his unitary notion of being-in-the-world. According to this reinterpretation, the various modes of being are united in more basic capacity of taking-as or making-present-to.
The works of Wilhelm Dilthey shaped Heidegger's very early project of developing a "hermeneutics of factical life", and his hermeneutical transformation of phenomenology. There is little doubt that Heidegger seized upon Dilthey's concept of hermeneutics. Heidegger's novel ideas about ontology required a gestalt formation, not merely a series of logical arguments, in order to demonstrate his fundamentally new paradigm of thinking, and the hermeneutic circle offered a new and powerful tool for the articulation and realization of these ideas.
Søren Kierkegaard contributed much to Heidegger's treatment of the existentialist aspects of his thought located in Division II of Being and Time. Heidegger's concepts of anxiety (Angst) and mortality draw on Kierkegaard and are indebted to the way in which the latter lays out the importance of our subjective relation to truth, our existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world.
Philosophy
See also: Heideggerian terminologyFundamental ontology
See also: Fundamental ontologyAccording to scholar Taylor Carman, traditional ontology asks "Why is there anything?", whereas Heidegger's fundamental ontology asks "What does it mean for something to be?" Heidegger's ontology "is fundamental relative to traditional ontology in that it concerns what any understanding of entities necessarily presupposes, namely, our understanding of that by virtue of which entities are entities".
This line of inquiry is "central to Heidegger's philosophy". He accuses the Western philosophical tradition of mistakenly trying to understand being as such as if it were an ultimate entity. Heidegger modifies traditional ontology by focusing instead on the meaning of being. This kind of ontological inquiry, he claims, is required to understand the basis of our understanding, scientific and otherwise.
In short, before asking what exists, Heidegger contends that people must first examine what "to exist" even means.
Being and Time
See also: Being and TimeIn his first major work, Being and Time, Heidegger pursues this ontological inquiry by way of an analysis of the kind of being that people have, namely, that humans are the sort of beings able to pose the question of the meaning of being. According to Canadian philosopher Sean McGrath Heidegger was probably influenced by Scotus in this approach. His term for us, in this phenomenological context, is Dasein.
This procedure works because Dasein's pre-ontological understanding of being shapes experience. Dasein's ordinary and even mundane experience of "being-in-the-world" provides "access to the meaning" or "sense of being"; that is, the terms in which "something becomes intelligible as something." Heidegger proposes that this ordinary "prescientific" understanding precedes abstract ways of knowing, such as logic or theory. Being and Time is designed to show how this implicit understanding can be made progressively explicit through phenomenology and hermeneutics.
Being-in-the-world
Heidegger introduces the term Dasein to denote a "living being" through its activity of "being there". Understood as a unitary phenomenon rather than a contingent, additive combination, it is characterized by Heidegger as "being-in-the-world".
Heidegger insists that the 'in' of Dasein's being-in-the-world is an 'in' of involvement or of engagement, not of objective, physical enclosedness. The sense in which Dasein is 'in' the world is the sense of "residing" or "dwelling" in the world. Heidegger provides a few examples: "having to do with something, producing something, attending to something and looking after it, making use of something".
Just as 'being-in' does not denote objective, physical enclosedness, so 'world', as Heidegger uses the term, does not denote a universe of physical objects. The world, in Heidegger's sense, is to be understood according to our sense of our possibilities: things present themselves to people in terms of their projects, the uses to which they can put them. The 'sight' with which people grasp equipment is not a mentalistic intentionality, but what Heidegger calls 'circumspection'. This is to say that equipment reveals itself in terms of its 'towards-which,' in terms of the work it is good for. In the everyday world, people are absorbed within the equipmental totality of their work-world. Moreover, on Heidegger's analysis, this entails a radical holism. In his own words, "there 'is' no such thing as an equipment".
For example, when someone sits down to dinner and picks up their fork, they are not picking up an object with good stabbing properties: they are non-reflectively engaging an 'in-order-to-eat'. When it works as expected, equipment is transparent; when it is used, it is subsumed under the work toward which it is employed. Heidegger calls this structure of practically ordered reference relations the 'worldhood of the world'.
Heidegger calls the mode of being of such entities "ready-to-hand", for they are understood only in being handled. If the fork is made of plastic, however, and it snaps in the course of using it, then it assumes the mode of being that Heidegger calls "present-at-hand." For now the fork needs to be made the object of focal awareness, considering it in terms of its properties. Is it too broken to use? If so, could the diner possibly get by with another utensil or just with their fingers? This kind of equipmental breakdown is not the only way that objects become present-at-hand for us, but Heidegger considers it typical of the way that this shift occurs in the course of ordinary goings-on.
In this way, Heidegger creates a theoretical space for the categories of subject and object, while at the same time denying that they apply to our most basic way of moving about in the world, of which they are instead presented as derivative.
Heidegger presents three primary structural features of being-in-the-world: understanding, attunement, and discourse. He calls these features "existentiales" or "existentialia" (Existenzialien) to distinguish their ontological status, as distinct from the "categories" of metaphysics.
- Understanding is "our fundamental ability to be someone, to do things, to get around in the world". It is the basic "know-how" in terms of which Dasein goes about pursuing the usually humdrum tasks that make up daily life. Heidegger argues that this mode of understanding is more fundamental than theoretical understanding.
- Attunement is "our way of finding ourselves thrust into the world". It can also be translated as "disposition" or "affectedness". (The standard translation of Macquarrie and Robinson uses "state-of-mind", but this misleadingly suggests a private mental state.) There is no perfect equivalent for Heidegger's Befindlichkeit, which is not even an ordinary German word. What needs to be conveyed, however, is "being found in a situation where things and opinions already matter".
- Discourse (sometimes: talk or telling ) is "the articulation of the world into recognizable, communicable patterns of meaning." It is implicated in both understanding attunement: "The world that is opened up by moods and grasped by understanding gets organized by discourse. Discourse makes language possible." According to Heidegger, "Discourse is the articulation of intelligibility." In its most basic form, this referential whole manifests itself in the way things are told apart just in the course of using them.
Heidegger unifies these three existential features of Dasein in a composite structure he terms "care": "ahead-of-itself-being-already-in-(the-world) as being-amidst (entities encountered within-the-world)." What unifies this formula is temporality. Understanding is oriented towards future possibilities, attunement is shaped by the past, and discourse discloses the present in those terms. In this way, the investigation into the being of Dasein leads to time. Much of Division II of Being and Time is devoted to a more fundamental reinterpretation of the findings of Division I in terms of Dasein's temporality.
Das Man
As implied in the analysis of both attunement and discourse, Dasein is "always already", or a priori, a social being. In Heidegger's technical idiom, Dasein is "Dasein-with" (Mitsein), which he presents as equally primordial with "being-one's self" (Selbstsein).
Heidegger's term for this existential feature of Dasein is das Man, which is a German pronoun, man, that Heidegger turns into a noun. In English it is usually translated as either "the they" or "the one" (sometimes also capitalized); for, as Heidegger puts it, "By 'others' we do not mean everyone else but me.... They are rather those from whom for the most part, one does not distinguish oneself—those among whom one is too". Quite frequently the term is just left in the German.
According to philosopher Hubert Dreyfus, part of Heidegger's aim is to show that, contrary to Husserl, individuals do not generate an intersubjective world from their separate activities; rather, "these activities presuppose the disclosure of one shared world." This is one way in which Heidegger breaks from the Cartesian tradition of beginning from the perspective of individual subjectivity.
Dreyfus argues that the chapter on das Man is "the most confused" in Being and Time and so is often misinterpreted. The problem, he says, is that Heidegger's presentation conflates two opposing influences. The first is Dilthey's account of the role that public and historical contexts have in the production of significance. The second is Kierkegaard's insistence that truth is never to be found in the crowd.
The Diltheyian dimension of Heidegger's analysis positions das Man as ontologically existential in the same way as understanding, affectedness, and discourse. This dimension of Heidegger's analysis captures the way that a socio-historical "background" makes possible the specific significance that entities and activities can have. Philosopher Charles Taylor expands upon the term: "It is that of which I am not simply unaware... but at the same time I cannot be said to be explicitly or focally aware of it, because that status is already occupied by what it is making intelligible". For this reason, background non-representationally informs and enables engaged agency in the world, but is something that people can never make fully explicit to themselves.
The Kierkegaardian influence on Heidegger's analysis introduces a more existentialist dimension to Being and Time. (Existentialism is a broad philosophical movement largely defined by Jean-Paul Sartre and is not to be confused with Heidegger's technical analysis of the specific existential features of Dasein.) Its central notion is authenticity, which emerges as a problem from the "publicness" built into the existential role of das Man. In Heidegger's own words:
In this inconspicuousness and unascertainability, the real dictatorship of the 'they' is unfolded. We take pleasure and enjoy ourselves as they take pleasure; we read, see and judge about literature and art as they see and judge; likewise we shrink back from the 'great mass' as they shrink back; we find 'shocking' what they find shocking. The 'they', which is nothing definite, and which we all are, through not as the sum, prescribes the kind of being of everydayness.
This "dictatorship of das Man" threatens to undermine Heidegger's entire project of uncovering the meaning of being because it does not seem possible, from such a condition, to even raise the question of being that Heidegger claims to pursue. He responds to this challenge with his account of authenticity.
Authenticity
Heidegger's term Eigentlichkeit is a neologism, in which Heidegger stresses the root eigen, meaning "own." So this word, usually translated "authenticity", could just as well be translated "ownedness" or "being one's own". Authenticity, according to Heidegger, is a matter of taking responsibility for being, that is, the stand that people take with respect to their ultimate projects. It is, in his terms, a matter of taking a properly "resolute" stand on "for-the-sake-of-which". Put differently, the "self" to which one is true in authenticity is not something just "there" to be discovered, but instead is a matter of "on-going narrative construction".
Scholars Somogy Varga and Charles Guignon describe three ways by which Dasein might attain an authentic relation to itself from out of its "fallen" condition as "they"-self. First, a powerful mood such as anxiety can disclose Dasein to itself as an ultimately isolated individual. Second, direct confrontation with Dasein's "ownmost" potential for death can similarly disclose to Dasein its own irreducible finitude. Third, experiencing "the call of conscience" can disclose to Dasein its own "guilt" (Schuld) as the debt it has to itself in virtue of having taken over pre-given possibilities that it is now Dasein's own responsibility to maintain.
Philosopher Michael E. Zimmerman describes authenticity as "resolving to accept the openness which, paradoxically, one already is". He emphasizes that this is a matter, not of "intellectual comprehension", but of "hard-won insight". Authenticity is ultimately a matter of allowing the ego to be "eclipsed by the manifestation of one's finitude".
Although the term "authenticity" disappears from Heidegger's writing after Being and Time, Zimmerman argues that it is supplanted in his later thought by the less subjective or voluntaristic notion of Ereignis. This ordinary German term for "event" or "happening" is theorized by Heidegger as the appropriation of Dasein into a cosmic play of concealment and appearance.
Later works: The Turn
See also: KehreHeidegger's "Turn", which is sometimes referred to by the German die Kehre, refers to a change in his work as early as 1930 that became clearly established by the 1940s, according to some commentators, who variously describe a shift of focus or a major change in outlook.
Heidegger himself frequently used the term to refer to the shift announced at the end of Being and Time from "being and time" to "time and being". However, he rejected the existence of the "sharp 'about turn'" posited by some interpreters. Scholar Michael Inwood also calls attention to the fact that many of the ideas from Being and Time are retained in a different vocabulary in his later work—and also that, in other cases, a word or expression common throughout his career comes to acquire a different meaning in the later works.
This supposed shift—applied here to cover about 30 years of Heidegger's 40-year writing career—has been described by commentators from widely varied viewpoints, for instance, from dwelling (being) in the world to doing (temporality) in the world. This aspect, in particular the 1951 essay "Building Dwelling Thinking", has influenced several architectural theorists.
Other interpreters believe the Turn can be overstated or doesn't exist at all. For instance, Thomas Sheehan believes this supposed change is "far less dramatic than usually suggested", and entails merely a change in focus and method. Mark Wrathall argued that the Turn isn't found in Heidegger's writings, but is simply a misconception.
Some notable later works are "The Origin of the Work of Art" (1935), Contributions to Philosophy (1937), "Letter on Humanism" (1946), "Building Dwelling Thinking" (1951), "The Question Concerning Technology" (1954), and "What Is Called Thinking?" (1954).
The history of being
The idea of asking about being may be traced back via Aristotle to Parmenides. Heidegger claims to revive this question of being that had been largely forgotten by the metaphysical tradition extending from Plato to Descartes, a forgetfulness extending into the Age of Enlightenment, as well as modern science and technology. In pursuit of the retrieval of the question, Heidegger spends considerable time reflecting on ancient Greek thought, in particular on Plato, Parmenides, Heraclitus, and Anaximander.
In his later philosophy, Heidegger attempts to reconstruct the "history of being" in order to show how the different epochs in the history of philosophy were dominated by different conceptions of being. His goal is to retrieve the original experience of being present in the early Greek thought that was covered up by later philosophers.
According to W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz, Heidegger believed "the thinking of Heraclitus and Parmenides, which lies at the origin of philosophy, was falsified and misinterpreted" by Plato and Aristotle, thus tainting all of subsequent Western philosophy. In his Introduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger states, "Among the most ancient Greek thinkers, it is Heraclitus who was subjected to the most fundamentally un-Greek misinterpretation in the course of Western history, and who nevertheless in more recent times has provided the strongest impulses toward redisclosing what is authentically Greek."
Charles Guignon writes that Heidegger aims to correct this misunderstanding by reviving Presocratic notions of being with an emphasis on "understanding the way beings show up in (and as) an unfolding happening or event." Guignon adds that "we might call this alternative outlook 'event ontology.'"
Language
In Being and Time, language is presented as logically secondary to Dasein's understanding of the world and its significance. On this conception of worldhood, language can develop from prelinguistic significance.
Post-turn, Heidegger refines his position to present some basic words (e.g., phusis, the Greek term that roughly translates to "nature") as world-disclosive, that is, as establishing the foundational parameters in terms of which Dasein's understanding can occur in the specific ways that it does. It is in this context that Heidegger proclaims that "Language is the house of being."
In the present age, he says, the language of "technology", or instrumental reason, flatten the significance of our world. For salvation, he turns to poetry.
Heidegger rejected the notion of language being purely a means of communication. Language construed us such, he believed, would form the basis of an age of technology, the digital thought processes of which would only use language to organise and communicate the coverage of that which exists. Thinking in terms of calculation and digital processing would put man at odds with language, at the centre of everything that exists. If man would believe that they would have language at their disposal, that they would be the one to use it, then, Heidegger believed, man would completely miss the core tenet of language itself: "It is language that speaks, not man. Man only speaks if they neatly correspond to language." In this way, Heidegger wanted to point out that man is only a participant of language that they have not themselves created. Man is bound within a sort of process of transfer and may only act with respect to anything the language conveys.
In this, however, Heidegger does not think in terms of philosophy of culture: The tautology of the formulation language speaks (originally in German "die Sprache spricht") is his way of trying to prevent the phenomenon of language to be used with respect to anything else than language itself. In line with his unique thinking, he is seeking to avoid having to justify the language by anything else. In this way, language could for instance never be explained by the sheer transmission of acoustic sounds, or speaking. According to Heidegger, language is rather difficult to fathom because we are too close to it, hence we need to speak about that which usually remains unmentioned because it is just to close to us. His work "Unterwegs zur Sprache" (On the way to language) is an attempt to reach "a place we already are in."
Influences
Heidegger dedicated many of his lectures to both Nietzsche and Hölderlin.Friedrich Nietzsche and Friedrich Hölderlin were both important influences on Heidegger, and many of his lecture courses were devoted to one or the other, especially in the 1930s and 1940s. The lectures on Nietzsche focused on fragments posthumously published under the title The Will to Power, rather than on Nietzsche's published works. Heidegger reads The Will to Power as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics, and the lectures are a kind of dialogue between the two thinkers.
Michael Allen Gillespie says that Heidegger's theoretical acceptance of "destiny" has much in common with the millenarianism of Marxism. But Marxists believe Heidegger's "theoretical acceptance is antagonistic to practical political activity and implies fascism". Gillespie, however, says "the real danger" from Heidegger isn't quietism but fanaticism. Modernity has cast mankind toward a new goal "on the brink of profound nihilism" that is "so alien it requires the construction of a new tradition to make it comprehensible."
Gillespie extrapolates from Heidegger's writings that humankind may degenerate into "scientists, workers, and brutes". According to Gillespie, Heidegger envisaged this abyss to be the greatest event in the history of the West because it might enable humanity to comprehend being more profoundly and primordially than the Presocratics.
The poetry of Friedrich Hölderlin became an increasingly central focus of Heidegger's later work and thought. Heidegger grants Hölderlin a singular place within the history of being and the history of Germany, as a herald whose thought is yet to be "heard" in Germany or the West more generally. Many of Heidegger's works from the 1930s onwards include meditations on lines from Hölderlin's poetry, and several of the lecture courses are devoted to the reading of a single poem; for example, Hölderlin's Hymn "The Ister".
Heidegger and the Nazi Party
Main article: Heidegger and NazismThe rectorate
Adolf Hitler was sworn in as Chancellor of Germany on 30 January 1933. Heidegger was elected rector of the University of Freiburg on 21 April 1933, and assumed the position the following day. On 1 May, he joined the Nazi Party.
On 27 May 1933, Heidegger delivered his inaugural address, the Rektoratsrede (titled "The Self-assertion of the German University"), in a hall decorated with swastikas, with members of the Sturmabteilung (SA) and prominent Nazi Party officials present.
That summer he delivered a lecture on a fragment of Heraclitus (usually translated in English: "War is the father of all"). His notes on this lecture appear under the heading "Struggle as the essence of Beings." In this lecture he suggests that if an enemy cannot be found for the people then one must be invented, and once conceptualized and identified, then the 'beings' who have discovered or invented this enemy must strive for the total annihilation of the enemy.
His tenure as rector was fraught with difficulties from the outset. Some Nazi education officials viewed him as a rival, while others saw his efforts as comical. Some of Heidegger's fellow Nazis also ridiculed his philosophical writings as gibberish. He finally offered his resignation as rector on 23 April 1934, and it was accepted on 27 April. Heidegger remained a member of both the academic faculty and of the Nazi Party until the end of the war.
Philosophical historian Hans Sluga wrote, "Though as rector he prevented students from displaying an anti-Semitic poster at the entrance to the university and from holding a book burning, he kept in close contact with the Nazi student leaders and clearly signaled to them his sympathy with their activism."
In 1945, Heidegger wrote of his term as rector, giving the writing to his son Hermann; it was published in 1983:
The rectorate was an attempt to see something in the movement that had come to power, beyond all its failings and crudeness, that was much more far-reaching and that could perhaps one day bring a concentration on the Germans' Western historical essence. It will in no way be denied that at the time I believed in such possibilities and for that reason renounced the actual vocation of thinking in favor of being effective in an official capacity. In no way will what was caused by my own inadequacy in office be played down. But these points of view do not capture what is essential and what moved me to accept the rectorate.
Treatment of Husserl
Beginning in 1917, German-Jewish philosopher Edmund Husserl championed Heidegger's work, and helped Heidegger become his successor for the chair in philosophy at the University of Freiburg in 1928.
On 6 April 1933, the Gauleiter of Baden Province, Robert Wagner, suspended all Jewish government employees, including present and retired faculty at the University of Freiburg. Heidegger's predecessor as rector formally notified Husserl of his "enforced leave of absence" on 14 April 1933.
Heidegger became Rector of the University of Freiburg on 22 April 1933. The following week the national Reich law of 28 April 1933 replaced Reichskommissar Wagner's decree. The Reich law required the firing of Jewish professors from German universities, including those, such as Husserl, who had converted to Christianity. The termination of the retired professor Husserl's academic privileges thus did not involve any specific action on Heidegger's part.
Heidegger had by then broken off contact with Husserl, other than through intermediaries. Heidegger later claimed that his relationship with Husserl had already become strained after Husserl publicly "settled accounts" with Heidegger and Max Scheler in the early 1930s.
Heidegger did not attend his former mentor's cremation in 1938, for which he later declared himself regretful: "That I failed to express again to Husserl my gratitude and respect for him upon the occasion of his final illness and death is a human failure that I apologized for in a letter to Mrs. Husserl". In 1941, under pressure from publisher Max Niemeyer, Heidegger agreed to remove the dedication to Husserl from Being and Time (restored in post-war editions).
Heidegger's behavior towards Husserl has provoked controversy. Hannah Arendt initially suggested that Heidegger's behavior precipitated Husserl's death. She called Heidegger a "potential murderer". However, she later recanted her accusation.
Post-rectorate period
After the failure of Heidegger's rectorship, he withdrew from most political activity, but remained a member of the Nazi Party. In May 1934 he accepted a position on the Committee for the Philosophy of Law in the Academy for German Law, where he remained active until at least 1936. The academy had official consultant status in preparing Nazi legislation such as the Nuremberg racial laws that came into effect in 1935. In addition to Heidegger, such Nazi notables as Hans Frank, Julius Streicher, Carl Schmitt, and Alfred Rosenberg belonged to the Academy and served on this committee.
In a 1935 lecture, later published in 1953 as part of the book Introduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger refers to the "inner truth and greatness" of the Nazi movement, but he then adds a qualifying statement in parentheses: "namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity". However, it subsequently transpired that this qualification had not been made during the original lecture, although Heidegger claimed that it had been. This has led scholars to argue that Heidegger still supported the Nazi party in 1935 but that he did not want to admit this after the war, and so he attempted to silently correct his earlier statement.
In private notes written in 1939, Heidegger took a strongly critical view of Hitler's ideology; however, in public lectures, he seems to have continued to make ambiguous comments which, if they expressed criticism of the regime, did so only in the context of praising its ideals. For instance, in a 1942 lecture, published posthumously, Heidegger said of recent German classics scholarship, "In the majority of "research results," the Greeks appear as pure National Socialists. This overenthusiasm on the part of academics seems not even to notice that with such "results" it does National Socialism and its historical uniqueness no service at all, not that it needs this anyhow."
An important witness to Heidegger's continued allegiance to Nazism during the post-rectorship period is his former student Karl Löwith, who met Heidegger in 1936 while Heidegger was visiting Rome. In an account set down in 1940 (though not intended for publication), Löwith recalled that Heidegger wore a swastika pin to their meeting, though Heidegger knew that Löwith was Jewish. Löwith also recalled that Heidegger "left no doubt about his faith in Hitler", and stated that his support for Nazism was in agreement with the essence of his philosophy.
Heidegger rejected the "biologically grounded racism" of the Nazis, replacing it with linguistic-historical heritage.by living according to the principle of race had themselves promoted the very reasoning by which they were now being attacked and so they had no right to complain when it was being used against them by the Germans promoting their own racial purity."
Post-war period
After the end of World War II, Heidegger was summoned to appear at a denazification hearing. Heidegger's former student and lover Hannah Arendt spoke on his behalf at this hearing, while Karl Jaspers spoke against him. He was charged on four counts, dismissed from the university and declared a "follower" (Mitläufer) of Nazism. Heidegger was forbidden to teach between 1945 and 1951. One consequence of this teaching ban was that Heidegger began to engage far more in the French philosophical scene.
In his postwar thinking, Heidegger distanced himself from Nazism, but his critical comments about Nazism seem scandalous to some since they tend to equate the Nazi war atrocities with other inhumane practices related to rationalization and industrialisation, including the treatment of animals by factory farming. For instance in a lecture delivered at Bremen in 1949, Heidegger said: "Agriculture is now a motorized food industry, the same thing in its essence as the production of corpses in the gas chambers and the extermination camps, the same thing as blockades and the reduction of countries to famine, the same thing as the manufacture of hydrogen bombs."
In 1967 Heidegger met with the Jewish poet Paul Celan, a concentration camp survivor. Having corresponded since 1956, Celan visited Heidegger at his country retreat and wrote an enigmatic poem about the meeting, which some interpret as Celan's wish for Heidegger to apologize for his behavior during the Nazi era.
Heidegger's defenders, notably Arendt, see his support for Nazism as arguably a personal " 'error' " (a word which Arendt placed in quotation marks when referring to Heidegger's Nazi-era politics). Defenders think this error was irrelevant to Heidegger's philosophy. Critics such as Levinas, Karl Löwith, and Theodor Adorno claim that Heidegger's support for Nazism revealed flaws inherent in his thought.
Der Spiegel interview
On 23 September 1966, Heidegger was interviewed by Georg Wolff, a former Nazi, and Rudolf Augstein for Der Spiegel magazine, in which he agreed to discuss his political past provided that the interview be published posthumously. ("Only a God Can Save Us" was published five days after his death, on 31 May 1976.) In the interview, Heidegger defended his entanglement with Nazism in two ways. First, he claimed that there was no alternative, saying that with his acceptance of the position of rector of the University of Freiburg he was trying to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and thus had to compromise with the Nazi administration. Second, he admitted that he saw an "awakening" (Aufbruch) which might help to find a "new national and social approach," but said that he changed his mind about this in 1934, when he refused, under threat of dismissal, to remove from the position of dean of the faculty those who were not acceptable to the Nazi party, and he consequently decided to resign as rector.
In his interview Heidegger defended as double-speak his 1935 lecture describing the "inner truth and greatness of this movement." He affirmed that Nazi informants who observed his lectures would understand that by "movement" he meant Nazism. However, Heidegger asserted that his dedicated students would know this statement wasn't praise for the Nazi Party. Rather, he meant it as he expressed it in the parenthetical clarification later added to Introduction to Metaphysics (1953), namely, "the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity."
The eyewitness account of Löwith from 1940, contradicts the account given in the Der Spiegel interview in two ways: that he did not make any decisive break with Nazism in 1934, and that Heidegger was willing to entertain more profound relations between his philosophy and political involvement. The Der Spiegel interviewers did not bring up Heidegger's 1949 quotation comparing the industrialization of agriculture to the extermination camps. In fact, the interviewers were not in possession of much of the evidence now known for Heidegger's Nazi sympathies. Furthermore, Der Spiegel journalist Georg Wolff had been an SS-Hauptsturmführer with the Sicherheitsdienst, stationed in Oslo during World War II, and had been writing articles with antisemitic and racist overtones in Der Spiegel since the end of the war.
The Farías debate
Jacques Derrida, Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, and Jean-François Lyotard, among others, all engaged in debate and disagreement about the relation between Heidegger's philosophy and his Nazi politics. These debates included the question of whether it was possible to do without Heidegger's philosophy, a position which Derrida in particular rejected. Forums where these debates took place include the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as "Les Fins de l'homme à partir du travail de Jacques Derrida: colloque de Cerisy, 23 juillet-2 août 1980", Derrida's "Feu la cendre/cio' che resta del fuoco", and the studies on Paul Celan by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida, which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987.
The Black Notebooks
In 2014, Heidegger's Black Notebooks were published although he had written in them between 1931 and the early 1970s. The notebooks contain several examples of anti-Semitic sentiments, which have led to reevaluation of Heidegger's relation to Nazism. An example of Heidegger using anti-Semitic language he once wrote "world Judaism is ungraspable everywhere and doesn't need to get involved in military action while continuing to unfurl its influence, whereas we are left to sacrifice the best blood of the best of our people". The term and notion of "world Judaism" was first promoted by the anti-Semitic text The Protocols of the Elders of Zion and later appeared in Hitler's infamous book Mein Kampf. In another instance Heidegger wrote "by living according to the principle of race had themselves promoted the very reasoning by which they were now being attacked and so they had no right to complain when it was being used against them by the Germans promoting their own racial purity". However, in the notebooks there are instances of Heidegger writing critically of Biological racism and biological oppression.
A notable entry in the notebooks are his writings about his mentor and former friend Edmund Husserl specifically relating to Husserl Jewish heritage. In 1939, only a year after Husserl's death, Heidegger wrote in his Black Notebooks:
the occasional increase in the power of Judaism is grounded in the fact that Western metaphysics, especially in its modern evolution, offered the point of attachment for the expansion of an otherwise empty rationality and calculative capacity, and these thereby created for themselves an abode in the "spirit" without ever being able, on their own, to grasp the concealed decisive domains. The more originary and inceptual the future decisions and questions become, all the more inaccessible will they remain to this 'race.' (Thus Husserl's step to the phenomenological attitude, taken in explicit opposition to psychological explanation and to the historiological calculation of opinions, will be of lasting importance—and yet this attitude never reaches into the domains of the essential decisions.)
This would seem to imply that Heidegger considered Husserl to be philosophically limited by his Jewishness.
Reception
Influence
Heidegger is often considered to be among the most important and influential philosophers of the 20th century by many observers. American Philosopher Richard Rorty has ranked Heidegger as among the most important philosophers along with John Dewey and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Simon Critchley has praised Heidegger as the "most important and influential philosopher in the continental tradition in the 20th century".
Slovenian philosopher Slavoj Žižek has referred to Heidegger as a "great philosopher" and rejected the notion that his alleged anti-semitism against him tainted his philosophy.
In France, there is a very long and particular history of reading and interpreting Heidegger's work. Because Heidegger's discussion of ontology is sometimes interpreted as rooted in an analysis of the mode of existence of individual human beings (Dasein), his work has often been associated with existentialism. Derrida sees deconstruction is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term "déconstruction" is a term coined to translate Heidegger's use of the words "Destruktion"—literally "destruction"—and "Abbau"—more literally "de-building"). The influence of Heidegger on Sartre's 1943 Being and Nothingness is marked. Heidegger himself, however, argued that Sartre had misread his work.
Hubert Dreyfus introduced Heidegger's notion of "being-in-the-world" to research in Artificial intelligence. According to Dreyfus, long-standing research questions such as the Frame problem can be only dissolved within an Heideggerian framework. Heidegger also profoundly influenced Enactivism and Situated robotics. Former Trump chief strategist Steve Bannon has expressed admiration for Heidegger and has praised his philosophy.
Some writers on Heidegger's work see possibilities within it for dialogue with traditions of thought outside of Western philosophy, particularly East Asian thinking. Despite perceived differences between Eastern and Western philosophy, some of Heidegger's later work, particularly "A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer", does show an interest in initiating such a dialogue. Heidegger himself had contact with a number of leading Japanese intellectuals, including members of the Kyoto School, notably Hajime Tanabe and Kuki Shūzō. The scholar Chang Chung-Yuan stated, "Heidegger is the only Western Philosopher who not only intellectually understands Tao, but has intuitively experienced the essence of it as well." Philosopher Reinhard May sees great influence of Taoism and Japanese scholars in Heidegger's work, although this influence is not acknowledged by the author. He asserts it can be shown that Heidegger sometimes "appropriated wholesale and almost verbatim major ideas from the German translations of Daoist and Zen Buddhist classics." To this he adds, "This clandestine textual appropriation of non-Western spirituality, the extent of which has gone undiscovered for so long, seems quite unparalleled, with far-reaching implications for our future interpretation of Heidegger's work."
Notable figures known to be influenced by Heidegger's work today include Aleksandr Dugin, a prominent Russian far-right political philosopher.
Criticism
According to Husserl, Being and Time claimed to deal with ontology, but only did so in the first few pages of the book. Having nothing further to contribute to an ontology independent of human existence, Heidegger changed the topic to Dasein. Whereas Heidegger argued that the question of human existence is central to the pursuit of the question of being, Husserl criticized this as reducing phenomenology to "philosophical anthropology" and offering an abstract and incorrect portrait of the human being. Aspects of his work have been criticized by those who acknowledge his influence. Some questions raised about Heidegger's philosophy include the priority of ontology, the status of animals, the nature of the religious, Heidegger's supposed neglect of ethics (Emmanuel Levinas), the body (Maurice Merleau-Ponty), sexual difference (Luce Irigaray), and space (Peter Sloterdijk). A. J. Ayer objected that Heidegger proposed vast, overarching theories regarding existence that were completely unverifiable through empirical demonstration and logical analysis.
In France, there is a very long and particular history of reading and interpreting Heidegger. In 1929 the Neo-Kantian Ernst Cassirer and Heidegger engaged in an influential debate, during the Second Davos Hochschulkurs in Davos, concerning the significance of Kantian notions of freedom and rationality. Whereas Cassirer defended the role of rationality in Kant, Heidegger argued for the priority of the imagination.The reception of Heidegger's philosophy by Anglo-American analytic philosophy, beginning with the logical positivists, was almost uniformly negative. Rudolf Carnap accused Heidegger of offering an "illusory" ontology, criticizing him for committing the fallacy of reification and for wrongly dismissing the logical treatment of language which, according to Carnap, can only lead to writing "nonsensical pseudo-propositions".
Hegelian-Marxist thinkers, especially György Lukács and the Frankfurt School, associated the style and content of Heidegger's thought with irrationalism and criticized its political implications. For instance, Theodor Adorno wrote an extended critique of the ideological character of Heidegger's early and later use of language in the Jargon of Authenticity, and Jürgen Habermas admonishes the influence of Heidegger on recent French philosophy in his polemic against "postmodernism" in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity.
Bertrand Russell considered Heidegger an obscurantist, writing, "Highly eccentric in its terminology, his philosophy is extremely obscure. One cannot help suspecting that language is here running riot. An interesting point in his speculations is the insistence that nothingness is something positive. As with much else in Existentialism, this is a psychological observation made to pass for logic." According to Richard Polt, this quote expresses the sentiments of many 20th-century analytic philosophers concerning Heidegger.
In film
- Der Zauberer von Meßkirch (1989) is a German TV documentary about Heidegger, co-directed by Ulrich Boehm and Rüdiger Safranski.
- The film director Terrence Malick translated Heidegger's 1929 essay Vom Wesen des Grundes into English. It was published under the title The Essence of Reasons (1969). It is also frequently said of Malick that his cinema has Heideggerian sensibilities.
- The Ister (2004) is a film based on Heidegger's 1942 lecture course on Friedrich Hölderlin, and features Jean-Luc Nancy, Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Bernard Stiegler, and Hans-Jürgen Syberberg.
- Being in the World (2010) draws on Heidegger's work to explore what it means to be human in a technological age. A number of Heidegger scholars are interviewed, including Hubert Dreyfus, Mark Wrathall, Albert Borgmann, John Haugeland, and Taylor Carman.
See also
- Daseinsanalysis
- Heidegger Gesamtausgabe
- Hermeneutic idealism
- Hölderlin's Hymn "The Ister"
- Khôra
- Object-oriented ontology
- Sous rature
Notes
- See his published courses in Gesamtausgabe. Early Freiburg lecture courses, 1919–1923.
- Provisional ruling October 5, 1946; final ruling December 28, 1946; Hugo Ott, Martin Heidegger: A Political Life, (Harper Collins, 1993, page 348).
- In The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time, Theodor Kisiel designates the first version of the project that culminates in Being and Time, "the Dilthey draft".
- Michael Inwood provides a brief discussion of this term to illustrate Heidegger's use of language more generally: "The word 'care', which corresponds closely, if not exactly, to the German Sorge, has a range of senses. We can see this from the adjectives it forms and the words they contrast with: 'careworn' and 'carefree'; 'careful' and 'careless'; 'caring' and 'uncaring'. These oppositions are not the same: one can be, for example, both careworn and careless. In ordinary usage not everyone is careworn, careful and caring all the time. Some of us are carefree, careless or uncaring. Heidegger makes two innovations. First, he uses 'care' in a broad sense which underlies its diversification into the careworn, the careful and the caring. Second, in this sense of 'care', he insists, everyone cares; no one is wholly carefree, careless or uncaring. It is only because everyone is, in this fundamental sense, care-ful, that we can ever be carefree, careless or uncaring in the ordinary, or as he has it, the 'ontical', senses of these words. In the 'ontological' sense of 'care', everyone cares. All human beings, again, are 'ahead of themselves' (sich vorweg), roughly 'up to something' or on the look out for what to do. What about those mired in hopeless despair? Even those, Heidegger insists, are 'ahead of themselves': 'Hopelessness does not tear Dasein away from its possibilities; it is only a particular mode of being toward these possibilities' (BT, 236)."
- "In a 1947 piece, in which Heidegger distances his views from Sartre's existentialism, he links the turn to his own failure to produce the missing divisions of Being and Time . ... At root Heidegger's later philosophy shares the deep concerns of Being and Time, in that it is driven by the same preoccupation with Being and our relationship with it that propelled the earlier work. ... he later Heidegger does seem to think that his earlier focus on Dasein bears the stain of a subjectivity that ultimately blocks the path to an understanding of Being. This is not to say that the later thinking turns away altogether from the project of transcendental hermeneutic phenomenology. The project of illuminating the a priori conditions on the basis of which entities show up as intelligible to us is still at the heart of things."
- See also J. Habermas, "Martin Heidegger: on the publication of the lectures of 1935", in Richard Wolin, ed., The Heidegger Controversy (MIT Press, 1993). The controversial page of the 1935 manuscript is missing from the Heidegger Archives in Marbach; however, Habermas's scholarship leaves little doubt about the original wording.
- The 1966 interview published in 1976 after Heidegger's death as "Only a God Can Save Us". Der Spiegel. Translated by William J. Richardson. 31 May 1976. pp. 193–219. For critical readings, see the "Special Feature on Heidegger and Nazism", Critical Inquiry, 15 (2) (Winter 1989 ed.), 1989, doi:10.1086/ci.15.2.1343581, particularly the contributions by Jürgen Habermas and Blanchot. The issue includes partial translations of Jacques Derrida's Of Spirit and Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe's Heidegger, Art, and Politics: the Fiction of the Political.
Bibliography
References
- ^ "Martin Heidegger". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 12 October 2011. Retrieved 20 July 2024.
- ^ "Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) - Universitätbibliothek Freiburg". University Library Freiburg. Retrieved 20 July 2024.
- ^ Wells 2008.
- ^ Inwood 2019, chapter 1.
- Alfieri 2015, p. 6.
- Luft 2015, p. 461.
- Worldcat website Archived 1 December 2023 at the Wayback Machine Retrieved 27 November 2023.
- Altman 2012, p. 79.
- ^ Korab-Karpowicz, §1.
- Heidegger 2009, p. xxxvi.
- Schalow & Denker 2010, p. 135.
- Cammann & Soboczynski 2014.
- Safranski 1998, pp. 85–88, 108–81.
- Inwood 2019, chapter 10.
- Gross & Kemmann 2005, p. 65.
- ^ Wheeler 2020, §1.
- Young-Bruehl 2004, p. 50.
- Popova, Maria (25 April 2016). "The Remarkable Love Letters of Hannah Arendt and Martin Heidegger". Archived from the original on 24 January 2024. Retrieved 24 January 2024.
- Wolin 2015.
- Fleischacker 2008.
- Steinfels 1995.
- Findlay 2002, p. 32.
- Bambach 2003, p. 82.
- Hemming 2013, chapter 7.
- Farin 2016.
- ^ Sheehan 1988.
- Evans 2005, pp. 419–22.
- Young 1998, pp. 3, 11.
- Young 1998, p. 3.
- ^ Inwood 2014.
- Safranski 1998.
- Safranski 1998, p. 373.
- Lambert 2007, pp. 157–69.
- Safranski 1998, p. 432.
- ^ Fiske 1976.
- Gadamer 1994, p. 18.
- Dostal 1993, p. 142.
- Kisiel & Buren 1994, p. 244.
- ^ Wheeler 2020, §2.1.
- Krell 1975.
- Moran 2000.
- Rockmore 2003, pp. 477–494.
- Kisiel 1993, p. 313.
- Ormiston & Schrift 1990, pp. 32–33.
- Nelson 2014, pp. 109–28.
- Dreyfus 1991, Appendix.
- Carman 2003, pp. 8–52.
- Dahlstrom 2004.
- Heidegger 1962, §3.
- Wheeler 2020, §2.2.1.
- McGrath, Sean J. (2003). "Heidegger and Duns Scotus on Truth and Language". The Review of Metaphysics. 57 (2): 339–358. JSTOR 20131978. Archived from the original on 1 December 2023. Retrieved 28 November 2023.
- Sandkühler 2010.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 151.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 12.
- Heidegger 1962, pp. 1–27.
- Whittingham 2018.
- Inwood 1999.
- Horrigan-Kelly, Millar & Dowling 2016.
- ^ Wheeler 2020, §2.2.3.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 54.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 56.
- Polt 1999, pp. 46–49.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 69.
- ^ Polt 1999, pp. 46–61, esp. diagram on p.61.
- ^ Dreyfus 1991, pp. 88–100.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 97, qtd. in translators' fn. 1.
- Polt 1999, p. 50.
- Dreyfus 1991, pp. 71–72.
- Wheeler 2020, §2.2.2.
- Dreyfus 1991, pp. 40–42.
- Inwood 1999, pp. 61–62.
- ^ Polt 1999, p. 65.
- Heidegger 1996a, p. xv.
- ^ Dreyfus 1991, p. 168.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 161.
- Dreyfus 1991, p. 214.
- Inwood 1999, pp. 2–3.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 192.
- Dreyfus 1991, pp. 238–39.
- Dreyfus 1991, pp. 244–45.
- Wheeler 2020, §2.2.7.
- Polt 1999, p. 85.
- Inwood 1999, p. 31.
- Inwood 1999, p. 212.
- Heidegger 1962, p. 118.
- Dreyfus 1991, p. 142.
- ^ Dreyfus 1991, p. 143.
- Taylor 1993, p. 325.
- Taylor 1993, p. 327.
- Heidegger 1962, pp. 126–27.
- ^ Varga & Guignon 2014, §3.1.
- Inwood 1999, pp. 22–23.
- Zimmerman 1981, p. xx.
- Zimmerman 1981, p. xix.
- Zimmerman 1981, p. xxvii.
- Zimmerman 1981, pp. xxiv–xxviii.
- Richardson 1963.
- ^ Wheeler 2020, §3.1.
- ^ Inwood 1999, p. 8.
- Heidegger 2002.
- Davies 2017.
- Polt & Fried 2001, p. 15.
- Wrathall 2010.
- Inwood 1999, §History of being.
- Korab-Karpowicz, §4.
- Korab-Karpowicz 2016, p. 58.
- Heidegger 2014.
- Polt & Fried 2001, p. 36.
- Inwood 1999, p. 208.
- ^ Inwood 1999, p. 209.
- Wegmarken. GA 9, S. 75.
- Der Satz vom Grund. GA 10, S. 143.
- Unterwegs zur Sprache. GA 12, S. 199.
- Raffoul & Nelson 2013, p. 224.
- Gillespie 1984, p. 133.
- Gillespie 1984, p. 148.
- Gillespie 1984, p. 151.
- Sharpe 2018.
- ^ Heidegger, Martin (1933). "The Saying of Hearaclitus: Struggle as the essence of Beings". Being & Truth. Indiana University Press (published 2010). p. 124. ISBN 978-0253355119.
- Sluga 2013, p. 149.
- Neske & Kettering 1990, p. 29.
- Benhabib 2003, p. 120.
- Heidegger 1990, p. 48.
- ^ Augstein, Wolff & Heidegger 1976, pp. 193–219.
- Safranski 1998, pp. 258–58.
- Ettinger 1997, p. 37.
- Habermas 1989, pp. 452–54.
- Heidegger 2016, §47.
- Heidegger 1996b, pp. 79–80.
- Wolin 1991.
- Wheeler 2020, §3.5.
- Maier-Katkin 2010, p. 249.
- Janicaud 2015.
- Lyon 2006, p. 66.
- Anderson 1991.
- Murray 1978, pp. 293–303.
- Löwith 1989, p. 57.
- McGrath 2008, p. 92.
- Janich 2013, p. 178.
- Assheuer 2014.
- Oltermann, Philip (13 March 2014). "Heidegger's 'black notebooks' reveal antisemitism at core of his philosophy". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Archived from the original on 30 November 2023. Retrieved 7 November 2023.
- Mitchell, Andrew J.; Trawny, Peter (5 September 2017). Heidegger's Black Notebooks: Responses to Anti-Semitism. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-54438-2. Archived from the original on 28 November 2023. Retrieved 26 November 2023.
- Escudero, Jesús Adrián (2015). "Heidegger's Black Notebooks and the Question of Anti-Semitism". Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual. 5: 21–49. doi:10.5840/gatherings201552. Archived from the original on 13 May 2023. Retrieved 7 November 2023.
- Wheeler 2020.
- Heidegger 2017, pp. 67–68.
- Watts, Michael, ed. (2011), "Preface", The Philosophy of Heidegger, Continental European Philosophy, Acumen Publishing, pp. vii–ix, doi:10.1017/UPO9781844652655.001, ISBN 978-1-84465-263-1, retrieved 22 June 2024
- Critchley, Simon (8 June 2009). "Being and Time, part 1: Why Heidegger matters". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 22 June 2024.
- Žižek, Slavoj (13 May 2015). "Slavoj Žižek: Why Heidegger should not be criminalised". New Statesman. Retrieved 2 July 2024.
- Zuckert 1991.
- Heidegger 1998, pp. 250–51.
- (Eds.): Husbands P.; Holland O.; Wheeler M. (2008). Why Heideggerian AI Failed and How Fixing It Would Require Making It More Heideggerian (in: The Mechanical Mind in History). MIT Press. pp. 331–371.
- Scheuermann, Christoph (29 October 2018). "Stephen Bannon Tries Rightwing Revolution in Europe". Der Spiegel. ISSN 2195-1349. Retrieved 21 April 2024.
- Stonebridge, Lyndsey (8 April 2023). "Who is afraid of Martin Heidegger?". New Statesman. Retrieved 21 April 2024.
- Ma 2007.
- Oldmeadow 2004, pp. 351–54.
- Laozi 2013, p. 8.
- May 1996, p. xv.
- Sharpe, Matthew (2 April 2020). "In the Crosshairs of the Fourfold: Critical Thoughts on Aleksandr Dugin's Heidegger". Critical Horizons. 21 (2): 167–187. doi:10.1080/14409917.2020.1759284. ISSN 1440-9917.
- Husserl 1997.
- Holland 2018, pp. 139–43.
- Elden 2012, pp. 85–88.
- Gorner 2000, p. 90.
- Nirenberg 2011.
- Carnap 1931.
- Carnap 1966.
- Rockmore 1992, pp. 57, 75, 149, 258.
- Adorno 1973.
- Habermas 1990, chapter VI.
- Russell 1959, p. 303.
- Polt 1999, p. 123.
- Boy, Christof (23 January 1989). "Nebulöse Schwärmerei für Heidegger". Der Tagesspiegel (in German). Retrieved 1 July 2024.
- Patterson 2003, pp. 179–91.
- Cavell 1979, p. xv.
Works cited
For ease of reference, citations of Being and Time should always cite to the pagination of the standard German edition, which is included in the margins of both of the English translations, each of which has its virtues.
Primary sources
Heidegger's collected writings are published by Vittorio Klostermann. The Gesamtausgabe was begun during Heidegger's lifetime. He defined the order of publication and dictated that the principle of editing should be "ways not works". Publication has not yet been completed. The current executor of Martin Heidegger's Literary Estate is his grandson and a lawyer, Arnulf Heidegger (1969– ).
- Heidegger, Martin (1962). Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Harper Collins.
- Heidegger, Martin (1971a). "A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and an Inquirer". On the Way to Language. Translated by Peter D. Hertz. Harper & Row.
- Heidegger, Martin (1971b). Poetry, Language, Thought. Translated by Albert Hofstadter. Albert Hofstadter.
- Heidegger, Martin (1976). What is Called Thinking?. Translated by J. Glenn Gray. Harper Perennial.
- Heidegger, Martin (1990). "Der Spiegel Interview". In Günther Neske and Emil Kettering (ed.). Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers. Paragon House.
- Heidegger, Martin (1991). David Farrell Krell (ed.). Nietzsche. Translated by Stambaugh, Joan; Krell, David Farrell; Capuzzi, Frank A. HarperOne. ISBN 0-06-063841-9. OCLC 22492313.
- Heidegger, Martin (1996a). Being and Time. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. SUNY Press.
- Heidegger, Martin (1996b). Hölderlin's Hymn "The Ister". Translated by William McNeill and Julia Davis. Indiana University Press.
- Heidegger, Martin (1998). "Letter on Humanism". In William McNeil (ed.). Pathmarks. Translated by William McNeil. Cambridge University Press.
- Heidegger, Martin (2002). "Time and Being". On Time and Being. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-32375-7.
- Heidegger, Martin (2009). Theodore Kisiel and Thomas Sheehan (ed.). Becoming Heidegger: On the Trail of his Early Occasional Writings, 1910-1927 (2nd ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-0-9701679-9-6.
- Heidegger, Martin (2012). Contributions to Philosophy: (Of the Event). Translated by Richard Rojcewicz. Indiana University Press. ISBN 9780253001276.
- Heidegger, Martin (2014). Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (2nd ed.). Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0-300-18612-3.
- Heidegger, Martin (2016). Mindfulness. Translated by Parvis Emad and Thomas Kalary. Bloomsbury Academic.
- Heidegger, Martin (2017). Ponderings XII–XV: Black Notebooks 1939–1941. Translated by Richard Rojcewicz. Indiana University Press. ISBN 9780253029317.
Secondary sources
- Adorno, Theodor W. (1973). The Jargon of Authenticity. Translated by Knut Tarnowski and Frederic Will. Northwestern University Press.
- Alfieri, Francesco (2015). The Presence of Duns Scotus in the Thought of Edith Stein: The question of Individuality. Springer. ISBN 978-3319156620.
