Misplaced Pages

Material conditional: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 22:27, 9 November 2012 editGregbard (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers90,738 edits lnk← Previous edit Revision as of 22:50, 9 November 2012 edit undoGregbard (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers90,738 editsm hatNext edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{redirect|Logical conditional|other related meanings|Conditional statement}} {{redirect|Logical conditional|other related meanings|Conditional statement}}
:''For the rule of inference which is similar conceptually and in name see: ]''


'''material implication''' (also known as '''material conditional''' or '''material consequence''') is a ] often symbolized by a forward arrow "→", and often simply called "implication." A single ] formed from the connection of two, for instance "''p''→''q''" (called a ]) is typically ] as "If ''p'', then ''q''" or "''q'' if ''p''". The material implication between two sentences ''p'', ''q'' is typically symbolized as '''material implication''' (also known as '''material conditional''' or '''material consequence''') is a ] often symbolized by a forward arrow "→", and often simply called "implication." A single ] formed from the connection of two, for instance "''p''→''q''" (called a ]) is typically ] as "If ''p'', then ''q''" or "''q'' if ''p''". The material implication between two sentences ''p'', ''q'' is typically symbolized as

Revision as of 22:50, 9 November 2012

"Logical conditional" redirects here. For other related meanings, see Conditional statement.
For the rule of inference which is similar conceptually and in name see: Material implication (rule of inference)

material implication (also known as material conditional or material consequence) is a logical connective often symbolized by a forward arrow "→", and often simply called "implication." A single statement formed from the connection of two, for instance "pq" (called a conditional statement) is typically interpreted as "If p, then q" or "q if p". The material implication between two sentences p, q is typically symbolized as

  1. p q {\displaystyle p\rightarrow q} ;
  2. p q {\displaystyle p\supset q} ;
  3. p q {\displaystyle p\Rightarrow q} (Although this symbol is often used for logical consequence (i.e. logical implication) rather than for material implication.)

As placed within the material conditionals above, p is known as the antecedent, and q as the consequent, of the conditional. One can also use compounds as components, for example pq → (rs). There, the compound pq (short for "p and q") is the antecedent, and the compound rs is the consequent, of the larger conditional of which those compounds are components.

Implication is a form of logical consequence. For instance, in an argument such as "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew" the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew." is a material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son," not a formal consequence. The validity of the argument depends on the the meanings of the words "Fred," "Mike," "brother," "son," and "nephew," not the logical form of the argument.

In classical logic, the compound pq is equivalent to the negative compound: not (both p and not q). In everyday English, saying "It is false that if p then q" is not often taken as flatly equivalent to saying "p is true and q is false" but, when used within classical logic, those phrasings are taken as logically equivalent. (Other senses of English "if...then..." require other logical forms.)

Definitions of the material conditional

Logicians have many different views on the nature of material implication and approaches to explain its sense.

As a truth function

In classical logic, the compound pq is logically equivalent to the negative compound: not both p and not q. Thus the compound pq is false if and only if both p is true and q is false. By the same stroke, pq is true if and only if either p is false or q is true (or both). Thus → is a function from pairs of truth values of the components p, q to truth values of the compound pq, whose truth value is entirely a function of the truth values of the components. Hence, the compound pq is called truth-functional. The compound pq is logically equivalent also to ¬pq (either not p, or q (or both)), and to ¬q → ¬p (if not q then not p). But it is not equivalent to ¬p → ¬q, which is equivalent to qp.

Truth table

The truth table associated with the material conditional not p or q (symbolized as p → q) and the logical implication p implies q (symbolized as p → q, or Cpq) is as follows:

p q p → q
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T

As a formal connective

The material conditional can be considered as a symbol of a formal theory, taken as a set of sentences, satisfying all the classical inferences involving →, in particular the following characteristic rules:

  1. Modus ponens;
  2. Conditional proof;
  3. Classical contraposition;
  4. Classical reductio.

Unlike truth-functional one, this approach to logical connectives permits the examination of structurally identical propositional forms in various logical systems, where somewhat different properties may be demonstrated. For example, in intuitionistic logic which rejects proofs by contraposition as valid rules of inference, (p → q) ⇒ ¬p ∨ q is not a propositional theorem, but the material conditional is used to define negation.

Formal properties

When studying logic formally, the material conditional is distinguished from the semantic consequence relation A B {\displaystyle A\models B} , if every interpretation that makes A true also makes B true. However, there is a close relationship between the two in most logics, including classical logic. For example, the following principles hold:

  • If Γ ψ {\displaystyle \Gamma \models \psi } then φ 1 φ n ψ {\displaystyle \varnothing \models \varphi _{1}\land \dots \land \varphi _{n}\rightarrow \psi } for some φ 1 , , φ n Γ {\displaystyle \varphi _{1},\dots ,\varphi _{n}\in \Gamma } . (This is a particular form of the deduction theorem.)
  • The converse of the above
  • Both {\displaystyle \rightarrow } and {\displaystyle \models } are monotonic; i.e., if Γ ψ {\displaystyle \Gamma \models \psi } then Δ Γ ψ {\displaystyle \Delta \cup \Gamma \models \psi } , and if φ ψ {\displaystyle \varphi \rightarrow \psi } then ( φ α ) ψ {\displaystyle (\varphi \land \alpha )\rightarrow \psi } for any α, Δ. (In terms of structural rules, this is often referred to as weakening or thinning.)

