Misplaced Pages

Democratic peace theory: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 18:56, 11 April 2006 editPmanderson (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers62,752 edits Methods: reconsolidate← Previous edit Revision as of 01:07, 13 April 2006 edit undoUltramarine (talk | contribs)33,507 edits Lesser conflicts: Added lost wordsNext edit →
(30 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{disputed}}
{{TOCright}} {{TOCright}}
A '''democratic peace theory''' or simply '''democratic peace''' (often '''DPT''' and sometimes '''democratic pacifism''') is a ] in ], ], and ] which holds that ]—specifically, ]—never or almost never go to ] with one another. It can trace its philosophical roots to ]. A '''democratic peace theory''' or simply '''democratic peace''' (often '''DPT''' and sometimes '''democratic pacifism''') is a ] in ], ], and ] which holds that ]—specifically, ]—never or almost never go to ] with one another. It can trace its philosophical roots to ].
Line 7: Line 6:
==History== ==History==
{{See main|Perpetual peace}} {{See main|Perpetual peace}}

]
Democratic peace theory is a relatively new development. No ancient author seems to have considered it true. Democratic governments, as well as sociologists to study them, were scarce before the 19th century. Democratic peace theory is a relatively new development. No ancient author seems to have considered it true. Democratic governments, as well as sociologists to study them, were scarce before the 19th century.


Until the late Enlightenment, the word ''democracy'' usually meant ] (or pure) democracy, which was treated with suspicion. Even the idea that ]s tend to be peaceful is recent; ] believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing Rome as the prime example. Until the late Enlightenment, the word ''democracy'' usually meant ] (or pure) democracy, which was treated with suspicion. Even the idea that ]s tend to be peaceful is recent; ] believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing Rome as the prime example.


]
It was ] who first foreshadowed the theory in his essay ''Perpetual Peace'' written in ], although he thought that ] was only one of several necessary conditions for a perpetual peace. US President ] advocated the idea in politics during and after ]. It was ] who first foreshadowed the theory in his essay ''Perpetual Peace'' written in ], although he thought that ] was only one of several necessary conditions for a perpetual peace. US President ] advocated the idea in politics during and after ].


Line 42: Line 42:
Singer and Small (1976) discussed both propositions; they found no support for the general, monadic, proposition, and very few peace theorists hold it.<ref>Singer and Small 1976;</ref> Rummel was previously "virtually alone" in doing so; Rummel's evidence is drawn only from 1976-1980; and the post-Vietnam years may be exceptional.<ref> See Russett 2003, p. 139 n. 3, and Gelditsch 1992.</ref> Doyle (1997) argued that the absence of a monadic peace is only to be expected: the same ideologies that cause liberal states to be at peace with each other inspire idealistic wars with the illiberal, whether to defend oppressed foreign minorities or avenge countrymen settled abroad. <ref> Doyle 1997, p. 272 </ref> Singer and Small (1976) discussed both propositions; they found no support for the general, monadic, proposition, and very few peace theorists hold it.<ref>Singer and Small 1976;</ref> Rummel was previously "virtually alone" in doing so; Rummel's evidence is drawn only from 1976-1980; and the post-Vietnam years may be exceptional.<ref> See Russett 2003, p. 139 n. 3, and Gelditsch 1992.</ref> Doyle (1997) argued that the absence of a monadic peace is only to be expected: the same ideologies that cause liberal states to be at peace with each other inspire idealistic wars with the illiberal, whether to defend oppressed foreign minorities or avenge countrymen settled abroad. <ref> Doyle 1997, p. 272 </ref>


There are also some more recent monadic papers, which find a slight monadic effect;<ref> cited in ,</ref> Müller and Wolff (2004), in listing them, find monadic theories as "neither necessary nor convincing"; Müller finds, that, instead, democracies have varied greatly in their belligerence against non-democracies. The ''militant'' democracies since 1950 have been ], ], the ] and the ].<ref>Müller 2004</ref> There are also some more recent monadic papers, which find a slight monadic effect;<ref> cited in ,</ref> Müller and Wolff (2004), in listing them, find monadic theories as "neither necessary nor convincing"; Müller finds, that, instead, democracies have varied greatly in their belligerence against non-democracies. The ''militant'' democracies since 1950 have been ], ], the ] and the ].<ref>Müller 2004</ref> Two of the ''militant democracies'' listed above were dominant naval powers, and therefore had greater choice whether and where to fight.<ref> Compare ]: ''The Influence of Sea Power on History'', ''ad init.''.</ref>


===The absolute peace === ===The absolute peace ===
Line 62: Line 62:


Some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy {{Harvard citation|Goenner|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Kim|Rousseau|2005}}. Some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy {{Harvard citation|Goenner|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Kim|Rousseau|2005}}.

=== Less internal violence ===
One study finds that the most democratic and the most authoritarian states have few ]s, and intermediate regimes the most. The probability for a civil war is also increased by political change, regardless whether toward greater democracy or greater autocracy. Intermediate regimes continue to be the most prone to civil war, regardless of the time since the political change. In the long run, since intermediate regimes are less stable than autocracies, which in turn are less stable than democracies, durable democracy is the most probable end-point of the process of ] {{Harvard citation|Hegre|Ellington|Gates|Gleditsch|2001}}. One study finds that the most democratic nations have the least terrorism {{Harvard citation|Abadie|2004}}. One study finds that ] and ] are rare in democracies {{Harvard citation|Harff|2003}}. Another that ] is rare {{Harvard citation|Rummel|1997}}.

One study {{Harvard citation|Davenport|Armstrong II|2004}} lists several other studies and states: "Repeatedly, democratic political systems have been found to decrease political bans, censorship, torture, disappearances and mass killing, doing so in a linear fashion across diverse measurements, methodologies, time periods, countries, and contexts." It concludes: "Across measures and methodological techniques, it is found that below a certain level, democracy has no impact on human rights violations, but above this level democracy infuences repression in a negative and roughly linear manner." One study {{Harvard citation|Davenport|Armstrong II|2003}} states that thirty years worth of statistical research has revealed that only two variables decrease human rights violations: political democracy and economic development. Of this democracy is more important and more easily created.


== Definitions == == Definitions ==
Line 90: Line 95:


==Methods== ==Methods==
The straightforward argument for the democratic peace is: given the number of wars over the past two centuries, if democracies fought each other as often as any other pair of states, there should have been dozens of wars between democracies. Instead, depending on the study, we find zero, or one, or two, and the exceptions generally involve marginal democracies.<ref>See for example Maoz 1997, p.164-5, which finds that there should have been 57 pair-years of democracies at war on expectation if there were no democratic peace; and in fact there was one</ref>. The straightforward argument for the democratic peace is: given the number of wars over the past two centuries, if democracies fought each other as often as any other pair of states, there should have been dozens of wars between democracies. Instead, depending on the study, we find zero, or one, or two, and the exceptions generally involve marginal democracies.<ref>See for example Maoz 1997, p.164-5, which finds that there should have been 57 pair-years of democracies at war on expectation if there were no democratic peace; and in fact there was one</ref>. A review {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}} lists many studies finding that this peacefulness is statistically significant.

There are also some difficulties in the application of statistical methods to the problem, especially to question of causation.<ref> The difficulties and disputes involved are discussed at some length in ''Case studies and theory development in the social sciences'' by Alexander L. George and Andrew Bennett. </ref>
One problem is that as the ] Mearsheimer (1990) put it, "democracies have been few in number over the past two centuries, and thus there have few opportunities where democracies were in a position to fight one another";<ref>Q Mearshimer 1990, p.50; the argument is supported at length by Spiro 1994, Layne 1994. </ref> so there isn't enough data to be as sure of the democratic peace as of ], as Wayman, a supporter of the democratic peace, admits. "If we rely solely on whether there has been an inter-democratic war, it is going to take many more decades of peace to build our confidence in the stability of the democratic peace", especially with the present small rate of warfare. This is worse if we try to divide our data to look for other factors which might cause peace, or try to control for those factors when found. <ref> Wayman 1998</ref>

One problem is that as the ] Mearsheimer put it, "democracies have been few in number over the past two centuries, and thus there have few opportunities where democracies were in a position to fight one another";<ref>Q Mearshimer 1990, p.50; the argument is supported at length by Spiro 1994, Layne 1994. </ref> so there isn't enough data to be as sure of the democratic peace as of ], as Wayman, a supporter of the democratic peace, admits. "If we rely solely on whether there has been an inter-democratic war, it is going to take many more decades of peace to build our confidence in the stability of the democratic peace", especially with the present small rate of warfare. This is worse if we try to divide our data to look for other factors which might cause peace, or try to control for those factors when found. <ref> Wayman 1998</ref>


This is particularly cogent against the more stringent definitions of democracy, which tend to be made by those closer to the absolute peace; and also with respect to the nineteenth century data. Even the looser definitions of democracy admit only a dozen states before the late nineteenth century, and many of them are young or have limited franchise<ref>See lists in Doyle 1997, p.261 ff.; and Russett 1993</ref> This is particularly cogent against the more stringent definitions of democracy, which tend to be made by those closer to the absolute peace; and also with respect to the nineteenth century data. Even the looser definitions of democracy admit only a dozen states before the late nineteenth century, and many of them are young or have limited franchise<ref>See lists in Doyle 1997, p.261 ff.; and Russett 1993</ref>


===Lesser conflicts=== ===Lesser conflicts===
Stuart Bremer (1993) <ref>Bremer 1993</ref> reacted to this by studying lesser conflicts (''Militarized Interstate Disputes'' in the jargon; MID's and wars together are "militarized interstate conflicts") instead, since they have been far more common; and this solution has become popular. Lesser conflics between democracies have been more violent; but rarer, less bloody, and less likely to spread. <ref>Wayman 2002</ref> <ref> See ; ; . MIDs include the conflicts that precede a war; so the difference between MIDs and MICs nay be less than it appears. </ref> Democracies are less belligerent, negotiate more,<ref></ref> and military conflicts between any two democracies are rarely repeated.<ref> .</ref> There have been many more MIDs than wars; the Correlates of War Project counts several thousands during the last two centuries . Many researchers reacted to this by studying lesser conflicts (''Militarized Interstate Disputes'' in the jargon; MID's and wars together are "militarized interstate conflicts") instead, since they have been far more common. A review {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}} lists many studies that have reported that democratic pairs of states are less likely to be involved in MIDs than other pairs of states.