- Altman, William H. F. (2012). Martin Heidegger and the First World War: Being and Time as Funeral Oration. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-0739171684.
- Assheuer, Thomas (21 March 2014). "Das vergiftete Erbe" [The poisoned heritage]. Die Zeit (in German). Archived from the original on 4 April 2023. Retrieved 18 June 2022.
- Anderson, Mark M. (1 April 1991). "The 'Impossibility of Poetry': Celan and Heidegger in France". New German Critique (53): 3–18. doi:10.2307/488241. ISSN 0094-033X. JSTOR 488241.
- Augstein, Rudolf; Wolff, Georg; Heidegger, Martin (1976). "Nur noch ein Gott kann uns retten". Der Spiegel: 193–219. Archived from the original on 6 February 2013. Retrieved 14 June 2013. English translation Archived 16 October 2013 at the Wayback Machine by William J. Richardson in Sheehan, Thomas, ed. (1981). Heidegger. The Man and the Thinker. Piscataway, New Jersey: Transaction Publishers. pp. 45–67. ISBN 978-1-412-81537-6.
- Bambach, Charles R. (2003). Heidegger's Roots: Nietzsche, National Socialism, and the Greeks. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0801472664.
- Benhabib, Seyla (2003). The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 9780742521513.
- Carman, Taylor (2003). Heidegger's Analytic: Interpretation, Discourse and Authenticity in Being and Time. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781139441995.
- Carnap, Rudolf (1931). "Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache" (PDF). Erkenntnis. 2: 219–241. doi:10.1007/BF02028153. S2CID 144658746. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.
- Carnap, Rudolf (1966). "The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language" (PDF). In A.J. Ayer (ed.). Logical Positivism. The Library of Philosophical Movements. New York: The Free Press. pp. 60–81. ISBN 978-0029011300. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.
- Cammann, Alexander; Soboczynski, Adam (30 January 2014). "Es ist wieder da". Die Zeit. Archived from the original on 6 May 2015. Retrieved 14 April 2015.
- Cavell, Stanley (1979). The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film, Enlarged Edition. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674961968.
- Dahlstrom, D. O. (2004). "Ontology". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Gale. Archived from the original on 29 January 2021. Retrieved 25 December 2020.
- Davies, Paul (11 April 2017). "Martin Heidegger (1889–1976)". Archived from the original on 26 January 2021. Retrieved 9 October 2020.
- Dostal, Robert J. (1993). "Time and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger". In Charles Guignon (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge University Press. pp. 141–69. ISBN 0-521-38597-0.
- Dreyfus, Hubert L. (1991). Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I. MIT Press.
- Elden, Stuart (2012). Sloterdijk Now. Polity. ISBN 9780745651361. Archived from the original on 21 June 2023. Retrieved 14 March 2023.
- Ettinger, Elzbieta (1997). Hannah Arendt/Martin Heidegger. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300072549.
- Evans, Richard J. (2005). The Coming of the Third Reich. Penguin Books. pp. 419–422. ISBN 978-0143034698.
- Farin, Ingo (2016). Reading Heidegger's "Black notebooks 1931--1941. Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England: The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262034012. Archived from the original on 1 March 2024. Retrieved 18 June 2022.
- Findlay, Edward F. (2002). Caring for the Soul in a Postmodern Age: Politics and Phenomenology in the Thought of Jan Patočka. SUNY Press. ISBN 9780791454855. Archived from the original on 21 June 2023. Retrieved 14 March 2023.
- Fleischacker, Samuel, ed. (August 2008). Heidegger's Jewish Followers: Essays on Hannah Arendt, Leo Strauss, Hans Jonas, and Emmanuel Levinas. Duquesne University Press. ISBN 978-0820704128.
- Fiske, Edward B. (27 May 1976). "Martin Heidegger, a Philosopher Who Affected Many Fields, Dies". The New York Times. Archived from the original on 13 December 2022. Retrieved 18 September 2019.
- Gadamer, Hans Georg (1994). Heidegger's Ways. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0791417379.
- Georgakis, Tziovanis; Ennis, Paul J. (2015). Heidegger in the Twenty-First Century. Springer. ISBN 978-9401796781.
- Gillespie, Michael Allen (1984). Hegel, Heidegger, and the Ground of History. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 9780226293769.
- Gorner, Paul (2000). Twentieth Century German Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-289309-3. Archived from the original on 13 November 2022. Retrieved 13 November 2022.
- Gross, Daniel M.; Kemmann, Ansgar, eds. (2005). Heidegger and Rhetoric. SUNY Press. ISBN 9780791465516. Archived from the original on 29 February 2024. Retrieved 18 June 2022.
- Habermas, Jürgen (1989). "Work and Weltanschauung: the Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective". Critical Inquiry. 15 (2): 452–54. doi:10.1086/448492. S2CID 143394757.
- Habermas, Jürgen (1990). The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures. Translated by Frederick Lawrence. MIT Press.
- Hemming, Laurence (2013). Heidegger and Marx : a productive dialogue over the language of humanism. Evanston, Ill: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0810128750.
- Herrmann, Friedrich-Wilhelm von; Alfieri, Francesco (2021). Martin Heidegger and the Truth About the Black Notebooks. Springer. ISBN 978-3030694951.
- Holland, Nancy J. (2018). Heidegger and the Problem of Consciousness. Indiana University Press. ISBN 9780253035981. Archived from the original on 29 February 2024. Retrieved 22 June 2020.
- Horrigan-Kelly, Marcella; Millar, Michelle; Dowling, Maura (2016). "Understanding the Key Tenets of Heidegger's Philosophy for Interpretive Phenomenological Research". International Journal of Qualitative Methods. 15 (January–December 2016: 1–8). doi:10.1177/1609406916680634. hdl:10379/7166. S2CID 152252826.
- Husserl, Edmund (1997). Psychological and transcendental phenomenology and the confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931). Kluwer.
- Inwood, Michael (1999). A Heidegger Dictionary. Blackwell.
- Inwood, Michael (12 April 2014). "Martin Heidegger: the philosopher who fell for Hitler". The Independent. Archived from the original on 24 February 2023. Retrieved 27 September 2018.
- Inwood, Michael (2019). Heidegger: A Very Short Introduction (2nd, ebook ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-256380-4.
- Janich, Oliver (2013). Die Vereinigten Staaten von Europa: Geheimdokumente enthüllen: Die dunklen Pläne der Elite. FinanzBuch Verlag. ISBN 9783862484713. Archived from the original on 29 February 2024. Retrieved 25 August 2020.
- Janicaud, Dominique (2015). Heidegger in France. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0253017734.
- Kisiel, Theodore (1993). The Genesis of Being and Time. California University Press.
- Kisiel, Theodore J.; Buren, John Van (1994). Reading Heidegger from the Start: Essays in His Earliest Thought. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0791420683.
- Krell, David Farrell (1975). "On the Manifold Meaning of Aletheia: Brentano, Aristotle, Heidegger". Research in Phenomenology. 5: 77–94. doi:10.1163/156916475x00114.
- Korab-Karpowicz, W. J. Martin Heidegger (1889—1976). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 January 2023. Retrieved 25 December 2020.
- Korab-Karpowicz, Julian W. (2016). The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger. Peter Lang. ISBN 978-3631712917.
- Lambert, Cesar (2007). "Some considerations about the correspondence between Martin Heidegger and Bernhard Welte". Revista de Filosofía. 63: 157–169. doi:10.4067/S0718-43602007000100012.
- Laozi (2013). Tao - a New Way of Thinking: A Translation of the Tao Tê Ching with an Introduction and Commentaries. Jessica Kingsley Publishers. ISBN 978-1848192010.
- Löwith, Karl (1989). Mein Leben in Deutschland vor und nach 1933: Ein Bericht. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag. ISBN 3-596-25677-1.
- Luft, Sebastian (2015). The Neo-Kantian Reader. Routledge. ISBN 978-0415452526.
- Lyon, James K. (2006). Paul Celan and Martin Heidegger: An Unresolved Conversation, 1951–1970. JHU Press. ISBN 978-0801883026.
- Ma, Lin (2007). Heidegger on East-West Dialogue: Anticipating the Event. Routledge. ISBN 9781135908690. Archived from the original on 22 August 2023. Retrieved 11 April 2020.
- Maier-Katkin, Daniel (2010). Stranger from Abroad: Hannah Arendt, Martin Heidegger, Friendship and Forgiveness. W. W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0393068337.
- May, Reinhard (1996). Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East Asian Influences on His Work. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0415140386.
- McGrath, S. J. (2008). Heidegger: A (Very) Critical Introduction. Wm. B. Eerdmans. ISBN 978-0802860071.
- Murray, Michael (1978). Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300022360.
- Moran, Dermot (2000). "Heidegger's Critique of Husserl's and Brentano's Accounts of Intentionality". Inquiry. 43 (1): 39–65. doi:10.1080/002017400321361. S2CID 54834191.
- Nelson, Eric S. (2014). "Heidegger and Dilthey: Language, History, and Hermeneutics", in Horizons of Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology, edited by Hans Pedersen and Megan Altman. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 109–28. ISBN 978-9401794411.
- Neske, Gunther; Kettering, Emil (1990). Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers. Paragon House. ISBN 978-1557783103.
- Nirenberg, David (13 January 2011). "When Philosophy Mattered". The New Republic. Archived from the original on 23 July 2020. Retrieved 23 July 2020.
- Oldmeadow, Harry (2004). Journeys East: 20th Century Western Encounters with Eastern Religious Traditions. World Wisdom. ISBN 9780941532570. Archived from the original on 29 February 2024. Retrieved 11 April 2020.
- Ormiston, Gayle L.; Schrift, Alan D. (January 1990). Transforming the Hermeneutic Context: From Nietzsche to Nancy. SUNY Press. ISBN 9780791401347. Archived from the original on 29 November 2022. Retrieved 29 November 2022.
- Patterson, Hannah, ed. (2003). The Cinema of Terrence Malick: Poetic Visions of America. Wallflower. ISBN 978-1903364765.
- Polt, Richard F. H. (1999). Heidegger: An Introduction. Cornell University Press.
- Polt, Richard; Fried, Gregory (2001). A Companion to Heidegger's Introduction to Metaphysics. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300085235.
- Raffoul, Francois; Nelson, Eric S. (2013). The Bloomsbury Companion to Heidegger. A&C Black. ISBN 9781441199850. Archived from the original on 5 July 2023. Retrieved 5 July 2023.
- Richardson, William J. (1963). Heidegger. Through Phenomenology to Thought. Preface by Martin Heidegger. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. 4th Edition Archived 21 June 2023 at the Wayback Machine (2003). The Bronx: Fordham University Press. ISBN 0-823-22255-1; ISBN 978-08-2322-255-1.
- Rockmore, Tom (1992). On Heidegger's Nazism and Philosophy. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0520077119.
- Rockmore, Tom (2003). "Dilthey and Historical Reason". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 226 (4): 477–494. doi:10.3917/rip.226.0477. JSTOR 23955847. S2CID 170687756.
- Russell, Bertrand (1959). Wisdom of the West; a historical survey of Western philosophy in its social and political setting. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. p. 303. ISBN 978-0-517-69041-3.
- Safranski, Rüdiger (1998). Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil. Translated by Ewald Osers. Harvard University Press.
- Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). "Ontologie". Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 11 March 2021. Retrieved 25 December 2020.
- Schalow, Frank; Denker, Alfred (2010). Historical Dictionary of Heidegger's Philosophy. Scarecrow Press.
- Sharpe, Matthew (2018). "Rhetorical Action in Rektoratsrede: Calling Heidegger's Gefolgschaft". Philosophy & Rhetoric. 51 (2): 176–201. doi:10.5325/philrhet.51.2.0176. S2CID 149519358.
- Sheehan, Thomas (16 June 1988). "Heidegger and the Nazis" (PDF). The New York Review of Books. Vol. 35, no. 10. pp. 38–47. Archived from the original (PDF) on 7 November 2011. Retrieved 27 April 2017.
- Sluga, Hans (2013). Heidegger's Crisis. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674365070.
- Steinfels, Peter (27 December 1995). "Emmanuel Levinas, 90, French Ethical Philosopher". The New York Times. Archived from the original on 21 June 2023. Retrieved 27 September 2018.
- Taylor, Charles (1993). "Engaged Agency and Background". In Charles Guignon (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge University Press. pp. 317–36. ISBN 0-521-38597-0.
- Varga, Somogy; Guignon, Charles (11 September 2014). "Authenticity". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2020 ed.). Archived from the original on 1 March 2024. Retrieved 11 September 2023.
- Wheeler, Michael (2020). "Martin Heidegger". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2020 ed.). Archived from the original on 30 June 2022. Retrieved 14 October 2020.
- Wells, John (23 May 2008). Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (3rd ed.). Pearson. ISBN 9781405881180.
- Whittingham, Matthew (2018). The Self and Social Relations. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-77246-2.
- Wolin, Richard (1991). The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0231075961.
- Wolin, Richard (2015). Heidegger's Children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Hans Jonas, and Herbert Marcuse. Princeton University Press. ISBN 9780691168616.
- Wrathall, Mark (2010). Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, and History. Cambridge University Press.
- Young, Julian (1998). Heidegger, Philosophy, Nazism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521644945.
- Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth (January 2004). Hannah Arendt: For Love of the World. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300105889.
- Zimmerman, Michael E. (1981). Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger's Concept of Authenticity. Ohio University Press. ISBN 978-0821405703.
- Zuckert, Catherine (1991). "The Politics of Derridean Deconstruction". Polity. 23 (3): 335–356. doi:10.2307/3235130. JSTOR 3235130. S2CID 147001554. Archived from the original on 6 September 2023. Retrieved 6 September 2023.
External links
Library resources aboutMartin Heidegger
By Martin Heidegger
Archival collections
- Original Heidegger manuscripts are kept at the Loyola University Chicago archives. See also "The transcripts and photocopies of Martin Heidegger's writings were given to Barbara Fiand, SNDdeN, Ph.D., by Fritz Heidegger in 1978".
- Martin Heidegger Collection, ca. 1918–1976
- Guide to the Student Notes from Lectures by Martin Heidegger. Special Collections and Archives, The UC Irvine Libraries, Irvine, California.
- Works by Heidegger and on Heidegger (categorization)
- Publications by and about Martin Heidegger in the catalogue Helveticat of the Swiss National Library
- Majority of Heidegger Archives. Online: Deutsches Literaturarchiv in the town of Marbach am Neckar, Germany. Also known as: DLA – German Literature Archive. Most of Martin Heidegger's manuscripts are in the DLA's collection. Search for Heidegger in their Manuscript collections is online here.
General information
- Political Texts – Rectoral Addresses
- W.J. Korab-Karpowicz, Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Karl Löwith, My Last Meeting with Heidegger, Rome 1936
- German Heidegger Society (in German)
- Arne D. Naess Jr., Martin Heidegger in Encyclopædia Britannica
- Martin Heidegger, Der Spiegel Interview by Rudolf Augstein and Georg Wolff, 23 September 1966; published 31 May 1976
- Heidegger's Notebooks Renew Focus on Anti-Semitism
- Newspaper clippings about Martin Heidegger in the 20th Century Press Archives of the ZBW
- Quick reference guide to the English translations of Heidegger
Works by Heidegger
- English translations of Heidegger's works
- Works by or about Martin Heidegger at the Internet Archive
Martin Heidegger | |
---|---|
Philosophy | |
Works |
|
Film and TV | |
Related topics |
- Georgakis & Ennis 2015, pp. ix–xiii.
- Herrmann & Alfieri 2021, p. xv.
- Martin Heidegger
- 1889 births
- 1976 deaths
- 20th-century German philosophers
- Anti-American sentiment in Germany
- Antisemitism in Germany
- Anti-Masonry
- Conservative Revolutionary movement
- Daseinsanalysis
- Infectious disease deaths in Germany
- Enactive cognition
- German epistemologists
- Existentialists
- German anti-communists
- German fascists
- German medievalists
- German Army personnel of World War I
- German Roman Catholics
- Hermeneutists
- Members of the Academy for German Law
- Metaphysicians
- Nazi Party members
- Nietzsche scholars
- Ontologists
- People from Meßkirch
- People from the Grand Duchy of Baden
- Phenomenologists
- German philosophers of art
- German philosophers of culture
- German philosophers of history
- German philosophers of language
- Philosophers of nihilism
- German philosophers of religion
- German philosophers of technology
- German political philosophers
- Theorists on Western civilization
- University of Freiburg alumni
- Academic staff of the University of Freiburg
- Academic staff of the University of Marburg
- Volkssturm personnel
- Philosophers of death