These principles do not hold in all logics, however. Obviously they do not hold in non-monotonic logics, nor do they hold in relevance logics.

Other properties of implication (following expressions are always true, for any logical values of variables):

  • distributivity: ( s ( p q ) ) ( ( s p ) ( s q ) ) {\displaystyle (s\rightarrow (p\rightarrow q))\rightarrow ((s\rightarrow p)\rightarrow (s\rightarrow q))}
  • transitivity: ( a b ) ( ( b c ) ( a c ) ) {\displaystyle (a\rightarrow b)\rightarrow ((b\rightarrow c)\rightarrow (a\rightarrow c))}
  • truth preserving: The interpretation under which all variables are assigned a truth value of 'true' produces a truth value of 'true' as a result of material implication.
  • commutativity of antecedents: ( a ( b c ) ) ( b ( a c ) ) {\displaystyle (a\rightarrow (b\rightarrow c))\equiv (b\rightarrow (a\rightarrow c))}

Note that a ( b c ) {\displaystyle a\rightarrow (b\rightarrow c)} is logically equivalent to ( a b ) c {\displaystyle (a\land b)\rightarrow c} ; this property is sometimes called currying. Because of these properties, it is convenient to adopt a right-associative notation for → where a b c {\displaystyle a\rightarrow b\rightarrow c} denotes a ( b c ) {\displaystyle a\rightarrow (b\rightarrow c)} .

Note also that comparison of truth table shows that a b {\displaystyle a\rightarrow b} is equivalent to ¬ a b {\displaystyle \neg a\lor b} , and it is sometimes convenient to replace one by the other in proofs. Such a replacement can be viewed as a rule of inference.

Philosophical problems with material conditional

Outside of mathematics, it is a matter of some controversy as to whether the truth function for material implication provides an adequate treatment of ‘conditional statements in English’ (a sentence in the indicative mood with a conditional clause attached, i.e., an indicative conditional, or false-to-fact sentences in the subjunctive mood, i.e., a counterfactual conditional). That is to say, critics argue that in some non-mathematical cases, the truth value of a compound statement, "if p then q", is not adequately determined by the truth values of p and q. Examples of non-truth-functional statements include: "p because q", "p before q" and "it is possible that p". “ the sixteen possible truth-functions of A and B, is the only serious candidate. First, it is uncontroversial that when A is true and B is false, "If A, B" is false. A basic rule of inference is modus ponens: from "If A, B" and A, we can infer B. If it were possible to have A true, B false and "If A, B" true, this inference would be invalid. Second, it is uncontroversial that "If A, B" is sometimes true when A and B are respectively (true, true), or (false, true), or (false, false)… Non-truth-functional accounts agree that "If A, B" is false when A is true and B is false; and they agree that the conditional is sometimes true for the other three combinations of truth-values for the components; but they deny that the conditional is always true in each of these three cases. Some agree with the truth-functionalist that when A and B are both true, "If A, B" must be true. Some do not, demanding a further relation between the facts that A and that B.”

The truth-functional theory of the conditional was integral to Frege's new logic (1879). It was taken up enthusiastically by Russell (who called it "material implication"), Wittgenstein in the Tractatus, and the logical positivists, and it is now found in every logic text. It is the first theory of conditionals which students encounter. Typically, it does not strike students as obviously correct. It is logic's first surprise. Yet, as the textbooks testify, it does a creditable job in many circumstances. And it has many defenders. It is a strikingly simple theory: "If A, B" is false when A is true and B is false. In all other cases, "If A, B" is true. It is thus equivalent to "~(A&~B)" and to "~A or B". "AB" has, by stipulation, these truth conditions.

— Dorothy Edgington, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Conditionals”

The meaning of the material conditional can sometimes be used in the natural language English "if condition then consequence" construction (a kind of conditional sentence), where condition and consequence are to be filled with English sentences. However, this construction also implies a "reasonable" connection between the condition (protasis) and consequence (apodosis) (see Connexive logic).

There are various kinds of conditionals in English; e.g., there is the indicative conditional and the subjunctive or counterfactual conditional. The latter do not have the same truth conditions as the material conditional. For an overview of some the various analyses, formal and informal, of conditionals, see the "References" section below.

See also

Conditionals

Further reading

External links

References

  1. Logical consequence, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  2. Clarke, Matthew C. (March 1996). "A Comparison of Techniques for Introducing Material Implication". Cornell University. Retrieved March 4, 2012.
  3. ^ Edgington, Dorothy (2008). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Conditionals". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 ed.).
Common logical connectives
Philosophy portal
Categories: