Revision as of 12:01, 21 July 2006 edit62.6.123.33 (talk)No edit summary← Previous edit | Revision as of 12:51, 21 July 2006 edit undoLingeron (talk | contribs)461 edits reverted back to last edit by Vision ThingNext edit → | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
] used by anarcho-capitalists .]] | ] used by anarcho-capitalists .]] | ||
{{Libertarianism}} | {{Libertarianism}} | ||
'''Anarcho-capitalism''' is an ] ] based on the idea of ], and a prohibition against initiatory ] and ]. It sees the only just basis for ] as arising from ] norms and an unlimited right of ] between sovereign individuals |
'''Anarcho-capitalism''' is an ] ] based on the idea of ], and a prohibition against initiatory ] and ]. It sees the only just basis for ] as arising from ] norms and an unlimited right of ] between sovereign individuals. For anarcho-capitalists, property may only be transferred by trade, gift, or abandonment; confiscation is seen as an illegitimate method of acquiring property from others, whether performed by private individuals, groups, collectives, or the state. Anarcho-capitalists reject the state as an unjustified monopolist and systematic aggressor against sovereign individuals, and would replace it with cooperatives, neighborhood associations, private businesses and similar non-monopolistic organizations. They embrace a form of ] ] ], and believe that all goods and services should be supplied through voluntary mechanisms like the ]. Because of this embrace of capitalism, there is considerable tension between anarcho-capitalists and those ]s who see the ] as being just as essential to anarchist philosophy as rejection of the state. | ||
The first well-known version of anarcho-capitalism was developed by ] economist and ] ] in the mid-20th century, synthesizing elements from Austrian School ], ] and 19th century ]. While Rothbard bases his philosophy on ], others, such as ], take a pragmatic ] approach by arguing that anarcho-capitalism should be implemented because such a system would have consequences superior to alternatives. | The first well-known version of anarcho-capitalism was developed by ] economist and ] ] in the mid-20th century, synthesizing elements from Austrian School ], ] and 19th century ]. While Rothbard bases his philosophy on ], others, such as ], take a pragmatic ] approach by arguing that anarcho-capitalism should be implemented because such a system would have consequences superior to alternatives. | ||
Line 79: | Line 79: | ||
Like classical liberalism, and unlike ], anarcho-capitalism permits the use of force, as long as it is in the defense of persons or property. The permissible extent of this defensive use of force is an arguable point among anarcho-capitalists. | Like classical liberalism, and unlike ], anarcho-capitalism permits the use of force, as long as it is in the defense of persons or property. The permissible extent of this defensive use of force is an arguable point among anarcho-capitalists. | ||
Another controversial application of defensive aggression is the act of revolutionary violence against tyrannical regimes. Many anarcho-capitalists admire ] as the legitimate act of individuals working together to fight against ] restrictions of their liberties. In fact, according to Murray Rothbard, the American Revolutionary War was the only war involving the United States that could be justified.<ref>Rothbard, Murray N. (1973) ''Reason'' Feb 1973, Retrieved ] ]</ref> |
Another controversial application of defensive aggression is the act of revolutionary violence against tyrannical regimes. Many anarcho-capitalists admire ] as the legitimate act of individuals working together to fight against ] restrictions of their liberties. In fact, according to Murray Rothbard, the American Revolutionary War was the only war involving the United States that could be justified.<ref>Rothbard, Murray N. (1973) ''Reason'' Feb 1973, Retrieved ] ]</ref> | ||
==Conflicts within anarcho-capitalist theory== | ==Conflicts within anarcho-capitalist theory== | ||
Line 90: | Line 90: | ||
{{main|Anarchism and anarcho-capitalism}} | {{main|Anarchism and anarcho-capitalism}} | ||
Many anarchists strongly argue that anarcho-capitalism is not a form of anarchism, since they believe capitalism to be inherently authoritarian. For example, individualist anarchist Kevin Carson argues that capitalism cannot occur without state power being used to expropriate surplus value from the laborer. <ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2001) "The Iron Fist Behind the Invisible Hand" Red Lion Press</ref> |
Many anarchists strongly argue that anarcho-capitalism is not a form of anarchism, since they believe capitalism to be inherently authoritarian. For example, individualist anarchist Kevin Carson argues that capitalism cannot occur without state power being used to expropriate surplus value from the laborer. <ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2001) "The Iron Fist Behind the Invisible Hand" Red Lion Press</ref> Anarchists favor purely voluntary interaction and oppose coercive interactions, but anarcho-capitalists and their anarchist opponents disagree on whether certain actions are voluntary. | ||
According to , capitalism is an economic ] that includes its own ]. They place anarcho-capitalism outside of the anarchist movement, and into the classical liberal tradition "] without statism = liberalism." ] is sometimes regarded as a form of "liberal-anarchism."<ref>Weisbord, Albert (1937) from ''The Conquest of Power'' (1937)</ref> However, some prominent anarchists, such as Benjamin Tucker<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (1893) ''Instead of a Book'' </ref>, regarded individualist anarchism as a form of socialism. Many traditional anarchists espouse a form of ], which they put forth as one reason that ], ], and ] are ]. While classical capitalists such as ] also accepted the labor theory of value, most modern economists, including anarcho-capitalists, state that value is subjective and adhere to ]. | According to , capitalism is an economic ] that includes its own ]. They place anarcho-capitalism outside of the anarchist movement, and into the classical liberal tradition "] without statism = liberalism." ] is sometimes regarded as a form of "liberal-anarchism."<ref>Weisbord, Albert (1937) from ''The Conquest of Power'' (1937)</ref> However, some prominent anarchists, such as Benjamin Tucker<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (1893) ''Instead of a Book'' </ref>, regarded individualist anarchism as a form of socialism. Many traditional anarchists espouse a form of ], which they put forth as one reason that ], ], and ] are ]. While classical capitalists such as ] also accepted the labor theory of value, most modern economists, including anarcho-capitalists, state that value is subjective and adhere to ]. | ||
Several scholars see anarcho-capitalism as a form of anarchism<ref>Sylvan, Richard ''Anarchism''. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, editors Goodin, Robert E. and Pettit, Philip. Blackwell Publishing, 1995, p.231</ref><ref name=IA>1) Tormey, Simon. ''Anti-Capitalism'', One World, 2004. 2)Perlin, Terry M. ''Contemporary Anarchism'', Transaction Books, NJ 1979. 3) Raico, Ralph. ''Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th Century'', Ecole Polytechnique, Centre de Recherce en Epistemologie Appliquee, Unité associée au CNRS, 2004. 4) Levy, Carl. ''Anarchism'', MS Encarta Encyclopedia. 5) Heider, Ulrike. ''Anarchism:Left, Right, and Green'', City Lights, 1994. 6) Outhwaite, William. ''The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought'', 2002. 7) Bottomore, Tom. '' Dictionary of Marxist Thought'', 1991.</ref> but |
Several scholars see anarcho-capitalism as a form of anarchism<ref>Sylvan, Richard ''Anarchism''. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, editors Goodin, Robert E. and Pettit, Philip. Blackwell Publishing, 1995, p.231</ref><ref name=IA>1) Tormey, Simon. ''Anti-Capitalism'', One World, 2004. 2)Perlin, Terry M. ''Contemporary Anarchism'', Transaction Books, NJ 1979. 3) Raico, Ralph. ''Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th Century'', Ecole Polytechnique, Centre de Recherce en Epistemologie Appliquee, Unité associée au CNRS, 2004. 4) Levy, Carl. ''Anarchism'', MS Encarta Encyclopedia. 5) Heider, Ulrike. ''Anarchism:Left, Right, and Green'', City Lights, 1994. 6) Outhwaite, William. ''The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought'', 2002. 7) Bottomore, Tom. '' Dictionary of Marxist Thought'', 1991.</ref> but academic Barbara Goodwin put anarcho-capitalism closer to libertarianism rather than to other forms of anarchism.<ref>Goodwin, Barbara. '''Using Political Ideas''', p. 148.</ref> The divide between anarcho-capitalism and anti-capitalist anarchist traditions has been termed as ] versus right anarchism by some individuals, such as Ulrike Heider who placed anarcho-capitalism on the far right.<ref>Heider, Ulrike (1994) City Lights Books ISBN 0872862895 Retrieved ] ]</ref> | ||
==History and influences== | ==History and influences== | ||
Line 152: | Line 152: | ||
Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism fall into several categories: practical criticisms which claim that anarcho-capitalism is unworkable in practice; critiques which claim that capitalism requires a coercive state to exist and that a society can be anarchist or capitalist, but not both; general critiques of the morality of capitalism and liberalism which also apply to anarcho-capitalism; and a utilitarian critique which claims that anarcho-capitalism would not maximize utility. | Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism fall into several categories: practical criticisms which claim that anarcho-capitalism is unworkable in practice; critiques which claim that capitalism requires a coercive state to exist and that a society can be anarchist or capitalist, but not both; general critiques of the morality of capitalism and liberalism which also apply to anarcho-capitalism; and a utilitarian critique which claims that anarcho-capitalism would not maximize utility. | ||
Various minarchist liberatarians, including ], argue that in the absence of a state, an anarcho-capitalist society would degenerate into a "war of all against all" |
Various minarchist liberatarians, including ], argue that in the absence of a state, an anarcho-capitalist society would degenerate into a "war of all against all"; others argue that the ] makes provision of protection service in an anarcho-capitalist society impractical. | ||
Many anarchists and socialists argue that certain capitalist transactions are not voluntary, and maintaining the capitalist character of a society requires coercion incompatible with an anarchist society. Socialists and other anti-capitalists also argue that a capitalist society, anarchist or not, has severe moral and/or practical failings which render it undesirable. | Many anarchists and socialists argue that certain capitalist transactions are not voluntary, and maintaining the capitalist character of a society requires coercion incompatible with an anarchist society. Socialists and other anti-capitalists also argue that a capitalist society, anarchist or not, has severe moral and/or practical failings which render it undesirable. | ||
Line 167: | Line 167: | ||
*], '''' Radical classical liberalism | *], '''' Radical classical liberalism | ||
*Davidson & Rees-Mogg, ''The Sovereign Individual'' Historians look at technology & implications | *Davidson & Rees-Mogg, ''The Sovereign Individual'' Historians look at technology & implications | ||
*], '']'' Classic consequentialist |
*], '']'' Classic consequentialist defense of anarchism | ||
*], '''' | *], '''' | ||
*], '''' Oppenheimer's thesis applied to early US history | *], '''' Oppenheimer's thesis applied to early US history |
Revision as of 12:51, 21 July 2006
Anarcho-capitalism is an individualist philosophy based on the idea of individual sovereignty, and a prohibition against initiatory coercion and fraud. It sees the only just basis for law as arising from private property norms and an unlimited right of contract between sovereign individuals. For anarcho-capitalists, property may only be transferred by trade, gift, or abandonment; confiscation is seen as an illegitimate method of acquiring property from others, whether performed by private individuals, groups, collectives, or the state. Anarcho-capitalists reject the state as an unjustified monopolist and systematic aggressor against sovereign individuals, and would replace it with cooperatives, neighborhood associations, private businesses and similar non-monopolistic organizations. They embrace a form of anti-statist laissez-faire capitalism, and believe that all goods and services should be supplied through voluntary mechanisms like the free market. Because of this embrace of capitalism, there is considerable tension between anarcho-capitalists and those anarchists who see the rejection of capitalism as being just as essential to anarchist philosophy as rejection of the state.
The first well-known version of anarcho-capitalism was developed by Austrian School economist and libertarian Murray Rothbard in the mid-20th century, synthesizing elements from Austrian School economics, classical liberalism and 19th century American individualist anarchism. While Rothbard bases his philosophy on natural law, others, such as David Friedman, take a pragmatic consequentialist approach by arguing that anarcho-capitalism should be implemented because such a system would have consequences superior to alternatives.
Philosophy
The nonaggression axiom
The term anarcho-capitalism was most likely coined in the mid-1950s by the economist Murray Rothbard. Other terms sometimes used for this philosophy, though not necessarily outside of anarcho-capitalist circles, include:
|
Anarcho-capitalism, as formulated by Rothbard and others, holds strongly to the central libertarian nonaggression axiom:
- The basic axiom of libertarian political theory holds that every man is a self owner, having absolute jurisdiction over his own body. In effect, this means that no one else may justly invade, or aggress against, another's person. It follows then that each person justly owns whatever previously unowned resources he appropriates or "mixes his labor with." From these twin axioms — self-ownership and "homesteading" — stem the justification for the entire system of property rights titles in a free-market society. This system establishes the right of every man to his own person, the right of donation, of bequest (and, concomitantly, the right to receive the bequest or inheritance), and the right of contractual exchange of property titles.
In general, the nonaggression axiom can be said to be a prohibition against the initiation of force, or the threat of force, against persons (i.e., direct violence, assault, murder) or property (i.e., fraud, burglary, theft, taxation). The initiation of force is usually referred to as aggression or coercion. The difference between anarcho-capitalists and other libertarians is largely one of the degree to which they take this axiom. Minarchist libertarians, such as most people involved in Libertarian political parties, would retain the state in some smaller and less invasive form, retaining at the very least public police, courts and military; others, however, might give further allowance for other government programs. In contrast, anarcho-capitalists reject any level of state intervention, defining the state as a coercive monopoly and, as the only entity in human society that derives its income from legal aggression, an entity that inherently violates the central axiom of libertarianism. Some, such as Rothbard, accept the nonaggression axiom on an intrinsic moral or natural law basis. Others, such as Friedman, take a consequentialist or egoist approach; rather than maintaining that aggression is intrinsically immoral, they maintain that a law against aggression can only come about by contract between self-interested parties who agree to refrain from initiating coercion against each other. It is in terms of the non-aggression principle that Rothbard defined anarchism; he defined "anarchism as a system which provides no legal sanction for such aggression " and said that "what anarchism proposes to do, then, is to abolish the State, i.e. to abolish the regularized institution of aggressive coercion." In an interview with New Banner, Rothbard said that "capitalism is the fullest expression of anarchism, and anarchism is the fullest expression of capitalism."
Original appropriation
Central to anarcho-capitalism are the concepts of self-ownership and original appropriation:
Everyone is the proper owner of his own physical body as well as of all places and nature-given goods that he occupies and puts to use by means of his body, provided only that no one else has already occupied or used the same places and goods before him. This ownership of "originally appropriated" places and goods by a person implies his right to use and transform these places and goods in any way he sees fit, provided only that he does not change thereby uninvitedly the physical integrity of places and goods originally appropriated by another person. In particular, once a place or good has been first appropriated by, in John Locke's phrase, 'mixing one's labor' with it, ownership in such places and goods can be acquired only by means of a voluntary — contractual — transfer of its property title from a previous to a later owner.
Anarcho-capitalism uses the following terms in ways that may differ from common usage or various anarchist movements:
|
This is the root of anarcho-capitalist property rights, and where they differ from collectivist forms of anarchism. Original appropriation allows an individual to claim any "unused" property, including land, and by improving or otherwise using it, own it with the same absolute right as his own body. According to Rothbard, original appropriation of land is not legitimate by merely claiming it or building a fence around it; it is only by using land — by mixing one's labor with it — that original appropriation is legitimized: "Any attempt to claim a new resource that someone does not use would have to be considered invasive of the property right of whoever the first user will turn out to be." As a practical matter, in terms of the ownership of land, anarcho-capitalists recognize that there are few (if any) parcels of land left on Earth whose ownership was not at some point in time transferred as the result of coercion, usually through seizure by some form of state. However, unless records and titles exist to confirm the theft and the rightful individual owner most do not believe that this history de-legitimizes current ownerships which are based on consensual transactions.
By accepting an axiomatic definition of private property and property rights, anarcho-capitalists deny the legitimacy of a state on principle:
- "For, apart from ruling out as unjustified all activities such as murder, homicide, rape, trespass, robbery, burglary, theft, and fraud, the ethics of private property is also incompatible with the existence of a state defined as an agency that possesses a compulsory territorial monopoly of ultimate decision-making (jurisdiction) and/or the right to tax."
The contractual society
The society envisioned by anarcho-capitalists has been called the Contractual Society; " a society based purely on voluntary action, entirely unhampered by violence or threats of violence." Because this system relies on voluntary agreements (contracts) between individuals as the only legal framework, it is difficult to predict precisely what the particulars of this society would look like. Those particulars are disputed both among anarcho-capitalists and between them and their critics.