Stuart Bremer (1993) and many others have also studied ]s involving peace or war. Bremer did a study of seven variables traditionally expected to produce peace or war. He found that ''six'' of them had a genuine effect, independent of all the others, in predicting whether a given pair of states were likely to go to war or not. Mutual democracy was fourth of these, behind the existence of a common boundary (which predicts war), an alliance between the two states, and higher than average wealth per head (both of which predict peace). <ref>Bremer 1993</ref> There has been many similar studies after this, often giving very different results depending on methodology and included variables, which has caused criticism. However, a common thread in virtually all results is an emphasis on the relationship between democracy and peace {{Harvard citation|Ray|2005}}, {{Harvard citation|Oneal|Russett|2004}}.

Lesser conflics between democracies have been more violent; but rarer, less bloody, and less likely to spread. <ref>Wayman 2002</ref> <ref> See ; ; . MIDs include the conflicts that precede a war; so the difference between MIDs and MICs nay be less than it appears. </ref> Democracies are less belligerent, negotiate more,<ref></ref> and military conflicts between any two democracies are rarely repeated.<ref> .</ref> There have been many more MIDs than wars; the Correlates of War Project counts several thousands during the last two centuries .


When examining the inter-liberal MIDs in more detail, one study {{Harvard citation|Wayman|2002}} finds that they are less likely to involve third parties, the target of the hostility is less likely reciprocate, if the target reciprocates the response is usually proportional to the provocation, and the disputes are less likely to cause any loss of life. The most common action was "Seizure of Material or Personnel" When examining the inter-liberal MIDs in more detail, one study {{Harvard citation|Wayman|2002}} finds that they are less likely to involve third parties, the target of the hostility is less likely reciprocate, if the target reciprocates the response is usually proportional to the provocation, and the disputes are less likely to cause any loss of life. The most common action was "Seizure of Material or Personnel"



Studies find that the probability that disputes between states will be resolved peacefully is positively affected by the degree of democracy exhibited by the least democratic state involved in that dispute. Disputes between democratic states are significantly shorter than disputes involving at least one undemocratic state. Democratic states are more likely to be amenable to third party mediation when they are involved in disputes with each other {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}}. Studies find that the probability that disputes between states will be resolved peacefully is positively affected by the degree of democracy exhibited by the least democratic state involved in that dispute. Disputes between democratic states are significantly shorter than disputes involving at least one undemocratic state. Democratic states are more likely to be amenable to third party mediation when they are involved in disputes with each other {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}}.
Line 110: Line 115:


Some Kantians do not expect the democratic peace to include undeveloped states; they find that mutual democracy does not have any pacific effect if either of the democracies is poor - in fact the chance of conflicts increases. Naturally, the pacific effect still exists, but is lessened, for countries with less severe poverty. <ref> Less than $1400/head; see , other papers by Mousseau, and </ref> It may well be that the culture of democracy is distorted by the stresses of poverty; the degree required to cancel or reverse the effects of the democratic peace is that of Zimbabwe - a misery unknown among democracies during the period studied. Some Kantians do not expect the democratic peace to include undeveloped states; they find that mutual democracy does not have any pacific effect if either of the democracies is poor - in fact the chance of conflicts increases. Naturally, the pacific effect still exists, but is lessened, for countries with less severe poverty. <ref> Less than $1400/head; see , other papers by Mousseau, and </ref> It may well be that the culture of democracy is distorted by the stresses of poverty; the degree required to cancel or reverse the effects of the democratic peace is that of Zimbabwe - a misery unknown among democracies during the period studied.

===Multivariable studies===
Many papers have studied the ]s involving peace or war. For example, Stuart Bremer (1993) <ref>Bremer 1992</ref> did a sutdy of seven variables traditionally expected to produce peace or war. He found that ''six'' of them had a genuine effect, independent of all the others, in predicting whether a given pair of states were likely to go to war or not. Mutual democracy was fourth of these, behind the existence of a common boundary (which predicts war), an alliance between the two states, and higher than average wealth per head (both of which predict peace).

Ray {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}} collected a dozen such studies showing that democracy has some statistically significant correlation with peace, "even after controlling for a large number of factors" (not, of course, all controlled simultaneously); including economic interdependence, membership in international organizations, contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic wealth and economic growth, power ratio, and political stability. <ref>The collection is in ; quote from Bremer 1993; more recent multivariate studies are , , , and . </ref>


=== Progressive research program === === Progressive research program ===
] suggested that what he called a "progressive research program" is better than a "degenerative" when it is can explain the same phenomena as the "degenerative" one, but is also marked by growth and the discovery of important novel facts. In contrast, the supporters of the "degenerative" program do not make important new empirical discoveries, but instead mostly adjustments to their theory in order to defend it from competitors. On study argues that the democratic peace theory is now the "progressive" program in international relations. The theory can explain the empirical phenomena previously explained by the earlier dominant research program, ]. In addition, the initial discovery, that democracies do not make war on one another, has created a rapidly growing literature and a constantly growing list of novel empirical regularities, as noted above {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}}, {{Harvard citation|Chernoff|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Harrison|2005}}. ] suggested that what he called a "progressive research program" is better than a "degenerative" when it is can explain the same phenomena as the "degenerative" one, but is also marked by growth and the discovery of important novel facts. In contrast, the supporters of the "degenerative" program do not make important new empirical discoveries, but instead mostly adjustments to their theory in order to defend it from competitors. On study argues that the democratic peace theory is now the "progressive" program in international relations. The theory can explain the empirical phenomena previously explained by the earlier dominant research program, ]. In addition, the initial discovery, that democracies do not make war on one another, has created a rapidly growing literature and a constantly growing list of novel empirical regularities. {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}}, {{Harvard citation|Chernoff|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Harrison|2005}}. Many of these findings are discussed elsewhere in this article. Another example is that a review {{Harvard citation|Ray|2003}} lists several studies finding that democracies are more likely to ally with one another than with other states. Such alliances are likely to last longer than alliances involving nondemocracies.

==Arguments and evidence==

] and others <br> ]]
]]

The theory is well-studied with more than a hundred researchers having published many more articles. <ref> {{cite web | author=Rummel, R.J | title=Democratic Peace Bibliography Version 3.0 | work=Freedom, Democracy, Peace; Power, Democide, and War | url=http://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/BIBLIO.HTML | accessdate=October 2 | accessyear=2005}} </ref> Several ] studies mention in their introduction that most people who undertake research into the theory accept it as an empirical fact, including several of those mentioned below.<ref> For example: , . </ref>

===Less internal violence===
One study finds that the most democratic and the most authoritarian states have few ]s, and intermediate regimes the most. The probability for a civil war is also increased by political change, regardless whether toward greater democracy or greater autocracy. Intermediate regimes continue to be the most prone to civil war, regardless of the time since the political change. In the long run, since intermediate regimes are less stable than autocracies, which in turn are less stable than democracies, durable democracy is the most probable end-point of the process of ] {{Harvard citation|Hegre|Ellington|Gates|Gleditsch|2001}}. One study finds that the most democratic nations have the least terrorism {{Harvard citation|Abadie|2004}}. One study finds that ] and ] are rare in democracies {{Harvard citation|Harff|2003}}. Another that ] is rare {{Harvard citation|Rummel|1997}}.

One study {{Harvard citation|Davenport|Armstrong II|2004}} lists several other studies and states: "Repeatedly, democratic political systems have been found to decrease political bans, censorship, torture, disappearances and mass killing, doing so in a linear fashion across diverse measurements, methodologies, time periods, countries, and contexts." It concludes: "Across measures and methodological techniques, it is found that below a certain level, democracy has no impact on human rights violations, but above this level democracy infuences repression in a negative and roughly linear manner." One study {{Harvard citation|Davenport|Armstrong II|2003}} states that thirty years worth of statistical research has revealed that only two variables decrease human rights violations: political democracy and economic development. Of this democracy is more important and more easily created.

===The post-Cold War peace===
The ], released in October 2005 by the ], documents the dramatic decline in warfare and civil wars since the end of the ]. It claims that the two main causes of this decline are the end of the Cold War itself and ]; but also claims that the three Kantian factors have contributed materially. <ref> </ref> The improvement in the peace of the world since the end of the Cold War has been tabulated here.<ref> See of the ].</ref> Rummel argues that democracy is the main explanation and that the continuing increase in democracy worldwide will soon lead to an end to wars and ], possibly around or even before the middle of this century.<ref></ref>


==Possible exceptions== ==Possible exceptions==
Line 153: Line 138:


==Causes== ==Causes==
These theories have traditionally been categorized into two groups: explanations that focus on democratic norms and explanations that focus on democratic
The democratic peace has been derived both from institutional and cultural constraints on the behavior of democratic societies. The case for institutional constrainsts goes back to Kant (1795), who wrote :
political structures {{Harvard citation|Gelpi|Griesdorf|2001}}.
:"f the consent of the citizens is required in order to decide that war should be declared (and in this constitution it cannot but be the case), nothing is more natural than that they would be very cautious in commencing such a poor game, decreeing for themselves all the calamities of war. Among the latter would be: having to fight, having to pay the costs of war from their own resources, having painfully to repair the devastation war leaves behind, and, to fill up the measure of evils, load themselves with a heavy national debt that would embitter peace itself and that can never be liquidated on account of constant wars in the future" <ref>Kant, 1795, Cf. Reiss 1970:100</ref>


