Revision as of 22:55, 7 September 2007 editCeoil (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, IP block exemptions, Pending changes reviewers171,987 editsm →Life: ce← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 06:58, 24 December 2024 edit undoSer Amantio di Nicolao (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Administrators6,252,162 edits Copying from Category:16th-century Italian historians to Category:Italian male non-fiction writers using Cat-a-lot | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Florentine statesman, diplomat, and political theorist (1469–1527)}} | |||
{{pp-semi-protected|small=yes}} | |||
{{ |
{{other uses|Machiavelli (disambiguation)|Macchiavelli (surname)}} | ||
{{Use dmy dates|date=June 2023}} | |||
{{Infobox philosopher | |||
{{Infobox_Philosopher | | |||
|region = ] | |||
|era = ] | |||
|image = Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli.jpg | |||
color = #B0C4DE | | |||
|caption = Portrait by ], {{circa|1550–1600}} | |||
image_name = Santi di Tito - Niccolo Machiavelli's portrait headcrop.jpg | | |||
|name = Niccolò Machiavelli | |||
image_caption = in the robes of a Florentine public official. | | |||
|birth_date = {{birth date|1469|5|3|df=y}} | |||
name = Niccolò Machiavelli | | |||
|birth_place = ], ] | |||
birth = ], ] (Florence)| | |||
|death_date = {{death date and age|1527|6|21|1469|5|3|df=y}} | |||
death = ], ] (Florence) | | |||
|death_place = Florence, Republic of Florence | |||
school_tradition = ], ], ] | | |||
|school_tradition = {{ubl|]|]}} | |||
main_interests = ], ], ] | | |||
|main_interests = ] and ], ], history | |||
|notable_works = {{ubl|'']''|'']''}} | |||
influenced = ], ], ]| | |||
|spouse = {{marriage|Marietta ]|1501}} | |||
] , ] | |||
|notable_ideas = Classical realism, '']'', ], ] | |||
|signature = Machiavelli Signature.svg | |||
}} | }} | ||
'''Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli''' (], ] – ], ]) was an ] ], ], ], and romantic comedic ]. He is a figure of the ] and a central figure of its political component, most widely known for his treatises on ] political theory ('']'') on the one hand and ] ('']'') on the other. | |||
'''Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli'''{{efn|{{IPAc-en|ˈ|n|ɪ|k|ə|l|əʊ|_|ˌ|m|æ|k|i|ə|ˈ|v|ɛ|l|i}} {{respell|NIK|ə|loh|_|MAK|ee|ə|VEL|ee}}, {{IPAc-en|USalso|-|_|ˌ|m|ɑː|k|-}} {{respell|-_|MAHK|-}};<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.ldoceonline.com/dictionary/niccolo-machiavelli|title=Machiavelli, Niccolò|work=]|publisher=]|accessdate=5 August 2023}}</ref><ref>{{Cite dictionary |url=http://www.lexico.com/en/definition/Machievelli,+Niccol%C3%B2 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220210021945/https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavelli,_niccolo?s=t |url-status=dead |archive-date=10 February 2022 |title=Machievelli, Niccolò |dictionary=] US English Dictionary |publisher=]}}</ref><ref>{{cite American Heritage Dictionary|Machiavelli|access-date=9 February 2022}}</ref> {{IPA|it|nikkoˈlɔ mmakjaˈvɛlli|lang}}; also ] in English as '''Nicholas Machiavel''' ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|m|æ|k|i|ə|v|ɛ|l}} {{respell|MAK|ee|ə|vel}}, {{IPAc-en|USalso|ˈ|m|ɑː|k|-}} {{respell|MAHK|-}}).}} (3 May 1469 – 21 June 1527) was a ]<ref>Dietz, Mary G.. Machiavelli, Niccolò (1469–1527), 1998, https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-S080-1. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis</ref><ref>Berridge, G.R., Lloyd, L. (2012). M. In: Barder, B., Pope, L.E., Rana, K.S. (eds) The Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Diplomacy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137017611_13</ref> diplomat, author, philosopher, and historian who lived during the ]. He is best known for his political treatise '']'' ({{lang|it|Il Principe}}), written around 1513 but not published until 1532, five years after his death.<ref>For example: {{cite web|url= https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title= Niccolo Machiavelli – Italian statesman and writer|date= 17 June 2023}} and {{Cite web|url= https://www.iep.utm.edu/machiave/|title= Niccolò Machiavelli |website= Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=1 November 2018}}</ref> He has often been called the father of modern ] and ].<ref>For example: {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1w5sCPpcDPMC&pg=PA65|title=Between Eternities: On the Tradition of Political Philosophy, Past, Present, and Future|last=Smith|first=Gregory B.|date=2008|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0739120774|page=65}}, {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2d4qgsSLZQgC&pg=PA29|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|date=2004|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0739106310|page=29}}, {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=W5m6lCFR53YC|title=What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies|last=Strauss|year=1988|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226777139|page=41}}</ref> | |||
==Life== | |||
].]] | |||
Machiavelli was born in ] village near of the city-state of ], Italy, in 1469, and was the second son of Bernardo di Nicolo Machiavelli, a lawyer, and of Bartolommea di Stefano Nelli. His education left him with a thorough knowledge of the Latin and Italian classics. Machiavelli was born into a tumultuous era, in which ]s were leading armies, and wealthy city-states of Italy were falling one after another into the hands of foreign powers—France, Spain and the ]. It was a time of constantly shifting alliances, ] who changed sides without warning, and governments rising and falling in the space of weeks. Perhaps most significantly during this erratic upheaval was the ] in 1527 by rampaging soldiers of the Holy Roman Empire, the first time that Rome had been sacked by a Germanic army in nearly twelve centuries. Rich cities such as Florence and Genoa suffered a similar fate during these years. | |||
For many years he served as a senior official in the ] with responsibilities in diplomatic and military affairs. He wrote comedies, carnival songs, and poetry. His personal correspondence is also important to historians and scholars of Italian correspondence.<ref>{{harvnb|Najemy|1993|p=missing}}</ref> He worked as ] to the second ] of the Republic of Florence from 1498 to 1512, when the ] were out of power. | |||
He entered government service as a clerk/ambassador in 1494; that same year, Florence expelled the ] family, who had ruled the city for nearly sixty years, and restored the ]. Machiavelli was named as a member of the Council responsible for diplomatic negotiations and military matters. From 1499 to 1512, he was sent on a number of diplomatic missions to the court of ] in France, ] of Aragón, and the Papacy in Rome. From 1502 to 1503, he was a witness to the effective statebuilding methods of the soldier/churchman ], an immensely capable general and statesman who was at that time engaged in enlarging his territories in central Italy through a mixture of audacity, prudence, self-reliance, firmness and, not infrequently, cruelty. | |||
After his death Machiavelli's name came ] of the sort he advised most famously in his work, ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|access-date=8 August 2019}}</ref> He claimed that his experience and reading of history showed him that politics has always involved deception, treachery, and crime.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/mythofstate0000cass|url-access=registration|quote=ernst cassirer the myth of the state.|title=The Myth of the State|last=Cassirer|first=Ernst|date=1946|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=978-0300000368|pages=–145}}</ref> He advised rulers to engage in evil when political necessity requires it, and argued specifically that successful reformers of states should not be blamed for killing other leaders who could block change.<ref>For example, ''The Prince'' chap. 15, and ''The Discourses'' Book I, chapter 9</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E7mScxst9UoC&q=history%20of%20political%20philosophy&pg=PT315|title=History of Political Philosophy|last1=Strauss|first1=Leo|last2=Cropsey|first2=Joseph|year= 2012|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226924717|page=297}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=machiavelli's%20virtue&pg=PA178|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year= 1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503721|page=178}}</ref> Machiavelli's ''Prince'' has been surrounded by controversy since it was published. Some consider it to be a straightforward description of political reality. Others view ''The Prince'' as a manual, teaching would-be tyrants how they should seize and maintain power.<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Giorgini |first1= Giovanni |title= Five Hundred Years of Italian Scholarship on Machiavelli's Prince |journal= Review of Politics |date= 2013 |volume= 75 |issue= 4 |pages= 625–640|doi= 10.1017/S0034670513000624|s2cid= 146970196 | issn=0034-6705}}</ref> Even into recent times, some scholars, such as ], have restated the traditional opinion that Machiavelli was a "teacher of evil".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Strauss|first=Leo|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oi2GDwAAQBAJ&q=thoughts+on+Machiavelli|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|year=2014|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226230979|language=en|page=9}}</ref> | |||
From 1503 to 1506, Machiavelli was responsible for the Florentine militia including the defense of the city. He distrusted mercenaries (a philosophy expounded at length in the ''Discorsi'' and in ''Il Principe'') and much preferred a citizen militia. In August 1512, following a tangled series of battles, treaties, and alliances, the Medici with the help of ] regained power in Florence and the republic was dissolved. Machiavelli, having played a significant role in the republic's anti-Medici government, was removed from office and in 1513 he was accused of conspiracy and arrested. Although tortured on the rack he denied his involvement and was eventually released. He retired to his estate at ] near Florence and began writing the treatises that would ensure his place in the development of political philosophy. | |||
Even though Machiavelli has become most famous for his work on principalities, scholars also give attention to the exhortations in his other works of political philosophy. While less well known than ''The Prince'', the '']'' (composed {{circa|1517}}) has been said to have paved the way for modern ].<ref>Harvey Mansfield and Nathan Tarcov, "Introduction to the Discourses". In their translation of the ''Discourses on Livy''</ref> His works were a major influence on ] authors who revived interest in ], such as ] and ].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Theodosiadis|first=Michail|date=June–August 2021|title=From Hobbes and Locke to Machiavelli's virtù in the political context of meliorism: popular eucosmia and the value of moral memory|journal=Polis Revista|volume=11|pages=25–60}}</ref> Machiavelli's political realism has continued to influence generations of academics and politicians, including ], and his approach has been compared to the '']'' of figures such as ].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Pflanze |first=Otto |date=1958 |title=Bismarck's "Realpolitik" |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1404857 |journal=The Review of Politics |volume=20 |issue=4 |pages=492–514 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500034185 |jstor=1404857 |s2cid=144663704 |issn=0034-6705}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Arendt |first=Hannah |title=The Human Condition |publisher=Chicago University Press |year=1988 |location=Chicago |page=77}}</ref> | |||
In a famous letter to his friend ], Machiavelli described how he spent his days in exile: | |||
] in ].]] | |||
<blockquote> | |||
When evening comes, I return home and go to my study. On the threshold I strip naked, taking off my muddy, sweaty workday clothes, and put on the robes of court and palace, and in this graver dress I enter the courts of the ancients and am welcomed by them, and there I taste the food that alone is mine, and for which I was born. And there I make bold to speak to them and ask the motives of their actions, and they, in their humanity reply to me. And for the space of four hours I forget the world, remember no vexation, fear poverty no more, tremble no more at death; I pass indeed into their world.<ref>''The Literary Works of Machiavelli'', trans. J.R. Hale. (Oxford: 1961), p. 139.</ref> | |||
</blockquote> | |||
== Life == | |||
Much has been made of the notion of two Machiavellis: one of ''The Prince'', one of the ''Discorsi''. But Machiavelli himself cut through the alleged confusion when he identified a unifying theme: | |||
{{For timeline|Timeline of Niccolò Machiavelli}} | |||
]]] | |||
<blockquote> | |||
Machiavelli was born in ], Italy, the third child and first son of attorney ] and his wife, Bartolomea di Stefano Nelli, on 3 May 1469.<ref>{{Harvtxt|de Grazia|1989}}</ref> The Machiavelli family is believed to be descended from the old ] and to have produced thirteen Florentine ],<ref>{{CathEncy|wstitle=Niccolò Machiavelli}}</ref> one of the offices of a group of nine citizens selected by drawing lots every two months and who formed the government, or ]; he was never, though, a full citizen of Florence because of the nature of Florentine citizenship in that time even under the republican regime. Machiavelli married Marietta ] in 1501. They had seven children, five sons and two daughters: Primerana, Bernardo, Lodovico, Guido, {{interlanguage link|lt=Piero|Piero Machiavelli|it}}, Baccina and Totto.<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Guarini|1999|p=21}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |title=Machiavèlli, Niccolò nell'Enciclopedia Treccani |url=https://www.treccani.it/enciclopedia/niccolo-machiavelli |access-date=2023-07-11 |website=www.treccani.it |language=it-IT}}</ref> | |||
All cities that ever at any time have been ruled by an absolute prince, by aristocrats or by the people, have had for their protection force combined with prudence, because the latter is not enough alone, and the first either does not produce things, or when they are produced, does not maintain them. Force and prudence, then, are the might of all the governments that ever have been or will be in the world.<ref>"Words to be Spoken on the Law for Appropriating Money", in ''Chief Works and Others'' , trans. Allan H. Gilbert, 3 vols. (Durham, NC: Duke Univ. Press, 1965), v. III, 1439.</ref> | |||
</blockquote> | |||
Machiavelli was born in a tumultuous era. The Italian ]s, and the families and individuals who ran them could rise and fall suddenly, as popes and the kings of France, Spain, and the ] waged acquisitive wars for regional influence and control. Political-military alliances continually changed, featuring ] (mercenary leaders), who changed sides without warning, and the rise and fall of many short-lived governments.<ref>Maurizio Viroli, ''Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli'' (2000), ch 1</ref> | |||
Machiavelli died in San Casciano, a few miles outside of Florence, in 1527. His resting place is unknown; however a ] in his honor was placed at the ] in Florence. | |||
Machiavelli was taught grammar, rhetoric, and Latin by his teacher, Paolo da Ronciglione.<ref>{{Citation|url=https://totallyhistory.com/niccolo-machiavelli/|title=Niccolo Machiavelli Biography – Life of Florentine Republic Official|date=13 December 2013}}</ref> It is unknown whether Machiavelli knew Greek; Florence was at the time one of the centres of Greek scholarship in Europe.<ref>{{cite web |title=Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) |url=https://iep.utm.edu/machiave/ |website=IEP |publisher=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> In 1494 Florence restored ], expelling the ] family that had ruled Florence for some sixty years. Shortly after the execution of ], Machiavelli was appointed to an office of the second chancery, a medieval writing office that put Machiavelli in charge of the production of official Florentine government documents.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QMasak4LLcQC&pg=PT28|title=The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli|last=Ridolfi|first=Roberto|year=2013|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1135026615|page=28|language=en}}</ref> Shortly thereafter, he was also made the secretary of the ''Dieci di Libertà e Pace''. | |||
==Works== | |||
===''Il Principe''=== | |||
{{main|The Prince}} | |||
].]] | |||
Machiavelli's best known work is ''The Prince'', in which he describes the arts by which a Prince (a ruler) can retain control of his realm. He focuses primarily on what he calls the ''principe nuovo'' or "new prince", under the assumption that a hereditary prince has an easier task since the people are accustomed to him. All a hereditary prince needs to do is carefully maintain the institutions that the people are used to; a new prince has a much more difficult task since he must stabilize his newfound power and build a structure that will endure. This task requires the Prince to be publicly above reproach but privately may require him to do things of an evil nature in order to achieve the greater good. | |||
In the first decade of the sixteenth century, he carried out several diplomatic missions, most notably to the papacy in Rome. Florence sent him to ] to pacify the leaders of two opposing factions which had broken into riots in 1501 and 1502; when this failed, the leaders were banished from the city, a strategy which Machiavelli had favoured from the outset.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=136|loc=notes}} From 1502 to 1503, he witnessed the brutal reality of the state-building methods of ] (1475–1507) and his father, ], who were then engaged in the process of trying to bring a large part of central Italy under their possession.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli {{!}} Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts|website=Encyclopædia Britannica|language=en|access-date=28 July 2019}}</ref> The pretext of defending Church interests was used as a partial justification by the Borgias. Other excursions to the court of ] and the Spanish court influenced his writings such as '']''. | |||
The Prince is different from other books about creating and controlling principalities because it doesn't tell the reader what an ideal prince or principality is. Machiavelli explains through examples which princes are the most successful in obtaining and maintaining power. He draws his examples from personal observations made while he was on diplomatic missions for Florence and from his readings in ancient history. His writing has the mark of the Renaissance upon it because he sprinkles his text with Latin phrases and many examples are drawn from Classical sources. | |||
At the start of the 16th century, Machiavelli conceived of a militia for Florence, and he then began recruiting and creating it.<ref name="Viroli 81–86">{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9hIPlryeSTQC&pg=PA105|title=Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|year= 2002|publisher=Macmillan|isbn=978-0374528003|pages= 81–86}}</ref> He distrusted mercenaries (a distrust that he explained in his official reports and then later in his theoretical works for their unpatriotic and uninvested nature in the war that makes their allegiance fickle and often unreliable when most needed),<ref>This point is made especially in ''The Prince'', Chap XII</ref> and instead staffed his army with citizens, a policy that yielded some positive results. By February 1506 he was able to have four hundred farmers marching on parade, suited (including iron breastplates), and armed with lances and small firearms.<ref name="Viroli 81–86"/> Under his command, Florentine citizen-soldiers conquered ] in 1509.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9hIPlryeSTQC&pg=PA105|title=Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|year= 2002|publisher=Macmillan|isbn=978-0374528003|page=105}}</ref> | |||
A careless reading of ''The Prince '' could easily lead one to believe that its central argument is "]" - which is a ] philosophical view ("telos" is Greek for ends) - that any evil action can be justified if it is done for a good purpose. This is a limited interpretation, however, because Machiavelli placed a number of restrictions on evil actions. First, he specified that the only acceptable end was the stabilization and health of the state; individual power ''for its own sake'' is not an acceptable end and does not justify evil actions. Second, Machiavelli does not dispense entirely with morality nor advocate wholesale selfishness or degeneracy. Instead he clearly lays out his definition of, for example, the criteria for acceptable cruel actions (it must be swift, effective, and short-lived). Notwithstanding the mitigating themes in ''The Prince'', the Catholic Church put the work in its ] and it was viewed in a negative light by many Humanists such as ]. | |||
] in Florence]] | |||
The primary contribution of "The Prince" to the history of political thought is its fundamental break between ] and ]. While Machiavelli emphasized the need for morality, the sole motivation of the prince ought to be the use of good and evil solely as instrumental means rather than ends in themselves. A wise prince is one who properly exercises this proper balance. ] is a guiding thread through which Machiavelli bases his philosophy. The Prince should be read strictly as a guidebook on getting to and preserving power. In contrast with ] and ], the ideal society is not the aim. In fact, Machiavelli emphasizes the need for the exercise of brute power where necessary and rewards, patron-clientalism etc. to preserve the status quo. Machiavelli's assumption, that human nature is fundamentally flawed, is also reflected in the need for brute force to attain practical ends. Complete trust and faith in one's subjects is not sustainable. | |||
Machiavelli's success was short-lived. In August 1512, the Medici, backed by ], used Spanish troops to defeat the Florentines at ].<ref>Many historians have argued that this was due to ]'s unwillingness to compromise with the Medici, who were holding Prato under siege.</ref> In the wake of the siege, ] resigned as Florentine head of state and fled into exile. The experience would, like Machiavelli's time in foreign courts and with the Borgia, heavily influence his political writings. The Florentine city-state and the republic were dissolved, with Machiavelli then being removed from office and banished from the city for a year.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} In 1513, the Medici accused him of conspiracy against them and had him imprisoned.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Skinner |first=Quentin |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kiYz6d278IC&q=quentin%20skinner%20machiavelli&pg=PT36 |title=Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2000 |isbn=978-0191540349 |publication-place=Oxford, England |page=36 |language=en}}</ref> Despite being subjected to torture{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} ("]", in which the prisoner is hanged from his bound wrists from the back, forcing the arms to bear the body's weight and dislocating the shoulders), he denied involvement and was released after three weeks. | |||
The term "Machiavellian" was adopted by some of Machiavelli's contemporaries, often used in the introductions of political tracts of the sixteenth century that offered more 'just' reasons of state, most notably those of ] and ]. The pejorative term '''Machiavellian''' as it is used today (or '''anti-Machiavellism''' as it was used from the sixteenth century) is thus a misnomer, as it describes one who deceives and manipulates others for gain; whether the gain is personal or not is of no relevance, only that any actions taken are only important insofar as they affect the results. It fails to include some of the more moderating themes found in Machiavelli's works and the name is now associated with the extreme viewpoint.<ref>And in at least one scholar's assessment, ''mistakenly'' so in the extreme. Writes Anthony Parel: "The authentic Machiavelli is one who subordinates personal interests for the common good… . If one is to speak of a Machiavellian personality one should mention ] and ] (to use own examples)." For more on the three sources of historical anti-Machiavellism, see '''Further Reading''', Parel, pp. 14-24.</ref> | |||
Machiavelli then retired to his farm estate at ], near ], where he devoted himself to studying and writing political treatises. During this period, he represented the Florentine Republic on diplomatic visits to France, Germany, and elsewhere in Italy.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} Despairing of the opportunity to remain directly involved in political matters, after a time he began to participate in intellectual groups in Florence and wrote several plays that (unlike his works on political theory) were both popular and widely known in his lifetime. Politics remained his main passion, and to satisfy this interest, he maintained a well-known correspondence with more politically connected friends, attempting to become involved once again in political life.<ref>Niccolò Machiavelli (1996), ''Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence'', Northern Illinois University Press, translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.</ref> In a letter to ], he described his experience: | |||
=== ''Discorsi'' === | |||
{{main|Discourses on Livy}} | |||
If ''The Prince'' was Machiavelli's textbook on a monarchy, his ''Discourse on the First Ten Books of Titus Livy'' (which comprise the early history of Rome) is a paean to the republic. The ''Discorsi'' constitute a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured, including the concept of checks and balances, the strength of a tripartite structure and the superiority of a republic over a principality. Its lessons are as relevant today as they were six centuries ago and clear applications of his practical political philosophy can be found in the governments of many democracies today. | |||
<blockquote>When evening comes, I go back home, and go to my study. On the threshold, I take off my work clothes, covered in mud and filth, and I put on the clothes an ambassador would wear. Decently dressed, I enter the ancient courts of rulers who have long since died. There, I am warmly welcomed, and I feed on the only food I find nourishing and was born to savour. I am not ashamed to talk to them and ask them to explain their actions and they, out of kindness, answer me. Four hours go by without my feeling any anxiety. I forget every worry. I am no longer afraid of poverty or frightened of death. I live entirely through them.<ref>Joshua Kaplan, "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance," ''The Modern Scholar'' (14 lectures in the series; lecture #7 / disc 4), 2005.</ref></blockquote> | |||
Take for example the following citations from "The Discourses": | |||
Machiavelli died on 21 June 1527 from a stomach ailment<ref>{{Cite web |title=Washingtonpost.com: Horizon Section |url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-srv/national/horizon/jan99/morality.htm |access-date=2023-11-03 |website=www.washingtonpost.com}}</ref> at the age of 58 after receiving his ].<ref>"Even such men as Malatesta and Machiavelli, after spending their lives in estrangement from the Church, sought on their deathbeds her assistance and consolations. Both made good confessions and received the Holy Viaticum." – Ludwig von Pastor, , Vol. 5, p. 137.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Black |first1=Robert |title=Machiavelli |year= 2013 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1317699583 |page=283 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=C54lAgAAQBAJ |language=en}}</ref> He was buried at the ] in Florence. In 1789 ], and ], initiated the construction of a monument on Machiavelli's tomb. It was sculpted by ], with an epitaph by Doctor Ferroni inscribed on it.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Sil |first1=Narasingha Prosad |title=Kauṭilya's Arthaśāstra: A Comparative Study |date=1985 |publisher=Academic Publishers Calcutta|page=217 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=A2_9tHqptIMC|language=en}}</ref>{{efn|The Latin legend reads: <small>TANTO NOMINI NULLUM PAR ELOGIUM</small> ("So great a name (has) no adequate praise" or "No ] (would be) a match for such a great name" or "There is no praise equal to so great a name.")}} | |||
* "In fact, when there is combined under the same constitution a prince, a nobility, and the power of the people, then these three powers will watch and keep each other reciprocally in check." Book I, Chapter II | |||
* "Doubtless these means are cruel and destructive of all civilized life, and neither Christian nor even human, and should be avoided by every one. In fact, the life of a private citizen would be preferable to that of a king at the expense of the ruin of so many human beings." Book I, Chapter XXVI | |||
* "Now in a well-ordered republic it should never be necessary to resort to extra-constitutional measures...." Book I, Chapter XXXIV | |||
* "...the governments of the people are better than those of princes." Book I, Chapter LVIII | |||
* "...if we compare the faults of a people with those of princes, as well as their respective good qualities, we shall find the people vastly superior in all that is good and glorious." Book I, Chapter LVIII | |||
* "For government consists mainly in so keeping your subjects that they shall be neither able nor disposed to injure you...." Book II, Chapter XXIII | |||
* "...no prince is ever benefited by making himself hated." Book III, Chapter XIX | |||
* "Let not princes complain of the faults committed by the people subjected to their authority, for they result entirely from their own negligence or bad example." Book III, Chapter XXIX | |||
(SOURCE: The Modern Library, New York, 1950, translated by Christian E. Detmold) | |||
==Major works== | |||
Another way of thinking about the two books is that ''The Prince'' was written hastily, in an attempt to secure a job with the new Medici rulers, whereas ''The Discourses'' constitute Machiavelli's serious political tract. In this the two books might reasonably be compared to two of ]'s works: the ] was written in a hurry to provide direction in the 1848 uprisings, while ] is Marx's real political thesis. | |||
===''The Prince''=== | |||
{{Main|The Prince}} | |||
], to whom the final version of ''The Prince'' was dedicated]] | |||
Machiavelli's best-known book ''Il Principe'' contains several maxims concerning politics. Instead of the more traditional target audience of a hereditary prince, it concentrates on the possibility of a "new prince". To retain power, the hereditary prince must carefully balance the interests of a variety of institutions to which the people are accustomed.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Zuckert |first=Catherine H. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yZUtDwAAQBAJ&q=catherine+zuckert+machiavelli |title=Machiavelli's Politics |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=2017 |isbn=978-0226434803}}</ref> By contrast, a new prince has the more difficult task in ruling: He must first stabilise his newfound power in order to build an enduring political structure. Machiavelli suggests that the political benefits of stability and security can be achieved in the face of moral corruption. Machiavelli believed that public and private morality had to be understood as two different things in order to rule well.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolo |title=The Prince |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1984 |isbn=0-19-281602-0 |location=Oxford, New York |pages=59–60}}</ref> As a result, a ruler must be concerned not only with reputation, but also must be positively willing to act unscrupulously at the right times. Machiavelli believed that, for a ruler, it was better to be widely feared than to be greatly loved; a loved ruler retains authority by obligation, while a feared leader rules by fear of punishment.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |year=1532 |location=Italy |pages=120–121}}</ref> As a political theorist, Machiavelli emphasized the "necessity" for the methodical exercise of brute force or deceit, including extermination of entire noble families, to head off any chance of a challenge to the prince's authority.<ref>Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', Chapter III</ref> | |||
Scholars often note that Machiavelli glorifies instrumentality in state building, an approach embodied by the saying, often attributed to interpretations of ''The Prince'', "]".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=harvey+mansfield+machiavelli |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1998 |isbn=978-0226503721}}</ref> Fraud and deceit are held by Machiavelli as necessary for a prince to use.<ref>''The Prince'', Chapter XVIII, "In What Mode Should Faith Be Kept By Princes"</ref> Violence may be necessary for the successful stabilization of power and introduction of new political institutions. Force may be used to eliminate political rivals, destroy resistant populations, and purge the community of other men strong enough of a character to rule, who will inevitably attempt to replace the ruler.<ref>''The Prince''. especially Chapters 3, 5 and 8</ref> In one passage, Machiavelli subverts the advice given by ] to avoid duplicity and violence, by saying that the prince should "be the fox to avoid the snares, and a lion to overwhelm the wolves". It would become one of Machiavelli's most famous maxims.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kiYz6d278IC&q=machiavelli+skinner|title=Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|date=2000-10-12|publisher=OUP Oxford|isbn=9780191540349|language=en}}</ref> Machiavelli's view that acquiring a state and maintaining it requires ] means has been noted as the chief theme of the treatise.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=12}}</ref> Machiavelli has become infamous for such political advice, ensuring that he would be remembered in history through the adjective "Machiavellian".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Kanzler |first=Peter |title=The Prince (1532), The Leviathan (1651), The Two Treatises of Government (1689), The Constitution of Pennsylvania (1776) |publisher=Peter Kanzler |year=2020 |isbn=978-1716844508 |page=22}}</ref> | |||
Due to the treatise's controversial analysis on politics, in 1559, the ] banned ''The Prince'', putting it on the ''{{lang|la|]}}''.<ref>{{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_yPeCwAAQBAJ&dq=index+librorum+prohibitorum+1559+machiavelli&pg=PA16 | title=The Routledge Guidebook to Machiavelli's the Prince | isbn=978-1-317-53673-4 | last1=Scott | first1=John T. | date=31 March 2016 | publisher=Routledge }}</ref><ref>Landon, W. J. (2005). Politics, Patriotism and Language: Niccolò Machiavelli's" secular Patria" and the Creation of an Italian National Identity (Vol. 57). Peter Lang.</ref> ], including ] ({{circa|1466}}{{snd}}1536), also viewed the book negatively. As a treatise, its primary intellectual contribution to the history of political thought is the fundamental break between political ] and political ], due to it being a manual on acquiring and keeping political power. In contrast with ] and ], Machiavelli insisted that an imaginary ideal society is not a model by which a prince should orient himself. | |||
Concerning the differences and similarities in Machiavelli's advice to ruthless and tyrannical princes in ''The Prince'' and his more republican exhortations in ''Discourses on Livy'', a few commentators assert that ''The Prince'', although written as advice for a monarchical prince, contains arguments for the superiority of republican regimes, similar to those found in the ''Discourses''. In the 18th century, the work was even called a ], for example by ] (1712–1778).<ref>''Discourse on Political Economy'': opening pages.</ref><ref>{{Cite web |last=Berlin |first=Isaiah |title=The Originality of Machiavelli |url=http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/published_works/ac/machiavelli.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20121202125009/http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/published_works/ac/machiavelli.pdf |archive-date=2 December 2012 |access-date=18 October 2012}}</ref> | |||
Scholars such as ] (1899–1973) and ] ({{b.|1932}}) have stated that sections of ''The Prince'' and his other works have deliberately esoteric statements throughout them.<ref>This point made most notably by {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}.</ref> However, Mansfield states that this is the result of Machiavelli's seeing grave and serious things as humorous because they are "manipulable by men", and sees them as grave because they "answer human necessities".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=machiavelli%27s+virtue |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1998 |isbn=978-0226503721 |pages=228–229}}</ref> | |||
The Marxist theorist ] (1891–1937) argued that Machiavelli's audience was the common people, as opposed to the ruling class, who were already made aware of the methods described through their education.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Thomas |first=Peter D. |year=2017 |title=The Modern Prince |journal=History of Political Thought |volume=38 |issue=3 |pages=523–544 |jstor=26210463}}</ref> | |||
===''Discourses on Livy''=== | |||
{{Main|Discourses on Livy}} | |||
The ''Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius'', written around 1517, and published in 1531, often referred to simply as the ''Discourses'' or ''Discorsi'', is nominally a discussion regarding the classical history of early ], although it strays far from this subject matter and also uses contemporary political examples to illustrate points. Machiavelli presents it as a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured. It is a larger work than ''The Prince'', and while it more openly explains the advantages of republics, it also contains many similar themes from his other works.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ia_oOgHlR58C|title=Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year=2001|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503707}}</ref> For example, Machiavelli has noted that to save a republic from corruption, it is necessary to return it to a "kingly state" using violent means.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.constitution.org/mac/disclivy1.htm|title=Discourses on Livy: Book 1, Chapter 18|website=www.constitution.org|access-date=9 May 2019}}</ref> He excuses Romulus for murdering his brother ] and co-ruler ] to gain absolute power for himself in that he established a "civil way of life".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+machiavelli|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 9|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref> Commentators disagree about how much the two works agree with each other, as Machiavelli frequently refers to leaders of republics as "princes".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=the+discourses+machiavelli+mansfield|title=Discourses on Livy|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref> Machiavelli even sometimes acts as an advisor to ].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+machiavelli|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 16|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&q=Thus,+the+charge+that+Machiavelli's+republic+is+a+tyranny+turns+out+to+be+true+after+&pg=PR60|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|year=2005|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1139448338|page=3}}</ref> Other scholars have pointed out the aggrandizing and imperialistic features of Machiavelli's republic.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yCsxDwAAQBAJ&q=hulliung+citizen+machiavelli|title=Citizen Machiavelli|last=Hulliung|first=Mark|year=2017|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1351528481}}</ref> Nevertheless, it became one of the central texts of modern ], and has often been argued to be a more comprehensive work than ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975|pp=183–219}}</ref> | |||
== Originality == | |||
] | |||
Major commentary on Machiavelli's work has focused on two issues: how unified and philosophical his work is and how innovative or traditional it is.<ref name=Fischer>{{Harvcoltxt|Fischer|2000}}</ref> | |||
=== Coherence === | |||
There is some disagreement concerning how best to describe the unifying themes, if there are any, that can be found in Machiavelli's works, especially in the two major political works, ''The Prince'' and ''Discourses''. Some commentators have described him as inconsistent, and perhaps as not even putting a high priority on consistency.<ref name=Fischer/><ref>Interpreting Modern Political Philosophy: From Machiavelli to Marx, pg. 40</ref> Others such as ] have argued that his ideas must have changed dramatically over time. Some have argued that his conclusions are best understood as a product of his times, experiences and education. Others, such as ] and ], have argued strongly that there is a strong and deliberate consistency and distinctness, even arguing that this extends to all of Machiavelli's works including his comedies and letters.<ref name=Fischer/><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=mansfield+machiavelli+virtue|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year=1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503721|language=en}}</ref> | |||
=== Influences === | |||
Commentators such as Leo Strauss have gone so far as to name Machiavelli as the deliberate originator of ] itself. Others have argued that Machiavelli is only a particularly interesting example of trends which were happening around him. In any case, Machiavelli presented himself at various times as someone reminding Italians of the old virtues of the Romans and Greeks, and other times as someone promoting a completely new approach to politics.<ref name=Fischer/> | |||
That Machiavelli had a wide range of influences is in itself not controversial. Their relative importance is however a subject of ongoing discussion. It is possible to summarize some of the main influences emphasized by different commentators. | |||
'''The Mirror of Princes genre''' | |||
{{Harvcoltxt|Gilbert|1938}} summarized the similarities between ''The Prince'' and the genre it obviously imitates, the so-called "]" style. This was a classically influenced genre, with models at least as far back as ] and ]. While Gilbert emphasized the similarities, however, he agreed with all other commentators that Machiavelli was particularly novel in the way he used this genre, even when compared to his contemporaries such as ] and ]. One of the major innovations Gilbert noted was that Machiavelli focused on the "deliberate purpose of dealing with a new ruler who will need to establish himself in defiance of custom". Normally, these types of works were addressed only to hereditary princes. (Xenophon is also an exception in this regard.) | |||
'''Classical republicanism''' | |||
Commentators such as ] and ], in the so-called "Cambridge School" of interpretation, have asserted that some of the republican themes in Machiavelli's political works, particularly the '']'', can be found in medieval Italian literature which was influenced by classical authors such as ].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GF6X2ow__MgC&q=quentin+skinner+machiavelli|title=The Foundations of Modern Political Thought: Volume 1, The Renaissance|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|year= 1978|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521293372|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1oj8CwAAQBAJ&q=pocock+machiavelli|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|last=Pocock|first=J. G. A.|year=2016|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=978-1400883516|language=en}}</ref> | |||
'''Classical political philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle''' | |||
], author of the '']'']] | |||
The Socratic school of classical political philosophy, especially ], had become a major influence upon European political thinking in the late ]. It existed both in the Catholicised form presented by ], and in the more controversial "]" form of authors like ]. Machiavelli was critical of Catholic political thinking and may have been influenced by Averroism. But he rarely cites Plato and Aristotle, and most likely did not approve of them. ] argued that the strong influence of ], a student of Socrates more known as a historian, rhetorician and soldier, was a major source of Socratic ideas for Machiavelli, sometimes not in line with Aristotle. While interest in ] was increasing in Florence during Machiavelli's lifetime, Machiavelli does not show particular interest in him, but was indirectly influenced by his readings of authors such as ], ] and ]. | |||
The major difference between Machiavelli and the Socratics, according to Strauss, is Machiavelli's materialism, and therefore his rejection of both a teleological view of nature and of the view that philosophy is higher than politics. With their ] understanding of things, Socratics argued that by nature, everything that acts, acts towards some end, as if nature desired them, but Machiavelli claimed that such things happen by blind chance or human action.<ref name=Strauss>{{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}}</ref> | |||
'''Classical materialism''' | |||
Strauss argued that Machiavelli may have seen himself as influenced by some ideas from classical materialists such as ], ] and ]. Strauss however sees this also as a sign of major innovation in Machiavelli, because classical materialists did not share the Socratic regard for political life, while Machiavelli clearly did.<ref name=Strauss/> | |||
'''Thucydides''' | |||
Some scholars note the similarity between Machiavelli and the Greek historian ], since both emphasized ].<ref>Paul Anthony Rahe, ''Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English Republic'' (2008), p. 282.</ref><ref>Jack Donnelly, ''Realism and International Relations'' (2000), p. 68.</ref> Strauss argued that Machiavelli may indeed have been influenced by ], but he felt it was a new combination: | |||
<blockquote>...contemporary readers are reminded by Machiavelli's teaching of Thucydides; they find in both authors the same "realism", i.e., the same denial of the power of the gods or of justice and the same sensitivity to harsh necessity and elusive chance. Yet Thucydides never calls in question the intrinsic superiority of nobility to baseness, a superiority that shines forth particularly when the noble is destroyed by the base. Therefore Thucydides' History arouses in the reader a sadness which is never aroused by Machiavelli's books. In Machiavelli we find comedies, parodies, and satires but nothing reminding of tragedy. One half of humanity remains outside of his thought. There is no tragedy in Machiavelli because he has no sense of the sacredness of "the common". – {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=292}}</blockquote> | |||
== Beliefs == | |||
Amongst commentators, there are a few consistently made proposals concerning what was most new in Machiavelli's work. | |||
=== Empiricism and realism versus idealism === | |||
Machiavelli is sometimes seen as the prototype of a modern empirical scientist, building generalizations from experience and historical facts, and emphasizing the uselessness of theorizing with the imagination.<ref name=Fischer/> | |||
{{blockquote|He emancipated politics from theology and moral philosophy. He undertook to describe simply what rulers actually did and thus anticipated what was later called the scientific spirit in which questions of good and bad are ignored, and the observer attempts to discover only what really happens.|Joshua Kaplan, 2005<ref name=twsC11r44fzf>{{cite news|author=Joshua Kaplan|title=Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance|publisher=The Modern Scholar|quote=14 lectures in the series; (lectures #7) – see disc 4|year=2005}}</ref>}} | |||
Machiavelli felt that his early schooling along the lines of traditional classical education was essentially useless for the purpose of understanding politics. Nevertheless, he advocated intensive study of the past, particularly regarding the founding of a city, which he felt was a key to understanding its later development.<ref name=twsC11r44fzf/> Moreover, he studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. Machiavelli denies the classical opinion that living virtuously always leads to happiness. For example, Machiavelli viewed misery as "one of the vices that enables a prince to rule."<ref>Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, ''History of Political Philosophy'' (1987), p. 300.</ref> Machiavelli stated that "it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved."<ref>Niccolò Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', Chap 17.</ref> In much of Machiavelli's work, he often states that the ruler must adopt unsavoury policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime. Because cruelty and fraud play such important roles in his politics, it is not unusual for certain issues (such as murder and betrayal) to be commonplace within his works.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/machiave/|title=Niccolò Machiavelli, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|last=|first=|date=|website=|archive-url=|archive-date=|access-date=}}</ref> | |||
A related and more controversial proposal often made is that he described how to do things in politics in a way which seemed neutral concerning who used the advice{{snd}}tyrants or good rulers.<ref name=Fischer/> That Machiavelli strove for realism is not doubted, but for four centuries scholars have debated how best to describe his morality. ''The Prince'' made the word ''Machiavellian'' a byword for deceit, despotism, and political manipulation. ] declared himself inclined toward the traditional view that Machiavelli was self-consciously a "teacher of evil", since he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oi2GDwAAQBAJ&q=leo+strauss|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|last=Strauss|first=Leo|year= 2014|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226230979|language=en}}</ref> Strauss takes up this opinion because he asserted that failure to accept the traditional opinion misses the "intrepidity of his thought" and "the graceful subtlety of his speech".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Strauss |first=Leo |url=http://archive.org/details/LeoStraussThoughtsOnMachiavelli_201411 |title=Leo Strauss "Thoughts On Machiavelli" |page=9}}</ref> Italian ] philosopher ] (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values, in reality, do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Carritt |first=E. F. |url=http://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.123166 |title=Benedetto Croce My Philosophy |date=1949}}</ref> German philosopher ] (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist{{snd}}a ] of politics{{snd}}in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Cassirer |first=Ernst |title=The Myth of the State |date=1961-09-10 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0-300-00036-8 |location=New Haven, Connecticut; London, England |pages=136 |language=English}}</ref> On the other hand, ] has argued that ''The Prince''{{'}}s advice presupposes the importance of ideas like ] in making changes to the political system.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://blogs.the-american-interest.com/stratblog/2011/05/03/when-isms-go-to-war/|title=When Isms go to War {{!}} StratBlog|date=29 October 2013|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131029210725/http://blogs.the-american-interest.com/stratblog/2011/05/03/when-isms-go-to-war/|access-date=29 October 2019|archive-date=29 October 2013}}</ref> | |||
=== Fortune === | |||
Machiavelli is generally seen as being critical of ] as it existed in his time, specifically its effect upon politics, and also everyday life.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=machiavelli |title=Discourses on Livy |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=2009 |isbn=978-0226500331 |page=131 |language=en-us}}</ref> In his opinion, Christianity, along with the ] ] that the Church had come to accept, allowed practical decisions to be guided too much by imaginary ] and encouraged people to lazily leave events up to ] or, as he would put it, chance, luck or fortune. While Christianity sees modesty as a virtue and pride as sinful, Machiavelli took a more classical position, seeing ambition, spiritedness, and the pursuit of glory as good and natural things, and part of the virtue and prudence that good princes should have. Therefore, while it was traditional to say that leaders should have virtues, especially prudence, Machiavelli's use of the words ''virtù'' and ''prudenza'' was unusual for his time, implying a spirited and immodest ambition. Mansfield describes his usage of ''virtù'' as a "compromise with evil".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&dq=machiavelli's%20virtue&pg=PA233 |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |date=1998-02-25 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-50372-1 |pages=233 |language=en-us}}</ref> Famously, Machiavelli argued that virtue and prudence can help a man control more of his future, in the place of allowing fortune to do so. | |||
Najemy has argued that this same approach can be found in Machiavelli's approach to love and desire, as seen in his comedies and correspondence. Najemy shows how Machiavelli's friend Vettori argued against Machiavelli and cited a more traditional understanding of fortune.{{sfn|Najemy|1993|p=missing}} | |||
On the other hand, ] in Machiavelli's time meant that classical pre-Christian ideas about virtue and prudence, including the possibility of trying to control one's future, were not unique to him. But humanists did not go so far as to promote the extra glory of deliberately aiming to establish a new state, in defiance of traditions and laws. | |||
While Machiavelli's approach had classical precedents, it has been argued that it did more than just bring back old ideas and that Machiavelli was not a typical humanist. {{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}} argues that the way Machiavelli combines classical ideas is new. While Xenophon and Plato also described realistic politics and were closer to Machiavelli than Aristotle was, they, like Aristotle, also saw philosophy as something higher than politics. Machiavelli was apparently a ] who objected to explanations involving ], or ]. | |||
Machiavelli's promotion of ambition among leaders while denying any higher standard meant that he encouraged risk-taking, and innovation, most famously the founding of new modes and orders. His advice to princes was therefore certainly not limited to discussing how to maintain a state. It has been argued that Machiavelli's promotion of innovation led directly to the argument for ] as an aim of ] and ]. But while a belief that humanity can control its own future, control nature, and "progress" has been long-lasting, Machiavelli's followers, starting with his own friend ], have tended to prefer peaceful progress through economic development, and not warlike progress. As Harvey {{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1995|p=74}} wrote: "In attempting other, more regular and scientific modes of overcoming fortune, Machiavelli's successors formalized and emasculated his notion of virtue." | |||
Machiavelli however, along with some of his classical predecessors, saw ambition and spiritedness, and therefore war, as inevitable and part of ]. | |||
Strauss concludes his 1958 book '']'' by proposing that this promotion of progress leads directly to the advent of new technologies being invented in both good and bad governments. Strauss argued that the unavoidable nature of such arms races, which existed before modern times and led to the collapse of peaceful civilizations, show that classical-minded men "had to admit in other words that in an important respect the good city has to take its bearings by the practice of bad cities or that the bad impose their law on the good".{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=298–299}} | |||
===Religion=== | |||
Machiavelli shows repeatedly that he saw religion as man-made, and that the value of religion lies in its contribution to social order and the rules of morality must be dispensed with if security requires it.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+on+livy|title=Discourses on Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11–15|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year= 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ehzOd8DVlNkC&q=the+prince+mansfield|title=The Prince: Second Edition|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year= 2010|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500508|pages=69–71|language=en}}</ref> In ''The Prince'', the ''Discourses'' and in the '']'' he describes "prophets", as he calls them, like ], ], ] and ] (he treated pagan and Christian patriarchs in the same way) as the greatest of new princes, the glorious and brutal founders of the most novel innovations in politics, and men whom Machiavelli assures us have always used a large amount of armed force and murder against their own people.<ref>Especially in the ''Discourses'' III.30, but also ''The Prince'' Chap.VI</ref> He estimated that these sects last from 1,666 to 3,000 years each time, which, as pointed out by Leo Strauss, would mean that Christianity became due to start finishing about 150 years after Machiavelli.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=314}}</ref> Machiavelli's concern with Christianity as a sect was that it makes men weak and inactive, delivering politics into the hands of cruel and wicked men without a fight.<ref>See for example {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=206}}.</ref> While Machiavelli's own religious allegiance has been debated, it is assumed that he had a low regard of contemporary Christianity.<ref>Parsons, W. B. (2016). Machiavelli's gospel: The critique of Christianity in the prince. Boydell & Brewer.</ref> | |||
While fear of ] can be replaced by fear of the prince, if there is a strong enough prince, Machiavelli felt that having a religion is in any case especially essential to keeping a republic in order.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Vavouras |first1=Elias |last2=Theodosiadis |first2=Michail |date=October 2024 |title=The Concept of Religion in Machiavelli: Political Methodology, Propaganda and Ideological Enlightenment |journal=Religions |language=en |volume=15 |issue=10 |pages=1203 |doi=10.3390/rel15101203 |doi-access=free |issn=2077-1444}}</ref> For Machiavelli, a truly great prince can never be conventionally religious himself, but he should make his people religious if he can. According to {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=226–227}} he was not the first person to explain religion in this way, but his description of religion was novel because of the way he integrated this into his general account of princes. | |||
Machiavelli's judgment that governments need religion for practical political reasons was widespread among modern proponents of republics until approximately the time of the ]. This, therefore, represents a point of disagreement between Machiavelli and late modernity.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=231}}</ref> | |||
===Positive side to factional and individual vice=== | |||
Despite the classical precedents, which Machiavelli was not the only one to promote in his time, Machiavelli's realism and willingness to argue that good ends justify bad things, is seen as a critical stimulus towards some of the most important theories of modern politics. | |||
Firstly, particularly in the ''Discourses on Livy'', Machiavelli is unusual in the positive side to factionalism in republics which he sometimes seems to describe. For example, quite early in the ''Discourses'', (in Book I, chapter 4), a chapter title announces that ''the disunion'' of the ] and ] in Rome ''"kept Rome free"''. That a community has different components whose interests must be balanced in any good regime is an idea with classical precedents, but Machiavelli's particularly extreme presentation is seen as a critical step towards the later political ideas of both a ] or ], ideas which lay behind the ], as well as many other modern state constitutions. | |||
Similarly, the modern economic argument for ], and most modern forms of economics, was often stated in the form of "]". Also in this case, even though there are classical precedents, Machiavelli's insistence on being both realistic and ambitious, not only admitting that vice exists but being willing to risk encouraging it, is a critical step on the path to this insight. | |||
Mansfield however argues that Machiavelli's own aims have not been shared by those he influenced. Machiavelli argued against seeing mere peace and economic growth as worthy aims on their own if they would lead to what Mansfield calls the "taming of the prince".<ref>{{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1993}}</ref> | |||
==Influence== | |||
]]] | |||
To quote Robert Bireley:<ref>Bireley, Robert (1990), ''The Counter Reformation Prince'', p. 14.</ref> | |||
{{blockquote|...there were in circulation approximately fifteen editions of the ''Prince'' and nineteen of the ''Discourses'' and French translations of each before they were placed on ] of ] in 1559, a measure which nearly stopped publication in Catholic areas except in France. Three principal writers took the field against Machiavelli between the publication of his works and their condemnation in 1559 and again by the Tridentine Index in 1564. These were the English cardinal ] and the Portuguese bishop ], both of whom lived for many years in Italy, and the Italian humanist and later bishop, ].}} | |||
Machiavelli's ideas had a profound impact on political leaders throughout the modern west, helped by the new technology of the printing press. During the first generations after Machiavelli, his main influence was in non-republican governments. Pole reported that ''The Prince'' was spoken of highly by ] in England and had influenced ] in his turn towards Protestantism, and in his tactics, for example during the ].<ref name="BireleyP15">{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=15}}</ref> A copy was also possessed by the Catholic king and emperor ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999|p=248}}</ref> In France, after an initially mixed reaction, Machiavelli came to be associated with ] and the ]. As {{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}} reports, in the 16th century, Catholic writers "associated Machiavelli with the Protestants, whereas Protestant authors saw him as Italian and Catholic". In fact, he was apparently influencing both Catholic and Protestant kings.<ref>While Bireley focuses on writers in the Catholic countries, {{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999}} makes the same observation, writing with more of a focus upon the Protestant ].</ref> | |||
One of the most important early works dedicated to criticism of Machiavelli, especially ''The Prince'', was that of the ], ], whose work commonly referred to as ''Discourse against Machiavelli'' or ''Anti Machiavel'' was published in ] in 1576.<ref>The first English edition was ''A Discourse upon the meanes of wel governing and maintaining in good peace, a Kingdome, or other principalitie'', translated by Simon Patericke.</ref> He accused Machiavelli of being an atheist and accused politicians of his time by saying that his works were the "Koran of the courtiers", that "he is of no reputation in the court of France which hath not Machiavel's writings at the fingers ends".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}</ref> Another theme of Gentillet was more in the spirit of Machiavelli himself: he questioned the effectiveness of immoral strategies (just as Machiavelli had himself done, despite also explaining how they could sometimes work). This became the theme of much future political discourse in Europe during the 17th century. This includes the Catholic ] writers summarised by Bireley: ], ], Carlo Scribani, ], ], and ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=18}}</ref> These authors criticized Machiavelli, but also followed him in many ways. They accepted the need for a prince to be concerned with reputation, and even a need for cunning and deceit, but compared to Machiavelli, and like later modernist writers, they emphasized ] much more than the riskier ventures of war. These authors tended to cite ] as their source for realist political advice, rather than Machiavelli, and this pretence came to be known as "]".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|pp=223–230}}</ref> "Black tacitism" was in support of princely rule, but "red tacitism" arguing the case for republics, more in the original spirit of Machiavelli himself, became increasingly important. Cardinal ] read The Prince while he was in Italy, and on which he gave his comments.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ip1oAgAAQBAJ&dq=found+this+type+of+book+to+be+written+by+an+enemy+of+the+human+race.+It+explains+every+means+whereby+religion,+justice+and+any+inclination+toward+virtue+could+be+destroyed%22&pg=PR20|title=Machiavelli's Prince: A New Reading|last=Benner|first=Erica|date=2013-11-28|publisher=OUP Oxford|isbn=9780191003929|language=en}}</ref> ], king of ] and patron of ], wrote ], with the aim of rebutting ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/Anti-Machiavel|title=Anti-Machiavel {{!}} treatise by Frederick the Great|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=2019-04-16}}</ref> | |||
] argued the case for what would become ] which would be based more upon real experience and experimentation, free from assumptions about metaphysics, and aimed at increasing control of nature. He named Machiavelli as a predecessor.]] | |||
Modern ] philosophy developed in the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, starting in the generations after Machiavelli. Modern political philosophy tended to be republican, but as with the Catholic authors, Machiavelli's realism and encouragement of innovation to try to control one's own fortune were more accepted than his emphasis upon war and factional violence. Not only was innovative economics and politics a result, but also ], leading some commentators to say that the 18th century ] involved a "humanitarian" moderating of Machiavellianism.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> | |||
The importance of Machiavelli's influence is notable in many important figures in this endeavour, for example ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}: "Jean Bodin's first comments, found in his ''Method for the Easy Comprehension of History'', published in 1566, were positive."</ref> ],<ref>Bacon wrote: "We are much beholden to Machiavelli and other writers of that class who openly and unfeignedly declare or describe what men do, and not what they ought to do." {{Citation|title=Of the Advancement of Learning|chapter=II.21.9}}. See {{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}} Chapter 4.</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}} chapter 6.</ref> ], ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Worden|1999}}</ref> ],<ref>{{cite encyclopedia|title=Spinoza's Political Philosophy|url= http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spinoza-political/#IntBac|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=19 March 2011|publisher= Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|year= 2013}}</ref> ], ],<ref>Danford "Getting Our Bearings: Machiavelli and Hume" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> ], and ]. Although he was not always mentioned by name as an inspiration, due to his controversy, he is also thought to have been an influence for other major philosophers, such as ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Schaefer|1990}}</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, chapter 11.</ref> ], ]<ref>Barnes Smith "The Philosophy of Liberty: Locke's Machiavellian Teaching" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> and ].<ref>Carrese "The Machiavellian Spirit of Montesquieu's Liberal Republic" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref><ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Shklar|1999}}</ref> Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who is associated with very different political ideas, viewed Machiavelli's work as a satirical piece in which Machiavelli exposes the faults of a one-man rule rather than exalting amorality. | |||
<blockquote>In the seventeenth century it was in England that Machiavelli's ideas were most substantially developed and adapted, and that republicanism came once more to life; and out of seventeenth-century English republicanism there were to emerge in the next century not only a theme of English political and historical reflection{{snd}}of the writings of the ] circle and of ] and of early parliamentary radicals{{snd}}but a stimulus to the ] in Scotland, on the Continent, and in America.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Worden|1999}}</ref></blockquote> | |||
].]] | |||
Scholars have argued that Machiavelli was a major indirect and direct influence upon the political thinking of the ] due to his overwhelming favouritism of ] and the republican type of government. According to John McCormick, it is still very much debatable whether or not Machiavelli was "an advisor of tyranny or partisan of liberty."<ref>John P. McCormick, ''Machiavellian democracy'' (Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 23.</ref> ], ] and ] followed Machiavelli's republicanism when they opposed what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared ] was creating with the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> Hamilton learned from Machiavelli about the importance of foreign policy for domestic policy, but may have broken from him regarding how rapacious a republic needed to be in order to survive.<ref>Walling "Was Alexander Hamilton a Machiavellian Statesman?" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref><ref>{{Harvtxt|Harper|2004}}</ref> ] was less influenced by Machiavelli.<ref>Spalding "The American Prince? George Washington's Anti-Machiavellian moment" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> | |||
The Founding Father who perhaps most studied and valued Machiavelli as a political philosopher was ], who profusely commented on the Italian's thought in his work, ''A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America''.<ref name="thompson">{{Harvtxt|Thompson|1995}}</ref> In this work, John Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and ], as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.<ref name="thompson" /> | |||
===20th century=== | |||
The 20th-century Italian Communist ] drew great inspiration from Machiavelli's writings on ethics, morals, and how they relate to the State and revolution in his writings on ], and how a society can be manipulated by controlling popular notions of morality.<ref>Marcia Landy, "Culture and Politics in the work of Antonio Gramsci," 167–188, in ''Antonio Gramsci: Intellectuals, Culture, and the Party'', ed. James Martin (New York: Routledge, 2002).</ref> | |||