One particular ramification is that transfer of property and services must be voluntary on the part of both parties. No external entities can force an individual to accept or deny a particular transaction. An employer might offer insurance and death benefits to same-sex couples; another might refuse to recognize any union outside his or her own faith. Individuals would be free to enter into contractual agreements as they saw fit.
One social structure that is not permissible under anarcho-capitalism is one that attempts to claim greater sovereignty than the individuals that form it. The state is a prime example, but another is the modern corporation — defined as a legal entity that exists under a different legal code than individuals as a means to shelter the individuals who own and run the corporation from possible legal consequences of acts by the corporation. It is worth noting that Rothbard allows a narrower definition of a corporation: "Corporations are not at all monopolistic privileges; they are free associations of individuals pooling their capital. On the purely free market, such men would simply announce to their creditors that their liability is limited to the capital specifically invested in the corporation ." However, this is a very narrow definition that only shelters owners from debt by creditors that specifically agree to the arrangement; it also does not shelter other liability, such as from malfeasance or other wrongdoing.
There are limits to the right to contract under some interpretations of anarcho-capitalism. Rothbard himself asserts that the right to contract is based in inalienable human rights and therefore any contract that implicitly violates those rights can be voided at will, which would, for instance, prevent a person from permanently selling himself or herself into slavery. Other interpretations conclude that banning such contracts would in itself be an unacceptably invasive interference in the right to contract.
Private law and order
Morris and Linda Tannehill, in The Market for Liberty, support natural law as the basis of an anarcho-capitalist society but "object to any statutory law whatsoever. They assert that all one has to do is ask if one is aggressing against another in order to decide if an act is right or wrong." Murray Rothbard, on the other hand, while also supporting a natural prohibition on force and fraud, supports a commonly-agreed upon legal code. Unlike both the Tannehills and Rothbard, David Friedman proposes that "the systems of law would be produced for profit on the open market, just as books and bras are produced today. There could be competition among different brands of law, just as there is competition among different brands of cars."
Anarcho-capitalists only believe in collective defense of individual liberty (i.e., courts, military or police forces) insofar as such groups are formed and paid for on an explicitly voluntary basis. According to Molinari, "Under a regime of liberty, the natural organization of the security industry would not be different from that of other industries." Proponents point out that private systems of justice and defense already exist, naturally forming where the market is allowed to compensate for the failure of the state: private arbitration, security guards, neighborhood watch groups, and so on. These private courts and police are sometimes referred to generically as Private Defense Agencies (PDAs.)
The defense of those unable to pay for such protection might be financed by charitable organizations relying on voluntary donation rather than by state institutions relying on coercive taxation, or by cooperative self-help by groups of individuals.
Retributive justice, meaning retaliatory force, is often a component of the contracts imagined for an anarcho-capitalist society. Some believe prisons or indentured servitude would be justifiable institutions to deal with those who violate anarcho-capitalist property relations, while others believe exile or forced restitution are sufficient.
The use of force
Like classical liberalism, and unlike pacifism, anarcho-capitalism permits the use of force, as long as it is in the defense of persons or property. The permissible extent of this defensive use of force is an arguable point among anarcho-capitalists.
Another controversial application of defensive aggression is the act of revolutionary violence against tyrannical regimes. Many anarcho-capitalists admire the American Revolution as the legitimate act of individuals working together to fight against tyrannical restrictions of their liberties. In fact, according to Murray Rothbard, the American Revolutionary War was the only war involving the United States that could be justified.
Conflicts within anarcho-capitalist theory
There is dispute on whether anarcho-capitalism is properly justifiable on deontological or consequentialist grounds. Natural-law anarcho-capitalism (such as that advocated by Rothbard) holds that rights can be determined through natural law and that consequences are not relevant to their determination. Consequentialists such as Friedman disagree, maintaining that rights are merely human constructs that rational humans create through contract as a result of concluding what sort of system leads to the best consequences.
Friedman describes an economic approach to anarcho-capitalism. His description differs with Rothbard's because it does not use moral arguments — i.e., it does not appeal to a theory of natural rights to justify itself. In Friedman's work, the economic argument is sufficient to derive the principles of anarcho-capitalism. Private defense or protection agencies and courts not only defend legal rights but supply the actual content of these rights and all claims on the free market. People will have the law system they pay for, and because of economic efficiency considerations resulting from individuals' utility functions, such law will tend to be libertarian in nature but will differ from place to place and from agency to agency depending on the tastes of the people who buy the law. Also unlike other anarcho-capitalists, most notably Rothbard, Friedman has never tried to deny the theoretical cogency of the neoclassical literature on "market failure," nor has he been inclined to attack economic efficiency as a normative benchmark.
Anarchism and anarcho-capitalism
Anarchism | |||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Concepts |
| ||||||
Issues |
| ||||||
Schools of thought |
| ||||||
Types of federation | |||||||
Economics | |||||||
Culture |
| ||||||
History |
| ||||||
People |
| ||||||
Lists |
| ||||||
By region |
| ||||||
Related topics |
Nietzsche and Max Stirner | ||||||
|
Many anarchists strongly argue that anarcho-capitalism is not a form of anarchism, since they believe capitalism to be inherently authoritarian. For example, individualist anarchist Kevin Carson argues that capitalism cannot occur without state power being used to expropriate surplus value from the laborer. Anarchists favor purely voluntary interaction and oppose coercive interactions, but anarcho-capitalists and their anarchist opponents disagree on whether certain actions are voluntary.
According to The Anarchist International, capitalism is an economic plutocracy that includes its own hierarchy. They place anarcho-capitalism outside of the anarchist movement, and into the classical liberal tradition "Plutarchy without statism = liberalism." American individualist anarchism is sometimes regarded as a form of "liberal-anarchism." However, some prominent anarchists, such as Benjamin Tucker, regarded individualist anarchism as a form of socialism. Many traditional anarchists espouse a form of labor theory of value, which they put forth as one reason that profit, rent, and wage labour are exploitive. While classical capitalists such as Adam Smith also accepted the labor theory of value, most modern economists, including anarcho-capitalists, state that value is subjective and adhere to marginalism.
Several scholars see anarcho-capitalism as a form of anarchism but academic Barbara Goodwin put anarcho-capitalism closer to libertarianism rather than to other forms of anarchism. The divide between anarcho-capitalism and anti-capitalist anarchist traditions has been termed as left anarchism versus right anarchism by some individuals, such as Ulrike Heider who placed anarcho-capitalism on the far right.
History and influences
Liberalism
Main article: LiberalismClassical liberalism is the primary influence with the longest history on anarcho-capitalist theory. Classical liberals have had two main themes since John Locke first expounded the philosophy: the liberty of man, and limitations of state power. The liberty of man was expressed in terms of natural rights, while limiting the state was based (for Locke) on a consent theory.
In the 19th century, classical liberals led the attack against statism. One notable was Frederic Bastiat (The Law), who wrote, "The state is the great fiction by which everybody seeks to live at the expense of everybody else." Henry David Thoreau wrote, "I heartily accept the motto, 'That government is best which governs least'; and I should like to see it acted up to more rapidly and systematically. Carried out, it finally amounts to this, which also I believe, 'That government is best which governs not at all'; and when men are prepared for it, that will be the kind of government which they will have."
One of the first liberals to discuss the possibility of privatizing protection of individual liberty and property was France's Jakob Mauvillon in the 18th century. Later, in the 1840s, Julius Faucher and Gustave de Molinari advocated the same. Molinari, in his essay The Production of Security, argued, "No government should have the right to prevent another government from going into competition with it, or to require consumers of security to come exclusively to it for this commodity." Molinari and this new type of anti-state liberal grounded their reasoning on liberal ideals and classical economics. Historian Ralph Raico asserts what that these liberal philosophers "had come up with was a form of individualist anarchism, or, as it would be called today, anarcho-capitalism or market anarchism." Unlike the liberalism of Locke, which saw the state as evolving from society, the anti-state liberals saw a fundamental conflict between the voluntary interactions of people — society — and the institutions of force — the State. This society versus state idea was expressed in various ways: natural society vs. artificial society, liberty vs. authority, society of contract vs. society of authority, and industrial society vs. militant society, just to name a few. The anti-state liberal tradition in Europe and the United States continued after Molinari in the early writings of Herbert Spencer, as well as in thinkers such as Paul Émile de Puydt and Auberon Herbert.
Ulrike Heider, in discussing the "anarcho-capitalists family tree," notes Max Stirner as the "founder of individualist anarchism" and "ancestor of laissez-faire liberalism." According to Heider, Stirner wants to "abolish not only the state but also society as an institution responsible for its members" and "derives his identity solely from property" with the question of property to be resolved by a 'war of all against all'." Stirner argued against the existence of the state in a fundamentally anti-collectivist way, to be replaced by a "Union of Egoists" but was not more explicit than that in his book The Ego and Its Own published in 1844.
Later, in the early 20th century, the mantle of anti-state liberalism was taken by the "Old Right". These were minarchist, antiwar, anti-imperialist, and (later) anti-New Dealers. Some of the most notable members of the Old Right were Albert Jay Nock, Rose Wilder Lane, Isabel Paterson, Frank Chodorov, Garet Garrett, and H. L. Mencken. In the 1950s, the new "fusion conservatism", also called "cold war conservatism", took hold of the right wing in the U.S., stressing anti-communism. This induced the libertarian Old Right to split off from the right, and seek alliances with the (now left-wing) antiwar movement, and to start specifically libertarian organizations such as the (U.S.) Libertarian Party.
Individualist anarchism in the United States
Main article: Individualist anarchism in the United StatesAnarcho-capitalism is influenced by the work of the 19th-century American individualist anarchists, and is regarded as a form of individualist anarchism by several scholars. However, this claim is highly controversial, and many individualist anarchists believe that capitalism cannot exist in the absence of a state. Rothbard sought to meld the 19th-century individualist theory with the principles of Austrian economics: "There is, in the body of thought known as 'Austrian economics', a scientific explanation of the workings of the free market (and of the consequences of government intervention in that market) which individualist anarchists could easily incorporate into their political and social Weltanschauung" (Egalitarianism). The 19th-century individualist anarchists espoused a labor theory of value, while the anarcho-capitalists adhere to a subjective theory, leading to differences over the legitimacy of profit. Anarchist historian Peter Marshall believes that anarcho-capitalists selectively interpret individualist anarchists texts, overlooking egalitarian implications. For example, Tucker opposed vast concentrations of wealth, which he believed were made possible by government intervention and state protected monopolies. He believed the most dangerous state intervention was the protection of a "banking monopoly" which concentrated capital in the hands of the privileged elite. Though, he also argued that harmful monopolies that were created by government intervention could be maintained in the absence of government protection because of the accumulation of great wealth (see predatory pricing). Anarcho-capitalists also oppose governmental restrictions on banking. They, like all Austrian economists, believe that monopoly can only come about through government intervention. Individualists anarchists have long argued that monopoly on credit and land interferes with the functioning of a free market economy. Although anarcho-capitalists disagree on the critical topics of profit, social egalitarianism, and the proper scope of private property, both schools of thought agree on other issues. Of particular importance to anarcho-capitalists and the individualists are the ideas of "sovereignty of the individual", a market economy, and the opposition to collectivism. Like the individualists, anarcho-capitalists believe that land may be originally appropriated by, and only by, occupation or use; however, most individualists believe it must continually be in use to retain title. Notable 19th-century American individualist anarchists include Lysander Spooner and Benjamin Tucker.
The Austrian School
Main article: Austrian SchoolThe Austrian School of economics was founded with the publication of Carl Menger's 1871 book Principles of Economics. Members of this school approach economics as an a priori system like logic or mathematics, rather than as an empirical science like geology. It attempts to discover axioms of human action (called "praxeology" in the Austrian tradition) and make deductions therefrom. Some of these praxeological axioms are:
- Humans act purposefully.
- Humans prefer more of a good to less.
- Humans prefer to receive a good sooner rather than later.
- Each party to a trade benefits ex ante.
These are macro-level generalizations, or heuristics, which are true for the many, but not necessarily true for any particular person.
Even in the early days, Austrian economics was used as a theoretical weapon against socialism and statist socialist policy. Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, a colleague of Menger, wrote one of the first critiques of socialism ever written in his treatise The Exploitation Theory of Socialism-Communism. Later, Friedrich Hayek wrote The Road to Serfdom, asserting that a command economy destroys the information function of prices, and that authority over the economy leads to totalitarianism. Another very influential Austrian economist was Ludwig von Mises, author of the praxeological work Human Action.
Murray Rothbard, a student of Mises, is the man who attempted to meld Austrian economics with classical liberalism and individualist anarchism, and is credited with coining the term "anarcho-capitalism". He was probably the first to use "libertarian" in its current (U.S.) pro-capitalist sense. He was a trained economist, but also knowledgeable in history and political philosophy. When young, he considered himself part of the Old Right, an anti-statist and anti-interventionist branch of the U.S. Republican party. When interventionist cold warriors of the National Review, such as William Buckley, gained influence in the Republican party in the 1950s, Rothbard quit that group and formed an alliance with left-wing antiwar groups. Later, Rothbard was a founder of the U.S. Libertarian Party. In the late 1950s, Rothbard was briefly involved with Ayn Rand's Objectivism, but later had a falling out. Rothbard's books, such as Man, Economy, and State, Power and Market, The Ethics of Liberty, and For a New Liberty, are considered by some to be classics of natural law libertarian thought.
Anarcho-capitalism in the real world
Anarcho-capitalism is largely theoretical, and even sympathetic critics say that it is unlikely ever to be more than a utopian ideal. Despite this, some anarcho-capitalist philosophers point to actual societies to support their claim that stateless capitalism can function in practice.
According to David Friedman, "Medieval Icelandic institutions have several peculiar and interesting characteristics; they might almost have been invented by a mad economist to test the lengths to which market systems could supplant government in its most fundamental functions." While not asserting that it was an anarcho-capitalist system, he argues that the Icelandic Commonwealth between 930 and 1262 had "some features" of an anarcho-capitalist society--while there was a single legal system, enforcement of law was entirely private; and so provides some evidence of how such a society would function. "Even where the Icelandic legal system recognized an essentially "public" offense, it dealt with it by giving some individual (in some cases chosen by lot from those affected) the right to pursue the case and collect the resulting fine, thus fitting it into an essentially private system."
However, some disagree with this assessment, arguing that Medieval Iceland was a communal rather than individualist society - eople of a communitarian nature... have reason to be attracted ... The economy barely knew the existence of markets. Social relations preceded economic relations. and that when a free market finally did arise, that it was the cause of the end of the republic - "During the 12th century, wealth and power began to accumulate in the hands of a few chiefs, and by 1220, six prominent families ruled the entire country. It was the internecine power struggle among these families, shrewdly exploited by King Haakon IV of Norway, that finally brought the old republic to an end."
Criticisms of anarcho-capitalism
Main article: Criticisms of anarcho-capitalismCriticisms of anarcho-capitalism fall into several categories: practical criticisms which claim that anarcho-capitalism is unworkable in practice; critiques which claim that capitalism requires a coercive state to exist and that a society can be anarchist or capitalist, but not both; general critiques of the morality of capitalism and liberalism which also apply to anarcho-capitalism; and a utilitarian critique which claims that anarcho-capitalism would not maximize utility.
Various minarchist liberatarians, including Objectivists, argue that in the absence of a state, an anarcho-capitalist society would degenerate into a "war of all against all"; others argue that the free rider problem makes provision of protection service in an anarcho-capitalist society impractical.
Many anarchists and socialists argue that certain capitalist transactions are not voluntary, and maintaining the capitalist character of a society requires coercion incompatible with an anarchist society. Socialists and other anti-capitalists also argue that a capitalist society, anarchist or not, has severe moral and/or practical failings which render it undesirable.
Anarcho-capitalist literature
Main article: Anarcho-capitalist literatureNonfiction
The following is a partial list of notable nonfiction works discussing anarcho-capitalism.
- Murray Rothbard Father of modern anarcho-capitalism:
- Man, Economy, and State The ultimate Austrian economics book,
- Power and Market Classification of State economic interventions,
- The Ethics of Liberty Moral justification of a free society
- Frederic Bastiat, The Law Radical classical liberalism
- Davidson & Rees-Mogg, The Sovereign Individual Historians look at technology & implications
- David D. Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom Classic consequentialist defense of anarchism
- Auberon Herbert, The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State
- Albert Jay Nock, Our Enemy the State Oppenheimer's thesis applied to early US history
- Juan Lutero Madrigal, anarcho-capitalism: principles of civilization
- Franz Oppenheimer, The State Analysis of State; political means vs. economic means
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia Academic philosopher on libertarianism
- Herbert Spencer, Social Statics Includes the essay "The Right to Ignore the State"
- Morris & Linda Tannahill, The Market for Liberty Classic on PDAs (private defense agencies)
Fiction
Anarcho-capitalism has been examined in certain works of literature, particularly science fiction. an example being Robert A. Heinlein's 1966 novel The Moon Is a Harsh Mistress, where he explores what he terms "rational anarchism."
Notes
- Rothbard, Murray N. (1988) "What's Wrong with Liberty Poll; or, How I Became a Libertarian", Liberty, July 1988, p.53
- ^ Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2001)"Anarcho-Capitalism: An Annotated Bibliography" Retrieved 23 May 2005
- Rothbard, Murray N. (1982) "Law, Property Rights, and Air Pollution" Cato Journal 2, No. 1 (Spring 1982): pp. 55-99. Retrieved 20 May 2005
- Rothbard, Murray N. (1973) For a new Liberty Collier Books, A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc., New York: pp.24-25. Retrieved 20 May 2005
- ^ Rothbard, Murray N. (1982) The Ethics of Liberty Humanities Press ISBN 0814775063:p162 Retrieved 20 May 2005
- Rothbard, Murray N. (1975) Society Without A State (pdf) Libertarian Forum newsletter (January 1975)
- Exclusive Interview With Murray Rothbard The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian Journal (25 February 1972)
- ^ Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2002) "Rothbardian Ethics" Retrieved 23 May 2005
- ^ Rothbard, Murray N. (1962) Man, Economy & State with Power and Market Ludwig von Mises Institute ISBN 0945466307 ch2 Retrieved 19 May 2005
- Nozick, Robert (1973) Anarchy, State, and Utopia
- Brown, Susan Love, The Free Market as Salvation from Government: The Anarcho-Capitalist View, Meanings of the Market: The Free Market in Western Culture, edited by James G. Carrier, Berg/Oxford, 1997, p. 113.
- Friedman, David. The Machinery of Freedom. Second edition. La Salle, Ill, Open Court, pp. 116-117.
- ^ Molinari, Gustave de (1849) The Production of Security (trans. J. Huston McCulloch) Retrieved 15 July 2006
- ^ Friedman, David D. (1973) The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism Harper & Row ISBN 0060910100 ch29
- "For a New Liberty", by Murray N. Rothbard
- O'Keeffe, Matthew (1989) "Retribution versus Restitution" Legal Notes No.5, Libertarian Alliance ISBN 1870614224 Retrieved 19 May 2005
- Rothbard, Murray N. (1973) Interview Reason Feb 1973, Retrieved 10 August 2005
- Carson, Kevin A. (2001) "The Iron Fist Behind the Invisible Hand" Red Lion Press
- Weisbord, Albert (1937) American Liberal-Anarchism from The Conquest of Power (1937)
- Tucker, Benjamin (1893) Instead of a Book
- Sylvan, Richard Anarchism. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, editors Goodin, Robert E. and Pettit, Philip. Blackwell Publishing, 1995, p.231
- ^ 1) Tormey, Simon. Anti-Capitalism, One World, 2004. 2)Perlin, Terry M. Contemporary Anarchism, Transaction Books, NJ 1979. 3) Raico, Ralph. Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th Century, Ecole Polytechnique, Centre de Recherce en Epistemologie Appliquee, Unité associée au CNRS, 2004. 4) Levy, Carl. Anarchism, MS Encarta Encyclopedia. 5) Heider, Ulrike. Anarchism:Left, Right, and Green, City Lights, 1994. 6) Outhwaite, William. The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought, 2002. 7) Bottomore, Tom. Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 1991.
- Goodwin, Barbara. Using Political Ideas, p. 148.
- Heider, Ulrike (1994) Anarchism: Left, Right, and Green City Lights Books ISBN 0872862895 Retrieved 19 May 2005
- Thoreau, Henry David (1849) Civil Disobedience
- Raico, Ralph (2004) Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th Century Ecole Polytechnique, Centre de Recherce en Epistemologie Appliquee, Unité associée au CNRS
- Heider, Ulrike. Anarchism: Left, Right and Green, San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1994, pp. 95-96
- Peacott, Joe "Individualism and Inequality" Bad Press
- http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/dward/newrightanarchocap.html
- ^ Friedman, David D. (1979) Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case, Retrieved 12 August 2005
- William Ian Miller, "Bloodtaking and Peacemaking: Feud, Law and Society in Saga Iceland", p. 306
- Hallberg Hallmundsson, an article on Iceland in the "Encyclopaedia Americana"
References
- Benson, Bruce: The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without The State
- Hart, David M.: Gustave de Molinari and the Anti-Statist Liberal Tradition Retrieved 14 September 2005
- Hoppe, Hans-Hermann: A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism
- Hoppe, Hans-Hermann: Democracy: The God That Failed
- Rothbard, Murray: For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto
- Rothbard, Murray: The Ethics of Liberty
- Spooner, Lysander: (1867) No Treason: The Constitution of No Authority Retrieved 19 May 2005
- Tannehill, Linda and Morris: The Market For Liberty
- Tucker, Benjamin: (1888) State Socialism and Anarchism:How Far They Agree, and Wherein They Differ Liberty 5.16, no. 120 (10 March 1888), pp. 2-3.Retrieved 20 May 2005
- Tucker, Benjamin: (1926) Labor and its Pay Retrieved 20 May 2005
- Van Notten, Michael: The Law of the Somalis, 2005
See also
Books
- Murray Rothbard Father of modern anarcho-capitalism:
- Man, Economy, and State The ultimate Austrian economics book,
- Power and Market Classification of State economic interventions,
- The Ethics of Liberty Moral justification of a free society
- Frederic Bastiat, The Law Radical classical liberalism
- Davidson & Rees-Mogg, The Sovereign Individual Historians look at technology & implications
- David D. Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom Classic utilitarian defense of anarchism
- Auberon Herbert, The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State
- Albert Jay Nock, Our Enemy the State Oppenheimer's thesis applied to early US history
- Juan Lutero Madrigal, anarcho-capitalism: principles of civilization
- Franz Oppenheimer, The State Analysis of State; political means vs. economic means
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia Academic philosopher on libertarianism
- Herbert Spencer, Social Statics Includes the essay "The Right to Ignore the State"
- Morris & Linda Tannahill, The Market for Liberty Classic on PDAs (private defense agencies)
- Robert Paul Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism
- Anarcho-Capitalism: An Annotated Bibliography by Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Related subjects
- Anarcho-capitalist literature
- Anarcho-capitalist terminology and symbolism
- Classical liberalism
- Digital gold bug
- Crypto-anarchism
- Free market
- Kritarchy
- Liberalism
- Libertarianism
- Market liberalism
- Polycentric law
- Private currency
- Tax resistance
- Spencer Heath
General
External links
Anarcho-capitalist websites and articles
- Strike The Root is an anarcho-capitalist essays, news, and forum.
- anti-state.com, has one of the more active forums and infrequent theoretical and practical articles, and hosts Private Property Anarchists and Anarcho-Socialists: Can We Get Along? by Gene Callahan
- Anarcho-capitalist FAQ
- Simply Anarchy is an anarcho-capitalist website with articles, links and a forum
- The Molinari Institute offers online resources for those interested in exploring the ideas of Market Anarchism
- Ancapistan Network comes with an ancap start-up, articles and links
- Bertrand Lemennicier, a renowned French anarcho-capitalist economist
- Cuthhyra is a resource promoting anarcho-capitalism through essays, humour, quotes, links and more.
- Bryan Caplan's "Anarchism Theory FAQ" is written from the perspective of an anarcho-capitalist.
- LewRockwell.com is a widely read anarcho-capitalist news site with the slogal "anti-state, anti-war, pro-market."
- A Legacy of Liberty and For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto by Murray N. Rothbard
- "Jesus Is an Anarchist: A Free-Market, Libertarian Anarchist, That Is—Otherwise What Is Called an Anarcho-Capitalist," (PDF) James Redford, June 1, 2006; or in HTML:
- The American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not so Wild, Wild, West Anarcho-capitalism in the old "Wild West" in the U.S.
- The anarcho-capitalist political theory of Murray N. Rothbard in its historical and intellectual context by Roberta Modugno Crocetta
- Panarchy, another way of considering things that is considered by some ultimately equivalent to anarcho-capitalism.
- A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Anarchism from the viewpoint of an anarcho-capitalist
- Sovereign Life and Sovereign Individual at Sovereignlife.com
- Individualist Anarchist Society at UC Berkeley
- Anarcho-Capitalism Lifestyle guide for Anarcho-capitalists
- The liberal theory of power a solution to complete anarcho-capitalism
- Sumit Dahiya "The home of the Anti-Government Pro-Enterprise Movement of India"
- Freedomain Radio anarcho-capitalism podcast and message board
- On Peter Sabatini's "Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy" by Richard A. Gardner
- The Philosophy of Liberty (animated)
- Economic Means to Freedom - Part IV: 25 Anarcho-Capitalist Things You Can Do Now!, by Frederick Mann
Criticisms
- Section F - Is "anarcho"-capitalism a type of anarchism? - "An Anarchist FAQ" Version 11.4 Accessed March 2006
- An Anarchist critique of Anarcho-Statism by anarcho - from Infoshop.org
- The Anarchist International Website Retrieved 20 May 2005
- Anarcho-Capitalism vs. Individualist Anarchism
- Jeff Draughn's Between Anarchism and Libertarianism: Defining a New Movement is a contemporary social anarchist critique of anarcho-capitalism
- The "Critiques Of Libertarianism" website contains critiques of both libertarianism and anarcho-capitalism.
- Collection of critical articles
- Ecology or "anarcho" capitalism by Ian MacSaorsa
- Interview with Noam Chomsky in which he discusses anarcho-capitalism
- Anarcho-Hucksters
- The New Right and Anarcho-capitalism from Chapter 36 of "Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism" by Peter Marshall
- Peter Sabatini's Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy
Criticisms by other radical capitalists
- Robert J. Binidotto's The Contradiction in Anarchism
- Paul Birch's A Fatal Instability in Anarcho-Capitalism? and Anarcho-Capitalism Dissolves into City States
- Tony Hollick's Impossibility of anarcho-capitalism
- Capitalism.org's rejection of the anarchist title
- A short selection by Leonard Peikoff, Ayn Rand's self-proclaimed intellectual heir, concerning anarchism
- The Anarcho-Libertarian Utopia — A Critique by Drieu Godefridi (Hayek Institute)
Other
- American Anarchism 19th Century Individualist Anarchist influence on Libertarianism by Wendy McElroy
- American Liberal-Anarchism from The Conquest of Power, by Albert Weisbord