One example from the first group is that the democratic culture may make the leaders accustomed to negotiation and compromise. {{Harvard citation|Weart|1998}}<ref>Müller and Wolff 1004</ref> A belief in human rights may make people in democracies reluctant to go to war, especially against other democracies. The decline in colonialism, also by democracies, may be related to a change in perception of non-European peoples and their rights {{Harvard citation|Ravlo|Gleditsch|2000}}.
Democracy thus gives influence to those most likely to be killed or wounded in wars, and their relatives and friends (and to those who pay the bulk of the war taxes). This mechanism is supported by the example of the ], in which the ] resisted and vetoed most royal proposals for war<ref>For a description, see {{cite book|title=The northern wars : war, state and society in northeastern Europe, 1558-1721 |first=Robert I.|last= Frost|publisher=Longman's|location= Harlow, England;New York}} 2000. Especially Pp. 9-11, 114, 181, 323. </ref>, like those of ]. This monadic theory must, however, explain why democracies do attack non-democratic states. One explanation is that these democracies were threatened or otherwise were provoked by the non-democratic states; Doyle argues that democracies are more likely to be provoked than other powers, since they conduct a more idealistic foreign policy. <ref>Doyle 1983</ref>


Bruce Russett (1993) also argues that the democratic culture affect the way leaders resolve conflicts. In addition, he holds that a social norm emerged in the later nineteenth century, that democracies should not fight each other, which has since been fostered by the horrible warnings of the two World Wars and the Cold War. He sees less effective traces of this norm in Greek antiquity. <ref> Russett 1993, p. 5-8, 35, 59-62, 73-4</ref> He thus explains the several crises between democracies that came close to war towards the end of the nineteenth century, between the then comparatively few democracies; whereas the more numerous recent democracies have had no such crises between them. (it is true that none of these ended in war, but actual wars between the Powers were usually avoided. <ref> For the greater tendency of the Powers to be involved in war, see Bremer 1992; the converse of this is that small-poweer status is an external cause of peace. Which side of the borderline Spain falls on depends on which edition of ]'s list you read..</ref>
The other mechanism is that democratic states are culturally inclined to settle their foreign disputes by discussion and conciliation, as they do domestically.<ref>Müller and Wolff 1004</ref>,


The case for institutional constrainsts goes back to Kant (1795), who wrote :
Bruce Russett (1993) holds that a social norm emerged in the later nineteenth century, that democracies should not fight each other, which has since been fostered by the horrible warnings of the two World Wars and the Cold War. He sees ineffective traces of this norm in Greek antiquity. <ref> Russett 1993, p. 5-8, 59-62, 73-4</ref> He thus explains the several crises between democracies that came close to war towards the end of the nineteenth century, between the then comparatively few democracies; whereas the more numerous recent democracies have had no such crises between them. (it is true that none of these ended in war, but actual wars between the Powers were usually avoided. The only such war in the period was the ], between a democracy and a state on the borderline of democracy.) <ref> For the greater tendency of the Powers to be involved in war, see Bremer 1992; the converse of this is that small-poweer status is an external cause of peace. Which side of the borderline Spain falls on depends on which edition of ]'s list you read..</ref>
:"f the consent of the citizens is required in order to decide that war should be declared (and in this constitution it cannot but be the case), nothing is more natural than that they would be very cautious in commencing such a poor game, decreeing for themselves all the calamities of war. Among the latter would be: having to fight, having to pay the costs of war from their own resources, having painfully to repair the devastation war leaves behind, and, to fill up the measure of evils, load themselves with a heavy national debt that would embitter peace itself and that can never be liquidated on account of constant wars in the future" <ref>Kant, 1795, Cf. Reiss 1970:100</ref>


Democracy thus gives influence to those most likely to be killed or wounded in wars, and their relatives and friends (and to those who pay the bulk of the war taxes) Russet (1993, p. 30). This monadic theory must, however, explain why democracies do attack non-democratic states. One explanation is that these democracies were threatened or otherwise were provoked by the non-democratic states; Doyle (1983) argues that democracies are more likely to be provoked than other powers, since they conduct a more idealistic foreign policy. <ref>Doyle 1983</ref>
*Studies also find that democracies are more likely to ally with one another than with other states. Such alliances are likely to last longer than alliances involving nondemocracies. <ref> </ref>

Two of the ''militant democracies'' listed above were dominant naval powers, and therefore had greater choice whether and where to fight.<ref> Compare ]: ''The Influence of Sea Power on History'', ''ad init.''.</ref>

A ] explanation (2004) is that the participation of the public and open debate send clear and reliable information regarding the intentions of democracies to other states. In contrast, it is difficult to know the intentions of nondemocratic leaders, what effect concessions will have, and if promises will be kept. Thus there will be mistrust and unwillingness to make concessions if at least one of the parties in a dispute is a nondemocracy. <ref> </ref>

=== Possible mechanisms ===
The democratic culture may make the leaders accustomed to negotiation and compromise {{Harvard citation|Weart|1998}} A belief in human rights may make people in democracies reluctant to go to war, especially against other democracies. The decline in colonialism, also by democracies, may be related to a change in perception of non-European peoples and their rights {{Harvard citation|Ravlo|Gleditsch|2000}}.


Studies show that democratic states are more likely than autocratic states to win the wars. One explanation is that democracies, for internal political and economic reasons, have greater resources. This might mean that democratic leaders are unlikely to select other democratic states as targets because they perceive them to be particularly formidable opponents. One study finds that interstate wars have important impacts on the fate of political regimes, and that the probability that a political leader will fall from power in the wake of a lost war is particularly high in democratic states {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}}. Studies show that democratic states are more likely than autocratic states to win the wars. One explanation is that democracies, for internal political and economic reasons, have greater resources. This might mean that democratic leaders are unlikely to select other democratic states as targets because they perceive them to be particularly formidable opponents. One study finds that interstate wars have important impacts on the fate of political regimes, and that the probability that a political leader will fall from power in the wake of a lost war is particularly high in democratic states {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}}.
Line 178: Line 157:


Several studies find that democracy, more ] causing greater economic ], and membership in more ] reduce the risk of war. This is often called the Kantian peace theory since it is similar to Kant's earlier theory about a perpetual peace. These variables positively affect each other but each has an independent pacifying effect. For example, democracy may empower economic interest groups that may be opposed to disruptive wars {{Harvard citation|Oneal|Russett|2001}}, {{Harvard citation|Lagazio|Russett|2004}}. However, some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy {{Harvard citation|Goenner|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Kim|Rousseau|2005}}. Several studies find that democracy, more ] causing greater economic ], and membership in more ] reduce the risk of war. This is often called the Kantian peace theory since it is similar to Kant's earlier theory about a perpetual peace. These variables positively affect each other but each has an independent pacifying effect. For example, democracy may empower economic interest groups that may be opposed to disruptive wars {{Harvard citation|Oneal|Russett|2001}}, {{Harvard citation|Lagazio|Russett|2004}}. However, some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy {{Harvard citation|Goenner|2004}}, {{Harvard citation|Kim|Rousseau|2005}}.

Several of these mechanisms may also apply to ]. The book ] find evidence for an oligarchic peace. One example is the ], in which the ] resisted and vetoed most royal proposals for war<ref>For a description, see {{cite book|title=The northern wars : war, state and society in northeastern Europe, 1558-1721 |first=Robert I.|last= Frost|publisher=Longman's|location= Harlow, England;New York}} 2000. Especially Pp. 9-11, 114, 181, 323. </ref>, like those of ].


=== Realist explanations === === Realist explanations ===
Line 192: Line 173:
There are at least five logically distinguishable classes of criticism. Note that they usually apply to no wars or few MIDs between democracies, not to little systematic violence in democracies. There are at least five logically distinguishable classes of criticism. Note that they usually apply to no wars or few MIDs between democracies, not to little systematic violence in democracies.


*That the theorist has not applied his criteria, for democracy or war or both, accurately to the historical record. Democracy has meant different things at different times, to establishing a unilinear or ahistorical understanding of democracy as the basis of any such theory will always be ontologically flawed. *That the researcher has not applied his criteria, for democracy or war or both, accurately to the historical record.
*That the criteria are not reasonable. For example, critics may prefer that liberal democracy should exclude or include both ] and the ] at the time of World War I, rather than count one as democratic and the other non-democratic, when they were quite similar societies. One should also recall that, before World War II, ] was democratically elected (a view rejected by ]), and so we cannot rely on democracy in itself to result in peace with other democracies. *That the criteria are not reasonable. For example, critics may prefer that liberal democracy should exclude or include both ] and the ] at the time of World War I, rather than count one as democratic and the other non-democratic, when they were quite similar societies. One should also recall that, before World War II, ] was democratically elected (a view rejected by ]), and so we cannot rely on democracy in itself to result in peace with other democracies. Democracy has meant different things at different times.
*That the theory may not actually mean very much, because it has limited its data below the level of significance, or because it promises only a limited peace, involving only a small class of states; for example, democracies have fought many offensive ] and ] wars (c.f., above, that the idea of democracy has also changed over time). Setting aside the question of whether the democratic peace applies to these cases at all, the predictions of democratic peace theory are still limited. No theorist denies that democracies have acted against one another by covert or non-military means. Even small military confrontations between democracies have happened. *That the theory may not actually mean very much, because it has limited its data below the level of significance, or because it promises only a limited peace, involving only a small class of states; for example, democracies have fought many offensive ] and ] wars (c.f., above, that the idea of democracy has also changed over time). Setting aside the question of whether the democratic peace applies to these cases at all, the predictions of democratic peace theory may still be limited. No researcher denies that democracies have acted against one another by covert or non-military means. Even small military confrontations between democracies have happened.
*That it is not democracy itself but some other external factor(s) which happened to be associated with democratic states that explain the peace.
*That it is not democracy itself but some other external factor(s) which happened to be associated with democratic states that explain the peace. One of the more obvious instances of such relationships includes mutual material interests; that is, liberal democracies tend to be situated in the so-termed ], and so inter-democratic war would hamper both sides' economic interests, as well as causing worldwide financial insecurity. As such, democratic peace theory reflects dated ontological premises that take no account of the effects of ] or (to cite another example) the arguments of ] such as ]. Moreover, if we stick to ] (1832) terms (that war is simply "the continuation of policy by other means" (see '']'')), liberal democracies have less to fight over as most of their interests are secured by the economic system that favours them. Other ] theorists observe that the 'special relationship' between the US and the UK may also reflect a shared language as well as interests. This last argument is, however, very new and has thus far not been fully exposited.
*Lastly, it has been argued that democratic peace theory is not really a theory but more of an ''observation'' that, historically speaking, democracies have been less likely to wage war amongst themselves. As such, this 'observation' does little to establish democratic peace as a stable referent within international relations. *Lastly, it has been argued that democratic peace theory is not really a theory but more of an ''observation'' that, historically speaking, democracies have been less likely to wage war amongst themselves. As such, this 'observation' does little to establish democratic peace as a stable referent within international relations.


Line 204: Line 185:
</ref> </ref>


Some democratic peace theorists have been criticzed for reclassifiying some conflitcs without pruning the whole list of formal wars similarly. Supporters and opponents of the democratic peace <ref>Bremer 1992, Gleditsch 1995; Gowa ''Ballots and Bullets''.</ref> agree that this is bad statistics. Some democratic peace theorists have been criticzed for reclassifiying some conflitcs without pruning the whole list of formal wars similarly. Supporters and opponents of the democratic peace <ref>Bremer 1992, Gleditsch 1995; Gowa ''Ballots and Bullets''.</ref> agree that this is bad statistics.

There are also some difficulties in the application of statistical methods to the problem, especially to question of causation.<ref> The difficulties and disputes involved are discussed at some length in ''Case studies and theory development in the social sciences'' by Alexander L. George and Andrew Bennett. </ref>


===Limited claims=== ===Limited claims===
Line 219: Line 202:
===External causes=== ===External causes===


There has been a confluence of the old theory (dating back to ] and ]) that ] will produce and ensure peace,<ref> See John Morley:''Life of Richard Cobden'' and Francois Furet: ''Passing of an Illusion''. </ref> with the modern theory that trade will produce democracy, or at least spread it to the non-democratic trading partner, as argued by ] and others. According to this, democracy and peace are indeed correlated, because they arise from a common cause. There has been a confluence of the old theory (dating back to ] and ]) that ] will produce and ensure peace,<ref> See John Morley:''Life of Richard Cobden'' and Francois Furet: ''Passing of an Illusion''. </ref> with the modern theory that trade will produce democracy, or at least spread it to the non-democratic trading partner, as argued by ] and others. According to this, democracy and peace are indeed correlated, because they arise from a common cause.{{citation needed}}


==Countercriticisms== ==Countercriticisms==
] and others <br> ]]
]]

The theory is well-studied with more than a hundred researchers having published many more articles. <ref> {{cite web | author=Rummel, R.J | title=Democratic Peace Bibliography Version 3.0 | work=Freedom, Democracy, Peace; Power, Democide, and War | url=http://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/BIBLIO.HTML | accessdate=October 2 | accessyear=2005}} </ref> Several ] studies mention in their introduction that most people who undertake research into the theory accept it as an empirical fact, including several of those mentioned below.<ref> For example: , . </ref>

Correlation is not causation. However, many studies, as those discussed in {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}}, {{Harvard citation|Ray|2005}}, {{Harvard citation|Oneal|Russett|2004}}, supporting the theory have controlled for many possible alternative causes of the peace. Examples of factors controlled for are geographic distance, geographic contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic wealth and economic growth, power ratio, and political stability. Several studies have also controlled for the possibility of reverse causality from peace to democracy {{Harvard citation|Mousseau|Shi|1999}},{{Harvard citation|Reiter|2001}}, {{Harvard citation|Reuveny|Li|2003}}. Correlation is not causation. However, many studies, as those discussed in {{Harvard citation|Ray|1998}}, {{Harvard citation|Ray|2005}}, {{Harvard citation|Oneal|Russett|2004}}, supporting the theory have controlled for many possible alternative causes of the peace. Examples of factors controlled for are geographic distance, geographic contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic wealth and economic growth, power ratio, and political stability. Several studies have also controlled for the possibility of reverse causality from peace to democracy {{Harvard citation|Mousseau|Shi|1999}},{{Harvard citation|Reiter|2001}}, {{Harvard citation|Reuveny|Li|2003}}.


Line 233: Line 221:


Wars tend very strongly to be between neighboring states. Gleditsch (1995) showed that the average distance between democracies is about 8000 miles, the same as the average distance between all states. He believes that the effect of distance in preventing war, modified by the democratic peace, explains the incidence of war as fully as it can be explained. <ref>Gleditsch 1995; </ref> Wars tend very strongly to be between neighboring states. Gleditsch (1995) showed that the average distance between democracies is about 8000 miles, the same as the average distance between all states. He believes that the effect of distance in preventing war, modified by the democratic peace, explains the incidence of war as fully as it can be explained. <ref>Gleditsch 1995; </ref>

Regarding how significant the theory is, Rummel argues that the continuing increase in democracy worldwide will soon lead to an end to wars and ], possibly around or even before the middle of this century.<ref></ref> The ], released in October 2005 by the ], documents the dramatic decline in warfare and civil wars since the end of the ]. However, it claims that the two main causes of this decline are the end of the Cold War itself and ]; but also claims that the three Kantian factors have contributed materially. <ref> </ref> The improvement in the peace of the world since the end of the Cold War has been tabulated here.<ref> See of the ].</ref>


==Harvard== ==Harvard==

Revision as of 01:07, 13 April 2006

A democratic peace theory or simply democratic peace (often DPT and sometimes democratic pacifism) is a theory in international relations, political science, and philosophy which holds that democracies—specifically, liberal democracies—never or almost never go to war with one another. It can trace its philosophical roots to Immanuel Kant.

Some theories of democratic peace also hold that lesser conflicts are rare between democracies, or that violence is in general less common within democracies, or that there is also peace between oligarchies.

History

Main article: Perpetual peace

Democratic peace theory is a relatively new development. No ancient author seems to have considered it true. Democratic governments, as well as sociologists to study them, were scarce before the 19th century.

Until the late Enlightenment, the word democracy usually meant direct (or pure) democracy, which was treated with suspicion. Even the idea that republics tend to be peaceful is recent; Niccolò Machiavelli believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing Rome as the prime example.

Immanuel Kant

It was Immanuel Kant who first foreshadowed the theory in his essay Perpetual Peace written in 1795, although he thought that liberal democracy was only one of several necessary conditions for a perpetual peace. US President Woodrow Wilson advocated the idea in politics during and after WWI.

The hope of a democratic peace shows in Woodrow Wilson's message asking Congress to declare war and is reflected in his two slogans: "a war to end war" and "a world safe for democracy". His plans for the Peace after that war, which can be traced back to 1894, were strongly similar to Kant's proposal, including both Kant’s cosmopolitan law and pacific union. The third of the Fourteen Points specified the removal of economic barriers between peaceful nations; the fourteenth provided for the League of Nations.

Dean Babst, a Wisconsin criminologist, wrote the first academic paper supporting the theory, in 1964, in Wisconsin Sociologist; he published a slightly more popularized version, eight years later, in the trade journal Industrial Research.

The peace theorists J. David Singer and Melvin Small in 1976 denied that democracies were in general less war-like than other nations; but they found only two marginal cases of democracies fighting each other. This paper was published in the Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, in 1976, and eventually brought the attention of several political scientists to the underlying contention — partly through Michael Doyle's lengthy discussion of the topic.

Rudolph J. Rummel of the University of Hawaii cited Babst's work in the fourth book of his five-volume work, Understanding Conflict and War (1975-1981). He has since written extensively on the democratic peace, and has also drawn considerable lay attention to the subject.

There have been numerous studies in the field since. Most studies have found some form of democratic peace exists; although neither methodological disputes nor doubtful cases are entirely resolved. . Many of these papers are discussed elsewhere in this article.

Influence

Democratic peace theory has been extremely divisive among the students of international relations. It is rooted in the idealist and liberal traditions; and is strongly opposed to the realist idea of the balance of power. However, democratic peace theory has come to be more widely accepted and have in some democracies affected policy.

Presidents of both the major American parties have expressed support for the theory. Former President Bill Clinton of the Democratic Party: "Ultimately, the best strategy to ensure our security and to build a durable peace is to support the advance of democracy elsewhere. Democracies don't attack each other." Current President George W. Bush of the Republican Party: "And the reason why I'm so strong on democracy is democracies don't go to war with each other. And the reason why is the people of most societies don't like war, and they understand what war means.... I've got great faith in democracies to promote peace. And that's why I'm such a strong believer that the way forward in the Middle East, the broader Middle East, is to promote democracy."

Some fear that the democratic peace theory may be used to justify wars againt nondemocracies in order to bring lasting peace, in a democratic crusade. This was part of the rhetoric for the United States' intervention in World War I, and similar arguments have been part of American political rhetoric since the fall of the Soviet Union. Some point out that the democratic peace theory has been used to justify the 2003 Iraq War, others argue that this justification was used only after the War had already started. However, research shows that attempts to create democracies by using external force has often failed eventually. Supporting internal democratic movements and using diplomacy may be far more succesful and less costly. Thus, the theory and related research, if they were correctly understood, may actually be an argument against a democratic crusade.

Types of theory

What follows is not a division into schools; two theorists may agree on one question and disagree on another.

The separate peace

Are democracies more peaceful with everybody, or only with each other?

Babst (1964) asserted the first proposition, that democracies are more peaceful in general, which is now called the monadic peace; his evidence was for the special case: that democracies do not fight with each other, now called the dyadic peace.

Singer and Small (1976) discussed both propositions; they found no support for the general, monadic, proposition, and very few peace theorists hold it. Rummel was previously "virtually alone" in doing so; Rummel's evidence is drawn only from 1976-1980; and the post-Vietnam years may be exceptional. Doyle (1997) argued that the absence of a monadic peace is only to be expected: the same ideologies that cause liberal states to be at peace with each other inspire idealistic wars with the illiberal, whether to defend oppressed foreign minorities or avenge countrymen settled abroad.

There are also some more recent monadic papers, which find a slight monadic effect; Müller and Wolff (2004), in listing them, find monadic theories as "neither necessary nor convincing"; Müller finds, that, instead, democracies have varied greatly in their belligerence against non-democracies. The militant democracies since 1950 have been India, Israel, the United Kingdom and the United States. Two of the militant democracies listed above were dominant naval powers, and therefore had greater choice whether and where to fight.

The absolute peace

Is the interdemocratic peace a necessity, or only a very strong tendency?

One researcher argues that the interdemocratic peace is a necessary and mechanical connection; an "absolute (or point) assertion", in the words of one of them.. This is distinct from the question:

Have there in fact been no wars between democracies, or have there been one or two exceptions?

If the absolute peace is true, it would follow that there have been no wars; but several theorists agree that that there have been no wars in fact, but disagree vehemently with the absolute peace. Bremer, in his 1993 paper, which strongly supports the democratic peace as a potent and independent force, finds that it is a "stochastic regularity", and holds that "uncertainty reduction (which is not the same thing as explanation)" is the best possible result in analyzing the ultimately indeterminate onset of war, which includes an irreducibly random factor; we should avoid determinism, "'iron laws'", and "'necessary and sufficient conditions'". He also deplores the "religious fervor" which "trumpet to the world that if all states were democratic, war would cease to plague mankind" Since a probability of exactly zero is unprovable, it is "fruitless to debate the question of whether democracies never or only very rarely fight one another".. Wayman also agrees on the point of fact, but disputes the mechanical view.

Other theorists regard the democratic peace as an empirical or statistical regularity: wars between democracies have not occured, are rare, or very rare, but not impossible. Many researchers have found no wars. Some agree that there have not actually been any yet; others see one or two (usually marginal) exceptions. Some straddle the question of fact, saying "very rare or nonexistent". This difference amounts to the question of whether something that happens once in a blue moon has happened yet; and is discussed further below.

The Kantian peace

Is liberal democracy sufficient by itself, or do trade and intergovernmental orgranizations also produce peace?

Michael Doyle (1983) reintroduced Kant's three articles into democratic peace theory. He argued that a pacific union of liberal states has been growing for the past two centuries. He denies that a pair of states will be peaceful simply because they are both liberal democracies; if that were enough, liberal states would not be aggressive towards weak non-liberal states (as the history of American relations with Mexico shows they are). Rather, liberal democracy is a necessary condition for international organization and hospitality (which are Kant's other two articles) — and all three are sufficient to produce peace. Kantian peace theorists are uniform either; other Kantians disagree. For example, Doyle argument that all three in the triad must be present has not been repeated by other researchers.

Several theorists, led by Bruce Russett and John R. Oneal have since found multiple causes for such general peace as we have seen; usually about three, which resemble Kant's. Several of these theorists call their result the Kantian peace. The modern Kantian theory argues that democracy, more trade causing greater economic interdependence, and membership in more intergovernmental organizations are positively related to each other; but that each has an independent pacifying effect. This idea is in keeping with the theory of Institutionalism or Neoliberalism.

Some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy (Goenner 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFGoenner2004 (help), (Kim & Rousseau 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFKimRousseau2005 (help).

Less internal violence

One study finds that the most democratic and the most authoritarian states have few civil wars, and intermediate regimes the most. The probability for a civil war is also increased by political change, regardless whether toward greater democracy or greater autocracy. Intermediate regimes continue to be the most prone to civil war, regardless of the time since the political change. In the long run, since intermediate regimes are less stable than autocracies, which in turn are less stable than democracies, durable democracy is the most probable end-point of the process of democratization (Hegre et al. 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFHegreEllingtonGatesGleditsch2001 (help). One study finds that the most democratic nations have the least terrorism (Abadie 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFAbadie2004 (help). One study finds that genocide and politicide are rare in democracies (Harff 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFHarff2003 (help). Another that democide is rare (Rummel 1997) harv error: no target: CITEREFRummel1997 (help).

One study (Davenport & Armstrong II 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFDavenportArmstrong_II2004 (help) lists several other studies and states: "Repeatedly, democratic political systems have been found to decrease political bans, censorship, torture, disappearances and mass killing, doing so in a linear fashion across diverse measurements, methodologies, time periods, countries, and contexts." It concludes: "Across measures and methodological techniques, it is found that below a certain level, democracy has no impact on human rights violations, but above this level democracy infuences repression in a negative and roughly linear manner." One study (Davenport & Armstrong II 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFDavenportArmstrong_II2003 (help) states that thirty years worth of statistical research has revealed that only two variables decrease human rights violations: political democracy and economic development. Of this democracy is more important and more easily created.

Definitions

A democratic peace theory has to define what it means by "democracy" and what it means by "peace" (or, more often, "war"), and what it claims as the link between the two.

Democracy

Democracies have been defined differently by different researchers; this accounts for some of the variations in their findings. In general, they require a relatively wide franchise, at least in historical terms; competitive elections; civil rights; and a constitutional government.

There is general agreement that the democratic peace applies to liberal democracies, with "freedom of speech, religion, and organization; and a constitutional framework of law to which the government is subordinate and that guarantees equal rights." Russett, in an effort to prove a stronger theorem, does not require civil rights.

Wide franchise can be, in different authors, from half the adult population down to 10%, or even lower. Explicitly requiring women's suffrage would mean there could have been no interdemocratic wars before New Zealand enacted it in 1894. The effect of this variation on the list of democracies is not great, although Great Britain can be argued to have achieved wide franchise at various dates between 1832 and 1918.

Theorists differ on the extent to which the executive must be chosen by election. Many would accept Babst's definition that he either be elected directly or freely chosen by an elected body. Singer required that the parliament be at least equal to the executive. Babst and Rummel also require secret ballot, which was first practised in 1856

Doyle, who writes (1983) of "liberal régimes" rather than "democracies", allows greater power to hereditary monarchs than other theories; for example, he counts the rule of Louis-Philippe of France - and that of Robespierre - as a liberal regíme. He describes Wilhelmine Germany as "a difficult case....In practice, a liberal state under republican law for domestic affairs...divorced from the control of its citizenry in foreign affairs."

In this usage he follows Kant, who opposed (direct) "democracy" since it is "necessarily despotism, as it establishes an executive power contrary to the general will; all being able to decide against one whose opinion may differ, the will of all is therefore not that of all: which is contradictory and opposite to liberty." Instead, Kant favors a constitutional republic where individual liberty is protected from the will of the majority. Russett (1993) and Antholis's study of ancient Greece follows Greek usage, which meant direct democracy, although not necessarily without constitutional constraints.<def>Russett 1993, p.45ff.</def>

Continuous classification

Researchers often use Ted Gurr's Polity Data Set which scores each state on two scales, one of democracy and one for autocracy, for each year since 1800; as well as others. The use of this has varied. Some researchers have done correlations between the democracy scale and belligerence; others have treated it as a binary classification by (as its maker does) calling all states with a high democracy score and a low autocracy score democracies; yet others have used the difference of the two scores, sometimes again making this into a binary classification. Other such rankings have made by Steve Chan and by Ze'ev Maoz.

Nascent democracies

Doyle treats one exceptional case by observing that both sides were under liberal goverments less than three years old, and so democracy had not stabilized; Rummel and Weart have treated this as a general rule, excluding from consideration any war in which either side has been a democracy for less than three years; the former argues that this is enough time for "democratic proceedures to be accepted, and democratic culture to settle in." Additionally, this allows for other states to actually come to the recognition of the state as a democracy.

War

Quantitative research on international wars usually define war as a military conflict with more than 1000 killed in battle. This is the definition used in the Correlates of War Project which has also supplied the data for many studies on war. Some researchers have used different definitions. For example, Weart (1998) defines war as more than 200 battle deaths. . Some have defined wars are a clash or series of clashes, allowing for only one victor, characterized by a highly ritualized beginning and end

Methods

The straightforward argument for the democratic peace is: given the number of wars over the past two centuries, if democracies fought each other as often as any other pair of states, there should have been dozens of wars between democracies. Instead, depending on the study, we find zero, or one, or two, and the exceptions generally involve marginal democracies.. A review (Ray 1998) lists many studies finding that this peacefulness is statistically significant.

One problem is that as the Realist Mearsheimer (1990) put it, "democracies have been few in number over the past two centuries, and thus there have few opportunities where democracies were in a position to fight one another"; so there isn't enough data to be as sure of the democratic peace as of Boyle's Law, as Wayman, a supporter of the democratic peace, admits. "If we rely solely on whether there has been an inter-democratic war, it is going to take many more decades of peace to build our confidence in the stability of the democratic peace", especially with the present small rate of warfare. This is worse if we try to divide our data to look for other factors which might cause peace, or try to control for those factors when found.

This is particularly cogent against the more stringent definitions of democracy, which tend to be made by those closer to the absolute peace; and also with respect to the nineteenth century data. Even the looser definitions of democracy admit only a dozen states before the late nineteenth century, and many of them are young or have limited franchise

Lesser conflicts

Many researchers reacted to this by studying lesser conflicts (Militarized Interstate Disputes in the jargon; MID's and wars together are "militarized interstate conflicts") instead, since they have been far more common. A review (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help) lists many studies that have reported that democratic pairs of states are less likely to be involved in MIDs than other pairs of states.

Stuart Bremer (1993) and many others have also studied multiple correlations involving peace or war. Bremer did a study of seven variables traditionally expected to produce peace or war. He found that six of them had a genuine effect, independent of all the others, in predicting whether a given pair of states were likely to go to war or not. Mutual democracy was fourth of these, behind the existence of a common boundary (which predicts war), an alliance between the two states, and higher than average wealth per head (both of which predict peace). There has been many similar studies after this, often giving very different results depending on methodology and included variables, which has caused criticism. However, a common thread in virtually all results is an emphasis on the relationship between democracy and peace (Ray 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2005 (help), (Oneal & Russett 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFOnealRussett2004 (help).

Lesser conflics between democracies have been more violent; but rarer, less bloody, and less likely to spread. Democracies are less belligerent, negotiate more, and military conflicts between any two democracies are rarely repeated. There have been many more MIDs than wars; the Correlates of War Project counts several thousands during the last two centuries .

When examining the inter-liberal MIDs in more detail, one study (Wayman 2002) harv error: no target: CITEREFWayman2002 (help) finds that they are less likely to involve third parties, the target of the hostility is less likely reciprocate, if the target reciprocates the response is usually proportional to the provocation, and the disputes are less likely to cause any loss of life. The most common action was "Seizure of Material or Personnel"

Studies find that the probability that disputes between states will be resolved peacefully is positively affected by the degree of democracy exhibited by the least democratic state involved in that dispute. Disputes between democratic states are significantly shorter than disputes involving at least one undemocratic state. Democratic states are more likely to be amenable to third party mediation when they are involved in disputes with each other (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help).

In international crises that include the threat or use of military force, one study finds that if the parties are democracies, then relative military strength has no effect on who wins. This is different from when nondemocracies are involved. These results are the same also if the conflicting parties are formal allies (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help). Similarly, a study of the behavior of states that joined ongoing militarized disputes reports that power is important only to autocracies: democracies do not seem to base their alignment on the power of the sides in the dispute (Werner & Lemke 1997) harv error: no target: CITEREFWernerLemke1997 (help).

Some Kantians do not expect the democratic peace to include undeveloped states; they find that mutual democracy does not have any pacific effect if either of the democracies is poor - in fact the chance of conflicts increases. Naturally, the pacific effect still exists, but is lessened, for countries with less severe poverty. It may well be that the culture of democracy is distorted by the stresses of poverty; the degree required to cancel or reverse the effects of the democratic peace is that of Zimbabwe - a misery unknown among democracies during the period studied.

Progressive research program

Imre Lakatos suggested that what he called a "progressive research program" is better than a "degenerative" when it is can explain the same phenomena as the "degenerative" one, but is also marked by growth and the discovery of important novel facts. In contrast, the supporters of the "degenerative" program do not make important new empirical discoveries, but instead mostly adjustments to their theory in order to defend it from competitors. On study argues that the democratic peace theory is now the "progressive" program in international relations. The theory can explain the empirical phenomena previously explained by the earlier dominant research program, realism in international relations. In addition, the initial discovery, that democracies do not make war on one another, has created a rapidly growing literature and a constantly growing list of novel empirical regularities. (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help), (Chernoff 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFChernoff2004 (help), (Harrison 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFHarrison2005 (help). Many of these findings are discussed elsewhere in this article. Another example is that a review (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help) lists several studies finding that democracies are more likely to ally with one another than with other states. Such alliances are likely to last longer than alliances involving nondemocracies.

Possible exceptions

Several researchers have found no wars between democracies. See the article about the book Never at War (1998) for a discussion of specific cases. For a discussion which claims to presents argument on both sides, see the librarian Matthew White's personal website .

As said above, some researchers see no cases in which democracies have gone to full-scale war; others see one or two exceptions. The wars most commonly suggested as exceptions are the Spanish-American War and the Continuation War with Finland, insofar as some of the Allies were at war with Finland. World War I has also been mentioned, chiefly in popular writing. Even those who regard them as exceptions regard them as marginal cases.

Three researchers have written whole books to show that democracies have never ever gone to war with each other; they accomplish this by arguing, that, for every apparent war between "primâ facie democracies", there is some reason why these aren't real democracies or a real war. This rhetorical approach has led to the democratic peace being dismissed, by the military affairs columnist of the Asia Times, as subject to the no true Scotsman problem..

Frank Wayman (2002) joins them on the "one narrow point", the fact of no wars between democracies, but deplores the rush to a general conclusion.. Zeev Maoz used to agree on the matter of fact, but has refined his criteria, and in 1997 counts the Spanish-American War as a war between democracies. Other authors simply describe war between democracies as "rare", "very rare", "rare or non-existent". Nils Petter Gleditsch (1995) and Stuart Bremer (1993) each discuss one or two marginal exceptions; but neither of them find this an obstacle to supporting the existence and force of the democratic peace; Gleditsch sees the (somewhat technical) state of war between Finland and the Western Allies during World War II, as a special case, which should probably be treated separately: an incidental state of war between democracies during large multi-polar wars, which are fortunately rare. The importance of this exception depends on what forms of hostility you regard as serious; Wayman regards the formal declaration of war by Great Britain and Australia as the "most severe" hostility between democracies, but the actual consequences amounted to a single bombing raid and some destruction of commerce. Jeanne Gowa also considers the Spanish-American War and the Continuation War the only outright exceptions to the democratic peace. Correlation studies do not have exceptions, only outliers.

Mansfield and Snyder, who support that well-established liberal democracies have not made war, state that emerging democracies with weak political institutions are especially likely to go to war, whether or not they win, as a means of handling internal tension. They find that all wars between democracies involve one less than five years old; Hensel found the same of almost all lesser conflicts. Ray disowns them. Since some of the component articles were published in Foreign Affairs, "they obviously intended to discourage policies inspired by the democratic peace proposition that were designed to bring about such transitions."

Along the same line, Jack Levy wrote, back in 1989, "as close to anything we have to empirical law in international relations."

Some Kantians have less trouble with exceptions. Bruce Russett (1993) sees the Kantian peace as developing in history; therefore he finds the thirteen certain, and thirty-five possible, wars between Greek democracies as part of the history of this development. While he sees no true exceptions in the modern world, he regards the half-dozen "near misses" as further evidence of an emerging peace: three or four of them are among the few and incomplete democracies of the nineteenth century; only one or two among the many democracies of the twentieth.

Doyle (1983) argues that a democracy which is not part of international organizations and is not part of the international web of hospitality and commerce is not part of the separate peace. Kant (1795) himself held that some wars are to be expected; the resulting suffering is what will convince the nations to actually do the reasonable thing, and establish a lasting peace; and some Kantian theorists agree.

Causes

These theories have traditionally been categorized into two groups: explanations that focus on democratic norms and explanations that focus on democratic political structures (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help).

One example from the first group is that the democratic culture may make the leaders accustomed to negotiation and compromise. (Weart 1998) harv error: no target: CITEREFWeart1998 (help) A belief in human rights may make people in democracies reluctant to go to war, especially against other democracies. The decline in colonialism, also by democracies, may be related to a change in perception of non-European peoples and their rights (Ravlo & Gleditsch 2000) harv error: no target: CITEREFRavloGleditsch2000 (help).

Bruce Russett (1993) also argues that the democratic culture affect the way leaders resolve conflicts. In addition, he holds that a social norm emerged in the later nineteenth century, that democracies should not fight each other, which has since been fostered by the horrible warnings of the two World Wars and the Cold War. He sees less effective traces of this norm in Greek antiquity. He thus explains the several crises between democracies that came close to war towards the end of the nineteenth century, between the then comparatively few democracies; whereas the more numerous recent democracies have had no such crises between them. (it is true that none of these ended in war, but actual wars between the Powers were usually avoided.

The case for institutional constrainsts goes back to Kant (1795), who wrote :

"f the consent of the citizens is required in order to decide that war should be declared (and in this constitution it cannot but be the case), nothing is more natural than that they would be very cautious in commencing such a poor game, decreeing for themselves all the calamities of war. Among the latter would be: having to fight, having to pay the costs of war from their own resources, having painfully to repair the devastation war leaves behind, and, to fill up the measure of evils, load themselves with a heavy national debt that would embitter peace itself and that can never be liquidated on account of constant wars in the future"

Democracy thus gives influence to those most likely to be killed or wounded in wars, and their relatives and friends (and to those who pay the bulk of the war taxes) Russet (1993, p. 30). This monadic theory must, however, explain why democracies do attack non-democratic states. One explanation is that these democracies were threatened or otherwise were provoked by the non-democratic states; Doyle (1983) argues that democracies are more likely to be provoked than other powers, since they conduct a more idealistic foreign policy.

Studies show that democratic states are more likely than autocratic states to win the wars. One explanation is that democracies, for internal political and economic reasons, have greater resources. This might mean that democratic leaders are unlikely to select other democratic states as targets because they perceive them to be particularly formidable opponents. One study finds that interstate wars have important impacts on the fate of political regimes, and that the probability that a political leader will fall from power in the wake of a lost war is particularly high in democratic states (Ray 1998).

As decribed in (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help), several studies have argued that liberal leaders face institutionalized constraints that impede their capacity to mobilize the state’s resources for war without the consent of a broad spectrum of interests. Moreover, these constraints are readily apparent to other states and cannot be manipulated by leaders. Thus, democracies send credible signals to other states of an aversion to using force. These signals allow democratic states to avoid conflicts with one another, but they may attract aggression from nondemocratic states. Democracies may be pressured to respond to such aggression—perhaps even preemptively—through the use of force. Also as described in (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help), studies have argued that when democratic leaders do choose to escalate international crises, their threats are taken as highly credible, since there must be a relatively large public opinion for these actions. In disputes between liberal states, the credibility of their bargaining signals allows them to negotiate a peaceful settlement before mobilization.

A game-theoretic explanation similar to the last two above is that the participation of the public and the open debate send clear and reliable information regarding the intentions of democracies to other states. In contrast, it is difficult to know the intentions of nondemocratic leaders, what effect concessions will have, and if promises will be kept. Thus there will be mistrust and unwillingness to make concessions if at least one of the parties in a dispute is a nondemocracy (Levy & Razin 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFLevyRazin2004 (help).