] read ''The Prince'' and annotated his own copy.<ref>Service, Robert. ''Stalin: A Biography'', p.10.</ref> | |||
In the 20th century there was also renewed interest in Machiavelli's play '']'' (1518), which received numerous stagings, including several in New York, at the ] in 1976 and the ] in 1979, as a musical comedy by ] in Munich's Anti Theatre in 1971, and at London's ] in 1984.<ref name="Jann Racquoi 1979">Review by Jann Racquoi, ''Heights/Inwood Press of North Manhattan'', 14 March 1979.</ref> | |||
{{Anchor|Machiavellian}} | |||
=== "Machiavellian" === | |||
]'' (]), used as an example of a successful ruler in ''The Prince'']] | |||
Machiavelli's works are sometimes even said to have contributed to the modern negative connotations of the words ''politics'' and ''politician'',<ref>{{Harvtxt|Bireley|1990|p=241}}</ref> and it is sometimes thought that it is because of him that ''Old Nick'' became an English term for the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Fischer|2000|p=94}}</ref> More obviously, the adjective ''Machiavellian'' became a term describing a form of politics that is "marked by cunning, duplicity, or bad faith".<ref>{{Cite dictionary|title=Definition of MACHIAVELLIAN|dictionary=]|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Machiavellian|access-date=17 October 2018}}</ref> ''Machiavellianism'' also remains a popular term used casually in political discussions, often as a byword for bare-knuckled political realism.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&q=paul%20a%20rahe&pg=PR36|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|year=2005|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1139448338|page=xxxvi|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Meinecke |first=Friedrich |date=1957 |title=Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d'État and Its Place in Modern History |page=36 |url=https://archive.org/details/machiavellismdoc00mein |publisher=Yale University Press}}</ref> | |||
While Machiavellianism is notable in the works of Machiavelli, scholars generally agree that his works are complex and have equally influential themes within them. For example, J. G. A. {{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975}} saw him as a major source of the ] that spread throughout England and North America in the 17th and 18th centuries and Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}, whose view of Machiavelli is quite different in many ways, had similar remarks about Machiavelli's influence on republicanism and argued that even though Machiavelli was a teacher of evil he had a "grandeur of vision" that led him to advocate immoral actions. Whatever his intentions, which are still debated today, he has become associated with any proposal where "]". For example, Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=297}} wrote: | |||
{{blockquote|Machiavelli is the only political thinker whose name has come into common use for designating a kind of politics, which exists and will continue to exist independently of his influence, a politics guided exclusively by considerations of expediency, which uses all means, fair or foul, iron or poison, for achieving its ends{{snd}}its end being the aggrandizement of one's country or fatherland{{snd}}but also using the fatherland in the service of the self-aggrandizement of the politician or statesman or one's party.}} | |||
{{anchor|Machiavel}} | |||
===In popular culture=== | |||
{{main|Machiavelli in popular culture}} | |||
Due to Machiavelli's popularity, he has been featured in various ways in cultural depictions. In ] (Elizabethan and Jacobian), the term "]" (from 'Nicholas Machiavel', an "anglicization" of Machiavelli's name based on French) was used for a stock antagonist that resorted to ruthless means to preserve the power of the state, and is now considered a synonym of "Machiavellian".<ref>Kahn, V. (1994). Machiavellian rhetoric: From the counter-reformation to Milton. Princeton University Press.</ref><ref>{{cite web|access-date=31 December 2021|title=Machiavel|url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803100122752|website=Oxford Reference}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|access-date=31 December 2021|title=MACHIAVEL English Definition and Meaning {{!}} Lexico.com|url=https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavel|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210516180221/https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavel|url-status=dead|archive-date=16 May 2021|website=Lexico Dictionaries }}</ref> | |||
]'s play '']'' (ca. 1589) contains a prologue by a character called Machiavel, a ] ghost based on Machiavelli.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://player.fm/series/jew-of-malta-the-by-marlowe-christopher |title=Jew of Malta, The by MARLOWE, Christopher |work=Player FM |year=2016 |access-date=12 May 2018}}</ref> Machiavel expresses the cynical view that power is amoral, saying: | |||
{{blockquote|<poem> | |||
"I count religion but a childish toy, | |||
And hold there is no sin but ignorance." | |||
</poem>}} | |||
Shakespeares titular character, '']'', refers to Machiavelli in '']'', as the "murderous Machiavel".<ref>{{cite web | url=https://www.folger.edu/explore/shakespeares-works/henry-vi-part-3/read/ | title=Henry VI, Part 3 - Entire Play | Folger Shakespeare Library }}</ref> | |||
==Works== | |||
{{See also|Category:Works by Niccolò Machiavelli}} | |||
===Political and historical works=== | |||
] | |||
* '']'' (1499) | |||
* '']'' (1502) | |||
* '']'' (1502) – A ''Description of the Methods Adopted by the Duke Valentino when Murdering Vitellozzo Vitelli, Oliverotto da Fermo, the Signor Pagolo, and the Duke di Gravina Orsini'' | |||
* '']'' (1502) – A discourse about the provision of money. | |||
* ''Ritratti delle cose di Francia'' (1510) – Portrait of the affairs of France. | |||
* '']'' (1508–1512) – Portrait of the affairs of Germany. | |||
* '']'' (1513) | |||
* '']'' (1517) | |||
* ''Dell'Arte della Guerra'' (1519–1520) – '']'', high military science. | |||
* '']'' (1520) – A discourse about the reforming of Florence. | |||
* ''Sommario delle cose della citta di Lucca'' (1520) – A summary of the affairs of the city of Lucca. | |||
* ''The ] of Lucca'' (1520) – ''Vita di ] da Lucca'', a short biography. | |||
* ''Istorie Fiorentine'' (1520–1525) – '']'', an eight-volume history of the city-state Florence, commissioned by Giulio de' Medici, later ]. | |||
===Fictional works=== | |||
{{See also|Machiavelli as a dramatist}} | |||
{{Republicanism sidebar}} | |||
Besides being a statesman and political scientist, Machiavelli also translated classical works, and was a playwright (''Clizia'', ''Mandragola''), a poet (''Sonetti'', ''Canzoni'', ''Ottave'', ''Canti carnascialeschi''), and a novelist (''Belfagor arcidiavolo''). | |||
Some of his other work: | |||
* '']'' (1506) – a poem in ]. | |||
* '']'' (1509) – a poem. | |||
* ] or ''The Girl from Andros'' (1517) – a semi-autobiographical comedy, adapted from ].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://yaledailynews.com/blog/2012/04/18/first-time-machiavelli-translation-debuts-at-yale/|title=First-time Machiavelli translation debuts at Yale|date=18 April 2012|publisher=yaledailynews.com}}</ref> | |||
* '']'' (1518) – '']'' – a five-act prose comedy, with a verse prologue. | |||
* '']'' (1525) – a prose comedy. | |||
* '']'' (1515) – a novella. | |||
* '']'' (1517) – '']'' is a ] poem, a new version of the ] by ]. | |||
* ''Frammenti storici'' (1525) – fragments of stories. | |||
===Other works=== | ===Other works=== | ||
''Della Lingua'' (Italian for "On the Language") (1514), a dialogue about Italy's language is normally attributed to Machiavelli. | |||
Machiavelli also wrote plays (''Clizia'', ''Mandragola''), poetry (''Sonetti'', ''Canzoni'', ''Ottave'', ''Canti carnascialeschi'') and novels (''Belfagor arcidiavolo'') as well as translating classical works. | |||
Machiavelli's literary executor, Giuliano de' Ricci, also reported having seen that Machiavelli, his grandfather, made a comedy in the style of ] which included living Florentines as characters, and to be titled ''Le Maschere''. It has been suggested that due to such things as this and his style of writing to his superiors generally, there was very likely some animosity to Machiavelli even before the return of the Medici.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Godman|1998|p=240}}. Also see {{Harvtxt|Black|1999|pp=97–98}}</ref> | |||
*''Discorso sopra le cose di Pisa'' (1499) | |||
*''Del modo di trattare i popoli della Valdichiana ribellati'' (1502) | |||
*''Del modo tenuto dal duca Valentino nell' ammazzare Vitellozzo Vitelli, Oliverotto da Fermo, etc.'' (''Description of the Methods Adopted by the Duke Valentino when Murdering Vitellozzo Vitelli, Oliverotto da Fermo, the Signor Pagolo, and the Duke di Gravina Orsini'', 1502) | |||
*''Discorso sopra la provisione del danaro'' (1502) | |||
*''Decennale primo'' (1506, poem in terza rima) | |||
*''Ritratti delle cose dell'Alemagna'' (1508-1512) | |||
*''Decennale secondo'' (1509) | |||
*''Ritratti delle cose di Francia'' (1510) | |||
*''Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'' ('']'' - 3 vols., 1512-1517) | |||
*''Il Principe'' ('']'', 1513) | |||
*''Andria'' (1517, comedy translated from ]) | |||
*''Mandragola'' ('']'' - 1518, prose comedy in five acts, with prologue in verse) | |||
*''Della lingua'' (1514, dialogue) | |||
*''Clizia'' (1525, comedy in prose) | |||
*'']'' (1515, novel) | |||
*''Asino d'oro'' ('']'' - 1517, poem in terza rima, a new version of the ] by ]) | |||
*''Dell'arte della guerra'' ('']'', 1519-1520) | |||
*''Discorso sopra il riformare lo stato di Firenze'' (1520) | |||
*''Sommario delle cose della citta di Lucca'' (1520) | |||
*''Vita di ] da Lucca'' (''The Life of Castruccio Castracani of Lucca'', 1520) | |||
*''Istorie fiorentine'' ('']'' - 8 books, 1520-1525, commissioned by Giulio di Giuliano de' Medici who went on to become ]). | |||
*''Frammenti storici'' (1525) | |||
== |
==See also== | ||
{{Portal|Italy|Biography}} | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
==References== | |||
*] | |||
'''Footnotes''' | |||
*] | |||
{{notelist}} | |||
*] | |||
*] | |||
*] | |||
*] | |||
'''Citations''' | |||
== Notes == | |||
{{Reflist|30em}} | |||
<div class="references-small"> | |||
<References/> | |||
===Sources=== | |||
</div> | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Machiavelli |first1=Niccolò |translator=Daniel Donno |title=The Prince and Selected Discourses |year=1981 |publisher=Bantam Classic Books |location=New York |isbn=0553212273 |edition=}} | |||
* {{Cite book|last=Haitsma Mulier|first=Eco|chapter=A controversial republican|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Harper |first=John Lamberton |title=American Machiavelli: Alexander Hamilton and the Origins of US Foreign Policy |location=New York |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2004 |isbn=978-0521834858 }} | |||
* {{Cite book|last=Shklar|first=J.|chapter=Montesquieu and the new republicanism|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | |||
* {{Cite book|last=Worden|first=Blair|chapter=Milton's republicanism and the tyranny of heaven|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | |||
==Further reading== | ==Further reading== | ||
===Biographies=== | |||
*{{cite journal|last= Baron|first=Hans|title=Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of ''The Prince''|journal=English Historical Review|issue=76|year=1961|pages=217-253}} | |||
{{refbegin|30em}} | |||
*{{cite book|last= Bock|first=Gisela|coauthors=Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli, ed.|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1990}} | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Baron |first1=Hans |title=Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of 'the Prince' |journal=The English Historical Review |date=April 1961 |volume=76 |issue=299 |pages=217–253 |doi=10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217 |jstor=557541}} | |||
*{{cite book|last= Donaldson|first=Peter S.|title=Machiavelli and Mystery of State|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1989}} | |||
* Black, Robert. ''Machiavelli: From Radical to Reactionary''. London: Reaktion Books (2022) | |||
*{{cite book|last= ]|title=The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans|publisher=University of Chicago Press|year=1983, 2000}} | |||
* Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in ''Cambridge Modern History'' (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp. 190–218 | |||
*{{cite journal|last= Ingersoll|first=David E.|title=The Constant Prince: Private Interests and Public Goals in Machiavelli|journal=Western Political Quarterly|issue=21|date=December 1968|pages=588-596}} | |||
* Capponi, Niccolò. ''An Unlikely Prince: The Life and Times of Machiavelli'' (Da Capo Press; 2010) 334 pages | |||
*{{cite book|last= Magee|first=Brian|title=The Story of Philosophy|location=New York|publisher=DK Publishing|year=2001|pages=72-73}} | |||
* Celenza, Christopher S. ''Machiavelli: A Portrait'' (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2015) 240 pages. {{ISBN|978-0674416123}} | |||
*{{cite journal|last= Najemy|first=John M.|title=Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism|journal=American Historical Review|issue=101,1|year=1996|pages= 119-129}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Godman|first=Peter|title=From Poliziano to Machiavelli: Florentine Humanism in the High Renaissance|year=1998|publisher=Princeton University Press}} | |||
*{{cite book|last= Parel|first=Anthony|chapter=Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters|title=The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy|location=Toronto|year= 1972|pages=3-28}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=de Grazia|first=Sebastian|title=Machiavelli in Hell|year=1989|publisher=Knopf Doubleday Publishing |isbn=978-0679743422}}, an intellectual biography that won the Pulitzer Prize; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210309023042/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0679743421 |date=9 March 2021 }} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Pocock|first=J.G. A.|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|publisher=Princeton|origyear=1975}} | |||
* Hale, J. R. ''Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy'' (1961) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090619174443/http://www.questia.com/read/10359207?title=Machiavelli%20and%20Renaissance%20Italy |date=19 June 2009 }} | |||
*{{cite book|last= Soll|first=Jacob|title=Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism|publisher=University of Michigan Press|year=2005}} | |||
* Hulliung, Mark. ''Citizen Machiavelli'' (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 1983) | |||
*{{cite book|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B., ed.|title=The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works.'' Yale U. Press|year=2000}} | |||
* Lee, Alexander. ''Machiavelli: His Life and Times'' (London: Picador, 2020) | |||
*{{cite book|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B.|title=Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed|publisher=Northern Illinois University Press|year=1996}} | |||
* Oppenheimer, Paul. ''Machiavelli: A Life Beyond Ideology'' (London; New York: Continuum, 2011) {{ISBN|978-1847252210}} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|title=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|publisher=Farrar, Straus & Giroux|year=2000}} | |||
* Ridolfi, Roberto. ''The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (1963) | |||
* {{cite book|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|location=Lexington|year=2004}} | |||
* Schevill, Ferdinand. ''Six Historians'' (1956), pp. 61–91 | |||
*{{cite book|last= Wootton|first=David, ed.|title=Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli|location=Indianapolis|publisher=Hackett Pubs.|year=1994}} | |||
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli'', in ''Past Masters'' series. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1981. pp. vii, 102. {{ISBN|0192875167}} pbk. | |||
* Dirk Hoeges, ''Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano'', Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, ISBN 3-631-54669-6. | |||
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction'' (2d ed., 2019) {{ISBN|978-0198837572}} pbk. | |||
* Unger, Miles J. ''Machiavelli: A Biography'' (Simon & Schuster, 2011) | |||
* Villari, Pasquale. ''The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2 vols. 1892) (; ) | |||
* {{Citation|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|title=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|publisher=Farrar, Straus & Giroux|year=2000|title-link=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210324211333/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0374221871 |date=24 March 2021 }} | |||
* Viroli, Maurizio. ''Machiavelli'' (1998) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171020021045/https://www.questia.com/read/23271960?title=Machiavelli |date=20 October 2017 }} | |||
* Vivanti, Corrado. ''Niccolò Machiavelli: An Intellectual Biography'' (Princeton University Press; 2013) 261 pages | |||
{{refend}} | |||
===Political thought=== | |||
== External links == | |||
{{ |
{{refbegin|30em}} | ||
* Baron, Hans. ''The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny'' (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. ; ; also | |||
{{wikisource author}} | |||
* Baron, Hans. ''In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism'' (2 vols. 1988). | |||
{{commons|Niccolò Machiavelli}} | |||
* {{Citation|last= Baron|first=Hans|title=Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of ''The Prince''|journal=English Historical Review|issue=76|year=1961|pages=217–253|doi=10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217|volume=lxxvi|postscript= .|jstor=557541}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.jstor.org/stable/557541 |date=18 November 2022 }} | |||
* | |||
* ]. "The Originality of Machiavelli", in Berlin, Isaiah (1980). ''Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas''. New York: The Viking Press. | |||
*, works and summaries of Machiavelli | |||
* {{Citation|title=The Counter Reformation Prince|last=Bireley|first=Robert|year=1990}} | |||
*{{gutenberg author|id=Machiavelli|name=Machiavelli}} | |||
* {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli, servant of the Florentine republic|last=Black|first=Robert|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | |||
* at the ], including some of his works | |||
* {{Cite book |editor1-last=Bock |editor1-first=Gisela |editor2-last=Skinner |editor2-first=Quentin |editor3-last=Viroli |editor3-first=Maurizio |title=Machiavelli and Republicanism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9MNULqj7T4YC |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1993 |isbn=978-0521435895}} | |||
* : text, concordances and frequency list | |||
* Chabod, Federico (1958). ''Machiavelli & the Renaissance'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090619162346/http://www.questia.com/read/56380461?title=Machiavelli%20%26%20the%20Renaissance |date=19 June 2009 }}; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080820112213/http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01383 |date=20 August 2008 }} | |||
*, a Machiavelli webliography with a short introduction. | |||
* Connell, William J. (2001), "Machiavelli on Growth as an End," in Anthony Grafton and J.H.M. Salmon, eds., ''Historians and Ideologues: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Kelley'', Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 259–277. | |||
* Donskis, Leonidas, ed. (2011). Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi, {{ISBN|978-9042032774}}, E-{{ISBN|978-9042032781}} | |||
* ] "Niccolò Machiavelli: The Florentine Commune" in ''The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000. | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Fischer |first1=Markus |title=Machiavelli's Political Psychology |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Autumn 1997 |volume=59 |issue=4 |pages=789–829 |jstor=1408308 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500028333|s2cid=146570913 }} | |||
* {{Citation|title=Well-ordered License: On the Unity of Machiavelli's Thought|last=Fischer|first=Markus|publisher=Lexington Book|year=2000}} | |||
* {{cite book |last= Frederick II of Prussia|title=Anti-Machiavel: The Refutation of Machiavelli s Prince |date=1980 |orig-date=1740|translator-last=Sonnino|translator-first=Paul|publisher=Ohio University Press |location=Athens, OH |isbn=9780821405598}} | |||
* {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli and the crisis of the Italian republics|last=Guarini|first=Elena|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | |||
* {{Citation|title=Machiavelli's ''Prince'' and Its Forerunners|year=1938|publisher=Duke University Press|last=Gilbert|first=Allan}} | |||
* Gilbert, Felix. ''Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy'' (2nd ed. 1984) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055742/https://www.fulcrum.org/concern/monographs/rb68xf36w |date=18 November 2022 }} | |||
* Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. ''The Makers of Modern Strategy'' (1944) | |||
* Jensen, De Lamar, ed. ''Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist?'' (1960) essays by scholars {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100425072059/http://www.questia.com/read/34624137?title=Machiavelli%3A%20Cynic%2C%20Patriot%2C%20or%20Political%20Scientist%3F |date=25 April 2010 }} | |||
* {{Cite book |last= Jurdjevic |first= Mark |year= 2014 |title= A Great and Wretched City: Promise and Failure in Machiavelli's Florentine Political Thought |location= Cambridge, Massachusetts |publisher= ] |isbn= 978-0674725461}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Kennington|first=Richard|year=2004|title=On Modern Origins|publisher=Lexington Books}} | |||
* Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun. 1981), pp. 293–305 {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160808041013/http://www.jstor.org/stable/1961365 |date=8 August 2016 }} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|year=1993|title=Taming the Prince|publisher=The Johns Hopkins University Press}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|chapter=Machiavelli and the Idea of Progress|year=1995|editor1-last=Melzer|editor2-last=Weinberger|editor3-last=Zinman|title=History and the Idea of Progress|publisher=Cornell University Press}} | |||
* Mansfield, Harvey C. '' Machiavelli's Virtue'' (1996), 371 pp. | |||
* Mansfield, Harvey C. ''Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy'' (2001) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210311142259/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0226503704 |date=11 March 2021 }} | |||
* {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Machiavelli, Leonardo and the Science of Power | publisher = University of Notre Dame Press | year = 1996 | isbn = 978-0268014339 |author-link=Roger Masters}} See also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.nytimes.com/1996/12/08/us/scholar-sees-leonardo-s-influence-on-machiavelli.html?sec=&spon=&pagewanted=print |date=18 November 2022 }}. | |||
* {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Fortune is a River: Leonardo Da Vinci and Niccolò Machiavelli's Magnificent Dream to Change the Course of Florentine History | publisher = Simon & Schuster | year = 1998 | isbn = 978-0-452-28090-8 |author-link=Roger Masters}} Also available in Chinese ({{ISBN|9789572026113}}), Japanese ({{ISBN|978-4022597588}}), German ({{ISBN|978-3471794029}}), Portuguese ({{ISBN|978-8571104969}}), and Korean ({{ISBN|978-8984070059}}). See also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055738/https://www.nytimes.com/1998/07/17/books/books-of-the-times-a-river-ran-through-their-dreams.html?sec=&spon=&pagewanted=print |date=18 November 2022 }}. | |||
* {{Citation|last= Mattingly|first=Garrett|title=Machiavelli's Prince: Political Science or Political Satire?|journal=The American Scholar|issue=27|date=Autumn 1958|pages=482–491|postscript=.}} | |||
* {{Citation|title=Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513–1515|last=Najemy|first=John|year=1993|publisher=Princeton University Press}} | |||
* {{Citation|last= Najemy|first=John M.|title=Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism|journal=American Historical Review|issue=1|year=1996|pages= 119–129|doi=10.2307/2169227|volume=101|jstor= 2169227|postscript=.}} | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Parel |first1=A. J. |title=The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Spring 1991 |volume=53 |issue=2 |pages=320–339 |jstor=1407757 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500014649|s2cid=170629105 }} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Parel|first=Anthony|chapter=Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters|title=The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy|location=Toronto|year=1972|pages=3–28}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Parsons|first=William B.|title=Machiavelli's Gospel|year=2016|publisher=University of Rochester Press|isbn=978-1580464918}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Pocock|first=J.G.A.|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|publisher=Princeton|year=1975}} new ed. 2003, a highly influential study of ''Discourses'' and its vast influence; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210318183144/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0691114722 |date=18 March 2021 }}; also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20101007145157/http://www.questia.com/read/100774068?title=The%20Machiavellian%20Moment%3A%20Florentine%20Political%20Thought%20and%20the%20Atlantic%20Republican%20Tradition |date=7 October 2010 }} | |||
* Pocock, J. G. A. "The Machiavellian Moment Revisited: a Study in History and Ideology.: ''Journal of Modern History'' 1981 53(1): 49–72. {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180911191259/https://www.jstor.org/stable/1877064 |date=11 September 2018 }}. | |||
* {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul|title=Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution|year=1992}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090923182527/http://www.questia.com/library/book/republics-ancient-and-modern-classical-republicanism-and-the-american-revolution-vol-2-by-paul-a-rahe.jsp |date=23 September 2009 }} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|year=2006|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521851879}} Excerpt, reviews and Text search shows Machiavelli's ''Discourses'' had a major impact on shaping conservative thought. | |||
* Ruggiero, Guido. (2007) | |||
* {{Citation|first=David|last=Schaefer|year=1990|publisher=Cornell University Press|title=The Political Philosophy of Montaigne}}. | |||
* {{cite journal |last1=Scott |first1=John T. |last2=Sullivan |first2=Vickie B. |title=Patricide and the Plot of the Prince: Cesare Borgia and Machiavelli's Italy |journal=The American Political Science Review |date=1994 |volume=88 |issue=4 |pages=887–900 |doi=10.2307/2082714 |issn=0003-0554|jstor=2082714|s2cid=144798597 }} | |||
* Skinner, Quentin. ''The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, v. I, The Renaissance,'' (1978) | |||
* {{Citation|last= Soll|first=Jacob|title=Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism|publisher=University of Michigan Press|year=2005}} | |||
* Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ''Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2005) | |||
* {{Citation|chapter=Niccolò Machiavelli|title=History of Political Philosophy|edition=3rd|editor1-last=Strauss|editor1-first=Leo|editor2-last=Cropsey|editor2-first=Joseph|last=Strauss|first=Leo|year=1987|publisher=University of Chicago Press}} | |||
* {{Citation|last=Strauss|first=Leo|author-link = Leo Strauss|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|publisher=University of Chicago Press|location=Chicago|year=1958|isbn=978-0226777023}} | |||
* {{Citation|editor-last= Sullivan|editor-first=Vickie B.|title=The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works|publisher=Yale U. Press|year=2000}} | |||
* {{Citation|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B.|title=Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed|publisher=Northern Illinois University Press|year=1996}} | |||
* von Vacano, Diego, "The Art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham MD: Lexington: 2007. | |||
* {{Citation|first=C. Bradley |last=Thompson|title=John Adams's Machiavellian Moment| journal=The Review of Politics|volume=57|issue=3|year=1995|pages=389–417|doi=10.1017/S0034670500019689|s2cid=154074090 }}. Also in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}. | |||
* {{Citation|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|location=Lexington|year=2004}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Wight |first1=Martin |author-link1=Martin Wight |editor1-last=Wight |editor1-first=Gabriele |editor2-last= Porter |editor2-first=Brian |title=Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=978-0199273676 |url=http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780199273676.do |language=en}} | |||
* Zuckert, Catherine, (2017) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.google.com/books/edition/Machiavelli_s_Politics/yZUtDwAAQBAJ?hl=en&gbpv=1&dq=catherine+zuckert&printsec=frontcover |date=18 November 2022 }} | |||
{{refend}} | |||
===Italian studies=== | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Machiavelli}} | |||
{{refbegin|30em}} | |||
* Barbuto, Marcelo (2005), "Questa oblivione delle cose. Reflexiones sobre la cosmología de Maquiavelo (1469–1527)," ''Revista Daimon'', 34, Universidad de Murcia, pp. 34–52. | |||
* Barbuto, Marcelo (2008), "Discorsi, I, XII, 12–14. La Chiesa romana di fronte alla republica cristiana", ''Filosofia Politica'', 1, Il Mulino, Bologna, pp. 99–116. | |||
* Celli, Carlo ( 2009), ''Il carnevale di Machiavelli'', Firenze, L.S. Olschki. | |||
* ] (2015), ''Machiavelli nel Rinascimento italiano'', Milano, Franco Angeli. | |||
* Giuseppe Leone, "Silone e Machiavelli. Una scuola...che non crea prìncipi", pref. di Vittoriano Esposito, Centro Studi Ignazio Silone, Pescina, 2003. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (2004), "La Mandragola e il suo prologo", ''Interpres'', XXIII, pp. 106–142. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (2003), "Per la definizione della nozione di principe civile", ''Interpres'', XXII. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (2001), "I dettagli della filologia", ''Interpres'' XX, pp. 212–271. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1999a), "Note su Machiavelli", ''Interpres'' XVIII, pp. 91–145. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1999b), ''Saggio sul Principe'', Salerno Editrice, Roma. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1999c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola: valutazione politica e valutazione religiosa", Girolamo Savonarola. L´uomo e il frate". Atti del xxxv Convegno storico internazionale (Todi, II-14 ottobre 1998), CISAM, Spoleto, pp. 139–153. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1998a), ''Machiavelli e gli storici antichi, osservazioni su alcuni luoghi dei discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'', Quaderni di Filologia e critica, 13, Salerno Editrice, Roma. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1998b), "Machiavelli politico amante poeta", ''Interpres'' XVII, pp. 211–256. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1998c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola", ''Savonarola. Democrazia, tirannide, profezia'', a cura di G.C. Garfagnini, Florencia, Sismel-Edizioni del Galluzo, pp. 67–89. | |||
* Martelli, Mario and Bausi, Francesco (1997), "Politica, storia e letteratura: Machiavelli e Guicciardini", ''Storia della letteratura italiana'', E. Malato (ed.), vol. IV. Il primo Cinquecento, Salerno Editrice, Roma, pp. 251–320. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1985–1986), "Schede sulla cultura di Machiavelli", ''Interpres'' VI, pp. 283–330. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1982) "La logica provvidenzialistica e il capitolo XXVI del Principe", ''Interpres'' IV, pp. 262–384. | |||
* Martelli, Mario (1974), "L´altro Niccolò di Bernardo Machiavelli", ''Rinascimento'', XIV, pp. 39–100. | |||
* Sasso, Gennaro (1993), ''Machiavelli: storia del suo pensiero politico'', II vol., Bologna, Il Mulino, | |||
* Sasso, Gennaro (1987–1997) ''Machiavelli e gli antichi e altri saggi'', 4 vols., Milano, R. Ricciardi | |||
{{refend}} | |||
===Editions=== | |||
{{Persondata | |||
{{refbegin}} | |||
|NAME=Machiavelli, Niccolò | |||
'''Collections''' | |||
|ALTERNATIVE NAMES=Machiavelli, Niccolo | |||
* Gilbert, Allan H. ed. ''Machiavelli: The Chief Works and Others,'' (3 vol. 1965), the standard scholarly edition | |||
|SHORT DESCRIPTION=Italian politician and political theorist | |||
* Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. ''The Portable Machiavelli'' (1979) | |||
|DATE OF BIRTH=], ] | |||
* Penman, Bruce. ''The Prince and Other Political Writings,'' (1981) | |||
|PLACE OF BIRTH=] | |||
* {{Citation |editor-last=Wootton |editor-first=David |title=Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli |location=Indianapolis |publisher=Hackett Pubs. |year=1994}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210316084453/https://www.amazon.com/dp/087220247X |date=16 March 2021 }} | |||
|DATE OF DEATH=], ] | |||
|PLACE OF DEATH=Florence | |||
}} | |||
'''The Prince''' | |||
{{link FA|ar}} | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince with Related Documents |year=2016 |publisher=Bedford/St. Martin's |location=Boston |isbn=978-1319048921 |edition=2nd |url=http://www.macmillanlearning.com/Catalog/product/prince-secondedition-connell}}. Translated by ] | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Adagio Press |location=US |year=2015 |isbn=978-0996767705}}. Edited by W. Garner. Translated by Luigi Ricci. {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.amazon.com/Prince-Niccolo-Machiavelli/dp/0996767703 |date=18 November 2022 }} | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Penguin |location=London |year=1961 |isbn=978-0140449150}}. Translated by ] | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Penguin |location=London |year=2009 |isbn=978-1846140440}}. Translated by ] | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=W.W. Norton & Company |location=New York |year=1992 |isbn=0393962202}}. Translated by ] (Norton Critical Edition, 2nd ed., with "Backgrounds, Interpretations, Marginalia"). | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |year=2006 |title=El Principe/The Prince: Comentado Por Napoleon Bonaparte / Commentaries by Napoleon Buonaparte |publisher=Mestas Ediciones}}. Translated into Spanish by Marina Massa-Carrara | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1985}}. Translated by Harvey Mansfield | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |year=1995 |publisher=Everyman}}. Translated and Edited by Stephen J. Milner. Introduction, Notes and other critical apparatus by J.M. Dent. | |||
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Peter Bondanella (1998) 101 pp {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100425072104/http://www.questia.com/read/97573377?title=The%20Prince |date=25 April 2010 }} | |||
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Rufus Goodwin and Benjamin Martinez (2003) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210317074201/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0937832383 |date=17 March 2021 }} | |||
* ''The Prince'' (2007) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210310164023/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0979415403 |date=10 March 2021 }} | |||
* Machiavelli, Niccolò. ''The Prince,'' (1908 edition tr by W. K. Marriott) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090924041033/http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/1232 |date=24 September 2009 }} | |||
* {{Citation |last=Marriott |first=W. K. |title=The Prince |publisher=Red and Black Publishers |year=2008}} {{ISBN|978-1934941003}} | |||
* ''Il principe'' (2006) ed. by Mario Martelli and Nicoletta Marcelli, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, Salerno Editrice, Roma. | |||
'''The Discourses on Livy''' | |||
{{Link FA|ar}} | |||
* ''Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'' (2001), ed. by Francesco Bausi, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, II vol. Salerno Editrice, Roma. | |||
* ''The Discourses,'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120815054146/http://constitution.org/mac/disclivy_.htm |date=15 August 2012 }} | |||
* ''The Discourses,'' tr. with introduction and notes by L. J. Walker (2 vol 1950). | |||
* Machiavelli, Niccolò (1531). '']''. Translated by Leslie J. Walker, S.J, revisions by Brian Richardson (2003). London: Penguin Books. {{ISBN|0-14-044428-9}} | |||
* ''The Discourses,'' edited with an introduction by Bernard Crick (1970). | |||
'''The Art of War''' | |||
] | |||
* ''The Seven Books on the Art of War'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120716191533/http://www.constitution.org/mac/artofwar_.htm |date=16 July 2012 }} | |||
] | |||
* ''The Art of War'', University of Chicago Press, edited with new translation and commentary by ] (2003) | |||
] | |||
* ''The Art of War'' | |||
] | |||
* ''The Art of War'', Niccolò Machiavelli. Da Capo press edition, 2001, with introduction by Neal Wood. | |||
] | |||
] | |||
'''Florentine Histories''' | |||
] | |||
* ''History of Florence'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080920223244/http://www.gutenberg.org/files/2464/2464-h/2464-h.htm |date=20 September 2008 }} | |||
] | |||
* ''Reform of Florence'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120815053458/http://constitution.org/mac/florence.htm |date=15 August 2012 }} | |||
] | |||
* {{Citation |title=Florentine Histories |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |year=1988 |publisher=Princeton University Press}}. Translation by Laura F. Banfield and Harvey Mansfield, Jr. | |||
'''Correspondence''' | |||
* ''Epistolario privado. Las cartas que nos desvelan el pensamiento y la personalidad de uno de los intelectuales más importantes del Renacimiento'', Juan Manuel Forte (edición y traducción), Madrid, La Esfera de los Libros, 2007, 435 págs, {{ISBN|978-8497346610}} | |||
* ''The Private Correspondence of Niccolò Machiavelli,'' ed. by Orestes Ferrara; (1929) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090623124540/http://www.questia.com/read/77267435?title=The%20Private%20Correspondence%20of%20Nicolo%20Machiavelli |date=23 June 2009 }} | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence |year=1996 |publisher=Northern Illinois University Press}}. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices. | |||
* Also see {{Harvtxt|Najemy|1993}}. | |||
'''Poetry and comedy''' | |||
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=Comedies of Machiavelli |year=1985 |publisher=University Press of New England}} Bilingual edition of ''The Woman from Andros'', '']'', and '']'', edited by David Sices and James B. Atkinson. | |||
* Hoeges, Dirk. ''Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano'', Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, {{ISBN|3631546696}}. | |||
{{refend}} | |||
==External links== | |||
{{Sister project links |wikt=no |commons=Niccolò Machiavelli |b=no |n=no |q=Niccolò Machiavelli |s=Author:Niccolò Machiavelli |v=no |species=no}} | |||
* {{StandardEbooks|Standard Ebooks URL=https://standardebooks.org/ebooks/niccolo-machiavelli}} | |||
* {{Gutenberg author |id=563}} | |||
* {{Internet Archive author |sname=Niccolò Machiavelli}} | |||
* {{Librivox author |id=885}} | |||
* {{cite EB1911|wstitle=Machiavelli, Niccolò |volume=17 |pages=233–237 |short=x}} | |||
* | |||
* – ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.'' | |||
* {{cite Collier's New Encyclopedia|wstitle=Macchiavelli |volume=6 |page=53 |short=x}} | |||
* | |||
* ] article "" with extensive discussion of Machiavelli | |||
* : text, concordances and frequency list | |||
* : Italian and English text | |||
* | |||
{{Niccolò Machiavelli}} | |||
{{Political philosophy}} | |||
{{Authority control}} | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Machiavelli, Niccolo}} | |||
]<!--eponymous cat. always 1st--> | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 06:58, 24 December 2024
Florentine statesman, diplomat, and political theorist (1469–1527) For other uses, see Machiavelli (disambiguation) and Macchiavelli (surname).
Niccolò Machiavelli | |
---|---|
Portrait by Santi di Tito, c. 1550–1600 | |
Born | (1469-05-03)3 May 1469 Florence, Republic of Florence |
Died | 21 June 1527(1527-06-21) (aged 58) Florence, Republic of Florence |
Notable work | |
Spouse |
Marietta Corsini (m. 1501) |
Era | Renaissance philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | |
Main interests | Politics and political philosophy, military theory, history |
Notable ideas | Classical realism, virtù, modern republicanism, national interest |
Signature | |
Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli (3 May 1469 – 21 June 1527) was a Florentine diplomat, author, philosopher, and historian who lived during the Italian Renaissance. He is best known for his political treatise The Prince (Il Principe), written around 1513 but not published until 1532, five years after his death. He has often been called the father of modern political philosophy and political science.
For many years he served as a senior official in the Florentine Republic with responsibilities in diplomatic and military affairs. He wrote comedies, carnival songs, and poetry. His personal correspondence is also important to historians and scholars of Italian correspondence. He worked as secretary to the second chancery of the Republic of Florence from 1498 to 1512, when the Medici were out of power.
After his death Machiavelli's name came to evoke unscrupulous acts of the sort he advised most famously in his work, The Prince. He claimed that his experience and reading of history showed him that politics has always involved deception, treachery, and crime. He advised rulers to engage in evil when political necessity requires it, and argued specifically that successful reformers of states should not be blamed for killing other leaders who could block change. Machiavelli's Prince has been surrounded by controversy since it was published. Some consider it to be a straightforward description of political reality. Others view The Prince as a manual, teaching would-be tyrants how they should seize and maintain power. Even into recent times, some scholars, such as Leo Strauss, have restated the traditional opinion that Machiavelli was a "teacher of evil".
Even though Machiavelli has become most famous for his work on principalities, scholars also give attention to the exhortations in his other works of political philosophy. While less well known than The Prince, the Discourses on Livy (composed c. 1517) has been said to have paved the way for modern republicanism. His works were a major influence on Enlightenment authors who revived interest in classical republicanism, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau and James Harrington. Machiavelli's political realism has continued to influence generations of academics and politicians, including Hannah Arendt, and his approach has been compared to the Realpolitik of figures such as Otto von Bismarck.
Life
For a chronological guide, see Timeline of Niccolò Machiavelli.Machiavelli was born in Florence, Italy, the third child and first son of attorney Bernardo di Niccolò Machiavelli and his wife, Bartolomea di Stefano Nelli, on 3 May 1469. The Machiavelli family is believed to be descended from the old marquesses of Tuscany and to have produced thirteen Florentine Gonfalonieres of Justice, one of the offices of a group of nine citizens selected by drawing lots every two months and who formed the government, or Signoria; he was never, though, a full citizen of Florence because of the nature of Florentine citizenship in that time even under the republican regime. Machiavelli married Marietta Corsini in 1501. They had seven children, five sons and two daughters: Primerana, Bernardo, Lodovico, Guido, Piero [it], Baccina and Totto.
Machiavelli was born in a tumultuous era. The Italian city-states, and the families and individuals who ran them could rise and fall suddenly, as popes and the kings of France, Spain, and the Holy Roman Empire waged acquisitive wars for regional influence and control. Political-military alliances continually changed, featuring condottieri (mercenary leaders), who changed sides without warning, and the rise and fall of many short-lived governments.
Machiavelli was taught grammar, rhetoric, and Latin by his teacher, Paolo da Ronciglione. It is unknown whether Machiavelli knew Greek; Florence was at the time one of the centres of Greek scholarship in Europe. In 1494 Florence restored the republic, expelling the Medici family that had ruled Florence for some sixty years. Shortly after the execution of Savonarola, Machiavelli was appointed to an office of the second chancery, a medieval writing office that put Machiavelli in charge of the production of official Florentine government documents. Shortly thereafter, he was also made the secretary of the Dieci di Libertà e Pace.
In the first decade of the sixteenth century, he carried out several diplomatic missions, most notably to the papacy in Rome. Florence sent him to Pistoia to pacify the leaders of two opposing factions which had broken into riots in 1501 and 1502; when this failed, the leaders were banished from the city, a strategy which Machiavelli had favoured from the outset. From 1502 to 1503, he witnessed the brutal reality of the state-building methods of Cesare Borgia (1475–1507) and his father, Pope Alexander VI, who were then engaged in the process of trying to bring a large part of central Italy under their possession. The pretext of defending Church interests was used as a partial justification by the Borgias. Other excursions to the court of Louis XII and the Spanish court influenced his writings such as The Prince.
At the start of the 16th century, Machiavelli conceived of a militia for Florence, and he then began recruiting and creating it. He distrusted mercenaries (a distrust that he explained in his official reports and then later in his theoretical works for their unpatriotic and uninvested nature in the war that makes their allegiance fickle and often unreliable when most needed), and instead staffed his army with citizens, a policy that yielded some positive results. By February 1506 he was able to have four hundred farmers marching on parade, suited (including iron breastplates), and armed with lances and small firearms. Under his command, Florentine citizen-soldiers conquered Pisa in 1509.
Machiavelli's success was short-lived. In August 1512, the Medici, backed by Pope Julius II, used Spanish troops to defeat the Florentines at Prato. In the wake of the siege, Piero Soderini resigned as Florentine head of state and fled into exile. The experience would, like Machiavelli's time in foreign courts and with the Borgia, heavily influence his political writings. The Florentine city-state and the republic were dissolved, with Machiavelli then being removed from office and banished from the city for a year. In 1513, the Medici accused him of conspiracy against them and had him imprisoned. Despite being subjected to torture ("with the rope", in which the prisoner is hanged from his bound wrists from the back, forcing the arms to bear the body's weight and dislocating the shoulders), he denied involvement and was released after three weeks.
Machiavelli then retired to his farm estate at Sant'Andrea in Percussina, near San Casciano in Val di Pesa, where he devoted himself to studying and writing political treatises. During this period, he represented the Florentine Republic on diplomatic visits to France, Germany, and elsewhere in Italy. Despairing of the opportunity to remain directly involved in political matters, after a time he began to participate in intellectual groups in Florence and wrote several plays that (unlike his works on political theory) were both popular and widely known in his lifetime. Politics remained his main passion, and to satisfy this interest, he maintained a well-known correspondence with more politically connected friends, attempting to become involved once again in political life. In a letter to Francesco Vettori, he described his experience:
When evening comes, I go back home, and go to my study. On the threshold, I take off my work clothes, covered in mud and filth, and I put on the clothes an ambassador would wear. Decently dressed, I enter the ancient courts of rulers who have long since died. There, I am warmly welcomed, and I feed on the only food I find nourishing and was born to savour. I am not ashamed to talk to them and ask them to explain their actions and they, out of kindness, answer me. Four hours go by without my feeling any anxiety. I forget every worry. I am no longer afraid of poverty or frightened of death. I live entirely through them.
Machiavelli died on 21 June 1527 from a stomach ailment at the age of 58 after receiving his last rites. He was buried at the Church of Santa Croce in Florence. In 1789 George Nassau Clavering, and Pietro Leopoldo, Grand Duke of Tuscany, initiated the construction of a monument on Machiavelli's tomb. It was sculpted by Innocenzo Spinazzi, with an epitaph by Doctor Ferroni inscribed on it.
Major works
The Prince
Main article: The PrinceMachiavelli's best-known book Il Principe contains several maxims concerning politics. Instead of the more traditional target audience of a hereditary prince, it concentrates on the possibility of a "new prince". To retain power, the hereditary prince must carefully balance the interests of a variety of institutions to which the people are accustomed. By contrast, a new prince has the more difficult task in ruling: He must first stabilise his newfound power in order to build an enduring political structure. Machiavelli suggests that the political benefits of stability and security can be achieved in the face of moral corruption. Machiavelli believed that public and private morality had to be understood as two different things in order to rule well. As a result, a ruler must be concerned not only with reputation, but also must be positively willing to act unscrupulously at the right times. Machiavelli believed that, for a ruler, it was better to be widely feared than to be greatly loved; a loved ruler retains authority by obligation, while a feared leader rules by fear of punishment. As a political theorist, Machiavelli emphasized the "necessity" for the methodical exercise of brute force or deceit, including extermination of entire noble families, to head off any chance of a challenge to the prince's authority.
Scholars often note that Machiavelli glorifies instrumentality in state building, an approach embodied by the saying, often attributed to interpretations of The Prince, "The ends justify the means". Fraud and deceit are held by Machiavelli as necessary for a prince to use. Violence may be necessary for the successful stabilization of power and introduction of new political institutions. Force may be used to eliminate political rivals, destroy resistant populations, and purge the community of other men strong enough of a character to rule, who will inevitably attempt to replace the ruler. In one passage, Machiavelli subverts the advice given by Cicero to avoid duplicity and violence, by saying that the prince should "be the fox to avoid the snares, and a lion to overwhelm the wolves". It would become one of Machiavelli's most famous maxims. Machiavelli's view that acquiring a state and maintaining it requires evil means has been noted as the chief theme of the treatise. Machiavelli has become infamous for such political advice, ensuring that he would be remembered in history through the adjective "Machiavellian".
Due to the treatise's controversial analysis on politics, in 1559, the Catholic Church banned The Prince, putting it on the Index Librorum Prohibitorum. Humanists, including Erasmus (c. 1466 – 1536), also viewed the book negatively. As a treatise, its primary intellectual contribution to the history of political thought is the fundamental break between political realism and political idealism, due to it being a manual on acquiring and keeping political power. In contrast with Plato and Aristotle, Machiavelli insisted that an imaginary ideal society is not a model by which a prince should orient himself.
Concerning the differences and similarities in Machiavelli's advice to ruthless and tyrannical princes in The Prince and his more republican exhortations in Discourses on Livy, a few commentators assert that The Prince, although written as advice for a monarchical prince, contains arguments for the superiority of republican regimes, similar to those found in the Discourses. In the 18th century, the work was even called a satire, for example by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).
Scholars such as Leo Strauss (1899–1973) and Harvey Mansfield (b. 1932) have stated that sections of The Prince and his other works have deliberately esoteric statements throughout them. However, Mansfield states that this is the result of Machiavelli's seeing grave and serious things as humorous because they are "manipulable by men", and sees them as grave because they "answer human necessities".
The Marxist theorist Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937) argued that Machiavelli's audience was the common people, as opposed to the ruling class, who were already made aware of the methods described through their education.
Discourses on Livy
Main article: Discourses on LivyThe Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius, written around 1517, and published in 1531, often referred to simply as the Discourses or Discorsi, is nominally a discussion regarding the classical history of early Ancient Rome, although it strays far from this subject matter and also uses contemporary political examples to illustrate points. Machiavelli presents it as a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured. It is a larger work than The Prince, and while it more openly explains the advantages of republics, it also contains many similar themes from his other works. For example, Machiavelli has noted that to save a republic from corruption, it is necessary to return it to a "kingly state" using violent means. He excuses Romulus for murdering his brother Remus and co-ruler Titus Tatius to gain absolute power for himself in that he established a "civil way of life". Commentators disagree about how much the two works agree with each other, as Machiavelli frequently refers to leaders of republics as "princes". Machiavelli even sometimes acts as an advisor to tyrants. Other scholars have pointed out the aggrandizing and imperialistic features of Machiavelli's republic. Nevertheless, it became one of the central texts of modern republicanism, and has often been argued to be a more comprehensive work than The Prince.
Originality
Major commentary on Machiavelli's work has focused on two issues: how unified and philosophical his work is and how innovative or traditional it is.
Coherence
There is some disagreement concerning how best to describe the unifying themes, if there are any, that can be found in Machiavelli's works, especially in the two major political works, The Prince and Discourses. Some commentators have described him as inconsistent, and perhaps as not even putting a high priority on consistency. Others such as Hans Baron have argued that his ideas must have changed dramatically over time. Some have argued that his conclusions are best understood as a product of his times, experiences and education. Others, such as Leo Strauss and Harvey Mansfield, have argued strongly that there is a strong and deliberate consistency and distinctness, even arguing that this extends to all of Machiavelli's works including his comedies and letters.
Influences
Commentators such as Leo Strauss have gone so far as to name Machiavelli as the deliberate originator of modernity itself. Others have argued that Machiavelli is only a particularly interesting example of trends which were happening around him. In any case, Machiavelli presented himself at various times as someone reminding Italians of the old virtues of the Romans and Greeks, and other times as someone promoting a completely new approach to politics.
That Machiavelli had a wide range of influences is in itself not controversial. Their relative importance is however a subject of ongoing discussion. It is possible to summarize some of the main influences emphasized by different commentators.
The Mirror of Princes genre
Gilbert (1938) summarized the similarities between The Prince and the genre it obviously imitates, the so-called "Mirror of Princes" style. This was a classically influenced genre, with models at least as far back as Xenophon and Isocrates. While Gilbert emphasized the similarities, however, he agreed with all other commentators that Machiavelli was particularly novel in the way he used this genre, even when compared to his contemporaries such as Baldassare Castiglione and Erasmus. One of the major innovations Gilbert noted was that Machiavelli focused on the "deliberate purpose of dealing with a new ruler who will need to establish himself in defiance of custom". Normally, these types of works were addressed only to hereditary princes. (Xenophon is also an exception in this regard.)
Classical republicanism
Commentators such as Quentin Skinner and J.G.A. Pocock, in the so-called "Cambridge School" of interpretation, have asserted that some of the republican themes in Machiavelli's political works, particularly the Discourses on Livy, can be found in medieval Italian literature which was influenced by classical authors such as Sallust.
Classical political philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle
The Socratic school of classical political philosophy, especially Aristotle, had become a major influence upon European political thinking in the late Middle Ages. It existed both in the Catholicised form presented by Thomas Aquinas, and in the more controversial "Averroist" form of authors like Marsilius of Padua. Machiavelli was critical of Catholic political thinking and may have been influenced by Averroism. But he rarely cites Plato and Aristotle, and most likely did not approve of them. Leo Strauss argued that the strong influence of Xenophon, a student of Socrates more known as a historian, rhetorician and soldier, was a major source of Socratic ideas for Machiavelli, sometimes not in line with Aristotle. While interest in Plato was increasing in Florence during Machiavelli's lifetime, Machiavelli does not show particular interest in him, but was indirectly influenced by his readings of authors such as Polybius, Plutarch and Cicero.
The major difference between Machiavelli and the Socratics, according to Strauss, is Machiavelli's materialism, and therefore his rejection of both a teleological view of nature and of the view that philosophy is higher than politics. With their teleological understanding of things, Socratics argued that by nature, everything that acts, acts towards some end, as if nature desired them, but Machiavelli claimed that such things happen by blind chance or human action.
Classical materialism
Strauss argued that Machiavelli may have seen himself as influenced by some ideas from classical materialists such as Democritus, Epicurus and Lucretius. Strauss however sees this also as a sign of major innovation in Machiavelli, because classical materialists did not share the Socratic regard for political life, while Machiavelli clearly did.
Thucydides
Some scholars note the similarity between Machiavelli and the Greek historian Thucydides, since both emphasized power politics. Strauss argued that Machiavelli may indeed have been influenced by pre-Socratic philosophers, but he felt it was a new combination:
...contemporary readers are reminded by Machiavelli's teaching of Thucydides; they find in both authors the same "realism", i.e., the same denial of the power of the gods or of justice and the same sensitivity to harsh necessity and elusive chance. Yet Thucydides never calls in question the intrinsic superiority of nobility to baseness, a superiority that shines forth particularly when the noble is destroyed by the base. Therefore Thucydides' History arouses in the reader a sadness which is never aroused by Machiavelli's books. In Machiavelli we find comedies, parodies, and satires but nothing reminding of tragedy. One half of humanity remains outside of his thought. There is no tragedy in Machiavelli because he has no sense of the sacredness of "the common". – Strauss (1958, p. 292)
Beliefs
Amongst commentators, there are a few consistently made proposals concerning what was most new in Machiavelli's work.
Empiricism and realism versus idealism
Machiavelli is sometimes seen as the prototype of a modern empirical scientist, building generalizations from experience and historical facts, and emphasizing the uselessness of theorizing with the imagination.
He emancipated politics from theology and moral philosophy. He undertook to describe simply what rulers actually did and thus anticipated what was later called the scientific spirit in which questions of good and bad are ignored, and the observer attempts to discover only what really happens.
— Joshua Kaplan, 2005
Machiavelli felt that his early schooling along the lines of traditional classical education was essentially useless for the purpose of understanding politics. Nevertheless, he advocated intensive study of the past, particularly regarding the founding of a city, which he felt was a key to understanding its later development. Moreover, he studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. Machiavelli denies the classical opinion that living virtuously always leads to happiness. For example, Machiavelli viewed misery as "one of the vices that enables a prince to rule." Machiavelli stated that "it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved." In much of Machiavelli's work, he often states that the ruler must adopt unsavoury policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime. Because cruelty and fraud play such important roles in his politics, it is not unusual for certain issues (such as murder and betrayal) to be commonplace within his works.
A related and more controversial proposal often made is that he described how to do things in politics in a way which seemed neutral concerning who used the advice – tyrants or good rulers. That Machiavelli strove for realism is not doubted, but for four centuries scholars have debated how best to describe his morality. The Prince made the word Machiavellian a byword for deceit, despotism, and political manipulation. Leo Strauss declared himself inclined toward the traditional view that Machiavelli was self-consciously a "teacher of evil", since he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception. Strauss takes up this opinion because he asserted that failure to accept the traditional opinion misses the "intrepidity of his thought" and "the graceful subtlety of his speech". Italian anti-fascist philosopher Benedetto Croce (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values, in reality, do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make. German philosopher Ernst Cassirer (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist – a Galileo of politics – in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment. On the other hand, Walter Russell Mead has argued that The Prince's advice presupposes the importance of ideas like legitimacy in making changes to the political system.
Fortune
Machiavelli is generally seen as being critical of Christianity as it existed in his time, specifically its effect upon politics, and also everyday life. In his opinion, Christianity, along with the teleological Aristotelianism that the Church had come to accept, allowed practical decisions to be guided too much by imaginary ideals and encouraged people to lazily leave events up to providence or, as he would put it, chance, luck or fortune. While Christianity sees modesty as a virtue and pride as sinful, Machiavelli took a more classical position, seeing ambition, spiritedness, and the pursuit of glory as good and natural things, and part of the virtue and prudence that good princes should have. Therefore, while it was traditional to say that leaders should have virtues, especially prudence, Machiavelli's use of the words virtù and prudenza was unusual for his time, implying a spirited and immodest ambition. Mansfield describes his usage of virtù as a "compromise with evil". Famously, Machiavelli argued that virtue and prudence can help a man control more of his future, in the place of allowing fortune to do so.
Najemy has argued that this same approach can be found in Machiavelli's approach to love and desire, as seen in his comedies and correspondence. Najemy shows how Machiavelli's friend Vettori argued against Machiavelli and cited a more traditional understanding of fortune.
On the other hand, humanism in Machiavelli's time meant that classical pre-Christian ideas about virtue and prudence, including the possibility of trying to control one's future, were not unique to him. But humanists did not go so far as to promote the extra glory of deliberately aiming to establish a new state, in defiance of traditions and laws.
While Machiavelli's approach had classical precedents, it has been argued that it did more than just bring back old ideas and that Machiavelli was not a typical humanist. Strauss (1958) argues that the way Machiavelli combines classical ideas is new. While Xenophon and Plato also described realistic politics and were closer to Machiavelli than Aristotle was, they, like Aristotle, also saw philosophy as something higher than politics. Machiavelli was apparently a materialist who objected to explanations involving formal and final causation, or teleology.
Machiavelli's promotion of ambition among leaders while denying any higher standard meant that he encouraged risk-taking, and innovation, most famously the founding of new modes and orders. His advice to princes was therefore certainly not limited to discussing how to maintain a state. It has been argued that Machiavelli's promotion of innovation led directly to the argument for progress as an aim of politics and civilization. But while a belief that humanity can control its own future, control nature, and "progress" has been long-lasting, Machiavelli's followers, starting with his own friend Guicciardini, have tended to prefer peaceful progress through economic development, and not warlike progress. As Harvey Mansfield (1995, p. 74) wrote: "In attempting other, more regular and scientific modes of overcoming fortune, Machiavelli's successors formalized and emasculated his notion of virtue."
Machiavelli however, along with some of his classical predecessors, saw ambition and spiritedness, and therefore war, as inevitable and part of human nature.
Strauss concludes his 1958 book Thoughts on Machiavelli by proposing that this promotion of progress leads directly to the advent of new technologies being invented in both good and bad governments. Strauss argued that the unavoidable nature of such arms races, which existed before modern times and led to the collapse of peaceful civilizations, show that classical-minded men "had to admit in other words that in an important respect the good city has to take its bearings by the practice of bad cities or that the bad impose their law on the good".Strauss (1958, pp. 298–299)
Religion
Machiavelli shows repeatedly that he saw religion as man-made, and that the value of religion lies in its contribution to social order and the rules of morality must be dispensed with if security requires it. In The Prince, the Discourses and in the Life of Castruccio Castracani he describes "prophets", as he calls them, like Moses, Romulus, Cyrus the Great and Theseus (he treated pagan and Christian patriarchs in the same way) as the greatest of new princes, the glorious and brutal founders of the most novel innovations in politics, and men whom Machiavelli assures us have always used a large amount of armed force and murder against their own people. He estimated that these sects last from 1,666 to 3,000 years each time, which, as pointed out by Leo Strauss, would mean that Christianity became due to start finishing about 150 years after Machiavelli. Machiavelli's concern with Christianity as a sect was that it makes men weak and inactive, delivering politics into the hands of cruel and wicked men without a fight. While Machiavelli's own religious allegiance has been debated, it is assumed that he had a low regard of contemporary Christianity.
While fear of God can be replaced by fear of the prince, if there is a strong enough prince, Machiavelli felt that having a religion is in any case especially essential to keeping a republic in order. For Machiavelli, a truly great prince can never be conventionally religious himself, but he should make his people religious if he can. According to Strauss (1958, pp. 226–227) he was not the first person to explain religion in this way, but his description of religion was novel because of the way he integrated this into his general account of princes.
Machiavelli's judgment that governments need religion for practical political reasons was widespread among modern proponents of republics until approximately the time of the French Revolution. This, therefore, represents a point of disagreement between Machiavelli and late modernity.
Positive side to factional and individual vice
Despite the classical precedents, which Machiavelli was not the only one to promote in his time, Machiavelli's realism and willingness to argue that good ends justify bad things, is seen as a critical stimulus towards some of the most important theories of modern politics.
Firstly, particularly in the Discourses on Livy, Machiavelli is unusual in the positive side to factionalism in republics which he sometimes seems to describe. For example, quite early in the Discourses, (in Book I, chapter 4), a chapter title announces that the disunion of the plebs and senate in Rome "kept Rome free". That a community has different components whose interests must be balanced in any good regime is an idea with classical precedents, but Machiavelli's particularly extreme presentation is seen as a critical step towards the later political ideas of both a division of powers or checks and balances, ideas which lay behind the US constitution, as well as many other modern state constitutions.
Similarly, the modern economic argument for capitalism, and most modern forms of economics, was often stated in the form of "public virtue from private vices". Also in this case, even though there are classical precedents, Machiavelli's insistence on being both realistic and ambitious, not only admitting that vice exists but being willing to risk encouraging it, is a critical step on the path to this insight.
Mansfield however argues that Machiavelli's own aims have not been shared by those he influenced. Machiavelli argued against seeing mere peace and economic growth as worthy aims on their own if they would lead to what Mansfield calls the "taming of the prince".
Influence
To quote Robert Bireley:
...there were in circulation approximately fifteen editions of the Prince and nineteen of the Discourses and French translations of each before they were placed on the Index of Paul IV in 1559, a measure which nearly stopped publication in Catholic areas except in France. Three principal writers took the field against Machiavelli between the publication of his works and their condemnation in 1559 and again by the Tridentine Index in 1564. These were the English cardinal Reginald Pole and the Portuguese bishop Jeronymo Osorio, both of whom lived for many years in Italy, and the Italian humanist and later bishop, Ambrogio Caterino Politi.
Machiavelli's ideas had a profound impact on political leaders throughout the modern west, helped by the new technology of the printing press. During the first generations after Machiavelli, his main influence was in non-republican governments. Pole reported that The Prince was spoken of highly by Thomas Cromwell in England and had influenced Henry VIII in his turn towards Protestantism, and in his tactics, for example during the Pilgrimage of Grace. A copy was also possessed by the Catholic king and emperor Charles V. In France, after an initially mixed reaction, Machiavelli came to be associated with Catherine de' Medici and the St. Bartholomew's Day massacre. As Bireley (1990:17) reports, in the 16th century, Catholic writers "associated Machiavelli with the Protestants, whereas Protestant authors saw him as Italian and Catholic". In fact, he was apparently influencing both Catholic and Protestant kings.
One of the most important early works dedicated to criticism of Machiavelli, especially The Prince, was that of the Huguenot, Innocent Gentillet, whose work commonly referred to as Discourse against Machiavelli or Anti Machiavel was published in Geneva in 1576. He accused Machiavelli of being an atheist and accused politicians of his time by saying that his works were the "Koran of the courtiers", that "he is of no reputation in the court of France which hath not Machiavel's writings at the fingers ends". Another theme of Gentillet was more in the spirit of Machiavelli himself: he questioned the effectiveness of immoral strategies (just as Machiavelli had himself done, despite also explaining how they could sometimes work). This became the theme of much future political discourse in Europe during the 17th century. This includes the Catholic Counter Reformation writers summarised by Bireley: Giovanni Botero, Justus Lipsius, Carlo Scribani, Adam Contzen, Pedro de Ribadeneira, and Diego de Saavedra Fajardo. These authors criticized Machiavelli, but also followed him in many ways. They accepted the need for a prince to be concerned with reputation, and even a need for cunning and deceit, but compared to Machiavelli, and like later modernist writers, they emphasized economic progress much more than the riskier ventures of war. These authors tended to cite Tacitus as their source for realist political advice, rather than Machiavelli, and this pretence came to be known as "Tacitism". "Black tacitism" was in support of princely rule, but "red tacitism" arguing the case for republics, more in the original spirit of Machiavelli himself, became increasingly important. Cardinal Reginald Pole read The Prince while he was in Italy, and on which he gave his comments. Frederick the Great, king of Prussia and patron of Voltaire, wrote Anti-Machiavel, with the aim of rebutting The Prince.
Modern materialist philosophy developed in the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, starting in the generations after Machiavelli. Modern political philosophy tended to be republican, but as with the Catholic authors, Machiavelli's realism and encouragement of innovation to try to control one's own fortune were more accepted than his emphasis upon war and factional violence. Not only was innovative economics and politics a result, but also modern science, leading some commentators to say that the 18th century Enlightenment involved a "humanitarian" moderating of Machiavellianism.
The importance of Machiavelli's influence is notable in many important figures in this endeavour, for example Bodin, Francis Bacon, Algernon Sidney, Harrington, John Milton, Spinoza, Rousseau, Hume, Edward Gibbon, and Adam Smith. Although he was not always mentioned by name as an inspiration, due to his controversy, he is also thought to have been an influence for other major philosophers, such as Montaigne, Descartes, Hobbes, Locke and Montesquieu. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who is associated with very different political ideas, viewed Machiavelli's work as a satirical piece in which Machiavelli exposes the faults of a one-man rule rather than exalting amorality.
In the seventeenth century it was in England that Machiavelli's ideas were most substantially developed and adapted, and that republicanism came once more to life; and out of seventeenth-century English republicanism there were to emerge in the next century not only a theme of English political and historical reflection – of the writings of the Bolingbroke circle and of Gibbon and of early parliamentary radicals – but a stimulus to the Enlightenment in Scotland, on the Continent, and in America.
Scholars have argued that Machiavelli was a major indirect and direct influence upon the political thinking of the Founding Fathers of the United States due to his overwhelming favouritism of republicanism and the republican type of government. According to John McCormick, it is still very much debatable whether or not Machiavelli was "an advisor of tyranny or partisan of liberty." Benjamin Franklin, James Madison and Thomas Jefferson followed Machiavelli's republicanism when they opposed what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared Alexander Hamilton was creating with the Federalist Party. Hamilton learned from Machiavelli about the importance of foreign policy for domestic policy, but may have broken from him regarding how rapacious a republic needed to be in order to survive. George Washington was less influenced by Machiavelli.
The Founding Father who perhaps most studied and valued Machiavelli as a political philosopher was John Adams, who profusely commented on the Italian's thought in his work, A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America. In this work, John Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and Montesquieu, as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.
20th century
The 20th-century Italian Communist Antonio Gramsci drew great inspiration from Machiavelli's writings on ethics, morals, and how they relate to the State and revolution in his writings on Passive Revolution, and how a society can be manipulated by controlling popular notions of morality.
Joseph Stalin read The Prince and annotated his own copy.
In the 20th century there was also renewed interest in Machiavelli's play La Mandragola (1518), which received numerous stagings, including several in New York, at the New York Shakespeare Festival in 1976 and the Riverside Shakespeare Company in 1979, as a musical comedy by Peer Raben in Munich's Anti Theatre in 1971, and at London's National Theatre in 1984.
"Machiavellian"
Machiavelli's works are sometimes even said to have contributed to the modern negative connotations of the words politics and politician, and it is sometimes thought that it is because of him that Old Nick became an English term for the Devil. More obviously, the adjective Machiavellian became a term describing a form of politics that is "marked by cunning, duplicity, or bad faith". Machiavellianism also remains a popular term used casually in political discussions, often as a byword for bare-knuckled political realism.
While Machiavellianism is notable in the works of Machiavelli, scholars generally agree that his works are complex and have equally influential themes within them. For example, J. G. A. Pocock (1975) saw him as a major source of the republicanism that spread throughout England and North America in the 17th and 18th centuries and Leo Strauss (1958), whose view of Machiavelli is quite different in many ways, had similar remarks about Machiavelli's influence on republicanism and argued that even though Machiavelli was a teacher of evil he had a "grandeur of vision" that led him to advocate immoral actions. Whatever his intentions, which are still debated today, he has become associated with any proposal where "the end justifies the means". For example, Leo Strauss (1987, p. 297) wrote:
Machiavelli is the only political thinker whose name has come into common use for designating a kind of politics, which exists and will continue to exist independently of his influence, a politics guided exclusively by considerations of expediency, which uses all means, fair or foul, iron or poison, for achieving its ends – its end being the aggrandizement of one's country or fatherland – but also using the fatherland in the service of the self-aggrandizement of the politician or statesman or one's party.
In popular culture
Main article: Machiavelli in popular cultureDue to Machiavelli's popularity, he has been featured in various ways in cultural depictions. In English Renaissance theatre (Elizabethan and Jacobian), the term "Machiavel" (from 'Nicholas Machiavel', an "anglicization" of Machiavelli's name based on French) was used for a stock antagonist that resorted to ruthless means to preserve the power of the state, and is now considered a synonym of "Machiavellian".
Christopher Marlowe's play The Jew of Malta (ca. 1589) contains a prologue by a character called Machiavel, a Senecan ghost based on Machiavelli. Machiavel expresses the cynical view that power is amoral, saying:
"I count religion but a childish toy,
And hold there is no sin but ignorance."
Shakespeares titular character, Richard III, refers to Machiavelli in Henry VI, Part III, as the "murderous Machiavel".
Works
See also: Category:Works by Niccolò MachiavelliPolitical and historical works
- Discorso sopra le cose di Pisa (1499)
- Del modo di trattare i popoli della Valdichiana ribellati (1502)
- Descrizione del modo tenuto dal Duca Valentino nello ammazzare Vitellozzo Vitelli, Oliverotto da Fermo, il Signor Pagolo e il duca di Gravina Orsini (1502) – A Description of the Methods Adopted by the Duke Valentino when Murdering Vitellozzo Vitelli, Oliverotto da Fermo, the Signor Pagolo, and the Duke di Gravina Orsini
- Discorso sopra la provisione del danaro (1502) – A discourse about the provision of money.
- Ritratti delle cose di Francia (1510) – Portrait of the affairs of France.
- Ritratto delle cose della Magna (1508–1512) – Portrait of the affairs of Germany.
- The Prince (1513)
- Discourses on Livy (1517)
- Dell'Arte della Guerra (1519–1520) – The Art of War, high military science.
- Discorso sopra il riformare lo stato di Firenze (1520) – A discourse about the reforming of Florence.
- Sommario delle cose della citta di Lucca (1520) – A summary of the affairs of the city of Lucca.
- The Life of Castruccio Castracani of Lucca (1520) – Vita di Castruccio Castracani da Lucca, a short biography.
- Istorie Fiorentine (1520–1525) – Florentine Histories, an eight-volume history of the city-state Florence, commissioned by Giulio de' Medici, later Pope Clement VII.
Fictional works
See also: Machiavelli as a dramatistBesides being a statesman and political scientist, Machiavelli also translated classical works, and was a playwright (Clizia, Mandragola), a poet (Sonetti, Canzoni, Ottave, Canti carnascialeschi), and a novelist (Belfagor arcidiavolo).
Some of his other work:
- Decennale primo (1506) – a poem in terza rima.
- Decennale secondo (1509) – a poem.
- Andria or The Girl from Andros (1517) – a semi-autobiographical comedy, adapted from Terence.
- Mandragola (1518) – The Mandrake – a five-act prose comedy, with a verse prologue.
- Clizia (1525) – a prose comedy.
- Belfagor arcidiavolo (1515) – a novella.
- Asino d'oro (1517) – The Golden Ass is a terza rima poem, a new version of the classic work by Apuleius.
- Frammenti storici (1525) – fragments of stories.
Other works
Della Lingua (Italian for "On the Language") (1514), a dialogue about Italy's language is normally attributed to Machiavelli.
Machiavelli's literary executor, Giuliano de' Ricci, also reported having seen that Machiavelli, his grandfather, made a comedy in the style of Aristophanes which included living Florentines as characters, and to be titled Le Maschere. It has been suggested that due to such things as this and his style of writing to his superiors generally, there was very likely some animosity to Machiavelli even before the return of the Medici.
See also
References
Footnotes
- /ˈnɪkəloʊ ˌmækiəˈvɛli/ NIK-ə-loh MAK-ee-ə-VEL-ee, US also /- ˌmɑːk-/ - MAHK-; Italian: [nikkoˈlɔ mmakjaˈvɛlli]; also occasionally rendered in English as Nicholas Machiavel (/ˈmækiəvɛl/ MAK-ee-ə-vel, US also /ˈmɑːk-/ MAHK-).
- The Latin legend reads: TANTO NOMINI NULLUM PAR ELOGIUM ("So great a name (has) no adequate praise" or "No eulogy (would be) a match for such a great name" or "There is no praise equal to so great a name.")
Citations
- "Machiavelli, Niccolò". Longman Dictionary of Contemporary English. Longman. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
- "Machievelli, Niccolò". Lexico US English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 10 February 2022.
- "Machiavelli". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (5th ed.). HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 February 2022.
- Dietz, Mary G.. Machiavelli, Niccolò (1469–1527), 1998, https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-S080-1. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis
- Berridge, G.R., Lloyd, L. (2012). M. In: Barder, B., Pope, L.E., Rana, K.S. (eds) The Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Diplomacy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137017611_13
- For example: "Niccolo Machiavelli – Italian statesman and writer". 17 June 2023. and "Niccolò Machiavelli". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 November 2018.
- For example: Smith, Gregory B. (2008). Between Eternities: On the Tradition of Political Philosophy, Past, Present, and Future. Lexington Books. p. 65. ISBN 978-0739120774., Whelan, Frederick G. (2004). Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought. Lexington Books. p. 29. ISBN 978-0739106310., Strauss (1988). What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies. University of Chicago Press. p. 41. ISBN 978-0226777139.
- Najemy 1993, p. missing
- "Niccolo Machiavelli". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 8 August 2019.
- Cassirer, Ernst (1946). The Myth of the State. Yale University Press. pp. 141–145. ISBN 978-0300000368.
ernst cassirer the myth of the state.
- For example, The Prince chap. 15, and The Discourses Book I, chapter 9
- Strauss, Leo; Cropsey, Joseph (2012). History of Political Philosophy. University of Chicago Press. p. 297. ISBN 978-0226924717.
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. p. 178. ISBN 978-0226503721.
- Giorgini, Giovanni (2013). "Five Hundred Years of Italian Scholarship on Machiavelli's Prince". Review of Politics. 75 (4): 625–640. doi:10.1017/S0034670513000624. ISSN 0034-6705. S2CID 146970196.
- Strauss, Leo (2014). Thoughts on Machiavelli. University of Chicago Press. p. 9. ISBN 978-0226230979.
- Harvey Mansfield and Nathan Tarcov, "Introduction to the Discourses". In their translation of the Discourses on Livy
- Theodosiadis, Michail (June–August 2021). "From Hobbes and Locke to Machiavelli's virtù in the political context of meliorism: popular eucosmia and the value of moral memory". Polis Revista. 11: 25–60.
- Pflanze, Otto (1958). "Bismarck's "Realpolitik"". The Review of Politics. 20 (4): 492–514. doi:10.1017/S0034670500034185. ISSN 0034-6705. JSTOR 1404857. S2CID 144663704.
- Arendt, Hannah (1988). The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press. p. 77.
- de Grazia (1989)
- Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1913). "Niccolò Machiavelli" . Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
- Guarini (1999:21)
- "Machiavèlli, Niccolò nell'Enciclopedia Treccani". www.treccani.it (in Italian). Retrieved 11 July 2023.
- Maurizio Viroli, Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli (2000), ch 1
- Niccolo Machiavelli Biography – Life of Florentine Republic Official, 13 December 2013
- "Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527)". IEP. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Ridolfi, Roberto (2013). The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli. Routledge. p. 28. ISBN 978-1135026615.
- Machiavelli 1981, p. 136, notes.
- "Niccolo Machiavelli | Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 July 2019.
- ^ Viroli, Maurizio (2002). Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli. Macmillan. pp. 81–86. ISBN 978-0374528003.
- This point is made especially in The Prince, Chap XII
- Viroli, Maurizio (2002). Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli. Macmillan. p. 105. ISBN 978-0374528003.
- Many historians have argued that this was due to Piero Soderini's unwillingness to compromise with the Medici, who were holding Prato under siege.
- ^ Machiavelli 1981, p. 3, intro.
- Skinner, Quentin (2000). Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. p. 36. ISBN 978-0191540349.
- Niccolò Machiavelli (1996), Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence, Northern Illinois University Press, translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.
- Joshua Kaplan, "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance," The Modern Scholar (14 lectures in the series; lecture #7 / disc 4), 2005.
- "Washingtonpost.com: Horizon Section". www.washingtonpost.com. Retrieved 3 November 2023.
- "Even such men as Malatesta and Machiavelli, after spending their lives in estrangement from the Church, sought on their deathbeds her assistance and consolations. Both made good confessions and received the Holy Viaticum." – Ludwig von Pastor, History of the Popes, Vol. 5, p. 137.
- Black, Robert (2013). Machiavelli. Routledge. p. 283. ISBN 978-1317699583.
- Sil, Narasingha Prosad (1985). Kauṭilya's Arthaśāstra: A Comparative Study. Academic Publishers Calcutta. p. 217.
- Zuckert, Catherine H. (2017). Machiavelli's Politics. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226434803.
- Machiavelli, Niccolo (1984). The Prince. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 59–60. ISBN 0-19-281602-0.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1532). The Prince. Italy. pp. 120–121.
- Machiavelli, The Prince, Chapter III
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503721.
- The Prince, Chapter XVIII, "In What Mode Should Faith Be Kept By Princes"
- The Prince. especially Chapters 3, 5 and 8
- Skinner, Quentin (12 October 2000). Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780191540349.
- Strauss (1958, pp. 12)
- Kanzler, Peter (2020). The Prince (1532), The Leviathan (1651), The Two Treatises of Government (1689), The Constitution of Pennsylvania (1776). Peter Kanzler. p. 22. ISBN 978-1716844508.
- Scott, John T. (31 March 2016). The Routledge Guidebook to Machiavelli's the Prince. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-53673-4.
- Landon, W. J. (2005). Politics, Patriotism and Language: Niccolò Machiavelli's" secular Patria" and the Creation of an Italian National Identity (Vol. 57). Peter Lang.
- Discourse on Political Economy: opening pages.
- Berlin, Isaiah. "The Originality of Machiavelli" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2 December 2012. Retrieved 18 October 2012.
- This point made most notably by Strauss (1958).
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. pp. 228–229. ISBN 978-0226503721.
- Thomas, Peter D. (2017). "The Modern Prince". History of Political Thought. 38 (3): 523–544. JSTOR 26210463.
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (2001). Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503707.
- "Discourses on Livy: Book 1, Chapter 18". www.constitution.org. Retrieved 9 May 2019.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 9. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 16. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
- Rahe, Paul A. (2005). Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy. Cambridge University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-1139448338.
- Hulliung, Mark (2017). Citizen Machiavelli. Routledge. ISBN 978-1351528481.
- Pocock (1975, pp. 183–219)
- ^ Fischer (2000)
- Interpreting Modern Political Philosophy: From Machiavelli to Marx, pg. 40
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503721.
- Skinner, Quentin (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought: Volume 1, The Renaissance. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521293372.
- Pocock, J. G. A. (2016). The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1400883516.
- ^ Strauss (1958)
- Paul Anthony Rahe, Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English Republic (2008), p. 282.
- Jack Donnelly, Realism and International Relations (2000), p. 68.
- ^ Joshua Kaplan (2005). "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance". The Modern Scholar.
14 lectures in the series; (lectures #7) – see disc 4
- Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, History of Political Philosophy (1987), p. 300.
- Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince, Chap 17.
- "Niccolò Machiavelli, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
- Strauss, Leo (2014). Thoughts on Machiavelli. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226230979.
- Strauss, Leo. Leo Strauss "Thoughts On Machiavelli". p. 9.
- Carritt, E. F. (1949). Benedetto Croce My Philosophy.
- Cassirer, Ernst (10 September 1961). The Myth of the State. New Haven, Connecticut; London, England: Yale University Press. p. 136. ISBN 978-0-300-00036-8.
- "When Isms go to War | StratBlog". 29 October 2013. Archived from the original on 29 October 2013. Retrieved 29 October 2019.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. p. 131. ISBN 978-0226500331.
- Mansfield, Harvey C. (25 February 1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. p. 233. ISBN 978-0-226-50372-1.
- Najemy 1993, p. missing.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11–15. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2010). The Prince: Second Edition. University of Chicago Press. pp. 69–71. ISBN 978-0226500508.
- Especially in the Discourses III.30, but also The Prince Chap.VI
- Strauss (1987, p. 314)
- See for example Strauss (1958, p. 206).
- Parsons, W. B. (2016). Machiavelli's gospel: The critique of Christianity in the prince. Boydell & Brewer.
- Vavouras, Elias; Theodosiadis, Michail (October 2024). "The Concept of Religion in Machiavelli: Political Methodology, Propaganda and Ideological Enlightenment". Religions. 15 (10): 1203. doi:10.3390/rel15101203. ISSN 2077-1444.
- Strauss (1958, p. 231)
- Mansfield (1993)
- Bireley, Robert (1990), The Counter Reformation Prince, p. 14.
- Bireley (1990:15)
- Haitsma Mulier (1999:248)
- While Bireley focuses on writers in the Catholic countries, Haitsma Mulier (1999) makes the same observation, writing with more of a focus upon the Protestant Netherlands.
- The first English edition was A Discourse upon the meanes of wel governing and maintaining in good peace, a Kingdome, or other principalitie, translated by Simon Patericke.
- Bireley (1990:17)
- Bireley (1990:18)
- Bireley (1990:223–230)
- Benner, Erica (28 November 2013). Machiavelli's Prince: A New Reading. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780191003929.
- "Anti-Machiavel | treatise by Frederick the Great". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 April 2019.
- Kennington (2004), Rahe (2006)
- Bireley (1990:17): "Jean Bodin's first comments, found in his Method for the Easy Comprehension of History, published in 1566, were positive."
- Bacon wrote: "We are much beholden to Machiavelli and other writers of that class who openly and unfeignedly declare or describe what men do, and not what they ought to do." "II.21.9", Of the Advancement of Learning. See Kennington (2004) Chapter 4.
- Rahe (2006) chapter 6.
- Worden (1999)
- "Spinoza's Political Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2013. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
- Danford "Getting Our Bearings: Machiavelli and Hume" in Rahe (2006).
- Schaefer (1990)
- Kennington (2004), chapter 11.
- Barnes Smith "The Philosophy of Liberty: Locke's Machiavellian Teaching" in Rahe (2006).
- Carrese "The Machiavellian Spirit of Montesquieu's Liberal Republic" in Rahe (2006)
- Shklar (1999)
- Worden (1999)
- John P. McCormick, Machiavellian democracy (Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 23.
- Rahe (2006)
- Walling "Was Alexander Hamilton a Machiavellian Statesman?" in Rahe (2006).
- Harper (2004)
- Spalding "The American Prince? George Washington's Anti-Machiavellian moment" in Rahe (2006)
- ^ Thompson (1995)
- Marcia Landy, "Culture and Politics in the work of Antonio Gramsci," 167–188, in Antonio Gramsci: Intellectuals, Culture, and the Party, ed. James Martin (New York: Routledge, 2002).
- Service, Robert. Stalin: A Biography, p.10.
- Review by Jann Racquoi, Heights/Inwood Press of North Manhattan, 14 March 1979.
- Bireley (1990, p. 241)
- Fischer (2000, p. 94)
- "Definition of MACHIAVELLIAN". merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 17 October 2018.
- Rahe, Paul A. (2005). Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy. Cambridge University Press. p. xxxvi. ISBN 978-1139448338.
- Meinecke, Friedrich (1957). Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d'État and Its Place in Modern History. Yale University Press. p. 36.
- Kahn, V. (1994). Machiavellian rhetoric: From the counter-reformation to Milton. Princeton University Press.
- "Machiavel". Oxford Reference. Retrieved 31 December 2021.
- "MACHIAVEL English Definition and Meaning | Lexico.com". Lexico Dictionaries. Archived from the original on 16 May 2021. Retrieved 31 December 2021.
- "Jew of Malta, The by MARLOWE, Christopher". Player FM. 2016. Retrieved 12 May 2018.
- "Henry VI, Part 3 - Entire Play | Folger Shakespeare Library".
- "First-time Machiavelli translation debuts at Yale". yaledailynews.com. 18 April 2012.
- Godman (1998, p. 240). Also see Black (1999, pp. 97–98)
Sources
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1981). The Prince and Selected Discourses. Translated by Daniel Donno. New York: Bantam Classic Books. ISBN 0553212273.
- Haitsma Mulier, Eco (1999). "A controversial republican". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.
- Harper, John Lamberton (2004). American Machiavelli: Alexander Hamilton and the Origins of US Foreign Policy. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521834858.
- Shklar, J. (1999). "Montesquieu and the new republicanism". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.
- Worden, Blair (1999). "Milton's republicanism and the tyranny of heaven". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.
Further reading
Biographies
- Baron, Hans (April 1961). "Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of 'the Prince'". The English Historical Review. 76 (299): 217–253. doi:10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217. JSTOR 557541.
- Black, Robert. Machiavelli: From Radical to Reactionary. London: Reaktion Books (2022)
- Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in Cambridge Modern History (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp. 190–218 online Google edition
- Capponi, Niccolò. An Unlikely Prince: The Life and Times of Machiavelli (Da Capo Press; 2010) 334 pages
- Celenza, Christopher S. Machiavelli: A Portrait (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2015) 240 pages. ISBN 978-0674416123
- Godman, Peter (1998), From Poliziano to Machiavelli: Florentine Humanism in the High Renaissance, Princeton University Press
- de Grazia, Sebastian (1989), Machiavelli in Hell, Knopf Doubleday Publishing, ISBN 978-0679743422, an intellectual biography that won the Pulitzer Prize; excerpt and text search Archived 9 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- Hale, J. R. Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy (1961) online edition Archived 19 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine
- Hulliung, Mark. Citizen Machiavelli (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 1983)
- Lee, Alexander. Machiavelli: His Life and Times (London: Picador, 2020)
- Oppenheimer, Paul. Machiavelli: A Life Beyond Ideology (London; New York: Continuum, 2011) ISBN 978-1847252210
- Ridolfi, Roberto. The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli (1963)
- Schevill, Ferdinand. Six Historians (1956), pp. 61–91
- Skinner, Quentin. Machiavelli, in Past Masters series. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1981. pp. vii, 102. ISBN 0192875167 pbk.
- Skinner, Quentin. Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction (2d ed., 2019) ISBN 978-0198837572 pbk.
- Unger, Miles J. Machiavelli: A Biography (Simon & Schuster, 2011)
- Villari, Pasquale. The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli (2 vols. 1892) (Vol 1; Vol 2)
- Viroli, Maurizio (2000), Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli, Farrar, Straus & Giroux excerpt and text search Archived 24 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- Viroli, Maurizio. Machiavelli (1998) online edition Archived 20 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine
- Vivanti, Corrado. Niccolò Machiavelli: An Intellectual Biography (Princeton University Press; 2013) 261 pages
Political thought
- Baron, Hans. The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. excerpts and text search; ACLS E-books; also vol 2 in ACLS E-books
- Baron, Hans. In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism (2 vols. 1988).
- Baron, Hans (1961), "Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of The Prince", English Historical Review, lxxvi (76): 217–253, doi:10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217, JSTOR 557541. in JSTOR Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
- Berlin, Isaiah. "The Originality of Machiavelli", in Berlin, Isaiah (1980). Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas. New York: The Viking Press.
- Bireley, Robert (1990), The Counter Reformation Prince
- Black, Robert (1999), "Machiavelli, servant of the Florentine republic", in Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.), Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cambridge University Press
- Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio, eds. (1993). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521435895.
- Chabod, Federico (1958). Machiavelli & the Renaissance online edition Archived 19 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine; online from ACLS E-Books Archived 20 August 2008 at the Wayback Machine
- Connell, William J. (2001), "Machiavelli on Growth as an End," in Anthony Grafton and J.H.M. Salmon, eds., Historians and Ideologues: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Kelley, Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 259–277.
- Donskis, Leonidas, ed. (2011). Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi, ISBN 978-9042032774, E-ISBN 978-9042032781
- Everdell, William R. "Niccolò Machiavelli: The Florentine Commune" in The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
- Fischer, Markus (Autumn 1997). "Machiavelli's Political Psychology". The Review of Politics. 59 (4): 789–829. doi:10.1017/S0034670500028333. JSTOR 1408308. S2CID 146570913.
- Fischer, Markus (2000), Well-ordered License: On the Unity of Machiavelli's Thought, Lexington Book
- Frederick II of Prussia (1980) . Anti-Machiavel: The Refutation of Machiavelli s Prince. Translated by Sonnino, Paul. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press. ISBN 9780821405598.
- Guarini, Elena (1999), "Machiavelli and the crisis of the Italian republics", in Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.), Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cambridge University Press
- Gilbert, Allan (1938), Machiavelli's Prince and Its Forerunners, Duke University Press
- Gilbert, Felix. Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy (2nd ed. 1984) online from ACLS-E-books Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
- Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. The Makers of Modern Strategy (1944)
- Jensen, De Lamar, ed. Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist? (1960) essays by scholars online edition Archived 25 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine
- Jurdjevic, Mark (2014). A Great and Wretched City: Promise and Failure in Machiavelli's Florentine Political Thought. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674725461.
- Kennington, Richard (2004), On Modern Origins, Lexington Books
- Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," The American Political Science Review, Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun. 1981), pp. 293–305 in JSTOR Archived 8 August 2016 at the Wayback Machine
- Mansfield, Harvey (1993), Taming the Prince, The Johns Hopkins University Press
- Mansfield, Harvey (1995), "Machiavelli and the Idea of Progress", in Melzer; Weinberger; Zinman (eds.), History and the Idea of Progress, Cornell University Press
- Mansfield, Harvey C. Machiavelli's Virtue (1996), 371 pp.
- Mansfield, Harvey C. Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy (2001) excerpt and text search Archived 11 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- Roger Masters (1996), Machiavelli, Leonardo and the Science of Power, University of Notre Dame Press, ISBN 978-0268014339 See also NYT book review Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
- Roger Masters (1998), Fortune is a River: Leonardo Da Vinci and Niccolò Machiavelli's Magnificent Dream to Change the Course of Florentine History, Simon & Schuster, ISBN 978-0-452-28090-8 Also available in Chinese (ISBN 9789572026113), Japanese (ISBN 978-4022597588), German (ISBN 978-3471794029), Portuguese (ISBN 978-8571104969), and Korean (ISBN 978-8984070059). See also NYT book review Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
- Mattingly, Garrett (Autumn 1958), "Machiavelli's Prince: Political Science or Political Satire?", The American Scholar (27): 482–491.
- Najemy, John (1993), Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513–1515, Princeton University Press
- Najemy, John M. (1996), "Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism", American Historical Review, 101 (1): 119–129, doi:10.2307/2169227, JSTOR 2169227.
- Parel, A. J. (Spring 1991). "The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity". The Review of Politics. 53 (2): 320–339. doi:10.1017/S0034670500014649. JSTOR 1407757. S2CID 170629105.
- Parel, Anthony (1972), "Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters", The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy, Toronto, pp. 3–28
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - Parsons, William B. (2016), Machiavelli's Gospel, University of Rochester Press, ISBN 978-1580464918
- Pocock, J.G.A. (1975), The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition, Princeton new ed. 2003, a highly influential study of Discourses and its vast influence; excerpt and text search Archived 18 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine; also online 1975 edition Archived 7 October 2010 at the Wayback Machine
- Pocock, J. G. A. "The Machiavellian Moment Revisited: a Study in History and Ideology.: Journal of Modern History 1981 53(1): 49–72. Fulltext: in Jstor Archived 11 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine.
- Rahe, Paul (1992), Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution online edition Archived 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine
- Rahe, Paul A. (2006), Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0521851879 Excerpt, reviews and Text search shows Machiavelli's Discourses had a major impact on shaping conservative thought.
- Ruggiero, Guido. Machiavelli in Love: Sex, Self and Society in Renaissance Italy (2007)
- Schaefer, David (1990), The Political Philosophy of Montaigne, Cornell University Press.
- Scott, John T.; Sullivan, Vickie B. (1994). "Patricide and the Plot of the Prince: Cesare Borgia and Machiavelli's Italy". The American Political Science Review. 88 (4): 887–900. doi:10.2307/2082714. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 2082714. S2CID 144798597.
- Skinner, Quentin. The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, v. I, The Renaissance, (1978)
- Soll, Jacob (2005), Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism, University of Michigan Press
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Niccolò Machiavelli (2005)
- Strauss, Leo (1987), "Niccolò Machiavelli", in Strauss, Leo; Cropsey, Joseph (eds.), History of Political Philosophy (3rd ed.), University of Chicago Press
- Strauss, Leo (1958), Thoughts on Machiavelli, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0226777023
- Sullivan, Vickie B., ed. (2000), The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works, Yale U. Press
- Sullivan, Vickie B. (1996), Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed, Northern Illinois University Press
- von Vacano, Diego, "The Art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham MD: Lexington: 2007.
- Thompson, C. Bradley (1995), "John Adams's Machiavellian Moment", The Review of Politics, 57 (3): 389–417, doi:10.1017/S0034670500019689, S2CID 154074090. Also in Rahe (2006).
- Whelan, Frederick G. (2004), Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought, Lexington
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - Wight, Martin (2005). Wight, Gabriele; Porter, Brian (eds.). Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199273676.
- Zuckert, Catherine, (2017) "Machiavelli's Politics" Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
Italian studies
- Barbuto, Marcelo (2005), "Questa oblivione delle cose. Reflexiones sobre la cosmología de Maquiavelo (1469–1527)," Revista Daimon, 34, Universidad de Murcia, pp. 34–52.
- Barbuto, Marcelo (2008), "Discorsi, I, XII, 12–14. La Chiesa romana di fronte alla republica cristiana", Filosofia Politica, 1, Il Mulino, Bologna, pp. 99–116.
- Celli, Carlo ( 2009), Il carnevale di Machiavelli, Firenze, L.S. Olschki.
- Connell, William J. (2015), Machiavelli nel Rinascimento italiano, Milano, Franco Angeli.
- Giuseppe Leone, "Silone e Machiavelli. Una scuola...che non crea prìncipi", pref. di Vittoriano Esposito, Centro Studi Ignazio Silone, Pescina, 2003.
- Martelli, Mario (2004), "La Mandragola e il suo prologo", Interpres, XXIII, pp. 106–142.
- Martelli, Mario (2003), "Per la definizione della nozione di principe civile", Interpres, XXII.
- Martelli, Mario (2001), "I dettagli della filologia", Interpres XX, pp. 212–271.
- Martelli, Mario (1999a), "Note su Machiavelli", Interpres XVIII, pp. 91–145.
- Martelli, Mario (1999b), Saggio sul Principe, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
- Martelli, Mario (1999c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola: valutazione politica e valutazione religiosa", Girolamo Savonarola. L´uomo e il frate". Atti del xxxv Convegno storico internazionale (Todi, II-14 ottobre 1998), CISAM, Spoleto, pp. 139–153.
- Martelli, Mario (1998a), Machiavelli e gli storici antichi, osservazioni su alcuni luoghi dei discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio, Quaderni di Filologia e critica, 13, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
- Martelli, Mario (1998b), "Machiavelli politico amante poeta", Interpres XVII, pp. 211–256.
- Martelli, Mario (1998c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola", Savonarola. Democrazia, tirannide, profezia, a cura di G.C. Garfagnini, Florencia, Sismel-Edizioni del Galluzo, pp. 67–89.
- Martelli, Mario and Bausi, Francesco (1997), "Politica, storia e letteratura: Machiavelli e Guicciardini", Storia della letteratura italiana, E. Malato (ed.), vol. IV. Il primo Cinquecento, Salerno Editrice, Roma, pp. 251–320.
- Martelli, Mario (1985–1986), "Schede sulla cultura di Machiavelli", Interpres VI, pp. 283–330.
- Martelli, Mario (1982) "La logica provvidenzialistica e il capitolo XXVI del Principe", Interpres IV, pp. 262–384.
- Martelli, Mario (1974), "L´altro Niccolò di Bernardo Machiavelli", Rinascimento, XIV, pp. 39–100.
- Sasso, Gennaro (1993), Machiavelli: storia del suo pensiero politico, II vol., Bologna, Il Mulino,
- Sasso, Gennaro (1987–1997) Machiavelli e gli antichi e altri saggi, 4 vols., Milano, R. Ricciardi
Editions
Collections
- Gilbert, Allan H. ed. Machiavelli: The Chief Works and Others, (3 vol. 1965), the standard scholarly edition
- Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. The Portable Machiavelli (1979)
- Penman, Bruce. The Prince and Other Political Writings, (1981)
- Wootton, David, ed. (1994), Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli, Indianapolis: Hackett Pubs. excerpt and text search Archived 16 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
The Prince
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2016), The Prince with Related Documents (2nd ed.), Boston: Bedford/St. Martin's, ISBN 978-1319048921. Translated by William J. Connell
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2015), The Prince, US: Adagio Press, ISBN 978-0996767705. Edited by W. Garner. Translated by Luigi Ricci. Excerpt and text search Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1961), The Prince, London: Penguin, ISBN 978-0140449150. Translated by George Bull
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009), The Prince, London: Penguin, ISBN 978-1846140440. Translated by Tim Parks
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1992), The Prince, New York: W.W. Norton & Company, ISBN 0393962202. Translated by Robert M. Adams (Norton Critical Edition, 2nd ed., with "Backgrounds, Interpretations, Marginalia").
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (2006), El Principe/The Prince: Comentado Por Napoleon Bonaparte / Commentaries by Napoleon Buonaparte, Mestas Ediciones. Translated into Spanish by Marina Massa-Carrara
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1985), The Prince, University of Chicago Press. Translated by Harvey Mansfield
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1995), The Prince, Everyman. Translated and Edited by Stephen J. Milner. Introduction, Notes and other critical apparatus by J.M. Dent.
- The Prince ed. by Peter Bondanella (1998) 101 pp online edition Archived 25 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine
- The Prince ed. by Rufus Goodwin and Benjamin Martinez (2003) excerpt and text search Archived 17 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- The Prince (2007) excerpt and text search Archived 10 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- Machiavelli, Niccolò. The Prince, (1908 edition tr by W. K. Marriott) Gutenberg edition Archived 24 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine
- Marriott, W. K. (2008), The Prince, Red and Black Publishers ISBN 978-1934941003
- Il principe (2006) ed. by Mario Martelli and Nicoletta Marcelli, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
The Discourses on Livy
- Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio (2001), ed. by Francesco Bausi, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, II vol. Salerno Editrice, Roma.
- The Discourses, online 1772 edition Archived 15 August 2012 at the Wayback Machine
- The Discourses, tr. with introduction and notes by L. J. Walker (2 vol 1950).
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1531). The Discourses. Translated by Leslie J. Walker, S.J, revisions by Brian Richardson (2003). London: Penguin Books. ISBN 0-14-044428-9
- The Discourses, edited with an introduction by Bernard Crick (1970).
The Art of War
- The Seven Books on the Art of War online 1772 edition Archived 16 July 2012 at the Wayback Machine
- The Art of War, University of Chicago Press, edited with new translation and commentary by Christopher Lynch (2003)
- The Art of War online 1775 edition
- The Art of War, Niccolò Machiavelli. Da Capo press edition, 2001, with introduction by Neal Wood.
Florentine Histories
- History of Florence online 1901 edition Archived 20 September 2008 at the Wayback Machine
- Reform of Florence online 1772 edition Archived 15 August 2012 at the Wayback Machine
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1988), Florentine Histories, Princeton University Press. Translation by Laura F. Banfield and Harvey Mansfield, Jr.
Correspondence
- Epistolario privado. Las cartas que nos desvelan el pensamiento y la personalidad de uno de los intelectuales más importantes del Renacimiento, Juan Manuel Forte (edición y traducción), Madrid, La Esfera de los Libros, 2007, 435 págs, ISBN 978-8497346610
- The Private Correspondence of Niccolò Machiavelli, ed. by Orestes Ferrara; (1929) online edition Archived 23 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1996), Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence, Northern Illinois University Press. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.
- Also see Najemy (1993).
Poetry and comedy
- Machiavelli, Niccolò (1985), Comedies of Machiavelli, University Press of New England Bilingual edition of The Woman from Andros, The Mandrake, and Clizia, edited by David Sices and James B. Atkinson.
- Hoeges, Dirk. Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano, Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, ISBN 3631546696.
External links
- Works by Niccolò Machiavelli in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
- Works by Niccolò Machiavelli at Project Gutenberg
- Works by or about Niccolò Machiavelli at the Internet Archive
- Works by Niccolò Machiavelli at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- "Machiavelli, Niccolò" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 17 (11th ed.). 1911. pp. 233–237.
- Niccolò Machiavelli | Biography | Encyclopedia Britannica
- Machiavelli, Niccolò – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Macchiavelli" . Collier's New Encyclopedia. Vol. 6. 1921. p. 53.
- Niccolò Machiavelli, History.com
- William R. Everdell's article "From State to Free-State: The Meaning of the Word Republic from Jean Bodin to John Adams" with extensive discussion of Machiavelli
- Works by Niccolò Machiavelli: text, concordances and frequency list
- Niccolò Machiavelli – Opera Omnia: Italian and English text
- University of Adelaide's full texts of Machiavelli's works
- Niccolò Machiavelli
- Italian political philosophers
- Italian Renaissance writers
- 1469 births
- 1527 deaths
- Burials at Basilica of Santa Croce, Florence
- Consequentialists
- Italian dramatists and playwrights
- 15th-century Italian philosophers
- 16th-century Italian philosophers
- 16th-century Italian male writers
- Italian political writers
- Italian military writers
- Military theorists
- 15th-century people from the Republic of Florence
- 16th-century people from the Republic of Florence
- Philosophers of war
- Political realists
- Politicians from Florence
- 16th-century dramatists and playwrights
- Writers from Florence
- 15th-century Italian historians
- 16th-century Italian historians
- Italian male non-fiction writers
- Machiavellianism