Several studies find that democracy, more trade causing greater economic interdependence, and membership in more intergovernmental organizations reduce the risk of war. This is often called the Kantian peace theory since it is similar to Kant's earlier theory about a perpetual peace. These variables positively affect each other but each has an independent pacifying effect. For example, democracy may empower economic interest groups that may be opposed to disruptive wars (Oneal & Russett 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFOnealRussett2001 (help), (Lagazio & Russett 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFLagazioRussett2004 (help). However, some recent studies find no effect from trade but only from democracy (Goenner 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFGoenner2004 (help), (Kim & Rousseau 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFKimRousseau2005 (help).

Several of these mechanisms may also apply to oligarchies. The book Never at War find evidence for an oligarchic peace. One example is the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth, in which the Sejm resisted and vetoed most royal proposals for war, like those of Władysław IV Vasa.

Realist explanations

David E. Spiro (1994) points out at some length that much of the democratic peace is in fact peace between allied democratic states, which have (unlike other alliances), not broken down into war between the allies. He regards this effect as the reality of the demcratic peace; ascribing the rest of it to chance. However, this does not explain why democratic alliances are different.

Christopher Layne (1994) analysed the crises and brinkmanship that took place between non-allied democratic great powers, during the relatively brief period when such existed. He found no evidence either of institutional or cultural constraints against war; indeed, there was popular sentiment in favor of war on both sides. Instead, in all cases, one side concluded that it could not afford to risk that war at that time, and made the necessary concessions. However, other researches have examined some of these crises and reached different conclusions, arguing that perceptions of democracy prevented escalation. Also, there are new explanations different from those that Layne criticzed, like the game-theoretic one discussed below. In addition, if the realist explanation were true of all democracies, the results of crises between them would largely depend on their relative strength. A more recent study (2001) denies this.

Jeanne Gowa (1999) has criticzed the theory. She finds that there were so few democracies before 1939 that the claims of the theory are not significant. The democratic peace since 1945 she finds significant, but largely explained by the external cause of the Cold War. One may claim that any apparent association between democracy and peace is an illusion, due in part to chance, and in part to peace being induced by other and transient causes. In particular, the presence of a common foe may has frequently induced states, which happen to be democracies, to ally. Joanne Gowa observes that much of the history of peace between democracies consists of Western democracies not going to war with each other while allied against the Soviet Union, and argues that this offers limited hope that non-allied democracies will remain at peace. This again overlaps with the third category above, since there is also an argument that the relative peace of the twenty-first century (so far), is due to the completion of decolonization. (John Mearsheimer offers a similar analysis of the Anglo-American peace before 1945, caused by the German threat.) David Spiro would reply that these stable alliances are the democratic peace; although Gowa denies that the Western powers are in any sense "natural" allies. Gowa explains the Cold War peace between the Western powers as arising from their natural interests, in the traditional realist mode; this does not explain, nor is it intended to, the low domestic violence in democracies.

Gowa's use of statistics has been criticized, with several other studies finding opposing results. Ray objects that the same arguments should show that the Communist bloc would be at peace within itself; and it was not. Again, there were several wars and conflicts within the Western Alliance, but in each case involving a non-democratic member of the Free World (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help), (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help).

Criticisms

There are at least five logically distinguishable classes of criticism. Note that they usually apply to no wars or few MIDs between democracies, not to little systematic violence in democracies.

  • That the researcher has not applied his criteria, for democracy or war or both, accurately to the historical record.
  • That the criteria are not reasonable. For example, critics may prefer that liberal democracy should exclude or include both Germany and the United Kingdom at the time of World War I, rather than count one as democratic and the other non-democratic, when they were quite similar societies. One should also recall that, before World War II, Adolf Hitler was democratically elected (a view rejected by William Allen), and so we cannot rely on democracy in itself to result in peace with other democracies. Democracy has meant different things at different times.
  • That the theory may not actually mean very much, because it has limited its data below the level of significance, or because it promises only a limited peace, involving only a small class of states; for example, democracies have fought many offensive colonial and imperialistic wars (c.f., above, that the idea of democracy has also changed over time). Setting aside the question of whether the democratic peace applies to these cases at all, the predictions of democratic peace theory may still be limited. No researcher denies that democracies have acted against one another by covert or non-military means. Even small military confrontations between democracies have happened.
  • That it is not democracy itself but some other external factor(s) which happened to be associated with democratic states that explain the peace.
  • Lastly, it has been argued that democratic peace theory is not really a theory but more of an observation that, historically speaking, democracies have been less likely to wage war amongst themselves. As such, this 'observation' does little to establish democratic peace as a stable referent within international relations.

Often, the same theory will be seen as vulnerable to several of these criticisms at the same time.

Claimed errors

Spiro (1994) have criticized the democratic peace theorists for errors of fact and method. His most serious crticism applies to the statistical methods which calculate an expected number of wars between pairs of democracies by calculating the whole number of pairs of states at war and then multiplying by the proportion of pairs of states which are both democracies. He argues that the whole number of belligerent pairs is inflated by counting relatively formal states of war: In the Austro-Prussian War of 1866, several lesser German principalities took part on both sides. The number of pairs here is vastly increased by counting all of these as at war with each other, even when their forces never met. Again, Belgium was formally at war with North Korea and China during the Korean War, although fewer Belgians were killed than by falling off ladders. Spiro also shows that both wars and democracies are so rare that a war between democracies is unlikely in most years, even before making these corrections. One complication is that few states have been democracies continuously for two centuries; which can be handled by weighting each pair of democracies by the number of years they have both been democratic. Another is how do you count wars? If years matter, do you weight a war that lasts ten years ten times as much as a war that lasts one; or do you count onsets of war, and count each of these as one war? If countries A, B, and C, go to war against the alliance of D and E, is that one war or six? Is it still six if C never meets E on the battlefield? Russet (1995) and Maoz (1997) responded to this, for example with different methodology.

Some democratic peace theorists have been criticzed for reclassifiying some conflitcs without pruning the whole list of formal wars similarly. Supporters and opponents of the democratic peace agree that this is bad statistics.

There are also some difficulties in the application of statistical methods to the problem, especially to question of causation.

Limited claims

Liberal states do conduct covert operations against each other; the covert nature of the operation, however, prevents the publicity otherwise characteristic of a free state from applying to the question..

Some democratic peace theorists require that the executive result from a substantively contested election. This may be a cautious definition: For example, the National Archives of the United States notes that "For all intents and purposes, George Washington was unopposed for election as President, both in 1789 and 1792". (Under the original provisions for the Electoral College, there was no distinction between votes for President and Vice-President: each elector was required to vote for two distinct candidates, with the runner-up to be Vice-President. Every elector cast one of his votes for Washington, John Adams received a majority of the other votes; there were several other candidates: so the election for Vice President was contested.) Theories that require an actual transfer of power between parties would exclude the administration of John Adams. While later view would appear to exclude much of the early United States from the list of democracies, this has not been a subject of controversy in the academic literature.

Many democratic peace theories do not count conflicts as wars which do not kill a thousand on the battlefield; thus not the bloodless Cod Wars. Theories with a time lmit do not forbid, and are not violated by, aggression by an established democracy against a new, nascent or incipient democracy.

Colonial wars and imperialism

One criticism against a general peacefulness for liberal democracies is that they were involved in more colonial and imperialistic wars than other states during the 1816-1945 period. On the other hand, this relation disappears if controlling for factors like power and number of colonies. Liberal democracies have less of these wars than other states after 1945. This might be related to changes in the perception of non-European peoples, as embodied in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.

Related to this is the human rights violations committed against native people, sometimes by liberal democracies. One response is that many of the worst crimes were committed by nondemocracies, like in the European colonies before the nineteenth century, in King Leopold II of Belgium's privately owned Congo Free State, and in Stalin's Soviet Union. England abolished slavery in British territory in 1833, immediately after the First Reform Bill had significantly increased democracy. (Of course, the abolition of the slave trade had been enacted under the Tories; and many DPTs would disclaim so undemocratic a state as Melbourne's England in other contexts.)

External causes

There has been a confluence of the old theory (dating back to Richard Cobden and Benjamin Constant) that Free Trade will produce and ensure peace, with the modern theory that trade will produce democracy, or at least spread it to the non-democratic trading partner, as argued by Houshang Amiramahdi and others. According to this, democracy and peace are indeed correlated, because they arise from a common cause.

Countercriticisms

File:DP BACKSIDE V 16.JPG
Charts arguing in favour of DPT by R. J. Rummel and others
High Resolution PDF
File:DP CHART V19.JPG
High resolution PDF

The theory is well-studied with more than a hundred researchers having published many more articles. Several peer-reviewed studies mention in their introduction that most people who undertake research into the theory accept it as an empirical fact, including several of those mentioned below.

Correlation is not causation. However, many studies, as those discussed in (Ray 1998), (Ray 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2005 (help), (Oneal & Russett 2004) harv error: no target: CITEREFOnealRussett2004 (help), supporting the theory have controlled for many possible alternative causes of the peace. Examples of factors controlled for are geographic distance, geographic contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic wealth and economic growth, power ratio, and political stability. Several studies have also controlled for the possibility of reverse causality from peace to democracy (Mousseau & Shi 1999) harv error: no target: CITEREFMousseauShi1999 (help),(Reiter 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFReiter2001 (help), (Reuveny & Li 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFReuvenyLi2003 (help).

Several studies and reviews argue that the Realist criticisms are flawed. This include the critical studies made by Layne, Spiro, Gowa, and Rosato mentioned above. The critical realist studies are argued to have methodological problems and be contradicted by others which are better made. (Gelpi & Griesdorf 2001) harv error: no target: CITEREFGelpiGriesdorf2001 (help), (Ray 2003) harv error: no target: CITEREFRay2003 (help), (Kinsella 2005), (Slantchev, Alexandrova & Gartzke 2005) harv error: no target: CITEREFSlantchevAlexandrovaGartzke2005 (help).

One study (Weart 1998) harv error: no target: CITEREFWeart1998 (help) finds and mentions several other studies finding that democracies conduct diplomacy differently and more conciliatory compared do nondemocracies.

The same study argues that the peacefulness appears and disappears rapidly when democracy appears and disappears. This makes it unlikely that variables that change more slowly are the explanation.

It has also been suggested that democracies rarely fight wars because war, or impending war, tends to destroy democracy; This argument depends only on the internal conditions of one state; it shouldn't matter whether the war is with a democracy or not. It is therefore a mechanism for the general, or monadic, peacefulness of democracies. Mousseau and Shi studied (1999) all states, inquiring whether the onset of war decreased democracy, either temporarily or permanently, and found most wars had no significant effect, but some did.

Wars tend very strongly to be between neighboring states. Gleditsch (1995) showed that the average distance between democracies is about 8000 miles, the same as the average distance between all states. He believes that the effect of distance in preventing war, modified by the democratic peace, explains the incidence of war as fully as it can be explained.

Regarding how significant the theory is, Rummel argues that the continuing increase in democracy worldwide will soon lead to an end to wars and democide, possibly around or even before the middle of this century. The Human Security Report, released in October 2005 by the Human Security Centre, documents the dramatic decline in warfare and civil wars since the end of the Cold War. However, it claims that the two main causes of this decline are the end of the Cold War itself and decolonization; but also claims that the three Kantian factors have contributed materially. The improvement in the peace of the world since the end of the Cold War has been tabulated here.

Harvard

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Template:Harvard reference

Notes

  1. Wilson, T. Woodrow: Message to Congress April 2, 1917
  2. Nixon, Richard M.: Televised speech, November 3, 1969
  3. Russett, Bruce M. Grasping the Democratic Peace : Principles for a Post-Cold War World. . p 4.
  4. See the bibliography of Rummel's website. Rummel is partisan, and the bibliography lacks some recent papers; but still one of the better introductions to the subject.
  5. See Kinsella 2005
  6. Clinton, Bill. "1994 State Of The Union Address". Retrieved 2006-01-22.
  7. "President and Prime Minister Blair Discussed Iraq, Middle East". Retrieved October 3. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |accessdate= (help); Unknown parameter |accessyear= ignored (|access-date= suggested) (help)
  8. See papers cited on p. 59 of Chan 1997.
  9. Nixon, Richard. (1992). Seize The Moment: America's Challenge In A One-Superpower World. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 0671743430.
  10. Owen 2005 Russet 2004
  11. Bruce Russett (2005). "Bushwhacking the Democratic Peace". International Studies Perspectives. 6 (4): 395. (Weart, 1998)
  12. Singer and Small 1976;
  13. See Russett 2003, p. 139 n. 3, and Gelditsch 1992.
  14. Doyle 1997, p. 272
  15. cited in Müller and Wolff 2004,
  16. Müller 2004
  17. Compare Alfred Thayer Mahan: The Influence of Sea Power on History, ad init..
  18. Rummel, Ray, and Weart; quotation from Rummel 1983. For this paper being exceptional, see Gleditsch 1992
  19. Bremer 1993, Pp.231-2, 246
  20. Bremer 1992, p.330
  21. Wayman 2002
  22. See chiefly Wayman 2002
  23. Doyle 1983, which was substantially republished in 1986, and again into Chapter 8 of Doyle 1997.
  24. See, among others, Russett & Oneal Triangulating Peace and the preliminary papers Russett et al. (1998); Oneal and Russett (1999)
  25. Alexander Wendt,Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge, 1999), 68 and chapter 5 passim.
  26. Quote from Rummel 1997
  27. Russett, 1993, p.15
  28. Ray 1998, Doyle 1997, Small and Singer 1976. Doyle also includes states where any man is in principle capable of attaining enough property and therefore vote; thus nineteenth-century Belgium, which enfranchised 2% of the whole population. Rummel (1997) and Weart (1998) require 2/3 of the adult males, which is in practice towards the high end of this range.
  29. Rummel 1997, Appendix 1.1, Babst 1964, 1972
  30. Doyle 1983, 1997. Quote from Doyle 1983 footnote 8, pp.216-7.
  31. Such additional data sources include the "Conflict Data Set". Stockholm International Peace Research Institute. Retrieved October 3. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |accessdate= (help); Unknown parameter |accessyear= ignored (|access-date= suggested) (help) and "Data". Peter D. Watson Center for Conflict and Cooperation. Retrieved October 3. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |accessdate= (help); Unknown parameter |accessyear= ignored (|access-date= suggested) (help)
  32. Gleditsch 1992
  33. Maoz 1997
  34. Doyle 1983a, on the Pequena War; cf. Russett 1993. For the other two: Rummel 1997 Appendix 1.1.
  35. Weart 1998
  36. Russett, Bruce. 1993. "Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World". Princeton: Princeton University Press; 50-51.
  37. Manicas, Peter. 1989. "War and Democracy". London: Basil Blackwell; 27.
  38. See for example Maoz 1997, p.164-5, which finds that there should have been 57 pair-years of democracies at war on expectation if there were no democratic peace; and in fact there was one
  39. Q Mearshimer 1990, p.50; the argument is supported at length by Spiro 1994, Layne 1994.
  40. Wayman 1998
  41. See lists in Doyle 1997, p.261 ff.; and Russett 1993
  42. Bremer 1993
  43. Wayman 2002
  44. See Wayman 2002; Russet and Oneal 2004; Beck et al. 2004. MIDs include the conflicts that precede a war; so the difference between MIDs and MICs nay be less than it appears.
  45. Müller and Wulf 2004
  46. Hensel et al. 2000.
  47. Less than $1400/head; see Mousseau et al. 2003, other papers by Mousseau, and Hegre 2003
  48. Rummel 2005, Ray 1998b, Weart 2000
  49. Matthew White's website on the democratic peace
  50. Rummel 1997, Ray 1998 book, Weart 2000
  51. Quotation from Ray 1998, p.114
  52. No true Scotsman fights a war Asia Times 31 January 2006, by their military affairs columnist
  53. Wayman 2002
  54. Naoz 1997, p.165
  55. Gleditsch 1995 and others
  56. Chan 1997
  57. Gleditsch 1995, Bremer 1992. The data set Bremer happened to be using showed one exception, the French-Thai War of 1940, which is spurious; it happened after the setting up of the Vichy régime. But he notes that other data sets show other isolated exceptions; and objects to changing just "deviant" false positives, rather than a systematic re-examination of all cases, which might find false negatives.
  58. Wayman 2002. Canada may also have declared war; the United States did not.
  59. Gowa 1999
  60. ftnote. 48.
  61. Electing to Fight: Why Emerging Democracies Go to War. Edward D. Mansfield and Jack Snyder. : MIT Press, 2005, as reviewed in Owen 2005
  62. Hensel et al. 2000 Ray 2003
  63. Levy, Jack S. 1989. "The Causes of War: A Review of Theories and Evidence" in Behavior, Society, and Nuclear War, Volume 1, edited by P. E. Tetlock, J. L. Husbands, R. Jervis, P. C. Stern and C. Tilly. New York: Oxford University Press.
  64. Russett, 1993, p.20. List of wars, p.17
  65. Doyle (1983); but his only exceptions are the Paquisha War and the Lebanese air force's intervention in the Six Day War, both of which he dismisses as technical. Cross reference to this note:
  66. Cederman 2001, p. 18-19, quoting Kant's Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose (1784)
  67. Müller and Wolff 1004
  68. Russett 1993, p. 5-8, 35, 59-62, 73-4
  69. For the greater tendency of the Powers to be involved in war, see Bremer 1992; the converse of this is that small-poweer status is an external cause of peace. Which side of the borderline Spain falls on depends on which edition of Ted Gurr's list you read..
  70. Kant, 1795, Cf. Reiss 1970:100
  71. Doyle 1983
  72. For a description, see Frost, Robert I. The northern wars : war, state and society in northeastern Europe, 1558-1721. Harlow, England;New York: Longman's. 2000. Especially Pp. 9-11, 114, 181, 323.
  73. Spiro 1994; Layne 1994. Democratic Peace – Warlike Democracies? A Social Constructivist Interpretation of the Liberal Argument
  74. Gelpi and Griesdorf 2001
  75. Gowa: Bullets and Ballots chapter VI; "A democratic peace does not exist in the pre-1914 world, and it cannot be extrapolated to the post-Cold War era", p.113. Mearsheimer 1990. For the other side, Spiro 1990 .
  76. Ray 1998 Several of the conflicts Ray cites are nowhere near a thousand battlefield deaths.
  77. Russett 2005
  78. Spiro 1994, Maoz 1997, Bruce Russett (October 1995). "The Democratic Peace: And Yet It Moves". International Security. 19(4): 164–75. {{cite journal}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |1= (help)CS1 maint: year (link)
  79. Bremer 1992, Gleditsch 1995; Gowa Ballots and Bullets.
  80. The difficulties and disputes involved are discussed at some length in Case studies and theory development in the social sciences by Alexander L. George and Andrew Bennett.
  81. Doyle 1997, p. 292
  82. http://www.archives.gov/federal-register/electoral-college/votes/1789_1821.html#1788
  83. Rummel attributing this view to Ray
  84. Ravlo and Glieditsch 2000
  85. See John Morley:Life of Richard Cobden and Francois Furet: Passing of an Illusion.
  86. Rummel, R.J. "Democratic Peace Bibliography Version 3.0". Freedom, Democracy, Peace; Power, Democide, and War. Retrieved October 2. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |accessdate= (help); Unknown parameter |accessyear= ignored (|access-date= suggested) (help)
  87. For example: , .
  88. Mousseau and Shi 1999
  89. Gleditsch 1995;
  90. Rummel's Power Kills website, viewed February 10, 2006
  91. Human Security Report 2005 p.148-150.
  92. See the Global Confilict Trends page of the Center for Systematic Peace.

References

External links

Supportive

Critical

See also

Categories: