Revision as of 15:39, 28 February 2009 editDer Zeitgeist (talk | contribs)299 editsm →Existential psychoanalysis and psychotherapy: Added Husserl.← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 05:37, 30 December 2024 edit undoOAbot (talk | contribs)Bots440,440 editsm Open access bot: hdl updated in citation with #oabot. | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Philosophical form of enquiry into subjective existence}} | |||
{{double image|right|Kierkegaard.jpg|100|Nietzsche.later.years.jpg|114|The philosophers ] and ] foreshadowed existentialism.}} | |||
{{redirect|Existential|the logical sense of the term|Existential quantification|other uses|Existence (disambiguation)}} | |||
{{for|the philosophical position commonly seen as the antonym of existentialism |Essentialism}} | |||
{{Multiple image | |||
|image1=Kierkegaard.jpg | |||
|image2=Simone de Beauvoir 1955.jpg | |||
|image3=Nietzsche.later.years.jpg | |||
|image4=Jean-Paul_Sartre_FP.JPG | |||
|perrow=2 / 2 | |||
|footer=Clockwise from top left: ], ], ], ] | |||
|total_width=280 | |||
}} | |||
'''Existentialism''' is a family of ] views and inquiry that prioritize the ] of the human individual, study existence from the individual's perspective, and conclude that, despite the ]ity or incomprehensibility of the universe, individuals must still embrace responsibility for their actions and strive to lead ].<ref>{{Cite Merriam-Webster|existentialism}}</ref><ref>{{Cite Dictionary.com|existentialism}}</ref><ref>{{Cite Cambridge Dictionaries|existentialism}}</ref> In examining ], purpose, and ], existentialist thought often includes concepts such as ], ], ], and ].{{sfn|Solomon|1974|pp=1–2}} | |||
Existentialism is associated with several 19th- and 20th-century European philosophers who shared an emphasis on the human subject, despite often profound differences in thought.{{sfn|Crowell|2020}}<ref name="Macquarrie">{{cite book |first=John |last=Macquarrie |title=Existentialism |location=New York |publisher=] |pages=14–15 |year=1972}}</ref><ref name="Philosophy 1995 p. 259">{{cite book |title=Oxford Companion to Philosophy |url=https://archive.org/details/oxfordcompaniont00hond_471 |url-access=limited |editor-first=Ted |editor-last=Honderich |location=New York |publisher=] |year=1995 |page=|isbn=978-0-19-866132-0 }}</ref> Among the 19th-century figures now associated with existentialism are philosophers ] and ], as well as novelist ], all of whom critiqued ] and concerned themselves with the problem of ]. The word ''existentialism'', however, was not coined until the mid-20th century, during which it became most associated with contemporaneous philosophers ], ], ], ], ], ], and more controversially ]. | |||
'''Existentialism''' is a term that has been applied to the work of a number of nineteenth and twentieth century philosophers who, despite profound doctrinal differences<ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'', New York (1972), pages 18–21.</ref><ref>''Oxford Companion to Philosophy'', ed. Ted Honderich, New York (1995), page 259.</ref>, took the human subject — not merely the thinking subject, but the acting, feeling, living human individual<ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'', New York (1972), pages 14&ndash15.</ref><ref>D.E. Cooper ''Existentialism: A Reconstruction'' (Basil Blackwell, 1999, page 8)</ref> and his or her conditions of existence — as a starting point for philosophical thought. Existential philosophy is the explicit conceptual manifestation of an ''existential attitude''<ref>{{cite book | last = Solomon | first = Robert C. | authorlink = Robert C. Solomon | coauthors = | title = From Hegel to Existentialism | publisher = Oxford University Press | date = 1987 | location = | pages = 238 | url = http://books.google.com/books?id=3JA3vyj4slsC&pg=PA238 | doi = | id = | isbn = 0195061829}}</ref> that begins with a sense of disorientation and confusion in the face of an apparently meaningless or absurd world<ref>Robert C. Solomon, ''Existentialism'' (McGraw-Hill, 1974, pages 1&ndash2)</ref><ref>D.E. Cooper ''Existentialism: A Reconstruction'' (Basil Blackwell, 1999, page 8).</ref>. Many existentialists have also regarded traditional systematic or academic philosophy, in both style and content, as too abstract and remote from concrete human experience<ref>Ernst Breisach, ''Introduction to Modern Existentialism'', New York (1962), page 5</ref><ref>Walter Kaufmann, ''Existentialism: From Dostoevesky to Sartre'', New York (1956), page 12</ref>. | |||
Many existentialists considered traditional systematic or academic philosophies, in style and content, to be too abstract and removed from concrete human experience.<ref>{{cite book |first=Ernst |last=Breisach |title=Introduction to Modern Existentialism |location=New York |publisher=Grove Press |year=1962 |page=5}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |first=Walter |last=Kaufmann |title=Existentialism: From Dostoyevesky to Sartre |location=New York |publisher=Meridian |year=1956 |page=12}}</ref> A primary virtue in existentialist thought is ].{{sfn|Flynn|2006|p=}} Existentialism would influence many disciplines outside of philosophy, including ], drama, art, literature, and psychology.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Guignon |first1=Charles B. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NSvRzPye-gEC&q=psychoanalysis |title=Existentialism: Basic Writings |last2=Pereboom |first2=Derk |publisher=Hackett Publishing |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-87220-595-6 |page=xiii |via=]}}</ref> | |||
Existentialism emerged as a movement in twentieth-century literature and philosophy, foreshadowed most notably by nineteenth-century philosophers ] and ], though it had forerunners in earlier centuries. ] and ] also described existential themes in their literary works. Although there are some common tendencies amongst "existentialist" thinkers, there are major differences and disagreements among them (most notably the divide between atheistic existentialists like Sartre and theistic existentialists like Tillich); not all of them accept the validity of the term as applied to their own work.<ref>Walter Kaufmann. ''Existentialism: From Dostoevsky to Sartre''. (Cleveland: The World Publishing Company, 1956) 11</ref> | |||
Existentialist philosophy encompasses a range of perspectives, but it shares certain underlying concepts. Among these, a central tenet of existentialism is that personal freedom, individual responsibility, and deliberate choice are essential to the pursuit of self-discovery and the determination of life's meaning.<ref>{{Cite book |first=Paul |last=Kleinman |title=Philosophy 101: from Plato and Socrates to ethics and metaphysics, an essential primer on the history of thought |date=2013 |publisher=Adams Media |isbn=978-1-4405-6767-4 |oclc=869368682}}</ref> | |||
=== Origins of Existentialism === | |||
The term "existentialism" seems to have been coined by the French philosopher ] around 1943 <ref>D.E. Cooper ''Existentialism: A Reconstruction'' (basil Blackwell, 1999, page )</ref><ref>Thomas R. Flynn, ''Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction'' (Oxford University Press, 2006, page 89</ref> <ref>Christine Daigle, ''Existentialist Thinkers and Ethics'' (McGill-Queen's press, 2006, page 5)</ref> and adopted by Jean-Paul Sartre who, on October 29, 1945, discussed his own existentialist position in a lecture to the ] in Paris. The lecture was published as '']'', a short book which did much to popularize existentialist thought. <ref>''L'Existentialisme est un Humanisme'' (Editions Nagel, 1946); ''English'' Jean-Paul Sartre, ''Existentialism and Humanism'' (Eyre Methuen, 1948)</ref> | |||
== Etymology == | |||
The label has been applied retrospectively to other philosophers for whom existence, and in particular human existence, were key philosophical topics. ] had made human existence (''Dasein'') the focus of his work since the 1920s, and ] had called his philosophy "''Existenzphilosophie''" in the 1930s.<ref>John Potevi, ''A Dictionary of Continental Philosophy'' (Yale University press, 2006, page 325)</ref><ref>Thomas R. Flynn, ''Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction'' (Oxford University Press, 2006, page 89</ref> Both Heidegger and Jaspers had been influenced by the Danish philosopher, ], but the first much more by ]. For Kirkegaard the crisis of human existence had been a major theme.<ref>S. Kierkegaard, ''Concluding Unscientific Postscript'', "A First and Last Declaration": "…to read solo the original text of the individual, human-existence relationship, the old text, well known, handed down from the fathers, to read it through yet once more, if possible in a more heartfelt way."</ref><ref>Michael Weston, ''Kierkegaard and Modern Continental Philosophy'' (Routledge, 2003, page 35)</ref><ref>''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kierkegaard/</ref> and then he came to be regarded as the first existentialist,<ref>Christine Daigle, ''Existentialist Thinkers and Ethics'' (McGill-Queen's press, 2006, page 5)</ref> and has been called the "father of existentialism".<ref>''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kierkegaard/</ref> In fact he was the first to explicitly make existential questions a primary focus in his philosophy.<ref name="KierkegaardFerreira">Ferreira, M. Jamie, ''Kierkegaard'', Wiley & Sons, 2008.</ref> In retrospect, other writers have also implicitly discussed existentialist themes throughout the history of philosophy. | |||
The term ''existentialism'' ({{langx|fr|L'existentialisme}}) was coined by the ] philosopher ] in the mid-1940s.{{sfn|Cooper|1990|p=1}}{{sfn|Flynn|2006|p=89}}<ref name="Christine Daigle 2006, page 5">{{cite book |first=Christine |last=Daigle |title=Existentialist Thinkers and Ethics |publisher=] |date=2006 |page=5}}</ref> When Marcel first applied the term to ], at a colloquium in 1945, Sartre rejected it.<ref> | |||
Ann Fulton, ''Apostles of Sartre: Existentialism in America, 1945–1963'', Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1999, p. 12-13 & 18–19.</ref> Sartre subsequently changed his mind and, on October 29, 1945, publicly adopted the existentialist label in a lecture to the Club Maintenant in ], published as {{lang|fr|]}} (''Existentialism Is a Humanism''), a short book that helped popularize existentialist thought.<ref>''L'Existentialisme est un Humanisme'' (Editions Nagel, 1946); ''English'' Jean-Paul Sartre, ''Existentialism and Humanism'' (Eyre Methuen, 1948).</ref> Marcel later came to reject the label himself in favour of ''Neo-Socratic'', in honor of Kierkegaard's essay "]". | |||
Some scholars argue that the term should be used to refer only to the cultural movement in Europe in the 1940s and 1950s associated with the works of the philosophers Sartre, ], ], and ].{{sfn|Crowell|2020}} Others extend the term to Kierkegaard, and yet others extend it as far back as ].<ref>{{cite book |last=Crowell |first=Steven |title=The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism |location=Cambridge |date=2011 |page=316}}</ref> However, it is often identified with the philosophical views of Sartre.{{sfn|Crowell|2020}} | |||
Examples include: | |||
== Definitional issues and background == | |||
* ]'s teachings,<ref>Mulder Jr., Jack. ''Mystical And Buddhist Elements in Kierkegaard's Religious Thought'', Edwin Mellen Press, 2006</ref> | |||
The labels ''existentialism'' and ''existentialist'' are often seen as historical conveniences in as much as they were first applied to many philosophers long after they had died. While existentialism is generally considered to have originated with Kierkegaard, the first prominent existentialist philosopher to adopt the term as a self-description was Sartre. Sartre posits the idea that "what all existentialists have in common is the fundamental doctrine that ]", as the philosopher ] explains.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Copleston |first1=F. C. |date=January 1948 |title=Existentialism |journal=Philosophy |volume=23 |issue=84 |pages=19–37 |doi=10.1017/S0031819100065955 |issn=0031-8191 |s2cid=262276911 |jstor=3747384}}</ref> According to philosopher ], defining existentialism has been relatively difficult, and he argues that it is better understood as a general approach used to reject certain systematic philosophies rather than as a systematic philosophy itself.{{sfn|Crowell|2020}} In a lecture delivered in 1945, Sartre described existentialism as "the attempt to draw all the consequences from a position of consistent ]".<ref>See ]'s introduction to {{Cite book |last=Sartre |first=Jean-Paul |author-link=Jean-Paul Sartre |year=2000 |title=Nausea |location=London |publisher=] |isbn=978-0-141-18549-1 |page= }}</ref> For others, existentialism need not involve the rejection of God, but rather "examines mortal man's search for meaning in a meaningless universe", considering less "What is the good life?" (to feel, be, or do, good), instead asking "What is life good for?".<ref>{{cite web |last1=Abulof |first1=Uriel |title=Episode 1: The Jumping Off Place |url=https://www.edx.org/course/hope-human-odyssey-to-political-existentialism |website=Uriel Abulof, Human Odyssey to Political Existentialism (HOPE) |publisher=edX/Princeton |access-date=12 January 2021 |archive-date=5 August 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210805204711/https://www.edx.org/course/hope-human-odyssey-to-political-existentialism }}</ref> | |||
* the ] in the Book of ],<ref>Kierkegaard, Søren. ''Fear and Trembling'', Penguin Classics, 1985</ref> ]<ref name="KierkegaardLove">Kierkegaard, Søren. ''Works of Love'', Princeton University Press, 1998.</ref>, and ],<ref name="KierkegaardLove" /> | |||
* ] in his '']'',<ref name="KierkegaardStorm">Storm, D. Anthony. </ref> | |||
* ]' ], | |||
* ]' writings, | |||
* ]'s ], | |||
* ] '']''.<ref>Kaufmann, Walter. ''From Shakespeare to Existentialism''. Princeton University Press, 1980</ref> | |||
Although many outside ] consider the term existentialism to have originated from Kierkegaard, it is more likely that Kierkegaard adopted this term (or at least the term "existential" as a description of his philosophy) from the Norwegian poet and literary critic ].<ref>{{Cite journal |title=Welhaven og psykologien: Del 2. Welhaven peker fremover |trans-title=Welhaven and psychology: Part 2. Welhaven points forward |url=https://psykologtidsskriftet.no/fagessay/2008/10/welhaven-og-psykologien-del-2-welhaven-peker-fremover |access-date=2022-07-14 |journal=Tidsskrift for Norsk Psykologforening |date=October 2008 |volume=45 |issue=10 |language=nb |last1=Klempe |first1=Hroar}}</ref> This assertion comes from two sources: | |||
Individualist political theories, such as those advanced by ], advocated individual autonomy and self-determination rather than state rule over the individual. This kind of political philosophy, although not existential per se, provided a welcoming climate for existentialism. In 1670, ]'s unfinished notes were published under the title of '']'' ("''Thoughts''"). He described many fundamental themes common to what would be known as existentialism two and three centuries later.<ref name="KierkegaardStorm" /> Pascal argued that without a ], life would be meaningless and miserable. People would only be able to create obstacles and overcome them in an attempt to escape ]. These token-victories would ultimately become meaningless, since people would eventually die. This was good enough reason not to choose to become an ], according to Pascal. | |||
* The Norwegian philosopher Erik Lundestad refers to the Danish philosopher Fredrik Christian Sibbern. Sibbern is supposed to have had two conversations in 1841, the first with Welhaven and the second with Kierkegaard. It is in the first conversation that it is believed that Welhaven came up with "a word that he said covered a certain thinking, which had a close and positive attitude to life, a relationship he described as existential".<ref>Lundestad, 1998, p. 169.</ref> This was then brought to Kierkegaard by Sibbern. | |||
=== 19th century === | |||
* The second claim comes from the Norwegian historian ], who claimed to prove that Kierkegaard himself said the term ''existential'' was borrowed from the poet. He strongly believes that it was Kierkegaard himself who said that "] do not study philosophy 'existentially;' to use a phrase by Welhaven from one time when I spoke with him about philosophy."<ref>Slagstad, 2001, p. 89.</ref> | |||
] | |||
As early as 1835 in a letter to his friend ], the Danish philosopher ''']''' wrote one of his first existentially sensitive passages. In it, he describes a truth that is applicable for him: | |||
== Concepts == | |||
{{quote|''What I really lack is to be clear in my mind what I am to do, not what I am to know, except in so far as a certain knowledge must precede every action. The thing is to understand myself, to see what God really wishes me to do: '''the thing is to find a truth which is true for me, to find the idea for which I can live and die'''. ... I certainly do not deny that I still recognize an imperative of knowledge and that through it one can work upon men, but it must be taken up into my life, and that is what I now recognize as the most important thing.|Søren Kierkegaard|Letter to Peter Wilhelm Lund dated August 31, 1835, emphasis added<ref>Kierkegaard, Søren. ''The Essential Kierkegaard'', edited by Howard and Edna Hong. Princeton, 2000</ref>}} | |||
=== Existence precedes essence === | |||
The early thoughts of Kierkegaard would be formalized in his prolific philosophical and theological writings, many of which would later form the modern foundation of 20th century existentialism.<ref>Marino, Gordon. Ed. ''Basic Writings of Existentialism''. Modern Library, 2004.</ref><ref name="KierkegaardFerreira" /> | |||
{{Main|Existence precedes essence}} | |||
Sartre argued that a central proposition of existentialism is that existence precedes essence, which is to say that individuals shape themselves by existing and cannot be perceived through preconceived and ''a priori'' categories, an "essence". The actual life of the individual is what constitutes what could be called their "true essence" instead of an arbitrarily attributed essence others use to define them. Human beings, through their own ], create their own values and determine a meaning to their life.<ref>(Dictionary) "L'existencialisme" – see "l'identité de la personne" {{in lang|fr}}.</ref> This view is in contradiction to ] and ], who taught that essence precedes individual existence.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Aquinas: Metaphysics {{!}} Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/thomas-aquinas-metaphysics/ |access-date=2022-11-10 |language=en-US}}</ref> Although it was Sartre who explicitly coined the phrase, similar notions can be found in the thought of existentialist philosophers such as Heidegger, and Kierkegaard: | |||
==== Kierkegaard and Nietzsche ==== | |||
{{main|Kierkegaard and Nietzsche comparisons}} | |||
''']''' as well as ''']''' were two of the first philosophers considered fundamental to the existentialist movement, though neither used the term "existentialism" and it is unclear whether they would have supported the existentialism of the 20th century. Their focus was on human experience, rather than the objective truths of mathematics and science that are too detached or observational to truly get at human experience. Like Pascal, they were interested in people's quiet struggle with the apparent meaninglessness of life and the use of diversion to escape from boredom. But Pascal did not consider the role of making free choices, particularly regarding fundamental values and beliefs: such choices change the nature and identity of the chooser, in the view of Kierkegaard and Nietzsche.<ref name="Lup1">Luper, Steven. "Existing". Mayfield Publishing, 2000, p.4–5</ref><ref name="Lup2">Ibid, p. 11</ref> Kierkegaard's ] and Nietzsche's ] are examples of those who define the nature of their own existence. Great individuals invent their own values and create the very terms under which they excel. Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were also precursors to other intellectual movements, including ], ], and various strands of ]. | |||
{{Blockquote|The subjective ''thinker's form'', the form of his communication, is his ''style''. His form must be just as manifold as are the opposites that he holds together. The systematic ''eins, zwei, drei'' is an abstract form that also must inevitably run into trouble whenever it is to be applied to the concrete. To the same degree as the subjective thinker is concrete, to that same degree his form must also be concretely dialectical. But just as he himself is not a poet, not an ethicist, not a dialectician, so also his form is none of these directly. His form must first and last be related to existence, and in this regard he must have at his disposal the poetic, the ethical, the dialectical, the religious. Subordinate character, setting, etc., which belong to the well-balanced character of the esthetic production, are in themselves breadth; the subjective thinker has only one setting—existence—and has nothing to do with localities and such things. The setting is not the fairyland of the imagination, where poetry produces consummation, nor is the setting laid in England, and historical accuracy is not a concern. The setting is inwardness in existing as a human being; the concretion is the relation of the existence-categories to one another. Historical accuracy and historical actuality are breadth.|source=Søren Kierkegaard (''Concluding Postscript'', Hong pp. 357–358.)}} | |||
==== Dostoevsky and Kafka ==== | |||
Two of the first literary writers who were important to existentialism were the Czech author ''']''' and the Russian author ''']'''<ref>Hubben, William. ''Dostoevsky, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Kafka'', Scribner, 1997.</ref> Dostoevsky's '']'' details the story of a man who is unable to fit into society and unhappy with the identities he creates for himself. Many of Dostoevsky's novels, such as '']'', covered issues pertinent to existential philosophy while offering story lines divergent from secular existentialism: for example in ''Crime and Punishment'' one sees the protagonist, Raskolnikov, experience existential crises and move toward a worldview similar to ], which Dostoevsky had come to advocate. Kafka created often surreal and alienated characters who struggle with hopelessness and absurdity, notably in his most famous novella, '']'', or in his master novel, '']''. In his philosophical essay '']'', the French existentialist Albert Camus describes ''Kafka's oeuvre'' as "absurd in principle",<ref>Albert Camus, '']'' (Trans. Justin O'Brien, Hamish Hamilton, 1955, page 104)</ref> although he also finds present the same "tremendous cry of hope" as is to be found in religious existentialists such as Kierkegaard and Shestov, and which Camus himself rejects.<ref>Albert Camus, '']'' (Trans. Justin O'Brien, Hamish Hamilton, 1955, page 107)</ref> | |||
Some interpret the imperative to define oneself as meaning that anyone can wish to be anything. However, an existentialist philosopher would say such a wish constitutes an inauthentic existence – what Sartre would call "]". Instead, the phrase should be taken to say that people are defined only insofar as they act and that they are responsible for their actions. Someone who acts cruelly towards other people is, by that act, defined as a cruel person. Such persons are themselves responsible for their new identity (cruel persons). This is opposed to their genes, or ''human nature'', bearing the blame. | |||
=== Early 20th century === | |||
In the first decades of the 20th century, a number of philosophers – some working independently, but all influenced in varying degrees by Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Dostoevsky – developed positions which were existentialist in all but name. | |||
As Sartre said in his lecture '']'': "Man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world—and defines himself afterwards." The more positive, therapeutic aspect of this is also implied: a person can choose to act in a different way, and to be a good person instead of a cruel person.<ref>{{cite book |last=Baird |first=Forrest E. |author2=Walter Kaufmann |title=From Plato to Derrida |publisher=Pearson Prentice Hall |year=2008 |location=Upper Saddle River, New Jersey |isbn=978-0-13-158591-1}}</ref> | |||
The Spanish philosopher '''] y Jugo''', in his 1913 book ''The Tragic Sense of Life in Men and Nations'', emphasized the life of "flesh and bone" as opposed to that of abstract rationalism. Unamuno rejected systematic philosophy in favor of the individual's quest for faith. He retained a sense of the tragic, even absurd nature of the quest, symbolized by his enduring interest in ]' fictional character ]. A novelist, poet and dramatist as well as philosophy professor at the University of Salamanca, Unamuno's short story about a priest's crisis of faith, "Saint Manuel the Good, Martyr" has been collected in anthologies of existentialist fiction. Another Spanish thinker, ''']''', writing in 1914, held that the human existence must always be defined as the individual person combined with the concrete circumstances of his life: "''Yo soy yo y mi circunstancia''" ("I am myself and my circumstances"). Sartre likewise believed that human existence is not an abstract matter, but is always situated ("''en situation''"). | |||
Jonathan Webber interprets Sartre's usage of the term ''essence'' not in a modal fashion, i.e. as necessary features, but in a teleological fashion: "an essence is the relational property of having a set of parts ordered in such a way as to collectively perform some activity".<ref name="Webber">{{cite book |last1=Webber |first1=Jonathan |title=Rethinking Existentialism |date=2018 |publisher=Oxford: Oxford University Press |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/WEBRE-3}}</ref>{{rp|3}}{{sfn|Crowell|2020}} For example, it belongs to the essence of a house to keep the bad weather out, which is why it has walls and a roof. Humans are different from houses because—unlike houses—they do not have an inbuilt purpose: they are free to ''choose'' their own purpose and thereby shape their essence; thus, ''their existence precedes their essence''.<ref name="Webber"/>{{rp|1–4}} | |||
Although ''']''' wrote his major philosophical works in German, and studied and taught at the Universities of Berlin and ], he stands apart from the mainstream of German philosophy. Born into a Jewish family in Vienna in 1878, he was also a scholar of Jewish culture and involved at various times in ] and ]. In 1938, he moved permanently to ]. His best-known philosophical work was the short book ], published in 1922. For Buber, the fundamental fact of human existence, too readily overlooked by scientific rationalism and abstract philosophical thought, is "man with man", a dialogue which takes place in the so-called "sphere of between" (''"das Zwischenmenschliche"'').<ref>Maurice S. Friedman, ''Martin Buber. The Life of Dialogue'' (University of Chicago press, 1955, page 85)</ref> | |||
Sartre is committed to a radical conception of freedom: nothing fixes our purpose but we ourselves, our projects have no weight or inertia except for our endorsement of them.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Burnham |first1=Douglas |title=Existentialism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/existent/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=16 November 2020}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Cox |first1=Gary |title=The Sartre Dictionary |date=2008 |publisher=] |pages=41–42 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/COXTSD}}</ref> Simone de Beauvoir, on the other hand, holds that there are various factors, grouped together under the term ''sedimentation'', that offer resistance to attempts to change our direction in life. ''Sedimentations'' are themselves products of past choices and can be changed by choosing differently in the present, but such changes happen slowly. They are a force of inertia that shapes the agent's evaluative outlook on the world until the transition is complete.<ref name="Webber"/>{{rp|5,9,66}} | |||
Two Russian thinkers, ''']''' and ''']''' became well-known as existentialist thinkers during their post-Revolutionary exiles in Paris. Shestov, born into a Russian-Jewish family in Kiev, had launched an attack on rationalism and systematization in philosophy as early as 1905 in his book of aphorisms ''All Things Are Possible''. | |||
Sartre's definition of existentialism was based on Heidegger's magnum opus '']'' (1927). In the correspondence with ] later published as the '']'', Heidegger implied that Sartre misunderstood him for his own purposes of subjectivism, and that he did not mean that actions take precedence over being so long as those actions were not reflected upon.<ref>{{Cite book |title=Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to The Task of Thinking (1964) |last=Heidegger |first=Martin |publisher=Harper San Francisco |editor=David Farrell Krell |year=1993 |isbn=0-06-063763-3 |edition=Revised and expanded |location=San Francisco, California |oclc=26355951}}</ref> Heidegger commented that "the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement", meaning that he thought Sartre had simply switched the roles traditionally attributed to essence and existence without interrogating these concepts and their history.<ref>{{Cite book |title=Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to The Task of thinking (1964) |url=https://archive.org/details/basicwritings00heid |url-access=limited |last=Heidegger |first=Martin |publisher=Harper San Francisco |editor=David Farrell Krell |year=1993 |isbn=0-06-063763-3 |edition=Revised and expanded |location=San Francisco, California |pages= |oclc=26355951}}</ref> | |||
Berdyaev, also from Kiev but with a background in the Eastern Orthodox Church, drew a radical distinction between the world of spirit and the everyday world of objects. Human freedom, for Berdyaev, is rooted in the realm of spirit, a realm independent of scientific notions of causation. To the extent the individual human being lives in the objective world, he is estranged from authentic spiritual freedom. "Man" is not to be interpreted naturalistically, but as a being created in God's image, an originator of free, creative acts.<ref>Ernst Breisach, ''Introduction to Modern Existentialism'', New York (1962), pages 173&ndash176</ref> He published a major work on these themes, ''The Destiny of Man'' in 1931. | |||
=== The absurd === | |||
''']''', long before coining the term "existentialism", introduced important existentialist themes to a French audience in his early essay "Existence and Objectivity" (1925) and in his ''Metaphysical Journal'' (1927).<ref>Samuel M. Keen, "Gabriel Marcel" in Paul Edwards (ed.) ''The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan Publishing Co, 1967)</ref> A dramatist as well as a philosopher, Marcel found his philosophical starting point in a condition of metaphysical alientation; the human individual searching for harmony in a transient life. Harmony, for Marcel, was to be sought through "secondary reflection", a "dialogical" rather than "dialectical" approach to the world, characterized by "wonder and astonishment" and open to the "presence" of other people and of God rather than merely to "information" about them. For Marcel, such presence implied more than simply being there (as one thing might be in the presence of another thing); it connoted "extravagant" availability, and the willingness to put oneself at the disposal of the other.<ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'' (Pelican, 1973, page 110)</ref> Marcel contrasted "secondary reflection" with abstract, scientific-technical "primary reflection" which he associated with the activity of the abstract ] ego. For Marcel, philosophy was a concrete activity undertaken by a sensing, feeling human being incarnate — embodied — in a concrete world.<ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'' (Pelican, 1973, page 96)</ref><ref>Samuel M. Keen, "Gabriel Marcel" in Paul Edwards (ed.) ''The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan Publishing Co, 1967)</ref> Although ] adopted the term "existentialism" for his own philosophy in the 1940s, Marcel's thought has been described as "almost diametrically opposed" to that of Sartre.<ref>Samuel M. Keen, "Gabriel Marcel" in Paul Edwards (ed.) ''The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'' (Macmillan Publishing Co, 1967)</ref> Unlike Sartre, Marcel was a Christian, and became a Catholic convert in 1929. | |||
{{Main|Absurdism}} | |||
], the symbol of the absurdity of existence, painting by ] (1920)]] | |||
The notion of the absurd contains the idea that there is no meaning in the world beyond what meaning we give it. This meaninglessness also encompasses the amorality or "unfairness" of the world. This can be highlighted in the way it opposes the traditional ] perspective, which establishes that life's purpose is the fulfillment of God's commandments.{{sfn|Wartenberg|2008}} This is what gives meaning to people's lives. To live the life of the absurd means rejecting a life that finds or pursues specific meaning for man's existence since there is nothing to be discovered. According to Albert Camus, the world or the human being is not in itself absurd. The concept only emerges through the ] of the two; life becomes absurd due to the incompatibility between human beings and the world they inhabit.{{sfn|Wartenberg|2008}} This view constitutes one of the two interpretations of the absurd in existentialist literature. The second view, first elaborated by ], holds that absurdity is limited to actions and choices of human beings. These are considered absurd since they issue from human freedom, undermining their foundation outside of themselves.<ref>{{Cite book |title=The A to Z of Existentialism |last=Michelman |first=Stephen |publisher=The ], Inc. |year=2010 |isbn=978-0-8108-7589-0 |location=Lanham, Maryland |page=27}}</ref> | |||
In Germany, the psychologist and philosopher ''']''' — who later described existentialism as a "phantom" created by the public,<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers (The Library of Living Philosophers IX (Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, page 75/11)</ref> — called his own thought, heavily influenced by Kierkegaard and Nietzsche — ''Existenzphilosophie''. For Jaspers, "''Existenz''-philosophy is the way of thought by means of which man seeks to become himself...This way of thought does not cognize objects, but elucidates and makes actual the being of the thinker."<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers (The Library of Living Philosophers IX (Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, page 40)</ref> | |||
The absurd contrasts with the claim that "bad things don't happen to good people"; to the world, metaphorically speaking, there is no such thing as a good person or a bad person; what happens happens, and it may just as well happen to a "good" person as to a "bad" person.{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=3.1 Anxiety, Nothingness, the Absurd}} Because of the world's absurdity, anything can happen to anyone at any time and a tragic event could plummet someone into direct confrontation with the absurd. Many of the literary works of ], ], ], ], ], ], ],<ref name=luigitheatre>{{cite book |last1=Bassnett |first1=Susan |last2=Lorch |first2=Jennifer |title=Luigi Pirandello in the Theatre |date=March 18, 2014 |publisher=] |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FpwiAwAAQBAJ&q=existentialist&pg=PA182 |access-date=26 March 2015 |isbn=978-1-134-35114-5 |via=]}}</ref><ref name=understandex>{{cite book |last1=Thompson |first1=Mel |last2=Rodgers |first2=Nigel |title=Understanding Existentialism: Teach Yourself |date=2010 |publisher=] |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vfczAgAAQBAJ&q=pirandello+existentialism&pg=PT105 |isbn=978-1-4441-3421-6 |via=]}}</ref><ref name=crisisconsciousness>{{cite book |last1=Caputi |first1=Anthony Francis |title=Pirandello and the Crisis of Modern Consciousness |date=1988 |publisher=] |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0Qv2nuJF7yYC&q=pirandello+existentialist+absurdity&pg=PA80 |isbn=978-0-252-01468-0 |via=]}}</ref><ref name=masks>{{cite book |last1=Mariani |first1=Umberto |title=Living Masks: The Achievement of Pirandello |date=2010 |publisher=] |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vBviYn43H34C&q=pirandello+existential+absurd&pg=PT178 |access-date=26 March 2015 |isbn=978-1-4426-9314-2 |via=]}}</ref> ], ], and ] contain descriptions of people who encounter the absurdity of the world. | |||
Jaspers, a professor at the University of ], was acquainted with ''']''', who held a professorship at ] before acceding to Husserl's chair at ] in 1928. They held many philosophical discussions, but later became estranged over Heidegger's support of ]. They shared an admiration for Kierkegaard<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers (The Library of Living Philosophers IX (Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, page 75/2 and following)</ref>, and in the 1930s Heidegger lectured extensively on Nietzsche. Nevertheless, the extent to which Heidegger should be considered an existentialist is debatable. In '']'' he presented a method of rooting philosophical explanations in human existence (''Dasein'') to be analysed in terms of existential categories (''existentiale''); and this has led many commentators to treat him as an important figure in the existentialist movement. | |||
It is because of the devastating awareness of meaninglessness that Camus claimed in '']'' that "There is only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide." Although "prescriptions" against the possible deleterious consequences of these kinds of encounters vary, from Kierkegaard's religious "stage" to Camus' insistence on persevering in spite of absurdity, the concern with helping people avoid living their lives in ways that put them in the perpetual danger of having everything meaningful break down is common to most existentialist philosophers. The possibility of having everything meaningful break down poses a threat of ], which is inherently against the existentialist philosophy.<ref>{{cite book |first=Jean-Paul |last=Sartre |author-link=Jean-Paul Sartre |url=http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm |title=Existentialism is a Humanism |date=1946 |via=] |access-date=2010-03-08}}</ref> It has been said that the possibility of ] makes all humans existentialists. The ultimate hero of absurdism lives without meaning and faces suicide without succumbing to it.<ref>{{Cite journal |title=Suicide and Self-Deception |first=E. |last=Keen |journal=] |year=1973 |volume=60 |issue=4 |pages=575–85 |pmid=4772778 |url=http://www.pep-web.org/document.php?id=PSAR.060.0575A}}</ref> | |||
=== After the Second World War === | |||
Following the ], existentialism became a well-known and significant philosophical and cultural movement, mainly through the public prominence of two French writers, ''']''' and ''']''', who wrote best-selling novels, plays and widely-read journalism as well as theoretical texts. These years also saw the growing reputation outside Germany of Heidegger's book '']''. | |||
=== Facticity === | |||
Sartre had dealt with existentialist themes in his 1938 novel '']'' and the short stories in his 1939 collection '']'', and had published a major philosophical statement, '']'' in 1943, but it was in the two years following the liberation of Paris from the German occupying forces that he and his close associates — Camus, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and others — became internationally famous as the leading figures of a movement known as existentialism.<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'' (University of Chicago Press, 2004, chapter 3 ''passim'')</ref> In a very short space of time, Camus and Sartre in particular, became the leading public intellectuals of post-war France, achieving by the end of 1945 "a fame that reached across all audiences."<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'' (University of Chicago Press, 2004, page 44)</ref> Camus was an editor of the most popular leftist (former ]) newspaper '']''; Sartre launched his journal of leftist thought, '']'', and two weeks later gave the widely reported lecture on existentialism and humanism to a packed meeting of the ]. Beauvoir wrote that "not a week passed without the newspapers discussing us";<ref>Simone de Beauvoir, '']'', quoted in Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'' (University of Chicago Press, 2004, page 48)</ref> existentialism became "the first media craze of the postwar era."<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'' (University of Chicago Press, 2004, page 48)</ref> | |||
{{main|Facticity}} | |||
{{Technical|section|date=November 2020}} | |||
Facticity is defined by Sartre in '']'' (1943) as the '']'', which for humans takes the form of being and not being. It is the facts of one's personal life and as per Heidegger, it is "]." This can be more easily understood when considering facticity in relation to the temporal dimension of our past: one's past is what one is, meaning that it is what has formed the person who exists in the present. However, to say that one is only one's past would ignore the change a person undergoes in the present and future, while saying that one's past is only what one was, would entirely detach it from the present self. A denial of one's concrete past constitutes an inauthentic lifestyle, and also applies to other kinds of facticity (having a human body—e.g., one that does not allow a person to run faster than the speed of sound—identity, values, etc.).{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=2.1 Facticity and Transcendence}} | |||
By the end of 1947, Camus's earlier fiction and plays had been reprinted, his new play '']'' had been performed and his novel '']'' published; the first two novels of Sartre's '']'' trilogy had appeared, as had Beauvoir's novel '']''. Works by Camus and Sartre were already appearing in foreign editions. The Paris-based existentialists had become famous.<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'' (University of Chicago Press, 2004, chapter 3 ''passim'')</ref> | |||
Facticity is a limitation and a condition of freedom. It is a limitation in that a large part of one's facticity consists of things one did not choose (birthplace, etc.), but a condition of freedom in the sense that one's values most likely depend on it. However, even though one's facticity is "set in stone" (as being past, for instance), it cannot determine a person: the value ascribed to one's facticity is still ascribed to it freely by that person. As an example, consider two men, one of whom has no memory of his past and the other who remembers everything. Both have committed many crimes, but the first man, remembering nothing, leads a rather normal life while the second man, feeling trapped by his own past, continues a life of crime, blaming his own past for "trapping" him in this life. There is nothing essential about his committing crimes, but he ascribes this meaning to his past. | |||
Sartre had travelled to Germany in 1930 to study the ] of ] and ],<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidgger — Between Good and Evil'' (Harvard University Press, 1998, page 343</ref> and he included critical comments on their work in his major treatise '']''. Heidegger's thought had also become known in French philosophical circles through its use by ] in explicating Hegel in a series of lectures given in Paris in the 1930s.<ref>Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), ''The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics''(Hodder Arnold, 2006, page 158); see also Alexandre Kojève, '']'' (Cornell University Press, 1980)</ref> The lectures were highly influential; members of the audience included not only Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, but ], ], ], ] and ].<ref>Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), ''The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics''(Hodder Arnold, 2006, page 158)</ref> A selection from Heidegger's '']'' was published in French in 1938, and his essays began to appear in French philosophy journals. Heidegger read Sartre's work and was initially impressed, commenting: "Here for the first time I encountered an independent thinker who, from the foundations up, has experienced the area out of which I think, Your work shows such an immediate comprehension of my philosophy as I have never before encountered."<ref>Martin Hediegger, letter, quoted in Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidgger — Between Good and Evil'' (Harvard University Press, 1998, page 349)</ref>. Later, however, in response to a question posed by his French follower ]<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidgger — Between Good and Evil'' (Harvard University Press, 1998, page 356)</ref>, Heidegger distanced himself from Sartre's position and existentialism in general in his '']''.<ref>William J. Richardson, ''Martin Heidegger: From Phenomenology to Thought'' (Martjinus Nijhoff,1967, page 351)</ref> Heidegger's reputation continued to grow in France during the 1950s and 1960s. | |||
However, to disregard one's facticity during the continual process of self-making, projecting oneself into the future, would be to put oneself in denial of the conditions shaping the present self and would be inauthentic. The origin of one's projection must still be one's facticity, though in the mode of not being it (essentially). An example of one focusing solely on possible projects without reflecting on one's current facticity:{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=2.1 Facticity and Transcendence}} would be someone who continually thinks about future possibilities related to being rich (e.g. a better car, bigger house, better quality of life, etc.) without acknowledging the facticity of ''not currently having the financial means to do so''. In this example, considering both facticity and transcendence, an authentic mode of being would be considering future projects that might improve one's current finances (e.g. putting in extra hours, or investing savings) in order to arrive at a ''future-facticity'' of a modest pay rise, further leading to purchase of an affordable car. | |||
In the 1960s, Sartre attempted to reconcile existentialism and ] in his work '']''. A major theme throughout his writings was freedom and responsibility. | |||
Another aspect of facticity is that it entails ]. Freedom "produces" angst when limited by facticity and the lack of the possibility of having facticity to "step in" and take responsibility for something one has done also produces angst. | |||
Albert Camus was a friend of ], until their falling-out, and wrote several works with existential themes including '']'', '']'', '']'', and '']''. Camus, like many others, rejected the existentialist label, and considered his works to be concerned with people facing the absurd. In ''The Myth of ]'', Camus uses the analogy of the Greek myth to demonstrate the futility of existence. In the myth, Sisyphus is condemned for eternity to roll a rock up a hill, but when he reaches the summit, the rock will roll to the bottom again. Camus believes that this existence is pointless but that Sisyphus ultimately finds meaning and purpose in his task, simply by continually applying himself to it. | |||
Another aspect of existential freedom is that one can change one's values. One is responsible for one's values, regardless of society's values. The focus on ] in existentialism is related to the limits of responsibility one bears, as a result of one's freedom. The relationship between freedom and responsibility is one of interdependency and a clarification of freedom also clarifies that for which one is responsible.{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=3. Freedom and Value}}{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=3.2 The Ideality of Values}} | |||
''']''', an important existentialist who spent much of her life as Sartre's partner, wrote about feminist and existential ethics in her works, including '']'' and '']''. Although often overlooked due to her relationship with Sartre, de Beauvoir integrated existentialism with other forms of thinking such as feminism, unheard of at the time, resulting in alienation from fellow writers such as Camus. ], a Martiniquan-born critic of ], has been considered an important existentialist.<ref>Macey, David. ''Franz Fanon: a Biography''. New York City: ], USA. p. 129&ndash130.</ref> | |||
=== Authenticity === | |||
''']''', a important existential theologian following ] and ], applied existential concepts to ], and helped introduce ] to the general public. His seminal work ''The Courage to Be'' follows Kierkegaard's analysis of anxiety and life's absurdity, but puts forward the thesis that modern man must, via God, achieve selfhood in spite of life's absurdity. ''']''' used Kierkegaard's and ]'s philosophy of existence to demythologize Christianity by interpreting Christian mythical concepts into existential concepts. | |||
{{main|Authenticity (philosophy)|l1=Authenticity}} | |||
Many noted existentialists consider the theme of authentic existence important. ] involves the idea that one has to "create oneself" and live in accordance with this self. For an authentic existence, one should act as oneself, not as "one's acts" or as "one's genes" or as any other essence requires. The authentic act is one in accordance with one's freedom. A component of freedom is facticity, but not to the degree that this facticity determines one's transcendent choices (one could then blame one's background for making the choice one made ). Facticity, in relation to authenticity, involves acting on one's actual values when making a choice (instead of, like Kierkegaard's Aesthete, "choosing" randomly), so that one takes responsibility for the act instead of choosing either-or without allowing the options to have different values.{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=2.3 Authenticity}} | |||
''']''', an ], was for a time a companion of Sartre. His understanding of ]'s ] was far greater than that of Merleau-Ponty's fellow existentialists. It has been said that his work, ], greatly influenced Sartre. However, in later years they were to disagree irreparably, dividing many existentialists such as de Beauvoir, who sided with Sartre. ] would also be considered an existentialist through his use of history to reveal the constant alterations of created meaning, thus proving history's failure to produce a cohesive version of reality. | |||
In contrast, the inauthentic is the denial to live{{Clarify|reason=Does this mean ' choice to not live in accordance with one's freedom'? If so, the word 'denial' doesn't seem appropriate. But maybe something else is meant.|date=February 2023}} in accordance with one's freedom. This can take many forms, from pretending choices are meaningless or random, convincing oneself that some form of ] is true, or "mimicry" where one acts as "one should".{{citation needed|date=October 2021}} | |||
==Major concepts== | |||
===A focus on concrete existence=== | |||
Existentialist thinkers focus on the question of concrete human existence and the conditions of this existence rather than hypothesizing a human essence. However, even though the concrete individual existence must have priority in existentialism, certain conditions are commonly held to be "endemic" to human existence. | |||
How one "should" act is often determined by an image one has, of how one in such a role (bank manager, lion tamer, sex worker, etc.) acts. In ''Being and Nothingness'', Sartre uses the example of a waiter in "bad faith". He merely takes part in the "act" of being a typical waiter, albeit very convincingly.<ref name="Jean-Paul Sartre 2003">Jean-Paul Sartre, ''Being and Nothingness'', Routledge Classics (2003).</ref> This image usually corresponds to a social norm, but this does not mean that all acting in accordance with social norms is inauthentic. The main point is the attitude one takes to one's own freedom and responsibility and the extent to which one acts in accordance with this freedom.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism {{!}} Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/ |access-date=2022-11-10 |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
What these conditions are is better understood in light of the meaning of the word "existence," which comes from the Latin "existere," meaning "to stand out." Man exists in a state of distance from the world that he nonetheless remains in the midst of. This distance is what enables man to project meaning into the disinterested world of in-itselfs. This projected meaning remains fragile, constantly facing breakdown for any reason — from a tragedy to a particularly insightful moment. In such a breakdown, we are put face to face with the naked meaninglessness of the world, and the results can be devastating. It is in relation to this that ] famously claimed that "there is only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide" in his '']''. Although "prescriptions" against the possibly deleterious consequences of these kinds of encounters vary, from Kierkegaard's religious "stage" to Camus' insistence on persevering in spite of absurdity, the concern with helping people avoid living their lives in ways that put them in the perpetual danger of having everything meaningful break down is common to most existentialist philosophers. | |||
=== |
=== The Other and the Look === | ||
{{main| |
{{main|Other (philosophy)}} | ||
A central proposition of existentialism is that existence precedes ], which means that the actual life of the individual is what constitutes what could be called his "essence" instead of there being a predetermined essence that defines what it is to be a human. Although it was Sartre who explicitly coined the term, similar notions can be found in the thought of many existentialist philosophers, from Kierkegaard to Heidegger. | |||
The Other (written with a capital "O") is a concept more properly belonging to ] and its account of ]. However, it has seen widespread use in existentialist writings, and the conclusions drawn differ slightly from the phenomenological accounts. The Other is the experience of another free subject who inhabits the same world as a person does. In its most basic form, it is this experience of the Other that constitutes intersubjectivity and objectivity. To clarify, when one experiences someone else, and this Other person experiences the world (the same world that a person experiences)—only from "over there"—the world is constituted as objective in that it is something that is "there" as identical for both of the subjects; a person experiences the other person as experiencing the same things. This experience of the Other's look is what is termed the Look (sometimes the ]).{{sfn|Crowell|2020|loc=2.2 Alienation}} | |||
It is often claimed in this context that man defines himself, which is often perceived as stating that man can "wish" to be something — anything, a bird, for instance — and then be it. According to most existentialist philosophers, however, this would rather be a kind of inauthentic existence. What is meant by the statement is that man is (1) defined only insofar as he acts and (2) that he is responsible for his actions. To clarify, it can be said that a man who acts cruelly towards other people is, by that act, defined as a cruel man and in that same instance, he (as opposed to his genes, or "the cruel nature of man", for instance) is defined as being responsible for ''being'' this cruel man. As Sartre puts it in his ]: "man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world – and defines himself afterwards." Of course, the more positive, therapeutic aspect of this is also implied: You can choose to act in a different way, and to be a good person instead of a cruel person. Here it is also clear that since man can choose to be either cruel or good, he is, in fact, neither of these things ''essentially''.<ref>{{cite book | last = Baird | first = Forrest E. | authorlink = | coauthors = Walter Kaufmann | title = From Plato to Derrida | publisher = Pearson Prentice Hall | date = 2008 | location = Upper Saddle River, New Jersey | pages = | url = | doi = | id = | isbn = 0-13-158591-6 }}</ref> | |||
While this experience, in its basic phenomenological sense, constitutes the world as objective and oneself as objectively existing subjectivity (one experiences oneself as seen in the Other's Look in precisely the same way that one experiences the Other as seen by him, as subjectivity), in existentialism, it also acts as a kind of limitation of freedom. This is because the Look tends to objectify what it sees. When one experiences oneself in the Look, one does not experience oneself as nothing (no thing), but as something (some thing). In Sartre's example of a man peeping at someone through a keyhole, the man is entirely caught up in the situation he is in. He is in a pre-reflexive state where his entire consciousness is directed at what goes on in the room. Suddenly, he hears a creaking floorboard behind him and he becomes aware of himself as seen by the Other. He is then filled with shame for he perceives himself as he would perceive someone else doing what he was doing—as a ]. For Sartre, this phenomenological experience of shame establishes proof for the existence of other minds and defeats the problem of ]. For the conscious state of shame to be experienced, one has to become aware of oneself as an object of another look, proving a priori, that other minds exist.<ref>{{cite book |last=Sartre |first=Jean Paul |title=Being and Nothingness |date=1992 |publisher=Washington Square Press |isbn=978-0-230-00673-7 |location=New York |translator-first=Hazel E. |translator-last=Barnes |chapter=Chapter 1 |author-link=Jean-Paul Sartre}}</ref> The Look is then co-constitutive of one's facticity. | |||
===Angst=== | |||
], sometimes called dread, anxiety or even anguish is a term that is common to many existentialist thinkers. Although its concrete properties may vary slightly, it is generally held to be the experience of our freedom and responsibility. The archetypal example is the example of the experience one has when standing on a cliff where one not only fears falling off it, but also dreads the possibility of throwing oneself off. In this experience that "nothing is holding me back", one senses the lack of anything that predetermines you to either throw yourself off or to stand still, and one experiences one's own freedom. | |||
Another characteristic feature of the Look is that no Other really needs to have been there: It is possible that the creaking floorboard was simply the movement of an old house; the Look is not some kind of mystical telepathic experience of the actual way the Other sees one (there may have been someone there, but he could have not noticed that person). It is only one's perception of the way another might perceive him.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism {{!}} Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/ |access-date=2024-06-14 |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
It can also be seen in relation to the previous point how angst is before ''nothing'', and this is what sets it apart from fear which has an object. While in the case of fear, one can take definitive measures to remove the object of fear, in the case of angst, no such "constructive" measures are possible. The use of the word "nothing" in this context relates both to the inherent insecurity about the consequences of one's actions, and to the fact that, in experiencing one's freedom as angst, one also realizes that one will be fully responsible for these consequences; there is no ''thing'' in you (your genes, for instance) that acts in your stead, and that you can "blame" if something goes wrong. Not every choice is perceived as having dreadful possible consequences (and, it can be claimed, our lives would be unbearable if every choice facilitated dread), but that doesn't change the fact that freedom remains a condition of every action. One of the most extensive treatments of the existentialist notion of Angst is found in ] monumental work ''] (The Concept of Dread)''. | |||
=== |
=== Angst and dread === | ||
{{main|Angst}} | |||
The existentialist concept of freedom is often misunderstood as a sort of ] where almost anything is possible and where values are inconsequential to choice and action. This interpretation of the concept is often related to the insistence on the absurdity of the world and that there are no relevant or absolutely good or bad values. However, that there are no values to be found in the world ''in-itself'' doesn't mean that there are no values: each of us usually already has his values before a consideration of their validity is carried through, and it is, after all, upon these values we act. In Kierkegaard's Judge Vilhelm's account in '']'', making choices without allowing one's values to confer differing values to the alternatives, is, in fact, choosing not to make a choice — to flip a coin, as it were, and to leave everything to chance. This is considered to be a refusal to live in the consequence of one's freedom; an inauthentic existence. As such, existentialist freedom isn't situated in some kind of abstract space where everything is possible: since people are free, and since they already exist in the world, it is implied that their freedom is only in this world, and that it, too, is restricted by it. | |||
"Existential angst", sometimes called existential dread, anxiety, or ], is a term common to many existentialist thinkers. It is generally held to be a negative feeling arising from the experience of human freedom and responsibility.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Plesa |first=Patric |date=2021-07-14 |title=Reassessing Existential Constructs and Subjectivity: Freedom and Authenticity in Neoliberalism |journal=Journal of Humanistic Psychology |language=en |page=002216782110320 |doi=10.1177/00221678211032065 |issn=0022-1678|doi-access=free }}</ref>{{sfn|Aho|2023}} The archetypal example is the experience one has when standing on a cliff where one not only fears falling off it, but also dreads the possibility of throwing oneself off. In this experience that "nothing is holding me back", one senses the lack of anything that predetermines one to either throw oneself off or to stand still, and one experiences one's own freedom.<ref>{{Cite web |date=2018-02-20 |title=Soren Kierkegaard and The Psychology of Anxiety |url=https://academyofideas.com/2018/02/soren-kierkegaard-psychology-anxiety/ |access-date=2024-05-07 |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
What ''isn't'' implied in this account of existential freedom, however, is that one's values are immutable; a consideration of one's values may cause one to reconsider and change them. A consequence of this fact is that one is not only responsible for one's actions, but also for the values one holds. This entails that a reference to common values doesn't excuse the individual's actions: Even though these are the values of the society the individual is part of, they are also his own in the sense that s/he could choose them to be different at any time. Thus, the focus on freedom in existentialism is related to the limits of the responsibility one bears as a result of one's freedom: the relationship between freedom and responsibility is one of interdependency, and a clarification of freedom also clarifies what one is responsible for. | |||
It can also be seen in relation to the previous point how angst is before nothing, and this is what sets it apart from fear that has an object. While one can take measures to remove an object of fear, for angst no such "constructive" measures are possible. The use of the word "nothing" in this context relates to the inherent insecurity about the consequences of one's actions and to the fact that, in experiencing freedom as angst, one also realizes that one is fully responsible for these consequences. There is nothing in people (genetically, for instance) that acts in their stead—that they can blame if something goes wrong. Therefore, not every choice is perceived as having dreadful possible consequences (and, it can be claimed, human lives would be unbearable if every choice facilitated dread). However, this does not change the fact that freedom remains a condition of every action. | |||
=== Facticity === | |||
A concept closely related to freedom is that of ]. It is defined by Sartre in '']'' as that ] of which you are in the mode of not being. This can be more easily understood when considering it in relation to the temporal dimension of past: Your past is what you are in the sense that it co-constitutes you. However, to say that you are ''only'' your past would be to ignore a large part of reality (the present and the future) while saying that your past is only what you ''were'' in a way that would entirely detach it from you ''now''. A denial of one's own concrete past constitutes an inauthentic lifestyle, and the same goes for all other kinds of facticity (having a body (e.g. one that doesn't allow you to run faster than the speed of sound), identity, values, etc.). | |||
=== Despair === | |||
In relation to freedom, facticity is both a limitation and a condition of your freedom. It is a limitation in that a large part of your facticity consists of things you couldn't have chosen (birthplace, etc.), but a condition in the sense that your values most likely will depend on it. However, even though your facticity is "set in stone" (as being past, for instance), it cannot ''determine'' you: The value ascribed to your facticity is still ascribed to it freely ''by you''. As an example, consider two men, one of which has no memory of his past and the other remembers everything. They have both committed many crimes, but the first man, knowing nothing about this, leads a rather normal life while the second man, feeling trapped by his own past, continues a life of crime, blaming his own past for "trapping" him in this life. There is nothing essential about his committing crimes, but he ascribes this meaning to his past. | |||
{{Main|Philosophy of Søren Kierkegaard#Despair|l1=Despair}} | |||
{{See also|Existential crisis}} | |||
Despair is generally defined as a loss of hope.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.tfd.com/despair |title=despair – definition of despair by the Free Online Dictionary, Thesaurus and Encyclopedia |publisher=Tfd.com |access-date=2010-03-08}}</ref> In existentialism, it is more specifically a loss of hope in reaction to a breakdown in one or more of the defining qualities of one's self or identity. If a person is invested in being a particular thing, such as a bus driver or an upstanding citizen, and then finds their being-thing compromised, they would normally be found in a state of despair—a hopeless state. For example, a singer who loses the ability to sing may despair if they have nothing else to fall back on—nothing to rely on for their identity. They find themselves unable to be what defined their being. | |||
However, to disregard your facticity when you, in the continual process of self-making, ] yourself into the future, would be to put yourself in denial of yourself, and would thus be inauthentic. In other words, the origin of your projection will still have to be your facticity, although in the mode of not being it (essentially). | |||
What sets the existentialist notion of despair apart from the conventional definition is that existentialist despair is a state one is in even when they are not overtly in despair. So long as a person's identity depends on qualities that can crumble, they are in perpetual despair—and as there is, in Sartrean terms, no human essence found in conventional reality on which to constitute the individual's sense of identity, despair is a universal human condition. As Kierkegaard defines it in '']'': "Let each one learn what he can; both of us can learn that a person's unhappiness never lies in his lack of control over external conditions, since this would only make him completely unhappy."<ref>Either/Or Part II p. 188 Hong.</ref> In '']'', he says: | |||
Another aspect of facticity is that it entails angst, both in the sense that freedom "produces" angst when limited by facticity, and in the sense that the lack of the possibility of having facticity "step in" for you to take responsibility for something you have done also produces angst. | |||
{{Blockquote|When the God-forsaken worldliness of earthly life shuts itself in complacency, the confined air develops poison, the moment gets stuck and stands still, the prospect is lost, a need is felt for a refreshing, enlivening breeze to cleanse the air and dispel the poisonous vapors lest we suffocate in worldliness. ... Lovingly to hope all things is the opposite of despairingly to hope ] at all. Love hopes all things—yet is never put to shame. To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of the good is to hope. To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of evil is to fear. By the decision to choose hope one decides infinitely more than it seems, because it is an eternal decision.|author=Søren Kierkegaard|title=Works of Love|source=}} | |||
=== Authenticity and inauthenticity === | |||
The theme of authentic existence is common to many existentialist thinkers. It is often taken to mean that one has to "find oneself" and then live in accordance with this self, but in one sense, if one considers the self to be substantial or "fixed," that the self truly is some thing you can find if you look hard enough, this is a misunderstanding. | |||
== Opposition to positivism and rationalism == | |||
What is meant by authenticity is that in acting, one should act as oneself, not as ''One'', ''one's Genes'' or any other essence. The authentic act is one that is in accordance with one's freedom. Of course, as a condition of freedom is facticity, this includes one's facticity, but not to the degree that this facticity can in any way ''determine'' one's choices (in the sense that one could then blame one's background for making the choice one made). The role of facticity in relation to authenticity involves letting one's actual values come into play when one makes a choice (instead of, like Kierkegaard's Aesthete, "choosing" randomly), so that one also takes responsibility for the act instead of choosing either-or without allowing the options to have different values. | |||
{{See also|Positivism|Rationalism}} | |||
Existentialists oppose defining human beings as primarily rational, and, therefore, oppose both ] and ]. Existentialism asserts that people make decisions based on subjective meaning rather than pure rationality. | |||
In contrast to this, the inauthentic is the denial to live in accordance with one's freedom. This can take many forms, from pretending choices are meaningless or random, through convincing oneself that some form of ] is true, to a sort of "mimicry" where one acts as "''One'' should." How "One" should act is often determined by an image one has of how one such as oneself (say, a bank manager) acts. This image usually corresponds to some sort of social norm, but this does not mean that all acting in accordance with social norms is inauthentic: The main point is the attitude one takes to one's own freedom and responsibility, and the extent to which one acts in accordance with this freedom. | |||
The rejection of reason as the source of meaning is a common theme of existentialist thought, as is the focus on the ] and ] that we feel in the face of our own radical ] and our awareness of death. Kierkegaard advocated rationality as a means to interact with the objective world (e.g., in the natural sciences), but when it comes to existential problems, reason is insufficient: "Human reason has boundaries".<ref>''Søren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers'' Vol. 5, p. 5.</ref> | |||
Like Kierkegaard, Sartre saw problems with rationality, calling it a form of "bad faith", an attempt by the self to impose structure on a world of phenomena—"the Other"—that is fundamentally irrational and random. According to Sartre, rationality and other forms of bad faith hinder people from finding meaning in freedom. To try to suppress feelings of anxiety and dread, people confine themselves within everyday experience, Sartre asserted, thereby relinquishing their freedom and acquiescing to being possessed in one form or another by "the Look" of "the Other" (i.e., possessed by another person—or at least one's idea of that other person).<ref>{{Cite web |title=Ethics - Existentialism |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy |website=Encyclopedia Britannica |language=en |access-date=2020-05-28}}</ref> | |||
=== The Other and The Look === | |||
The Other (when written with a capitalised "o") is a concept more properly belonging to ] and its account of ]. However, the concept has seen widespread use in existentialist writings, and the conclusions drawn from it differ slightly from the phenomenological accounts. The experience of the Other is the experience of another free subject who inhabits the same world as you do. In its most basic form, it is this experience of the Other that constitutes intersubjectivity and objectivity. To clarify, when one experiences someone else, and that this Other person experiences the world (the same world that you experience), only from "over there", the world itself is constituted as objective in that it is something that is "there" as identical for both of the subjects; you experience the other person as experiencing the same as you. This experience of the Other's look is what is termed the Look (sometimes ]). | |||
== Religion == | |||
While this experience, in its basic phenomenological sense, constitutes the world as objective, and yourself as objectively existing subjectivity (you experience yourself as seen in the Other's Look in precisely the same way that you experience the Other as seen by you, as subjectivity), in existentialism, it also acts as a kind of limitation of your freedom. This is because the Look tends to objectify what it sees. As such, when one experiences oneself in the Look, one doesn't experience oneself as nothing (no thing), but as something. Sartre's own example of a man peeping at someone through a keyhole can help clarify this: At first, this man is entirely caught up in the situation he is in; he is in a pre-reflexive state where his entire consciousness is directed at what goes on in the room. Suddenly, he hears a creaking floorboard behind him, and he becomes aware of himself ''as seen by the Other''. He is thus filled with shame for he perceives himself as he would perceive someone else doing what he was doing, as a Peeping Tom. The Look is then co-constitutive of one's facticity. | |||
{{See also|Atheistic existentialism|Christian existentialism|Jewish existentialism}} | |||
An existentialist reading of the ] would demand that the reader recognize that they are an existing ] studying the words more as a recollection of events. This is in contrast to looking at a collection of "truths" that are outside and unrelated to the reader, but may develop a sense of reality/God. Such a reader is not obligated to follow the commandments as if an external agent is forcing these commandments upon them, but as though they are inside them and guiding them from inside. This is the task Kierkegaard takes up when he asks: "Who has the more difficult task: the teacher who lectures on earnest things a meteor's distance from everyday life—or the learner who should put it to use?"<ref>Kierkegaard, Soren. ''Works of Love''. Harper & Row, Publishers. New York, N.Y. 1962. p. 62.</ref> Philosophers such as ] and ] introduced the concept of existentialist ] into the field of ] and ], respectively.<ref>Sariel, Aviram. "Jonasian Gnosticism." Harvard Theological Review 116.1 (2023): 91-122.</ref> | |||
Another characteristic feature of the Look is that no Other ''really'' needs to have been there: It is quite possible that the creaking floorboard was nothing but the movement of an old house; the Look isn't some kind of mystical telepathic experience of the ''actual'' way the other sees you (there may also have been someone there, but he could have not noticed that you were there, or he could be another Peeping Tom who just wants to join you). | |||
== Confusion with nihilism == | |||
=== Reason=== | |||
{{See also|Existential nihilism}} | |||
Emphasizing action, freedom, and decision as fundamental, existentialists oppose themselves to ] and ]. That is, they argue against definitions of human beings as primarily rational. Rather, existentialists look at where people find meaning. Existentialism asserts that people actually make decisions based on the meaning to them rather than rationally. The rejection of reason as the source of meaning is a common theme of existentialist thought, as is the focus on the feelings of ] and ] that we feel in the face of our own radical ] and our awareness of death. Kierkegaard saw strong rationality as a mechanism humans use to counter their ], their fear of being in the world: "If I can believe that I am rational and everyone else is rational then I have nothing to fear and no reason to feel anxious about being free." {{fact}} However, Kierkegaard advocated rationality as means to interact with the objective world (e.g in the natural sciences), but when it comes to existential problems, reason is insufficent: "Human reason has boundaries".<ref>''Soren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers'' Vol 5, p. 5</ref> | |||
Although ] and existentialism are distinct philosophies, they are often confused with one another since both are rooted in the human experience of anguish and confusion that stems from the apparent meaninglessness of a world in which humans are compelled to find or create meaning.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/nihilism/#H3 |title=Nihilism |author=Alan Pratt |date=April 23, 2001 |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=] |access-date=November 18, 2018}}</ref> A primary cause of confusion is that ] was an important philosopher in both fields. | |||
Like Kierkegaard, Sartre saw problems with rationality, calling it a form of "bad faith", an attempt by the self to impose structure on a world of phenomena — "the Other" — that is fundamentally irrational and random. According to Sartre, rationality and other forms of bad faith hinder us from finding meaning in freedom. To try to suppress our feelings of anxiety and dread, we confine ourselves within everyday experience, Sartre asserts, thereby relinquishing our freedom and acquiescing to being possessed in one form or another by "the look" of "the Other" (i.e. possessed by another person — or at least our idea of that other person). In a similar vein, Camus believed that society and religion falsely teach humans that "the Other" has order and structure.<ref>Camus, Albert. "An Absurd Reasoning"</ref> For Camus, when an individual's consciousness, longing for order, collides with the Other's lack of order, a third element is born: absurdity. | |||
Existentialist philosophers often stress the importance of angst as signifying the absolute lack of any objective ground for action, a move that is often reduced to ] or ]. A pervasive theme in existentialist philosophy, however, is to persist through encounters with the absurd, as seen in ]'s philosophical essay '']'' (1942): "One must imagine Sisyphus happy".<ref>Camus, Albert. "The Myth of Sisyphus". .</ref> and it is only very rarely that existentialist philosophers dismiss morality or one's self-created meaning: ] regained a sort of morality in the religious (although he would not agree that it was ethical; the religious suspends the ethical), and ]'s final words in '']'' (1943): "All these questions, which refer us to a pure and not an accessory (or impure) reflection, can find their reply only on the ethical plane. We shall devote to them a future work."<ref name="Jean-Paul Sartre 2003"/> | |||
=== The Absurd === | |||
{{main|Absurdism}} | |||
The notion of the Absurd contains the idea that there is no meaning to be found in the world beyond what meaning we give to it. This meaninglessness also encompasses the amorality or "unfairness" of the world. This contrasts with "karmic" ways of thinking in which "bad things don't happen to good people"; to the world, metaphorically speaking, there is no such thing as a good person or a bad thing; what happens happens, and it may just as well happen to a good person as to a bad person. This contrasts our daily experience where most things appear to us as meaningful, and where good people do indeed, on occasion, receive some sort of "reward" for their goodness. Most existentialist thinkers, however, will maintain that this is not a necessary feature of the world, and that it definitely isn't a property of the world in-itself. Because of the world's absurdity, at any point in time, anything can happen to anyone, and a tragic event could plummet someone into direct confrontation with the Absurd. The notion of the absurd has been prominent in literature throughout history. ], ], ] and many of the literary works of ] and ] contain descriptions of people who encounter the absurdity of the world. ] studied the issue of "the absurd" in his essay '']''. | |||
== |
== History == | ||
=== Atheistic === | |||
Atheistic existentialism is the form of existentialism most commonly encountered in today's society. What sets it apart from ] is that it rejects the notion of a god and his transcendent will that should in some way dictate how we should live. It rejects the notion that there is any "created" meaning of life and the world, and that a ] is required of man in order for him to live an authentic life. In this kind of existentialism, belief in a god is often considered a form of ]. | |||
=== Precursors === | |||
In this kind of existentialism, the way to face the absurdity of the world is to create a meaning for yourself. This creation of meaning ''ex nihilo'' doesn't degrade your meaning as such, as all meaning would be created meaning. In other words, creating a meaning of your own life is completely legitimate, as long as you do not base it in "objective" existence, or let it be the main "pillar" of your life. According to Kierkegaard, one would be in a perpetual state of despair (although it would be an unrealised despair that one would flee from whenever it showed itself) if one had some meaning (It doesn't necessarily have to be one single meaning; even a multitude of meanings is fragile) as the main pillar of one's life. | |||
Some have argued that existentialism has long been an element of European religious thought, even before the term came into use. ] identified ] and ] as two specific examples.{{Sfn|Barrett|1958|pp=97, 133–157}} ] also identified ]'s ] ("]"), ], ], and ] as existentialists. According to Wahl, "the origins of most great philosophies, like those of ], ], and ], are to be found in existential reflections."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Wahl |first=Jean André |url=http://archive.org/details/shorthistoryofex00wahl |title=A Short History of Existentialism |date=1949 |publisher=Philosophical Library |location=New York |pages=32–33 |author-link=Jean Wahl}}</ref> Precursors to existentialism can also be identified in the works of Iranian Muslim philosopher ] (c. 1571–1635), who would posit that "]" becoming the principle expositor of the ], which is described as "alive and active".{{According to whom|date=January 2024}} | |||
=== 19th century === | |||
Two leading 20th century figures among atheist existentialists were ] and ]. | |||
=== |
==== Kierkegaard and Nietzsche ==== | ||
{{Main|Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche}} | |||
Theistic existentialism is, for the most part, ] in its outlook, because the way traced by Kierkegaard, ], ], ] and others is even nowadays quite strong. | |||
Kierkegaard is generally considered to have been the first existentialist philosopher.{{sfn|Crowell|2020}}{{sfn|Marino|2004|p=}}{{sfn|McDonald|Lippitt|Evans|2017}} He proposed that each individual—not reason, society, or religious orthodoxy—is solely tasked with giving ] to life and living it sincerely, or "authentically".<ref>{{cite book |last=Watts |first=Michael |title=Kierkegaard |url=https://archive.org/details/kierkegaard00watt |url-access=limited |publisher=Oneworld |year=2003 |pages=–6|isbn=978-1-85168-317-8 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Lowrie |first=Walter |title=Kierkegaard's attack upon "Christendom" |publisher=Princeton |year=1969 |pages=37–40}}</ref> | |||
But there have been existentialists of other theological persuasions, like ] (see ]) and ]. Unlike atheistic existentialists, they posit the existence of God, and that God is the source of our being. It is generally held that God has designed the world in such a way that we must define our own lives, and each individual is held accountable for his own self-definition. | |||
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were two of the first philosophers considered fundamental to the existentialist movement, though neither used the term "existentialism" and it is unclear whether they would have supported the existentialism of the 20th century. They focused on subjective human experience rather than the objective truths of mathematics and science, which they believed were too detached or observational to truly get at the human experience. Like Pascal, they were interested in people's quiet struggle with the apparent meaninglessness of life and the use of diversion to escape from ]. Unlike Pascal, Kierkegaard and Nietzsche also considered the role of making free choices, particularly regarding fundamental values and beliefs, and how such choices change the nature and identity of the chooser.{{sfn|Luper|2000|pp=4–5, 11}} Kierkegaard's ] and Nietzsche's ] are representative of people who exhibit ], in that they define the nature of their own existence. Nietzsche's idealized individual invents his own values and creates the very terms they excel under. By contrast, Kierkegaard, opposed to the level of abstraction in Hegel, and not nearly as hostile (actually welcoming) to ] as Nietzsche, argues through a pseudonym that the objective certainty of religious truths (specifically Christian) is not only impossible, but even founded on logical paradoxes. Yet he continues to imply that a ] is a possible means for an individual to reach a higher stage of existence that transcends and contains both an aesthetic and ethical value of life. Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were also precursors to other intellectual movements, including ], and various strands of ]{{citation needed|date=October 2021}} However, Kierkegaard believed that individuals should live in accordance with their thinking.{{sfn|McDonald|Lippitt|Evans|2017}} | |||
=== Nihilism === | |||
{{Article issues|disputed=May 2008|POV=May 2008}} | |||
{{Refimprove|date=July 2008}} | |||
{{Expert-verify|date=July 2008}} | |||
Though ] and existentialism are distinct philosophies, they are often confused with one another. A primary cause of confusion is that ] is a central philosopher in both fields, but also the fact that the notions of the absurd and the inherent meaninglessness of the world could be taken as implying a nihilistic position. A pervasive theme in the works of existentialist philosophy, however, is to persist ''through'' encounters with the absurd. | |||
In ''Twilight of the Idols'', Nietzsche's sentiments resonate the idea of "existence precedes essence." He writes, "no one ''gives'' man his qualities-- neither God, nor society, nor his parents and ancestors, nor he himself...No one is responsible for man's being there at all, for his being such-and-such, or for his being in these circumstances or in this environment...Man is not the effect of some special purpose of a will, and end..."<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Nietzsche |first1=Friedrich |title=The portable Nietzsche |last2=Kaufmann |first2=Walter |date=1994 |publisher=Penguin |isbn=978-0-14-015062-9 |edition=Repr. of the 1954 ed. publ. by The Viking Press, New York |series=Penguin books |location=New York}}</ref> Within this view, Nietzsche ties in his rejection of the existence of God, which he sees as a means to "redeem the world." By rejecting the existence of God, Nietzsche also rejects beliefs that claim humans have a predestined purpose according to what God has instructed. | |||
Adding to the confusion is a form of nihilism, ]. What sets existential nihilists apart from pure nihilists is that whilst pure nihilists do not believe in ] or ], existential nihilists only believe this in relation ''to life''. | |||
====Dostoyevsky==== | |||
Whilst existentialists will allow for meaning in life (meaning which they themselves project into it), existential nihilists will deny that this meaning is anything but self-deception. | |||
The first important literary author also important to existentialism was the Russian, Dostoyevsky.<ref>Hubben, William. ''Dostoyevsky, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Kafka, Jabber-wacky'', Scribner, 1997.</ref> Dostoyevsky's '']'' portrays a man unable to fit into society and unhappy with the identities he creates for himself. Sartre, in his book on existentialism '']'', quoted Dostoyevsky's '']'' as an example of ]. Other Dostoyevsky novels covered issues raised in existentialist philosophy while presenting story lines divergent from secular existentialism: for example, in '']'', the protagonist Raskolnikov experiences an existential crisis and then moves toward a Christian Orthodox worldview similar to that advocated by Dostoyevsky himself.<ref name="Rukhsana">{{Cite book |last=Rukhsana |first=Akhter |title=Existentialism and Its Relevance to the Contemporary System of Education in India: Existentialism and Present Educational Scenario |date=June 2014 |isbn=978-3-95489-277-8 |location=Hamburg |publisher=Anchor Academic |oclc=911266433}}</ref> | |||
==Criticism== | |||
=== Early 20th century === | |||
] criticised Existentialism, especially '']'' (1943), by Jean-Paul Sartre, for projecting anxiety and meaninglessness onto the nature of existence itself: "Insofar as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it ] specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics. Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory".<ref>Marcuse, Herbert. "Sartre's Existentialism". Printed in ''Studies in Critical Philosophy''. Translated by Joris De Bres. London: NLB, 1972. p. 161</ref> In 1946, Sartre already had replied to Marxist criticism of Existentialism in the lecture ''Existentialism is a humanism''.<ref></ref> In ''Jargon of Authenticity'', ] criticised Heidegger's philosophy, especially his use of language, as a mystifying ideology of advanced, industrial society, and its power structure. {{Fact|date=January 2007}} | |||
{{See also|Martin Heidegger}} | |||
In the first decades of the 20th century, a number of philosophers and writers explored existentialist ideas. The Spanish philosopher ], in his 1913 book ''The Tragic Sense of Life in Men and Nations'', emphasized the life of "flesh and bone" as opposed to that of abstract rationalism. Unamuno rejected systematic philosophy in favor of the individual's quest for faith. He retained a sense of the tragic, even absurd nature of the quest, symbolized by his enduring interest in the eponymous character from the ] novel '']''. A novelist, poet and dramatist as well as philosophy professor at the University of Salamanca, Unamuno wrote a short story about a priest's crisis of faith, '']'', which has been collected in anthologies of existentialist fiction. Another Spanish thinker, ], writing in 1914, held that human existence must always be defined as the individual person combined with the concrete circumstances of his life: "''Yo soy yo y mi circunstancia''" ("I am myself and my circumstances"). Sartre likewise believed that human existence is not an abstract matter, but is always situated ("''en situation''").<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Pitari |first1=Paolo |date=7 August 2020 |title=The Influence of Sartre’s “What Is Literature?” on David Foster Wallace’s Literary Project |url=https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/00111619.2020.1729690 |journal=Critique: Studies in Contemporary Fiction |volume=61 |issue=4 |pages=423–439 |doi=10.1080/00111619.2020.1729690 |access-date=22 December 2024|hdl=10278/3730293 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> | |||
In ''Letters on Humanism'', Heidegger criticized Sartre's existentialism: | |||
Although ] wrote his major philosophical works in German, and studied and taught at the Universities of Berlin and ], he stands apart from the mainstream of German philosophy. Born into a Jewish family in Vienna in 1878, he was also a scholar of Jewish culture and involved at various times in ] and ]. In 1938, he moved permanently to ]. His best-known philosophical work was the short book '']'', published in 1922.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Buber|first=Martin|title=I and Thou. Trans. Walter Kaufmann|publisher=Charles Scribner's Sons|year=1970|isbn=978-0-684-71725-8|location=United States}}</ref> For Buber, the fundamental fact of human existence, too readily overlooked by scientific rationalism and abstract philosophical thought, is "man with man", a dialogue that takes place in the so-called "sphere of between" (''"das Zwischenmenschliche"'').<ref>Maurice S. Friedman, ''Martin Buber. The Life of Dialogue'', University of Chicago Press, 1955, p. 85.</ref> | |||
:''Existentialism says existence precedes essence. In this statement he is taking ''existentia'' and ''essentia'' according to their metaphysical meaning, which, from Plato's time on, has said that ''essentia'' precedes ''existentia''. Sartre reverses this statement. But the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement. With it, he stays with metaphysics, in oblivion of the truth of Being.'' | |||
Two Russian philosophers, ] and ], became well known as existentialist thinkers during their post-Revolutionary exiles in Paris. Shestov had launched an attack on rationalism and systematization in philosophy as early as 1905 in his book of aphorisms ''All Things Are Possible''. Berdyaev drew a radical distinction between the world of spirit and the everyday world of objects. Human freedom, for Berdyaev, is rooted in the realm of spirit, a realm independent of scientific notions of causation. To the extent the individual human being lives in the objective world, he is estranged from authentic spiritual freedom. "Man" is not to be interpreted naturalistically, but as a being created in God's image, an originator of free, creative acts.<ref>Ernst Breisach, ''Introduction to Modern Existentialism'', New York (1962), pp. 173–76.</ref> He published a major work on these themes, ''The Destiny of Man'', in 1931. | |||
In ''From Descartes to Wittgenstein'', ] says that Heidegger's concept of ] and Sartre's concept of ] were self-inconsistent; both deny any universal moral creed, yet speak of these concepts as if everyone were bound to abide them. In chapter 18, he says: "In what sense Sartre is able to 'recommend' the authenticity, which consists in the purely self-made morality, is unclear. He does recommend it, but, by his own argument, his recommendation can have no objective force." However, despite the seemingly moral tone present in each, both Heidegger and Sartre stress throughout their respective works that these are not to be taken as evaluative concepts, and if we take their word for this (as Scruton does not), there is no inconsistency in this regard. Both authors appeal to the reader in all regards to decide for him/herself. | |||
], long before coining the term "existentialism", introduced important existentialist themes to a French audience in his early essay "Existence and Objectivity" (1925) and in his ''Metaphysical Journal'' (1927).<ref name="Samuel M. Keen 1967">Samuel M. Keen, "Gabriel Marcel" in Paul Edwards (ed.) ''The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy'', Macmillan Publishing Co, 1967.</ref> A dramatist as well as a philosopher, Marcel found his philosophical starting point in a condition of metaphysical alienation: the human individual searching for harmony in a transient life. Harmony, for Marcel, was to be sought through "secondary reflection", a "dialogical" rather than "dialectical" approach to the world, characterized by "wonder and astonishment" and open to the "presence" of other people and of God rather than merely to "information" about them. For Marcel, such presence implied more than simply being there (as one thing might be in the presence of another thing); it connoted "extravagant" availability, and the willingness to put oneself at the disposal of the other.<ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'', Pelican, 1973, p. 110.</ref> | |||
], such as ] and ], say Existentialists frequently are confused about the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being".<ref>Carnap, Rudolf, ''Uberwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Spache'' , Erkenntnis (1932), pp.219&ndash241. Carnap's critique of Heidegger's "What is Metaphysics".</ref> They argue that the verb is transitive, and pre-fixed to a ] (e.g., an apple ''is red''): without a predicate, the word is meaningless. Another alleged confusion, in existentialist metaphysical literature, is that existentialists try to understand the meaning of the word "nothing" (the negation of existence) by presuming it must refer to something. Borrowing Kant's argument<ref>Kant, ''Critique of Pure Reason'' A:595&ndash602. B:623&ndash627</ref> against the ] ''for'' the existence of God, logical positivists argue that existence is not a property. {{Fact|date=October 2007}} Existentialists would respond to both claims by an appeal to the reader's intuitive understanding on the matter, which is guided to this end through the descriptive content of their works. They treat the matter as beyond the scope of argument and logic. Even though Gödel epistemologically disproved positivism with ].<ref>GÖDEL AND THE NATURE OF MATHEMATICAL TRUTH A Talk with ] </ref> | |||
Marcel contrasted ''secondary reflection'' with abstract, scientific-technical ''primary reflection'', which he associated with the activity of the abstract ] ego. For Marcel, philosophy was a concrete activity undertaken by a sensing, feeling human being incarnate—embodied—in a concrete world.<ref name="Samuel M. Keen 1967"/><ref>John Macquarrie, ''Existentialism'', Pelican, 1973, p. 96.</ref> Although Sartre adopted the term "existentialism" for his own philosophy in the 1940s, Marcel's thought has been described as "almost diametrically opposed" to that of Sartre.<ref name="Samuel M. Keen 1967"/> Unlike Sartre, Marcel was a Christian, and became a Catholic convert in 1929. | |||
== Influence outside philosophy == | |||
=== Cultural movement and influence === | |||
The term ''existentialism'' was first adopted as a self-reference in the 1940s and 1950s by Jean-Paul Sartre, and the widespread use of literature as a means of disseminating their ideas by Sartre and his associates (notably novelist ]) meant existentialism "was as much a literary phenomenon as a philosophical one."<ref name=sep>{{sep entry|Existentialism|Steven Crowell|2004-08-23}}</ref> Among existentialist writers were Parisians ], ], ], and playwright ], the Norwegian ], and the Romanian friends ] and ]. Prominent artists such as the ] ], ], and ] have been understood in existentialist terms, as have ]s such as ] and ].<ref name=sep/> Individual films such as the 1952 western '']'' and '']'' (1999) have also been cited as existentialist.<ref>{{cite journal | |||
|last =Kavadlo | |||
|first =Jesse | |||
|year =2005 | |||
|title =The Fiction of Self-destruction: Chuck Palahniuk, Closet Moralist | |||
|journal =Stirrings Still, the International Journal of Existential Literature | |||
|url =http://www.stirrings-still.org/ss22.pdf | |||
|format =] | |||
|accessdate =2007-05-10 | |||
}}</ref><ref name="HighNoon01"></ref> Also, existential theological influence is apparent in the ]. | |||
In Germany, the psychiatrist and philosopher ]—who later described existentialism as a "phantom" created by the public<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers'' The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 75/11.</ref>—called his own thought, heavily influenced by Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, ''Existenzphilosophie''. For Jaspers, "''Existenz''-philosophy is the way of thought by means of which man seeks to become himself...This way of thought does not cognize objects, but elucidates and makes actual the being of the thinker".<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers'' The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 40.</ref> | |||
==== Literature ==== | |||
In the 20th century, existentialism experienced a resurgence in popular art forms. In fiction, ]'s 1928 novel '']'', based on an idea in Kierkegaard's ''Either/Or'' (1843),{{Specify|date=December 2007}} sold well in the West. ] and the ] adopted existentialist themes. "]" films began quoting and alluding to existentialist thought and thinkers. Existentialist novelists were generally seen as a mid-1950s phenomenon that continued until the mid- to late 1970s. Most of the major writers were either French or from French African colonies. Small circles of other Europeans were seen as literary precursors by the existentialists, but literary history increasingly has questioned the accuracy of this perception. | |||
Jaspers, a professor at the university of ], was acquainted with Heidegger, who held a professorship at ] before acceding to Husserl's chair at ] in 1928. They held many philosophical discussions, but later became estranged over Heidegger's support of ]. They shared an admiration for Kierkegaard,<ref>Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) ''The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers'' The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 75/2 and following.</ref> and in the 1930s, Heidegger lectured extensively on Nietzsche. Nevertheless, the extent to which Heidegger should be considered an existentialist is debatable. In ''Being and Time'' he presented a method of rooting philosophical explanations in human existence (''Dasein'') to be analysed in terms of existential categories (''existentiale''); and this has led many commentators to treat him as an important figure in the existentialist movement. | |||
After the 1970s, much cultural activity in art, cinema, and literature contains both ] and existential elements. Books such as '']?'' (1968) (now republished as '']'') by Philip K. Dick, and '']'' by ] all distort the line between reality and appearance while simultaneously espousing strong existential themes. Ideas from such thinkers as ], ], ], ], ], and ] permeate the works of artists such as Chuck Palahniuk, Irvine Welsh, Michael Szymczyk, David Lynch, Crispin Glover, and Charles Bukowski, and one often finds in their works a delicate balance between distastefulness and beauty. The novel ], by ] depicts the existentialism in its main character, Horacio Oliveira. | |||
=== After the Second World War === | |||
Existential themes have been evident throughout 20th century cinema. Many films portray characters going through the "]" or existential problems. Just as there is much controversy about the definition of existentialism, there is a fine line between existential and non-existential films. One might ask how certain movies can be considered existential, while others are not, and the judgment is purely subjective. However, for the sake of discussion, it is beneficial to provide a clear definition of existential movies. The most accurate definition says that existential movies are those which have strong plots that deal with subjects such as ], ], ], ], ] and ]. Furthermore, the definition states that movies ''which deal with the themes of existential literature seriously'' are also considered as being existential.<ref></ref> | |||
Following the Second World War, existentialism became a well-known and significant philosophical and cultural movement, mainly through the public prominence of two French writers, ] and ], who wrote best-selling novels, plays and widely read journalism as well as theoretical texts.<ref>{{cite book |last=Baert |first=Patrick |date=2015 |title=The Existentialist Moment: The Rise of Sartre as a Public Intellectual |publisher=Polity Press}}</ref> These years also saw the growing reputation of ''Being and Time'' outside Germany. | |||
A number of 1940s and 1950s-era films explored existential themes, including the US ] genre, which explored the ambiguous moral dilemmas of people drawn into the gangster underworld. Film noirs tend to revolve around heroes who are more flawed and morally questionable than the norm, often fall guys of one sort or another. The characteristic heroes of noir are described by many critics as "alienated" and "filled with existential bitterness."<ref>Silver, Alain, and Elizabeth Ward, eds. (1992). Film Noir: An Encyclopedic Reference to the American Style, 3d ed. Woodstock, N.Y.: Overlook Press. ISBN 0-87951-479-5 </ref> Film noir is often described as essentially pessimistic. The noir stories that are regarded as most characteristic tell of people trapped in unwanted situations (which, in general, they did not cause but are responsible for exacerbating), striving against random, uncaring fate, and frequently doomed. The movies are seen as depicting a world that is inherently corrupt. Classic film noir has been associated by many critics with the American social landscape of the era—in particular, with a sense of heightened anxiety and alienation that is said to have followed World War II. | |||
] and ]]] | |||
Sartre dealt with existentialist themes in his 1938 novel '']'' and the short stories in his 1939 collection '']'', and had published his treatise on existentialism, ''Being and Nothingness'', in 1943, but it was in the two years following the liberation of Paris from the German occupying forces that he and his close associates—Camus, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and others—became internationally famous as the leading figures of a movement known as existentialism.<ref name="Ronald Aronson 2004">Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'', University of Chicago Press, 2004, Chapter 3 ''passim.''</ref> In a very short period of time, Camus and Sartre in particular became the leading public intellectuals of post-war France, achieving by the end of 1945 "a fame that reached across all audiences."<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'', University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 44.</ref> Camus was an editor of the most popular leftist (former ]) newspaper '']''; Sartre launched his journal of leftist thought, '']'', and two weeks later gave the widely reported lecture on existentialism and ] to a packed meeting of the Club Maintenant. Beauvoir wrote that "not a week passed without the newspapers discussing us";<ref>Simone de Beauvoir, ''Force of Circumstance'', quoted in Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'', University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 48.</ref> existentialism became "the first media craze of the postwar era."<ref>Ronald Aronson, ''Camus and Sartre'', University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 48.</ref> | |||
Existentialist themes were also present in other genres. The French director ]'s 1950 fantasy-erotic film '']'' shows two inmates in solitary cells whose only contact is through a hole in their cell wall, who are spied on by the prison warden. Reviewer James Travers calls the film a "...visual poem evoking homosexual desire and existentialist suffering" which "... conveys the bleakness of a existence in a godless universe with painful believability"; he calls it "... probably the most effective fusion of existentialist philosophy and cinema."<ref>© James Travers 2005 http://72.14.205.104/search?q=cache:iPYJjAhhAuMJ:filmsdefrance.com/FDF_Un_chant_d_amour_rev.html</ref> | |||
By the end of 1947, Camus' earlier fiction and plays had been reprinted, his new play '']'' had been performed and his novel '']'' published; the first two novels of Sartre's '']'' trilogy had appeared, as had Beauvoir's novel '']''. Works by Camus and Sartre were already appearing in foreign editions. The Paris-based existentialists had become famous.<ref name="Ronald Aronson 2004"/> | |||
]'s 1957 anti-war film '']'' "illustrates, and even illuminates...existentialism" by examining the "necessary absurdity of the human condition" and the "horror of war"<ref>Holt, Jason. "Existential Ethics: Where do the Paths of Glory Lead?". In ''The Philosophy of Stanley Kubr''ick. By Jerold J. Abrams. Published 2007. University Press of Kentucky. ISBN 081312445X</ref>. The film tells the story of a fictional World War I French army regiment which is ordered to attack an impregnable German stronghold; when the attack fails, three soldiers are chosen at random, court-martialed by a "kangaroo court", and executed by firing squad. The film examines existential ethics, such as the issue of whether objectivity is possible and the "problem of authenticity".<ref>Holt, Jason. "Existential Ethics: Where do the Paths of Glory Lead?". In ''The Philosophy of Stanley Kubrick''. By Jerold J. Abrams. Published 2007. University Press of Kentucky. ISBN 081312445X</ref> | |||
Sartre had traveled to Germany in 1930 to study the ] of ] and ],<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, '']'', Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 343.</ref> and he included critical comments on their work in his major treatise ''Being and Nothingness''. Heidegger's thought had also become known in French philosophical circles through its use by ] in explicating Hegel in a series of lectures given in Paris in the 1930s.<ref>Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), ''The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics'' (Hodder Arnold, 2006, p. 158); see also Alexandre Kojève, ''Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit'' (Cornell University Press, 1980).</ref> The lectures were highly influential; members of the audience included not only Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, but ], ], ], ], and ].<ref>Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), ''The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics'' (Hodder Arnold, 2006, p. 158).</ref> A selection from ''Being and Time'' was published in French in 1938, and his essays began to appear in French philosophy journals. | |||
On the lighter side, the British comedy troupe ] have explored existential themes throughout their works, from many of the sketches in their original television show, the ], to their last major release and what is likely the most obvious example, the 1983 film ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.amazon.com/Films-with-an-Existential-Theme/lm/2XUY93GON1RKW|title=amazon.com's Films with an Existential Theme|accessdate=2009-02-02}}</ref>. Of the many adjectives (some listed in the introduction above) that might indicate an existential tone, the one utilized the most by the group is that of the absurd. | |||
]]] | |||
Heidegger read Sartre's work and was initially impressed, commenting: "Here for the first time I encountered an independent thinker who, from the foundations up, has experienced the area out of which I think. Your work shows such an immediate comprehension of my philosophy as I have never before encountered."<ref>Martin Heidegger, letter, quoted in Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidegger – Between Good and Evil'' (Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 349).</ref> Later, however, in response to a question posed by his French follower ],<ref>Rüdiger Safranski, ''Martin Heidegger – Between Good and Evil'' (Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 356).</ref> Heidegger distanced himself from Sartre's position and existentialism in general in his '']''.<ref>William J. Richardson, ''Martin Heidegger: From Phenomenology to Thought'' (Martjinus Nijhoff, 1967, p. 351).</ref> Heidegger's reputation continued to grow in France during the 1950s and 1960s. In the 1960s, Sartre attempted to reconcile existentialism and ] in his work '']''. A major theme throughout his writings was freedom and responsibility. | |||
Some contemporary films dealing with existential issues include '']'', '']'', and '']''<ref></ref>. Likewise, films throughout the 20th century such as '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', and '']'' also have existential qualities.<ref></ref> Notable directors known for their existentialist films include ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ].<ref></ref> ]'s ] focuses on the protagonist's desire to find existential meaning in life as he sees its end.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.latimes.com/entertainment/news/movies/la-et-synecdoche24-2008oct24,0,5252277.story|title=Review: 'Synecdoche, New York'|accessdate=2008-11-17}}</ref> | |||
Camus was a friend of Sartre, until their falling-out, and wrote several works with existential themes including '']'', ''Summer in Algiers'', '']'', and '']'', the latter being "considered—to what would have been Camus's irritation—the exemplary existentialist novel."<ref>{{Cite journal |last = Messud |first = Claire |author-link = Claire Messud |year = 2014 |title = A New 'L'Étranger' |url = http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2014/jun/05/camus-new-letranger/ |journal = ] |volume = 61 |number = 10 |access-date = 1 June 2014 }}</ref> Camus, like many others, rejected the existentialist label, and considered his works concerned with facing the absurd.{{sfn|Camus|1968}} In the titular book, Camus uses the analogy of the Greek myth of ] to demonstrate the futility of existence. In the myth, Sisyphus is condemned for eternity to roll a rock up a hill, but when he reaches the summit, the rock will roll to the bottom again. Camus believes that this existence is pointless but that Sisyphus ultimately finds meaning and purpose in his task, simply by continually applying himself to it. The first half of the book contains an extended rebuttal of what Camus took to be existentialist philosophy in the works of Kierkegaard, Shestov, Heidegger, and Jaspers. | |||
], an important existentialist who spent much of her life as Sartre's partner, wrote about feminist and existentialist ethics in her works, including '']'' and '']''. Although often overlooked due to her relationship with Sartre,<ref name = Bergoffen-SEoP>{{cite encyclopedia |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauvoir/|title=Simone de Beauvoir|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |author=Bergoffen, Debra|date=September 2010}}</ref> de Beauvoir integrated existentialism with other forms of thinking such as feminism, unheard of at the time, resulting in alienation from fellow writers such as Camus.<ref name="Rukhsana"/> | |||
], an important existentialist theologian following Kierkegaard and ], applied existentialist concepts to ], and helped introduce ] to the general public. His seminal work ''The Courage to Be'' follows Kierkegaard's analysis of anxiety and life's absurdity, but puts forward the thesis that modern humans must, via God, achieve selfhood in spite of life's absurdity. ] used Kierkegaard's and Heidegger's philosophy of existence to demythologize Christianity by interpreting Christian mythical concepts into existentialist concepts. | |||
], an ], was for a time a companion of Sartre. Merleau-Ponty's '']'' (1945) was recognized as a major statement of French existentialism.<ref>Madison, G. B., in Robert Audi's ''The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy'' (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 559).</ref> It has been said that Merleau-Ponty's work ''Humanism and Terror'' greatly influenced Sartre. However, in later years they were to disagree irreparably, dividing many existentialists such as de Beauvoir,<ref name="Rukhsana"/> who sided with Sartre. | |||
], an English writer, published his study '']'' in 1956, initially to critical acclaim. In this book and others (e.g. ''Introduction to the New Existentialism''), he attempted to reinvigorate what he perceived as a pessimistic philosophy and bring it to a wider audience. He was not, however, academically trained, and his work was attacked by professional philosophers for lack of rigor and critical standards.<ref>K. Gunnar Bergström, ''An Odyssey to Freedom'' University of Uppsala, 1983, p. 92. Colin Stanley, ''Colin Wilson, a Celebration: Essays and Recollections'' Cecil Woolf, 1988, p. 43.</ref> | |||
== Influence outside philosophy == | |||
=== Art === | |||
==== Film and television ==== | |||
] (''left'') and ] (''right'') in '']'' (1957)]] | |||
]'s 1957 ] '']'' "illustrates, and even illuminates...existentialism" by examining the "necessary absurdity of the ]" and the "horror of war".<ref name=Holt2007>Holt, Jason. "Existential Ethics: Where do the Paths of Glory Lead?". In ''The Philosophy of Stanley Kubrick''. By Jerold J. Abrams. Published 2007. University Press of Kentucky. SBN 0-8131-2445-X</ref> The film tells the story of a fictional World War I French army regiment ordered to attack an impregnable German stronghold; when the attack fails, three soldiers are chosen at random, court-martialed by a "]", and executed by firing squad. The film examines existentialist ethics, such as the issue of whether ] is possible and the "problem of ]".<ref name=Holt2007/> ]'s 1962 film '']'', based upon Franz Kafka's book of the same name (''Der Prozeß''), is characteristic of both existentialist and absurdist themes in its depiction of a man (Joseph K.) arrested for a crime for which the charges are neither revealed to him nor to the reader. | |||
'']'' is a Japanese ] animation series created by the ] studio ] and was both directed and written by ]. Existential themes of individuality, consciousness, freedom, choice, and responsibility are heavily relied upon throughout the entire series, particularly through the philosophies of ] and ]. Episode 16's title, {{Nihongo|"The Sickness Unto Death, And..."|死に至る病、そして|Shi ni itaru yamai, soshite}} is a reference to Kierkegaard's book, '']''. | |||
Some contemporary films dealing with existentialist issues include ], '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', and '']''.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.existential-therapy.com/Arts/Movies.htm |title=Existential & Psychological Movie Recommendations |publisher=Existential-therapy.com |access-date=2010-03-08 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100107010239/http://www.existential-therapy.com/Arts/Movies.htm |archive-date=2010-01-07 }}</ref> Likewise, films throughout the 20th century such as '']'', '']'', '']'', the ], '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', and '']'' also have existentialist qualities.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://uhaweb.hartford.edu/BEAUCHEMI/ |title=Existentialism in Film |publisher=Uhaweb.hartford.edu |access-date=2010-03-08 |archive-date=2010-01-13 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100113012444/http://uhaweb.hartford.edu/BEAUCHEMI/ }}</ref> | |||
Notable directors known for their existentialist films include ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ].<ref>{{cite web |url=http://hcl.harvard.edu/hfa/films/2005winter/existential.html |title=Existentialist Adaptations – Harvard Film Archive |publisher=Hcl.harvard.edu |access-date=2010-03-08 |archive-date=2011-01-27 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110127085429/http://hcl.harvard.edu/hfa/films/2005winter/existential.html }}</ref> ]'s '']'' focuses on the protagonist's desire to find existential meaning.<ref>{{cite news|url=http://www.latimes.com/entertainment/news/movies/la-et-synecdoche24-2008oct24,0,5252277.story|title=Review: 'Synecdoche, New York'|access-date=2008-11-17 | work=Los Angeles Times | first=Carina | last=Chocano | date=2008-10-24}}</ref> Similarly, in Kurosawa's '']'', the protagonist's experiences as an intern in a rural health clinic in Japan lead him to an ] whereby he questions his reason for being. This, in turn, leads him to a better understanding of humanity. The French film, '']'' (directed by ]) embraced various elements of existentialism.{{citation needed|date=April 2016}} The film '']'', released in 1994, depicts life in a prison in ], United States to explore several existentialist concepts.<ref>For an examination of the existentialist elements within the film, see ], issue 102, accessible , accessed 3 June 2014.</ref> | |||
==== Literature ==== | |||
]'' by ] (1925)|alt=A simple book cover in green displays the name of the author and the book]] | |||
Existential perspectives are also found in modern literature to varying degrees, especially since the 1920s. ]'s '']'' (''Voyage au bout de la nuit'', 1932) celebrated by both Sartre and Beauvoir, contained many of the themes that would be found in later existential literature, and is in some ways, the proto-existential novel. Jean-Paul Sartre's 1938 novel '']''<ref name=SartreNausea>{{Cite book | first= Jean-Paul| last= Sartre| translator-last=Baldick |translator-first=Robert |translator-link=Robert Baldick | title= Nausea|location= London| publisher= Penguin| year= 2000 |orig-date=1938 }}</ref> was "steeped in Existential ideas", and is considered an accessible way of grasping his philosophical stance.<ref name=Earnshaw2006>{{Cite book| first= Steven| last= Earnshaw| title = Existentialism: A Guide for the Perplexed|location= London| publisher= Continuum| year= 2006| page= 75| isbn= 0-8264-8530-8}}</ref> Between 1900 and 1960, other authors such as ], ], ], ], ], ], ],<ref name="luigitheatre"/><ref name="understandex"/><ref name="masks"/><ref name=luigip>{{cite book|last1=Cincotta|first1=Madeleine Strong|title=Luigi Pirandello: The Humorous Existentialist|date=1989|publisher=University of Wollongong Press|isbn=978-0-86418-090-2|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CUIoPQAACAAJ|access-date=26 March 2015}}</ref><ref name=luigi>{{cite book|last1=Bassanese|first1=Fiora A.|title=Understanding Luigi Pirandello|date=Jan 1, 1997|publisher=University of South Carolina Press|isbn=978-0-585-33727-2|url=https://archive.org/details/understandinglui0000bass|url-access=registration|quote=existential.|access-date=26 March 2015}}</ref><ref name=playwrights>{{cite book|last1=DiGaetani|first1=John Louis|title=Stages of Struggle: Modern Playwrights and Their Psychological Inspirations|date=Jan 25, 2008|publisher=McFarland|isbn=978-0-7864-8259-7|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=A5C9gbBCwvYC&q=luigi+pirandello+existentialism&pg=PA34|access-date=26 March 2015}}</ref> ],<ref name=ellison>{{cite book|last1=Graham|first1=Maryemma|last2=Singh|first2=Amritjit|title=Conversations with Ralph Ellison|date=1995|publisher=University of Mississippi Press|isbn=978-0-87805-781-8|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L0lb8WoLRDkC&q=existentialism&pg=PA84|access-date=26 March 2015}}</ref><ref name=existentialamerica>{{cite book|last1=Cotkin|first1=George|title=Existential American|date=2005|publisher=JHU Press|isbn=978-0-8018-8200-5|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MJS3SMamIxIC&q=ralph+ellison+existential|access-date=26 March 2015}}</ref><ref name=readinglearning>{{cite book|last1=Thomas|first1=Paul Lee|title=Reading, Learning, Teach Ralph Ellison|date=2008|publisher=Peter Lang|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XQ2Giri4RegC&q=ralph+ellison+existential&pg=PA18|access-date=26 March 2015|isbn=978-1-4331-0090-1}}</ref><ref name=ellisongenius>{{cite book|last1=Jackson|first1=Lawrence Patrick|title=Ralph Ellison: Emergence of Genius|date=2007|publisher=University of Georgia Press|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NCEV37_oA2AC&q=ralph+ellison+existential&pg=PA339|access-date=26 March 2015|isbn=978-0-8203-2993-2}}</ref> and ] composed literature or poetry that contained, to varying degrees, elements of existential or proto-existential thought. The philosophy's influence even reached pulp literature shortly after the turn of the 20th century, as seen in the existential disparity witnessed in Man's lack of control of his fate in the works of ].<ref>{{cite news|url=http://www.horrorreview.com/essay/eglovecraft12008.html |title=Zarathustra . . . Cthulhu . Meursault: Existential Futility in H.P. Lovecraft's 'The Call of Cthulhu' |access-date=2015-02-17 |work=The Horror Review |first=Michael |last=Gurnow |date=2008-10-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141006180224/http://www.horrorreview.com/essay/eglovecraft12008.html |archive-date=October 6, 2014 }}</ref> | |||
==== Theatre ==== | ==== Theatre ==== | ||
Sartre wrote '']'' in 1944, an existentialist ] originally published in French as ''Huis Clos'' (meaning '']'' or "behind closed doors"), which is the source of the popular quote, "Hell is other people." (In French, "L'enfer, c'est les autres"). The play begins with a Valet leading a man into a room that the audience soon realizes is in hell. Eventually he is joined by two women. After their entry, the Valet leaves and the door is shut and locked. All three expect to be tortured, but no torturer arrives. Instead, they realize they are there to torture each other, which they do effectively by probing each other's sins, desires, and unpleasant memories. | |||
Existentialist themes are displayed in the ], notably in ]'s '']'', in which two men divert themselves while they wait expectantly for someone (or something) named Godot who never arrives. They claim Godot is an acquaintance, but in fact, hardly know him, admitting they would not recognize him if they saw him. Samuel Beckett, once asked who or what Godot is, replied, "If I knew, I would have said so in the play." To occupy themselves, the men eat, sleep, talk, argue, sing, play games, ], swap hats, and contemplate ]—anything "to hold the terrible silence at bay".<ref>''The Times'', 31 December 1964. Quoted in Knowlson, J., ''Damned to Fame: The Life of Samuel Beckett'' (London: Bloomsbury, 1996), p. 57</ref> The play "exploits several archetypal forms and situations, all of which lend themselves to both comedy and ]."<ref>Cronin, A., ''Samuel Beckett The Last Modernist'' (London: Flamingo, 1997), p. 391</ref> The play also illustrates an attitude toward human experience on earth: the poignancy, oppression, camaraderie, hope, corruption, and bewilderment of human experience that can be reconciled only in the mind and art of the absurdist. The play examines questions such as death, the ] and the place of God in human existence. | |||
] wrote '']'' in ], an existentialist ] originally published in French as ''Huis Clos'' (meaning '']'' or "behind closed doors") which is the source of the popular quote, "Hell is other people." (In French, "l'enfer, c'est les autres"). The play begins with a Valet leading a man into a room that the audience soon realizes is in hell. Eventually he is joined by two women. After their entry, the Valet leaves and the door is shut and locked. All three expect to be tortured, but no torturer arrives. Instead, they realize they are there to torture each other, which they do effectively, by probing each other's sins, desires, and unpleasant memories. | |||
]'s '']'' is an ] ] first staged at the ] in 1966.<ref name="Chrono">{{cite web | author= Michael H. Hutchins | title=A Tom Stoppard Bibliography: Chronology | work=The Stephen Sondheim Reference Guide | url=http://www.sondheimguide.com/Stoppard/chronology.html | date=14 August 2006 | access-date=2008-06-23}}</ref> The play expands upon the exploits of two minor characters from ] '']''. Comparisons have also been drawn to ]'s '']'', for the presence of two central characters who appear almost as two halves of a single character. Many plot features are similar as well: the characters pass time by playing ], impersonating other characters, and interrupting each other or remaining silent for long periods of time. The two characters are portrayed as two clowns or fools in a world beyond their understanding. They stumble through philosophical arguments while not realizing the implications, and muse on the irrationality and randomness of the world. | |||
Existentialist themes are displayed in the ], notably in ]'s '']'', in which two men divert themselves while they wait expectantly for someone (or something) named Godot who never arrives. They claim Godot to be an acquaintance but in fact hardly know him, admitting they would not recognize him if they saw him. Samuel Beckett, once asked who or what Godot is, replied, "If I knew, I would have said so in the play." To occupy themselves they eat, sleep, talk, argue, sing, play games, ], swap hats, and contemplate ]—anything "to hold the terrible silence at bay".<ref>''The Times'', 31 December 1964. Quoted in Knowlson, J., ''Damned to Fame: The Life of Samuel Beckett'' (London: Bloomsbury, 1996), p 57</ref> The play "exploits several archetypal forms and situations, all of which lend themselves to both comedy and ]."<ref>Cronin, A., ''Samuel Beckett The Last Modernist'' (London: Flamingo, 1997), p 391</ref> The play also illustrates an attitude toward man's experience on earth: the poignancy, oppression, camaraderie, hope, corruption, and bewilderment of human experience that can only be reconciled in mind and art of the absurdist. The play examines questions such as death, the ] and the place of God in human existence. | |||
]'s '']'' also presents arguments founded on existentialist ideas.<ref>{{cite news |last=Wren|first=Celia |date= 12 December 2007 |title= From Forum, an Earnest and Painstaking 'Antigone' |url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/12/11/AR2007121102254.html |newspaper=Washington Post |access-date=2008-04-07}}</ref> It is a tragedy inspired by Greek mythology and the play of the same name (''Antigone'', by Sophocles) from the fifth century BC. In English, it is often distinguished from its antecedent by being pronounced in its original French form, approximately "Ante-GŌN." The play was first performed in Paris on 6 February 1944, during the Nazi occupation of France. Produced under Nazi censorship, the play is purposefully ambiguous with regards to the rejection of authority (represented by Antigone) and the acceptance of it (represented by Creon). The parallels to the French Resistance and the Nazi occupation have been drawn. Antigone rejects life as desperately meaningless but without affirmatively choosing a noble death. The crux of the play is the lengthy dialogue concerning the nature of power, fate, and choice, during which Antigone says that she is, "... disgusted with ...promise of a humdrum happiness." She states that she would rather die than live a mediocre existence. | |||
]'s '']'' is an ] ] first staged at the ] in 1966.<ref name="Chrono">{{cite web | author= Michael H. Hutchins | title=A Tom Stoppard Bibliography: Chronology | work=The Stephen Sondheim Reference Guide | url=http://www.sondheimguide.com/Stoppard/chronology.html | date=14 August 2006 | accessdate=2008-06-23}}</ref> The play expands upon the exploits of two minor characters from ] '']''. Comparisons have also been drawn to ]'s '']'', for the presence of two central characters who almost appear to be two halves of a single character. Many plot features are similar as well: the characters pass time by playing ], impersonating other characters, and interrupting each other or remaining silent for long periods of time. The two characters are portrayed as two clowns or fools in a world that is beyond their understanding. They stumble through philosophical arguments while not realizing the implications, and muse on the irrationality and randomness of the world. | |||
Critic ] in his book ''Theatre of the Absurd'' pointed out how many contemporary playwrights such as ], ], ], and ] wove into their plays the existentialist belief that we are absurd beings loose in a universe empty of real meaning. Esslin noted that many of these playwrights demonstrated the philosophy better than did the plays by Sartre and Camus. Though most of such playwrights, subsequently labeled "Absurdist" (based on Esslin's book), denied affiliations with existentialism and were often staunchly anti-philosophical (for example Ionesco often claimed he identified more with ] or with ] than with existentialism), the playwrights are often linked to existentialism based on Esslin's observation.<ref>Kernan, Alvin B. ''The Modern American Theater: A Collection of Critical Essays''. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: ], 1967.</ref> | |||
]'s '']'' also presents arguments founded on existentialist ideas.<ref>{{cite web |last=Wren|first=Celia |date= 12 December 2007 |title= From Forum, an Earnest and Painstaking 'Antigone' |url=http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/12/11/AR2007121102254.html |publisher=] |accessdate=2008-04-07}}</ref> It is a tragedy inspired by Greek mythology and the play of the same name (Antigone, by Sophocles) from the 5th century B.C. In English, it is often distinguished from its antecedent by being pronounced in its original French form, approximately "Ante-GŌN." The play was first performed in Paris on 6 February 1944, during the Nazi occupation of France. Produced under Nazi censorship, the play is purposefully ambiguous with regards to the rejection of authority (represented by Antigone) and the acceptance of it (represented by Creon). The parallels to the French Resistance and the Nazi occupation have been drawn. Antigone rejects life as desperately meaningless but without affirmatively choosing a noble death. The crux of the play is the lengthy dialogue concerning the nature of power, fate, and choice, during which Antigone says that she is "... disgusted with ...promise of a humdrum happiness"; she states that she would rather die than live a mediocre existence. | |||
=== Activism === | |||
] explores the existence and experiences of Black people in the world.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bassey |first=Magnus O. |date=2007 |title=What is Africana Critical Theory or Black Existential Philosophy? |journal=Journal of Black Studies |volume=37 |issue=6 |pages=914–935 |doi=10.1177/0021934705285563 |jstor=40034961 |s2cid=145250815 |issn=0021-9347}}</ref> Classical and contemporary thinkers include ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Gordon |first=Lewis R. |url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/mono/10.4324/9780203900758/existentia-africana-lewis-gordon |title=Existentia Africana: Understanding Africana Existential Thought |date=2000-04-11 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-203-90075-8 |location=New York |doi=10.4324/9780203900758}}</ref> | |||
Critic ] in his book ''Theatre of the Absurd'' pointed out how many contemporary playwrights such as ], ], ], and ] wove into their plays the existential belief that we are absurd beings loose in a universe empty of real meaning. Esslin noted that many of these playwrights demonstrated the philosophy better than did the plays by Sartre and Camus. Though most of such playwrights, subsequently labeled "Absurdist" (based on Esslin's book), denied affiliations with existentialism and were often staunchly anti-philosophical (for example Ionesco often claimed he identified more with ] or with ] than with existentialism), the playwrights are often linked to existentialism based on Esslin's observation.<ref>Kernan, Alvin B. ''The Modern American Theater: A Collection of Critical Essays''. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: ], 1967.</ref> | |||
=== Psychoanalysis and psychotherapy === | |||
==== Music ==== | |||
{{Main|Existential therapy}} | |||
{{Expand-section|examples and additional citations|date=February 2009}} | |||
A major offshoot of existentialism as a philosophy is existentialist psychology and psychoanalysis, which first crystallized in the work of ], Freud's closest associate for 20 years. Without awareness of the writings of Rank, ] was influenced by ], ], ], and ]. A later figure was ], who briefly met ] as a young man.<ref>{{cite book |last=Frankl |first=Viktor |title=Recollections: An Autobiography |publisher=Perseus Publishing |location=Massachusetts |date=2000 |page=51}}</ref> His ] can be regarded as a form of existentialist therapy. The existentialists would also influence ], antipositivist micro-], ], and ], with the work of thinkers such as ]{{sfn|Šajda|2011|p=38}} and ]. Foucault was a great reader of Kierkegaard even though he almost never refers to this author, who nonetheless had for him an importance as secret as it was decisive.<ref>{{cite book |last=Flynn |first=Thomas R. |title=Sartre, Foucault, and Historical Reason |page=323}}</ref> | |||
Many solo artists and bands have released existentially themed works ranging from single songs to entire albums. Some of these artists have focused and built their entire careers exploring these themes. Notable examples include ] of ], ] of ], ] of ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://facweb.stvincent.edu/academics/religiousstu/writings/rodkey1.html|title=The Existential Notion that "God is Dead" in Industrial Music|accessdate=2009-02-02}}</ref> among others. | |||
An early contributor to existentialist psychology in the United States was ], who was strongly influenced by ] and ]. One of the most prolific writers on techniques and theory of existentialist psychology in the US is ]. Yalom states that | |||
=== Theology === | |||
{{blockquote|Aside from their reaction against Freud's mechanistic, deterministic model of the mind and their assumption of a phenomenological approach in therapy, the existentialist analysts have little in common and have never been regarded as a cohesive ideological school. These thinkers—who include Ludwig Binswanger, ], ], V. E. Gebsattel, Roland Kuhn, G. Caruso, F. T. Buytendijk, G. Bally, and Victor Frankl—were almost entirely unknown to the American psychotherapeutic community until Rollo May's highly influential 1958 book ''Existence''—and especially his introductory essay—introduced their work into this country.<ref name=Yalom1980>{{Cite book |first=Irvin D. |last=Yalom |author-link=Irvin D. Yalom |title=Existential Psychotherapy |url=https://archive.org/details/existentialpsych00yalo_638 |url-access=limited |location=New York |publisher=] (Subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. |year=1980 |page= |isbn=0-465-02147-6}} Note: The copyright year has not changed, but the book remains in print.</ref>}} | |||
{{main|Christian existentialism}} | |||
] teachings had an indirect style, in which his point is often left unsaid for the purpose of letting the single individual confront the truth on their own.<ref>Palmer, Donald D. ''Kierkegaard For Beginners''. 1996. Writers And Readers Limited. London, England. p.25</ref> This is evident in his ]s, which are a response to a question he is asked. After he tells the parable, he returns the question to the ]. | |||
An ] reading of the Bible demands that the reader recognize that he is an existing ] studying the words more as a recollection of possible events. This is in contrast to looking at a collection of "truths" which are outside and unrelated to the reader, but may develop your reality/God.<ref>Hong, Howard V. "Historical Introduction" to ''Fear and Trembling''. Princeton University Press. Princeton, New Jersey. 1983. p. x</ref> Such a reader is not obligated to follow the commandments as if an external agent is forcing them upon him, but as though they are inside him and guiding him from inside. This is the task Kierkegaard takes up when he asks: "Who has the more difficult task: the teacher who lectures on earnest things a meteor's distance from everyday life-or the learner who should put it to use?"<ref>Kierkegaard, Soren. ''Works of Love''. Harper & Row, Publishers. New York, N.Y. 1962. p. 62</ref> Existentially speaking, the Bible doesn't become an authority in a person's life until they authorize the Bible to be their personal authority. Existentialism has had a significant influence on theology, notably on ] and on theologians and religious thinkers such as ], ], ], ] and ]. | |||
A more recent contributor to the development of a European version of existentialist psychotherapy is the British-based ].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Kass |first1=Sarah A. |date=April 2014 |title=Don't Fall Into Those Stereotype Traps: Women and the Feminine in Existential Therapy |journal=Journal of Humanistic Psychology |publication-date=11 March 2013 |volume=54 |issue=2 |pages=131–157 |doi=10.1177/0022167813478836}}</ref>{{rp|pp=142–144}} | |||
===Existential psychoanalysis and psychotherapy=== | |||
{{main|Existential therapy}} | |||
One of the major offshoots of existentialism as a philosophy is existential psychology and psychoanalysis, which first crystallized in the work of ], a clinician who was influenced by both ], ], ] and ]. A later figure was ], who had studied with ] and ] as a young man{{Fact|date=March 2007}}. His ] can be regarded as a form of existential therapy. | |||
An early contributor to existential psychology in the United States was ], who was influenced by ]. One of the most prolific writers on techniques and theory of existential psychology in the USA is ]. The person who has contributed most to the development of a European version of existential psychotherapy is the British-based ]. | |||
Anxiety's importance in existentialism makes it a popular topic in ]. Therapists often offer existentialist ] as an explanation for anxiety. The assertion is that anxiety is manifested of an individual's complete freedom to decide, and complete responsibility for the outcome of such decisions. Psychotherapists using an existentialist approach believe that a patient can harness his anxiety and use it constructively. Instead of suppressing anxiety, patients are advised to use it as grounds for change. By embracing anxiety as inevitable, a person can use it to achieve his full potential in life. ] also had major impetus from existentialist psychology and shares many of the fundamental tenets. ], based on the writings of ] and ], is a developing area of study within the academic study of psychology. It looks at what researchers claim are implicit emotional reactions of people confronted with the knowledge that they will eventually die.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Terror Management Theory – Ernest Becker Foundation |url=https://ernestbecker.org/resources/terror-management-theory/ |access-date=2022-11-10 |website=ernestbecker.org |language=en-US}}</ref> | |||
Also, ] has refreshed the Socratic tradition with his own blend of ]; as did ] with his Chromatiques Center in Belgium.{{citation needed|date=October 2021}} | |||
==See also== | |||
<div style="-moz-column-count:2; column-count:2;"> | |||
== Criticisms == | |||
* ] | |||
*] | |||
=== General criticisms === | |||
* ] | |||
] criticized "the profoundly unsound methods and the dangerous contempt for reason that have been so prominent in existentialism."<ref>Kaufmann, Walter Arnold, From Shakespeare To Existentialism (Princeton University Press 1979), p. xvi.</ref> ] philosophers, such as ] and ], assert that existentialists are often confused about the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being".<ref name="Carnap, Rudolf 1932 pp. 219">Carnap, Rudolf, ''Uberwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache'' , Erkenntnis (1932), pp. 219–41. Carnap's critique of Heidegger's "What is Metaphysics." | |||
* ] | |||
</ref> Specifically, they argue that the verb "is" is transitive and pre-fixed to a ] (e.g., an apple ''is red'') (without a predicate, the word "is" is meaningless), and that existentialists frequently misuse the term in this manner. Wilson has stated in his book ''The Angry Years'' that existentialism has created many of its own difficulties: "We can see how this question of freedom of the will has been vitiated by post-romantic philosophy, with its inbuilt tendency to laziness and ], we can also see how it came about that existentialism found itself in a hole of its own digging, and how the philosophical developments since then have amounted to walking in circles round that hole."<ref>Colin, Wilson, ''The Angry Years'' (2007), p. 214</ref> | |||
* ] | |||
=== Sartre's philosophy === | |||
Many critics argue Sartre's philosophy is contradictory. Specifically, they argue that Sartre makes metaphysical arguments despite his claiming that his philosophical views ignore ]. ] criticized ''Being and Nothingness'' for projecting anxiety and meaninglessness onto the nature of existence itself: "Insofar as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it ] specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics. Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory."<ref name="Marcuse1972">Marcuse, Herbert. "Sartre's Existentialism". Printed in ''Studies in Critical Philosophy''. Translated by Joris De Bres. London: NLB, 1972. p. 161.</ref> | |||
In ''Letter on Humanism'', Heidegger criticized Sartre's existentialism: | |||
{{blockquote|Existentialism says existence precedes essence. In this statement he is taking ''existentia'' and ''essentia'' according to their metaphysical meaning, which, from Plato's time on, has said that ''essentia'' precedes ''existentia''. Sartre reverses this statement. But the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement. With it, he stays with metaphysics, in oblivion of the truth of Being.<ref>Martin Heidegger, "Letter on Humanism", in ''Basic Writings: Nine Key Essays, plus the Introduction to ''Being and Time'' '', trans. David Farrell Krell (London, Routledge; 1978), p. 208. .</ref>}} | |||
== See also == | |||
{{div col|colwidth=25em}} | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] |
* ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ]{{div col end}} | |||
* '']'' (film) | |||
</div> | |||
== |
== References == | ||
=== Citations === | |||
{{reflist}} | {{reflist}} | ||
=== Bibliography === | |||
==References== | |||
{{refbegin}} | |||
*{{Harvard reference|title=Suhrawardi and the School of Illumination|first=Mehdi Amin|last=Razavi|year=1997|publisher=]|isbn=0700704124}} | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Aho |first1=Kevin |editor-last1=Zalta |editor-first1=Edward N. |editor-last2=Nodelman |editor-first2=Uri |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |title=Existentialism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existentialism/ |access-date=2024-11-18 |date=6 January 2023 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, ], ]}} | |||
*Albert Camus Lyrical and Critical essays. Edited by Philip Thody (interviev with Jeanie Delpech, in Les Nouvelles litteraires, November 15, 1945). pg 345. | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Barrett |first1=William |year=1958 |title=Irrational Man: A Study in Existential Philosophy |title-link=Irrational Man |edition=1st |location=Garden City, NY |publisher=Doubleday Anchor Books |oclc=14597959 |ol=6247210M}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Camus |first1=Albert |editor-last1=Thody |editor-first1=Philip |editor-link1=Philip Thody |translator-last1=Kennedy |translator-first1=Ellen Conroy |year=1968 |chapter=No, I am not an existentialist . . . ] in '']'', 15 November 1945] |title=Lyrical and Critical Essays |location=New York |publisher=Vintage Books |pages=345–348 |oclc=160250}} | |||
==Further reading== | |||
*{{cite book| |
* {{cite book |last1=Cooper |first1=David E. |author-link1=David E. Cooper |year=1990 |title=Existentialism: A Reconstruction |edition=1st |location=Oxford, England & Cambridge, MA |publisher=Basil Blackwell |isbn=978-0-631-16191-2}} | ||
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Crowell |first1=Steven |editor-last1=Zalta |editor-first1=Edward N. |editor-last2=Nodelman |editor-first2=Uri |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |title=Existentialism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/existentialism/ |access-date=2024-11-18 |edition=Winter 2022 |date=9 June 2020 |orig-date=first published 23 August 2004 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University}} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Cooper|first=David E.|title=Existentialism: A Reconstruction|year=1999|edition=2nd ed.|publisher=Blackwell|location=Oxford, UK|isbn=0-631-21322-8}} | |||
*{{cite book| |
* {{cite book |last1=Flynn |first1=Thomas R. |author-link1=Thomas R. Flynn |year=2006 |title=Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction |location=Oxford, England & New York, NY |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-280428-0}} | ||
* {{cite book |last1=Luper |first1=Steven |editor-last1=Luper |editor-first1=Steven |year=2000 |title=Existing: An Introduction to Existential Thought |location=Mountain View, CA |publisher=Mayfield Publishing Company |isbn=978-0-7674-0587-4}} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Marino|first=Gordon (ed.)|title=Basic Writings of Existentialism|year=2004|publisher=Modern Library|location=New York|isbn=0-375-75989-1}} | |||
*{{cite book| |
* {{cite book |last1=Marino |first1=Gordon |editor-last1=Marino |editor-first1=Gordon |year=2004 |chapter=Introduction |title=Basic Writings of Existentialism |location=New York |publisher=Modern Library |pages=ix–xvi |isbn=978-0-375-75989-5}} | ||
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=McDonald |first1=William |last2=Lippitt |first2=John |last3=Evans |first3=C. Stephen |editor-last1=Zalta |editor-first1=Edward N. |editor-last2=Nodelman |editor-first2=Uri |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |title=Søren Kierkegaard |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/kierkegaard/ |access-date=2024-11-18 |edition=Spring 2023 |date=10 November 2017 |orig-date=first published 3 December 1996 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University}} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Solomon|first=Robert C. (ed.)|authorlink=Robert C. Solomon|title=Existentialism|year=2005|edition=2nd ed.|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York|isbn=0-19-517463-1}} | |||
* {{cite book |last1=Šajda |first1=Peter |editor-last1=Stewart |editor-first1=Jon |editor-link1=Jon Stewart (philosopher) |year=2011 |chapter=Martin Buber: "No-One Can so Refute Kierkegaard as Kierkegaard Himself" |title=Kierkegaard and Existentialism |series=Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources |volume=9 |location=Farnham, England & Burlington, VT |publisher=Ashgate |pages=33–62 |isbn=978-1-4094-2641-7}} | |||
*{{cite book|last=Appignanesi|first=Richard|title=Introducing Existentialism|year=2006|edition=3nd ed.|publisher=Icon Books (UK), Totem Books (USA)|location=Thriplow, Cambridge|isbn=1-84046-717-7}} | |||
* {{cite book |editor-last1=Solomon |editor-first1=Robert C. |editor-link1=Robert C. Solomon |year=1974 |title=Existentialism |edition=1st |location=New York |publisher=Modern Library |isbn=978-0-394-31704-5}} | |||
*{{cite book|title=Being and Nothingness |first=Jean-Paul |last=Sartre }} | |||
*{{cite book|title=Existentialism |
* {{cite book |last1=Wartenberg |first1=Thomas E. |year=2008 |title=Existentialism: A Beginner's Guide |edition=ebook |location=Oxford, England |publisher=Oneworld |publication-date=2011 |isbn=978-1-78074-020-1}} | ||
{{refend}} | |||
*{{cite book|title= |last=Rose |first=Eugene (Fr. Seraphim) |authorlink=Seraphim Rose|publisher= Saint Herman Press (1 September 1994) |isbn=0-938635-15-8}} | |||
==External links== | ==External links== | ||
{{sister project links|d=Q38066|n=no|mw=no|m=no|species=no|c=Category:Existentialism|b=Introduction to Philosophy/Existentialism|s=no|v=no|voy=no}} | |||
;Introductions | |||
* {{cite IEP |url-id=existent}} | |||
* | |||
* {{In Our Time|Existentialism|p00547h8|Existentialism}} | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* {{Internet Archive|id=introducingexist0000appi|name=''Introducing Existentialism''|url-access=registration|at=no}} by ] & ] (Icon Books, 2001) | |||
* | |||
* | |||
;Journals and articles | |||
*: The International Journal of Existential Literature | |||
* Existential Analysis published by The Society for Existential Analysis | |||
;Existential psychotherapy | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* History of existentially-humanistic psychology's development in formerly Soviet nations | |||
{{Existentialism}} | |||
{{Navboxes | |||
|list= | |||
{{Philosophy topics}} | {{Philosophy topics}} | ||
{{continental philosophy}} | |||
{{metaphysics}} | |||
{{philosophy of religion}} | |||
{{Ethics}} | |||
{{Western culture}} | |||
}} | |||
{{Authority control}} | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Existentialism}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 05:37, 30 December 2024
Philosophical form of enquiry into subjective existence "Existential" redirects here. For the logical sense of the term, see Existential quantification. For other uses, see Existence (disambiguation). For the philosophical position commonly seen as the antonym of existentialism, see Essentialism. Clockwise from top left: Søren Kierkegaard, Simone de Beauvoir, Jean-Paul Sartre, Friedrich NietzscheExistentialism is a family of philosophical views and inquiry that prioritize the existence of the human individual, study existence from the individual's perspective, and conclude that, despite the absurdity or incomprehensibility of the universe, individuals must still embrace responsibility for their actions and strive to lead authentic lives. In examining meaning, purpose, and value, existentialist thought often includes concepts such as existential crises, angst, courage, and freedom.
Existentialism is associated with several 19th- and 20th-century European philosophers who shared an emphasis on the human subject, despite often profound differences in thought. Among the 19th-century figures now associated with existentialism are philosophers Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche, as well as novelist Fyodor Dostoevsky, all of whom critiqued rationalism and concerned themselves with the problem of meaning. The word existentialism, however, was not coined until the mid-20th century, during which it became most associated with contemporaneous philosophers Jean-Paul Sartre, Martin Heidegger, Simone de Beauvoir, Karl Jaspers, Gabriel Marcel, Paul Tillich, and more controversially Albert Camus.
Many existentialists considered traditional systematic or academic philosophies, in style and content, to be too abstract and removed from concrete human experience. A primary virtue in existentialist thought is authenticity. Existentialism would influence many disciplines outside of philosophy, including theology, drama, art, literature, and psychology.
Existentialist philosophy encompasses a range of perspectives, but it shares certain underlying concepts. Among these, a central tenet of existentialism is that personal freedom, individual responsibility, and deliberate choice are essential to the pursuit of self-discovery and the determination of life's meaning.
Etymology
The term existentialism (French: L'existentialisme) was coined by the French Catholic philosopher Gabriel Marcel in the mid-1940s. When Marcel first applied the term to Jean-Paul Sartre, at a colloquium in 1945, Sartre rejected it. Sartre subsequently changed his mind and, on October 29, 1945, publicly adopted the existentialist label in a lecture to the Club Maintenant in Paris, published as L'existentialisme est un humanisme (Existentialism Is a Humanism), a short book that helped popularize existentialist thought. Marcel later came to reject the label himself in favour of Neo-Socratic, in honor of Kierkegaard's essay "On the Concept of Irony".
Some scholars argue that the term should be used to refer only to the cultural movement in Europe in the 1940s and 1950s associated with the works of the philosophers Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Albert Camus. Others extend the term to Kierkegaard, and yet others extend it as far back as Socrates. However, it is often identified with the philosophical views of Sartre.
Definitional issues and background
The labels existentialism and existentialist are often seen as historical conveniences in as much as they were first applied to many philosophers long after they had died. While existentialism is generally considered to have originated with Kierkegaard, the first prominent existentialist philosopher to adopt the term as a self-description was Sartre. Sartre posits the idea that "what all existentialists have in common is the fundamental doctrine that existence precedes essence", as the philosopher Frederick Copleston explains. According to philosopher Steven Crowell, defining existentialism has been relatively difficult, and he argues that it is better understood as a general approach used to reject certain systematic philosophies rather than as a systematic philosophy itself. In a lecture delivered in 1945, Sartre described existentialism as "the attempt to draw all the consequences from a position of consistent atheism". For others, existentialism need not involve the rejection of God, but rather "examines mortal man's search for meaning in a meaningless universe", considering less "What is the good life?" (to feel, be, or do, good), instead asking "What is life good for?".
Although many outside Scandinavia consider the term existentialism to have originated from Kierkegaard, it is more likely that Kierkegaard adopted this term (or at least the term "existential" as a description of his philosophy) from the Norwegian poet and literary critic Johan Sebastian Cammermeyer Welhaven. This assertion comes from two sources:
- The Norwegian philosopher Erik Lundestad refers to the Danish philosopher Fredrik Christian Sibbern. Sibbern is supposed to have had two conversations in 1841, the first with Welhaven and the second with Kierkegaard. It is in the first conversation that it is believed that Welhaven came up with "a word that he said covered a certain thinking, which had a close and positive attitude to life, a relationship he described as existential". This was then brought to Kierkegaard by Sibbern.
- The second claim comes from the Norwegian historian Rune Slagstad, who claimed to prove that Kierkegaard himself said the term existential was borrowed from the poet. He strongly believes that it was Kierkegaard himself who said that "Hegelians do not study philosophy 'existentially;' to use a phrase by Welhaven from one time when I spoke with him about philosophy."
Concepts
Existence precedes essence
Main article: Existence precedes essenceSartre argued that a central proposition of existentialism is that existence precedes essence, which is to say that individuals shape themselves by existing and cannot be perceived through preconceived and a priori categories, an "essence". The actual life of the individual is what constitutes what could be called their "true essence" instead of an arbitrarily attributed essence others use to define them. Human beings, through their own consciousness, create their own values and determine a meaning to their life. This view is in contradiction to Aristotle and Aquinas, who taught that essence precedes individual existence. Although it was Sartre who explicitly coined the phrase, similar notions can be found in the thought of existentialist philosophers such as Heidegger, and Kierkegaard:
The subjective thinker's form, the form of his communication, is his style. His form must be just as manifold as are the opposites that he holds together. The systematic eins, zwei, drei is an abstract form that also must inevitably run into trouble whenever it is to be applied to the concrete. To the same degree as the subjective thinker is concrete, to that same degree his form must also be concretely dialectical. But just as he himself is not a poet, not an ethicist, not a dialectician, so also his form is none of these directly. His form must first and last be related to existence, and in this regard he must have at his disposal the poetic, the ethical, the dialectical, the religious. Subordinate character, setting, etc., which belong to the well-balanced character of the esthetic production, are in themselves breadth; the subjective thinker has only one setting—existence—and has nothing to do with localities and such things. The setting is not the fairyland of the imagination, where poetry produces consummation, nor is the setting laid in England, and historical accuracy is not a concern. The setting is inwardness in existing as a human being; the concretion is the relation of the existence-categories to one another. Historical accuracy and historical actuality are breadth.
— Søren Kierkegaard (Concluding Postscript, Hong pp. 357–358.)
Some interpret the imperative to define oneself as meaning that anyone can wish to be anything. However, an existentialist philosopher would say such a wish constitutes an inauthentic existence – what Sartre would call "bad faith". Instead, the phrase should be taken to say that people are defined only insofar as they act and that they are responsible for their actions. Someone who acts cruelly towards other people is, by that act, defined as a cruel person. Such persons are themselves responsible for their new identity (cruel persons). This is opposed to their genes, or human nature, bearing the blame.
As Sartre said in his lecture Existentialism is a Humanism: "Man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world—and defines himself afterwards." The more positive, therapeutic aspect of this is also implied: a person can choose to act in a different way, and to be a good person instead of a cruel person.
Jonathan Webber interprets Sartre's usage of the term essence not in a modal fashion, i.e. as necessary features, but in a teleological fashion: "an essence is the relational property of having a set of parts ordered in such a way as to collectively perform some activity". For example, it belongs to the essence of a house to keep the bad weather out, which is why it has walls and a roof. Humans are different from houses because—unlike houses—they do not have an inbuilt purpose: they are free to choose their own purpose and thereby shape their essence; thus, their existence precedes their essence.
Sartre is committed to a radical conception of freedom: nothing fixes our purpose but we ourselves, our projects have no weight or inertia except for our endorsement of them. Simone de Beauvoir, on the other hand, holds that there are various factors, grouped together under the term sedimentation, that offer resistance to attempts to change our direction in life. Sedimentations are themselves products of past choices and can be changed by choosing differently in the present, but such changes happen slowly. They are a force of inertia that shapes the agent's evaluative outlook on the world until the transition is complete.
Sartre's definition of existentialism was based on Heidegger's magnum opus Being and Time (1927). In the correspondence with Jean Beaufret later published as the Letter on Humanism, Heidegger implied that Sartre misunderstood him for his own purposes of subjectivism, and that he did not mean that actions take precedence over being so long as those actions were not reflected upon. Heidegger commented that "the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement", meaning that he thought Sartre had simply switched the roles traditionally attributed to essence and existence without interrogating these concepts and their history.
The absurd
Main article: AbsurdismThe notion of the absurd contains the idea that there is no meaning in the world beyond what meaning we give it. This meaninglessness also encompasses the amorality or "unfairness" of the world. This can be highlighted in the way it opposes the traditional Abrahamic religious perspective, which establishes that life's purpose is the fulfillment of God's commandments. This is what gives meaning to people's lives. To live the life of the absurd means rejecting a life that finds or pursues specific meaning for man's existence since there is nothing to be discovered. According to Albert Camus, the world or the human being is not in itself absurd. The concept only emerges through the juxtaposition of the two; life becomes absurd due to the incompatibility between human beings and the world they inhabit. This view constitutes one of the two interpretations of the absurd in existentialist literature. The second view, first elaborated by Søren Kierkegaard, holds that absurdity is limited to actions and choices of human beings. These are considered absurd since they issue from human freedom, undermining their foundation outside of themselves.
The absurd contrasts with the claim that "bad things don't happen to good people"; to the world, metaphorically speaking, there is no such thing as a good person or a bad person; what happens happens, and it may just as well happen to a "good" person as to a "bad" person. Because of the world's absurdity, anything can happen to anyone at any time and a tragic event could plummet someone into direct confrontation with the absurd. Many of the literary works of Kierkegaard, Beckett, Kafka, Dostoevsky, Ionesco, Miguel de Unamuno, Luigi Pirandello, Sartre, Joseph Heller, and Camus contain descriptions of people who encounter the absurdity of the world.
It is because of the devastating awareness of meaninglessness that Camus claimed in The Myth of Sisyphus that "There is only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide." Although "prescriptions" against the possible deleterious consequences of these kinds of encounters vary, from Kierkegaard's religious "stage" to Camus' insistence on persevering in spite of absurdity, the concern with helping people avoid living their lives in ways that put them in the perpetual danger of having everything meaningful break down is common to most existentialist philosophers. The possibility of having everything meaningful break down poses a threat of quietism, which is inherently against the existentialist philosophy. It has been said that the possibility of suicide makes all humans existentialists. The ultimate hero of absurdism lives without meaning and faces suicide without succumbing to it.
Facticity
Main article: FacticityThis section may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (November 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
Facticity is defined by Sartre in Being and Nothingness (1943) as the in-itself, which for humans takes the form of being and not being. It is the facts of one's personal life and as per Heidegger, it is "the way in which we are thrown into the world." This can be more easily understood when considering facticity in relation to the temporal dimension of our past: one's past is what one is, meaning that it is what has formed the person who exists in the present. However, to say that one is only one's past would ignore the change a person undergoes in the present and future, while saying that one's past is only what one was, would entirely detach it from the present self. A denial of one's concrete past constitutes an inauthentic lifestyle, and also applies to other kinds of facticity (having a human body—e.g., one that does not allow a person to run faster than the speed of sound—identity, values, etc.).
Facticity is a limitation and a condition of freedom. It is a limitation in that a large part of one's facticity consists of things one did not choose (birthplace, etc.), but a condition of freedom in the sense that one's values most likely depend on it. However, even though one's facticity is "set in stone" (as being past, for instance), it cannot determine a person: the value ascribed to one's facticity is still ascribed to it freely by that person. As an example, consider two men, one of whom has no memory of his past and the other who remembers everything. Both have committed many crimes, but the first man, remembering nothing, leads a rather normal life while the second man, feeling trapped by his own past, continues a life of crime, blaming his own past for "trapping" him in this life. There is nothing essential about his committing crimes, but he ascribes this meaning to his past.
However, to disregard one's facticity during the continual process of self-making, projecting oneself into the future, would be to put oneself in denial of the conditions shaping the present self and would be inauthentic. The origin of one's projection must still be one's facticity, though in the mode of not being it (essentially). An example of one focusing solely on possible projects without reflecting on one's current facticity: would be someone who continually thinks about future possibilities related to being rich (e.g. a better car, bigger house, better quality of life, etc.) without acknowledging the facticity of not currently having the financial means to do so. In this example, considering both facticity and transcendence, an authentic mode of being would be considering future projects that might improve one's current finances (e.g. putting in extra hours, or investing savings) in order to arrive at a future-facticity of a modest pay rise, further leading to purchase of an affordable car.
Another aspect of facticity is that it entails angst. Freedom "produces" angst when limited by facticity and the lack of the possibility of having facticity to "step in" and take responsibility for something one has done also produces angst.
Another aspect of existential freedom is that one can change one's values. One is responsible for one's values, regardless of society's values. The focus on freedom in existentialism is related to the limits of responsibility one bears, as a result of one's freedom. The relationship between freedom and responsibility is one of interdependency and a clarification of freedom also clarifies that for which one is responsible.
Authenticity
Main article: AuthenticityMany noted existentialists consider the theme of authentic existence important. Authenticity involves the idea that one has to "create oneself" and live in accordance with this self. For an authentic existence, one should act as oneself, not as "one's acts" or as "one's genes" or as any other essence requires. The authentic act is one in accordance with one's freedom. A component of freedom is facticity, but not to the degree that this facticity determines one's transcendent choices (one could then blame one's background for making the choice one made ). Facticity, in relation to authenticity, involves acting on one's actual values when making a choice (instead of, like Kierkegaard's Aesthete, "choosing" randomly), so that one takes responsibility for the act instead of choosing either-or without allowing the options to have different values.
In contrast, the inauthentic is the denial to live in accordance with one's freedom. This can take many forms, from pretending choices are meaningless or random, convincing oneself that some form of determinism is true, or "mimicry" where one acts as "one should".
How one "should" act is often determined by an image one has, of how one in such a role (bank manager, lion tamer, sex worker, etc.) acts. In Being and Nothingness, Sartre uses the example of a waiter in "bad faith". He merely takes part in the "act" of being a typical waiter, albeit very convincingly. This image usually corresponds to a social norm, but this does not mean that all acting in accordance with social norms is inauthentic. The main point is the attitude one takes to one's own freedom and responsibility and the extent to which one acts in accordance with this freedom.
The Other and the Look
Main article: Other (philosophy)The Other (written with a capital "O") is a concept more properly belonging to phenomenology and its account of intersubjectivity. However, it has seen widespread use in existentialist writings, and the conclusions drawn differ slightly from the phenomenological accounts. The Other is the experience of another free subject who inhabits the same world as a person does. In its most basic form, it is this experience of the Other that constitutes intersubjectivity and objectivity. To clarify, when one experiences someone else, and this Other person experiences the world (the same world that a person experiences)—only from "over there"—the world is constituted as objective in that it is something that is "there" as identical for both of the subjects; a person experiences the other person as experiencing the same things. This experience of the Other's look is what is termed the Look (sometimes the Gaze).
While this experience, in its basic phenomenological sense, constitutes the world as objective and oneself as objectively existing subjectivity (one experiences oneself as seen in the Other's Look in precisely the same way that one experiences the Other as seen by him, as subjectivity), in existentialism, it also acts as a kind of limitation of freedom. This is because the Look tends to objectify what it sees. When one experiences oneself in the Look, one does not experience oneself as nothing (no thing), but as something (some thing). In Sartre's example of a man peeping at someone through a keyhole, the man is entirely caught up in the situation he is in. He is in a pre-reflexive state where his entire consciousness is directed at what goes on in the room. Suddenly, he hears a creaking floorboard behind him and he becomes aware of himself as seen by the Other. He is then filled with shame for he perceives himself as he would perceive someone else doing what he was doing—as a Peeping Tom. For Sartre, this phenomenological experience of shame establishes proof for the existence of other minds and defeats the problem of solipsism. For the conscious state of shame to be experienced, one has to become aware of oneself as an object of another look, proving a priori, that other minds exist. The Look is then co-constitutive of one's facticity.
Another characteristic feature of the Look is that no Other really needs to have been there: It is possible that the creaking floorboard was simply the movement of an old house; the Look is not some kind of mystical telepathic experience of the actual way the Other sees one (there may have been someone there, but he could have not noticed that person). It is only one's perception of the way another might perceive him.
Angst and dread
Main article: Angst"Existential angst", sometimes called existential dread, anxiety, or anguish, is a term common to many existentialist thinkers. It is generally held to be a negative feeling arising from the experience of human freedom and responsibility. The archetypal example is the experience one has when standing on a cliff where one not only fears falling off it, but also dreads the possibility of throwing oneself off. In this experience that "nothing is holding me back", one senses the lack of anything that predetermines one to either throw oneself off or to stand still, and one experiences one's own freedom.
It can also be seen in relation to the previous point how angst is before nothing, and this is what sets it apart from fear that has an object. While one can take measures to remove an object of fear, for angst no such "constructive" measures are possible. The use of the word "nothing" in this context relates to the inherent insecurity about the consequences of one's actions and to the fact that, in experiencing freedom as angst, one also realizes that one is fully responsible for these consequences. There is nothing in people (genetically, for instance) that acts in their stead—that they can blame if something goes wrong. Therefore, not every choice is perceived as having dreadful possible consequences (and, it can be claimed, human lives would be unbearable if every choice facilitated dread). However, this does not change the fact that freedom remains a condition of every action.
Despair
Main article: Despair See also: Existential crisisDespair is generally defined as a loss of hope. In existentialism, it is more specifically a loss of hope in reaction to a breakdown in one or more of the defining qualities of one's self or identity. If a person is invested in being a particular thing, such as a bus driver or an upstanding citizen, and then finds their being-thing compromised, they would normally be found in a state of despair—a hopeless state. For example, a singer who loses the ability to sing may despair if they have nothing else to fall back on—nothing to rely on for their identity. They find themselves unable to be what defined their being.
What sets the existentialist notion of despair apart from the conventional definition is that existentialist despair is a state one is in even when they are not overtly in despair. So long as a person's identity depends on qualities that can crumble, they are in perpetual despair—and as there is, in Sartrean terms, no human essence found in conventional reality on which to constitute the individual's sense of identity, despair is a universal human condition. As Kierkegaard defines it in Either/Or: "Let each one learn what he can; both of us can learn that a person's unhappiness never lies in his lack of control over external conditions, since this would only make him completely unhappy." In Works of Love, he says:
When the God-forsaken worldliness of earthly life shuts itself in complacency, the confined air develops poison, the moment gets stuck and stands still, the prospect is lost, a need is felt for a refreshing, enlivening breeze to cleanse the air and dispel the poisonous vapors lest we suffocate in worldliness. ... Lovingly to hope all things is the opposite of despairingly to hope nothing at all. Love hopes all things—yet is never put to shame. To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of the good is to hope. To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of evil is to fear. By the decision to choose hope one decides infinitely more than it seems, because it is an eternal decision.
— Søren Kierkegaard, Works of Love
Opposition to positivism and rationalism
See also: Positivism and RationalismExistentialists oppose defining human beings as primarily rational, and, therefore, oppose both positivism and rationalism. Existentialism asserts that people make decisions based on subjective meaning rather than pure rationality. The rejection of reason as the source of meaning is a common theme of existentialist thought, as is the focus on the anxiety and dread that we feel in the face of our own radical free will and our awareness of death. Kierkegaard advocated rationality as a means to interact with the objective world (e.g., in the natural sciences), but when it comes to existential problems, reason is insufficient: "Human reason has boundaries".
Like Kierkegaard, Sartre saw problems with rationality, calling it a form of "bad faith", an attempt by the self to impose structure on a world of phenomena—"the Other"—that is fundamentally irrational and random. According to Sartre, rationality and other forms of bad faith hinder people from finding meaning in freedom. To try to suppress feelings of anxiety and dread, people confine themselves within everyday experience, Sartre asserted, thereby relinquishing their freedom and acquiescing to being possessed in one form or another by "the Look" of "the Other" (i.e., possessed by another person—or at least one's idea of that other person).
Religion
See also: Atheistic existentialism, Christian existentialism, and Jewish existentialismAn existentialist reading of the Bible would demand that the reader recognize that they are an existing subject studying the words more as a recollection of events. This is in contrast to looking at a collection of "truths" that are outside and unrelated to the reader, but may develop a sense of reality/God. Such a reader is not obligated to follow the commandments as if an external agent is forcing these commandments upon them, but as though they are inside them and guiding them from inside. This is the task Kierkegaard takes up when he asks: "Who has the more difficult task: the teacher who lectures on earnest things a meteor's distance from everyday life—or the learner who should put it to use?" Philosophers such as Hans Jonas and Rudolph Bultmann introduced the concept of existentialist demythologization into the field of Early Christianity and Christian Theology, respectively.
Confusion with nihilism
See also: Existential nihilismAlthough nihilism and existentialism are distinct philosophies, they are often confused with one another since both are rooted in the human experience of anguish and confusion that stems from the apparent meaninglessness of a world in which humans are compelled to find or create meaning. A primary cause of confusion is that Friedrich Nietzsche was an important philosopher in both fields.
Existentialist philosophers often stress the importance of angst as signifying the absolute lack of any objective ground for action, a move that is often reduced to moral or existential nihilism. A pervasive theme in existentialist philosophy, however, is to persist through encounters with the absurd, as seen in Albert Camus's philosophical essay The Myth of Sisyphus (1942): "One must imagine Sisyphus happy". and it is only very rarely that existentialist philosophers dismiss morality or one's self-created meaning: Søren Kierkegaard regained a sort of morality in the religious (although he would not agree that it was ethical; the religious suspends the ethical), and Jean-Paul Sartre's final words in Being and Nothingness (1943): "All these questions, which refer us to a pure and not an accessory (or impure) reflection, can find their reply only on the ethical plane. We shall devote to them a future work."
History
Precursors
Some have argued that existentialism has long been an element of European religious thought, even before the term came into use. William Barrett identified Blaise Pascal and Søren Kierkegaard as two specific examples. Jean Wahl also identified William Shakespeare's Prince Hamlet ("To be, or not to be"), Jules Lequier, Thomas Carlyle, and William James as existentialists. According to Wahl, "the origins of most great philosophies, like those of Plato, Descartes, and Kant, are to be found in existential reflections." Precursors to existentialism can also be identified in the works of Iranian Muslim philosopher Mulla Sadra (c. 1571–1635), who would posit that "existence precedes essence" becoming the principle expositor of the School of Isfahan, which is described as "alive and active".
19th century
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche
Main article: Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich NietzscheKierkegaard is generally considered to have been the first existentialist philosopher. He proposed that each individual—not reason, society, or religious orthodoxy—is solely tasked with giving meaning to life and living it sincerely, or "authentically".
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were two of the first philosophers considered fundamental to the existentialist movement, though neither used the term "existentialism" and it is unclear whether they would have supported the existentialism of the 20th century. They focused on subjective human experience rather than the objective truths of mathematics and science, which they believed were too detached or observational to truly get at the human experience. Like Pascal, they were interested in people's quiet struggle with the apparent meaninglessness of life and the use of diversion to escape from boredom. Unlike Pascal, Kierkegaard and Nietzsche also considered the role of making free choices, particularly regarding fundamental values and beliefs, and how such choices change the nature and identity of the chooser. Kierkegaard's knight of faith and Nietzsche's Übermensch are representative of people who exhibit freedom, in that they define the nature of their own existence. Nietzsche's idealized individual invents his own values and creates the very terms they excel under. By contrast, Kierkegaard, opposed to the level of abstraction in Hegel, and not nearly as hostile (actually welcoming) to Christianity as Nietzsche, argues through a pseudonym that the objective certainty of religious truths (specifically Christian) is not only impossible, but even founded on logical paradoxes. Yet he continues to imply that a leap of faith is a possible means for an individual to reach a higher stage of existence that transcends and contains both an aesthetic and ethical value of life. Kierkegaard and Nietzsche were also precursors to other intellectual movements, including postmodernism, and various strands of psychotherapy. However, Kierkegaard believed that individuals should live in accordance with their thinking.
In Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche's sentiments resonate the idea of "existence precedes essence." He writes, "no one gives man his qualities-- neither God, nor society, nor his parents and ancestors, nor he himself...No one is responsible for man's being there at all, for his being such-and-such, or for his being in these circumstances or in this environment...Man is not the effect of some special purpose of a will, and end..." Within this view, Nietzsche ties in his rejection of the existence of God, which he sees as a means to "redeem the world." By rejecting the existence of God, Nietzsche also rejects beliefs that claim humans have a predestined purpose according to what God has instructed.
Dostoyevsky
The first important literary author also important to existentialism was the Russian, Dostoyevsky. Dostoyevsky's Notes from Underground portrays a man unable to fit into society and unhappy with the identities he creates for himself. Sartre, in his book on existentialism Existentialism is a Humanism, quoted Dostoyevsky's The Brothers Karamazov as an example of existential crisis. Other Dostoyevsky novels covered issues raised in existentialist philosophy while presenting story lines divergent from secular existentialism: for example, in Crime and Punishment, the protagonist Raskolnikov experiences an existential crisis and then moves toward a Christian Orthodox worldview similar to that advocated by Dostoyevsky himself.
Early 20th century
See also: Martin HeideggerIn the first decades of the 20th century, a number of philosophers and writers explored existentialist ideas. The Spanish philosopher Miguel de Unamuno y Jugo, in his 1913 book The Tragic Sense of Life in Men and Nations, emphasized the life of "flesh and bone" as opposed to that of abstract rationalism. Unamuno rejected systematic philosophy in favor of the individual's quest for faith. He retained a sense of the tragic, even absurd nature of the quest, symbolized by his enduring interest in the eponymous character from the Miguel de Cervantes novel Don Quixote. A novelist, poet and dramatist as well as philosophy professor at the University of Salamanca, Unamuno wrote a short story about a priest's crisis of faith, Saint Manuel the Good, Martyr, which has been collected in anthologies of existentialist fiction. Another Spanish thinker, José Ortega y Gasset, writing in 1914, held that human existence must always be defined as the individual person combined with the concrete circumstances of his life: "Yo soy yo y mi circunstancia" ("I am myself and my circumstances"). Sartre likewise believed that human existence is not an abstract matter, but is always situated ("en situation").
Although Martin Buber wrote his major philosophical works in German, and studied and taught at the Universities of Berlin and Frankfurt, he stands apart from the mainstream of German philosophy. Born into a Jewish family in Vienna in 1878, he was also a scholar of Jewish culture and involved at various times in Zionism and Hasidism. In 1938, he moved permanently to Jerusalem. His best-known philosophical work was the short book I and Thou, published in 1922. For Buber, the fundamental fact of human existence, too readily overlooked by scientific rationalism and abstract philosophical thought, is "man with man", a dialogue that takes place in the so-called "sphere of between" ("das Zwischenmenschliche").
Two Russian philosophers, Lev Shestov and Nikolai Berdyaev, became well known as existentialist thinkers during their post-Revolutionary exiles in Paris. Shestov had launched an attack on rationalism and systematization in philosophy as early as 1905 in his book of aphorisms All Things Are Possible. Berdyaev drew a radical distinction between the world of spirit and the everyday world of objects. Human freedom, for Berdyaev, is rooted in the realm of spirit, a realm independent of scientific notions of causation. To the extent the individual human being lives in the objective world, he is estranged from authentic spiritual freedom. "Man" is not to be interpreted naturalistically, but as a being created in God's image, an originator of free, creative acts. He published a major work on these themes, The Destiny of Man, in 1931.
Gabriel Marcel, long before coining the term "existentialism", introduced important existentialist themes to a French audience in his early essay "Existence and Objectivity" (1925) and in his Metaphysical Journal (1927). A dramatist as well as a philosopher, Marcel found his philosophical starting point in a condition of metaphysical alienation: the human individual searching for harmony in a transient life. Harmony, for Marcel, was to be sought through "secondary reflection", a "dialogical" rather than "dialectical" approach to the world, characterized by "wonder and astonishment" and open to the "presence" of other people and of God rather than merely to "information" about them. For Marcel, such presence implied more than simply being there (as one thing might be in the presence of another thing); it connoted "extravagant" availability, and the willingness to put oneself at the disposal of the other.
Marcel contrasted secondary reflection with abstract, scientific-technical primary reflection, which he associated with the activity of the abstract Cartesian ego. For Marcel, philosophy was a concrete activity undertaken by a sensing, feeling human being incarnate—embodied—in a concrete world. Although Sartre adopted the term "existentialism" for his own philosophy in the 1940s, Marcel's thought has been described as "almost diametrically opposed" to that of Sartre. Unlike Sartre, Marcel was a Christian, and became a Catholic convert in 1929.
In Germany, the psychiatrist and philosopher Karl Jaspers—who later described existentialism as a "phantom" created by the public—called his own thought, heavily influenced by Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, Existenzphilosophie. For Jaspers, "Existenz-philosophy is the way of thought by means of which man seeks to become himself...This way of thought does not cognize objects, but elucidates and makes actual the being of the thinker".
Jaspers, a professor at the university of Heidelberg, was acquainted with Heidegger, who held a professorship at Marburg before acceding to Husserl's chair at Freiburg in 1928. They held many philosophical discussions, but later became estranged over Heidegger's support of National Socialism. They shared an admiration for Kierkegaard, and in the 1930s, Heidegger lectured extensively on Nietzsche. Nevertheless, the extent to which Heidegger should be considered an existentialist is debatable. In Being and Time he presented a method of rooting philosophical explanations in human existence (Dasein) to be analysed in terms of existential categories (existentiale); and this has led many commentators to treat him as an important figure in the existentialist movement.
After the Second World War
Following the Second World War, existentialism became a well-known and significant philosophical and cultural movement, mainly through the public prominence of two French writers, Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus, who wrote best-selling novels, plays and widely read journalism as well as theoretical texts. These years also saw the growing reputation of Being and Time outside Germany.
Sartre dealt with existentialist themes in his 1938 novel Nausea and the short stories in his 1939 collection The Wall, and had published his treatise on existentialism, Being and Nothingness, in 1943, but it was in the two years following the liberation of Paris from the German occupying forces that he and his close associates—Camus, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and others—became internationally famous as the leading figures of a movement known as existentialism. In a very short period of time, Camus and Sartre in particular became the leading public intellectuals of post-war France, achieving by the end of 1945 "a fame that reached across all audiences." Camus was an editor of the most popular leftist (former French Resistance) newspaper Combat; Sartre launched his journal of leftist thought, Les Temps Modernes, and two weeks later gave the widely reported lecture on existentialism and secular humanism to a packed meeting of the Club Maintenant. Beauvoir wrote that "not a week passed without the newspapers discussing us"; existentialism became "the first media craze of the postwar era."
By the end of 1947, Camus' earlier fiction and plays had been reprinted, his new play Caligula had been performed and his novel The Plague published; the first two novels of Sartre's The Roads to Freedom trilogy had appeared, as had Beauvoir's novel The Blood of Others. Works by Camus and Sartre were already appearing in foreign editions. The Paris-based existentialists had become famous.
Sartre had traveled to Germany in 1930 to study the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger, and he included critical comments on their work in his major treatise Being and Nothingness. Heidegger's thought had also become known in French philosophical circles through its use by Alexandre Kojève in explicating Hegel in a series of lectures given in Paris in the 1930s. The lectures were highly influential; members of the audience included not only Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, but Raymond Queneau, Georges Bataille, Louis Althusser, André Breton, and Jacques Lacan. A selection from Being and Time was published in French in 1938, and his essays began to appear in French philosophy journals.
Heidegger read Sartre's work and was initially impressed, commenting: "Here for the first time I encountered an independent thinker who, from the foundations up, has experienced the area out of which I think. Your work shows such an immediate comprehension of my philosophy as I have never before encountered." Later, however, in response to a question posed by his French follower Jean Beaufret, Heidegger distanced himself from Sartre's position and existentialism in general in his Letter on Humanism. Heidegger's reputation continued to grow in France during the 1950s and 1960s. In the 1960s, Sartre attempted to reconcile existentialism and Marxism in his work Critique of Dialectical Reason. A major theme throughout his writings was freedom and responsibility.
Camus was a friend of Sartre, until their falling-out, and wrote several works with existential themes including The Rebel, Summer in Algiers, The Myth of Sisyphus, and The Stranger, the latter being "considered—to what would have been Camus's irritation—the exemplary existentialist novel." Camus, like many others, rejected the existentialist label, and considered his works concerned with facing the absurd. In the titular book, Camus uses the analogy of the Greek myth of Sisyphus to demonstrate the futility of existence. In the myth, Sisyphus is condemned for eternity to roll a rock up a hill, but when he reaches the summit, the rock will roll to the bottom again. Camus believes that this existence is pointless but that Sisyphus ultimately finds meaning and purpose in his task, simply by continually applying himself to it. The first half of the book contains an extended rebuttal of what Camus took to be existentialist philosophy in the works of Kierkegaard, Shestov, Heidegger, and Jaspers.
Simone de Beauvoir, an important existentialist who spent much of her life as Sartre's partner, wrote about feminist and existentialist ethics in her works, including The Second Sex and The Ethics of Ambiguity. Although often overlooked due to her relationship with Sartre, de Beauvoir integrated existentialism with other forms of thinking such as feminism, unheard of at the time, resulting in alienation from fellow writers such as Camus.
Paul Tillich, an important existentialist theologian following Kierkegaard and Karl Barth, applied existentialist concepts to Christian theology, and helped introduce existential theology to the general public. His seminal work The Courage to Be follows Kierkegaard's analysis of anxiety and life's absurdity, but puts forward the thesis that modern humans must, via God, achieve selfhood in spite of life's absurdity. Rudolf Bultmann used Kierkegaard's and Heidegger's philosophy of existence to demythologize Christianity by interpreting Christian mythical concepts into existentialist concepts.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, an existential phenomenologist, was for a time a companion of Sartre. Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception (1945) was recognized as a major statement of French existentialism. It has been said that Merleau-Ponty's work Humanism and Terror greatly influenced Sartre. However, in later years they were to disagree irreparably, dividing many existentialists such as de Beauvoir, who sided with Sartre.
Colin Wilson, an English writer, published his study The Outsider in 1956, initially to critical acclaim. In this book and others (e.g. Introduction to the New Existentialism), he attempted to reinvigorate what he perceived as a pessimistic philosophy and bring it to a wider audience. He was not, however, academically trained, and his work was attacked by professional philosophers for lack of rigor and critical standards.
Influence outside philosophy
Art
Film and television
Stanley Kubrick's 1957 anti-war film Paths of Glory "illustrates, and even illuminates...existentialism" by examining the "necessary absurdity of the human condition" and the "horror of war". The film tells the story of a fictional World War I French army regiment ordered to attack an impregnable German stronghold; when the attack fails, three soldiers are chosen at random, court-martialed by a "kangaroo court", and executed by firing squad. The film examines existentialist ethics, such as the issue of whether objectivity is possible and the "problem of authenticity". Orson Welles's 1962 film The Trial, based upon Franz Kafka's book of the same name (Der Prozeß), is characteristic of both existentialist and absurdist themes in its depiction of a man (Joseph K.) arrested for a crime for which the charges are neither revealed to him nor to the reader.
Neon Genesis Evangelion is a Japanese science fiction animation series created by the anime studio Gainax and was both directed and written by Hideaki Anno. Existential themes of individuality, consciousness, freedom, choice, and responsibility are heavily relied upon throughout the entire series, particularly through the philosophies of Jean-Paul Sartre and Søren Kierkegaard. Episode 16's title, "The Sickness Unto Death, And..." (死に至る病、そして, Shi ni itaru yamai, soshite) is a reference to Kierkegaard's book, The Sickness Unto Death.
Some contemporary films dealing with existentialist issues include Melancholia, Fight Club, I Heart Huckabees, Waking Life, The Matrix, Ordinary People, Life in a Day, Barbie, and Everything Everywhere All at Once. Likewise, films throughout the 20th century such as The Seventh Seal, Ikiru, Taxi Driver, the Toy Story films, The Great Silence, Ghost in the Shell, Harold and Maude, High Noon, Easy Rider, One Flew Over the Cuckoo's Nest, A Clockwork Orange, Groundhog Day, Apocalypse Now, Badlands, and Blade Runner also have existentialist qualities.
Notable directors known for their existentialist films include Ingmar Bergman, Bela Tarr, Robert Bresson, Jean-Pierre Melville, François Truffaut, Jean-Luc Godard, Michelangelo Antonioni, Akira Kurosawa, Terrence Malick, Stanley Kubrick, Andrei Tarkovsky, Éric Rohmer, Wes Anderson, Woody Allen, and Christopher Nolan. Charlie Kaufman's Synecdoche, New York focuses on the protagonist's desire to find existential meaning. Similarly, in Kurosawa's Red Beard, the protagonist's experiences as an intern in a rural health clinic in Japan lead him to an existential crisis whereby he questions his reason for being. This, in turn, leads him to a better understanding of humanity. The French film, Mood Indigo (directed by Michel Gondry) embraced various elements of existentialism. The film The Shawshank Redemption, released in 1994, depicts life in a prison in Maine, United States to explore several existentialist concepts.
Literature
Existential perspectives are also found in modern literature to varying degrees, especially since the 1920s. Louis-Ferdinand Céline's Journey to the End of the Night (Voyage au bout de la nuit, 1932) celebrated by both Sartre and Beauvoir, contained many of the themes that would be found in later existential literature, and is in some ways, the proto-existential novel. Jean-Paul Sartre's 1938 novel Nausea was "steeped in Existential ideas", and is considered an accessible way of grasping his philosophical stance. Between 1900 and 1960, other authors such as Albert Camus, Franz Kafka, Rainer Maria Rilke, T. S. Eliot, Yukio Mishima, Hermann Hesse, Luigi Pirandello, Ralph Ellison, and Jack Kerouac composed literature or poetry that contained, to varying degrees, elements of existential or proto-existential thought. The philosophy's influence even reached pulp literature shortly after the turn of the 20th century, as seen in the existential disparity witnessed in Man's lack of control of his fate in the works of H. P. Lovecraft.
Theatre
Sartre wrote No Exit in 1944, an existentialist play originally published in French as Huis Clos (meaning In Camera or "behind closed doors"), which is the source of the popular quote, "Hell is other people." (In French, "L'enfer, c'est les autres"). The play begins with a Valet leading a man into a room that the audience soon realizes is in hell. Eventually he is joined by two women. After their entry, the Valet leaves and the door is shut and locked. All three expect to be tortured, but no torturer arrives. Instead, they realize they are there to torture each other, which they do effectively by probing each other's sins, desires, and unpleasant memories.
Existentialist themes are displayed in the Theatre of the Absurd, notably in Samuel Beckett's Waiting for Godot, in which two men divert themselves while they wait expectantly for someone (or something) named Godot who never arrives. They claim Godot is an acquaintance, but in fact, hardly know him, admitting they would not recognize him if they saw him. Samuel Beckett, once asked who or what Godot is, replied, "If I knew, I would have said so in the play." To occupy themselves, the men eat, sleep, talk, argue, sing, play games, exercise, swap hats, and contemplate suicide—anything "to hold the terrible silence at bay". The play "exploits several archetypal forms and situations, all of which lend themselves to both comedy and pathos." The play also illustrates an attitude toward human experience on earth: the poignancy, oppression, camaraderie, hope, corruption, and bewilderment of human experience that can be reconciled only in the mind and art of the absurdist. The play examines questions such as death, the meaning of human existence and the place of God in human existence.
Tom Stoppard's Rosencrantz & Guildenstern Are Dead is an absurdist tragicomedy first staged at the Edinburgh Festival Fringe in 1966. The play expands upon the exploits of two minor characters from Shakespeare's Hamlet. Comparisons have also been drawn to Samuel Beckett's Waiting for Godot, for the presence of two central characters who appear almost as two halves of a single character. Many plot features are similar as well: the characters pass time by playing Questions, impersonating other characters, and interrupting each other or remaining silent for long periods of time. The two characters are portrayed as two clowns or fools in a world beyond their understanding. They stumble through philosophical arguments while not realizing the implications, and muse on the irrationality and randomness of the world.
Jean Anouilh's Antigone also presents arguments founded on existentialist ideas. It is a tragedy inspired by Greek mythology and the play of the same name (Antigone, by Sophocles) from the fifth century BC. In English, it is often distinguished from its antecedent by being pronounced in its original French form, approximately "Ante-GŌN." The play was first performed in Paris on 6 February 1944, during the Nazi occupation of France. Produced under Nazi censorship, the play is purposefully ambiguous with regards to the rejection of authority (represented by Antigone) and the acceptance of it (represented by Creon). The parallels to the French Resistance and the Nazi occupation have been drawn. Antigone rejects life as desperately meaningless but without affirmatively choosing a noble death. The crux of the play is the lengthy dialogue concerning the nature of power, fate, and choice, during which Antigone says that she is, "... disgusted with ...promise of a humdrum happiness." She states that she would rather die than live a mediocre existence.
Critic Martin Esslin in his book Theatre of the Absurd pointed out how many contemporary playwrights such as Samuel Beckett, Eugène Ionesco, Jean Genet, and Arthur Adamov wove into their plays the existentialist belief that we are absurd beings loose in a universe empty of real meaning. Esslin noted that many of these playwrights demonstrated the philosophy better than did the plays by Sartre and Camus. Though most of such playwrights, subsequently labeled "Absurdist" (based on Esslin's book), denied affiliations with existentialism and were often staunchly anti-philosophical (for example Ionesco often claimed he identified more with 'Pataphysics or with Surrealism than with existentialism), the playwrights are often linked to existentialism based on Esslin's observation.
Activism
Black existentialism explores the existence and experiences of Black people in the world. Classical and contemporary thinkers include C.L.R James, Frederick Douglass, W.E.B DuBois, Frantz Fanon, Angela Davis, Cornel West, Naomi Zack, bell hooks, Stuart Hall, Lewis Gordon, and Audre Lorde.
Psychoanalysis and psychotherapy
Main article: Existential therapyA major offshoot of existentialism as a philosophy is existentialist psychology and psychoanalysis, which first crystallized in the work of Otto Rank, Freud's closest associate for 20 years. Without awareness of the writings of Rank, Ludwig Binswanger was influenced by Freud, Edmund Husserl, Heidegger, and Sartre. A later figure was Viktor Frankl, who briefly met Freud as a young man. His logotherapy can be regarded as a form of existentialist therapy. The existentialists would also influence social psychology, antipositivist micro-sociology, symbolic interactionism, and post-structuralism, with the work of thinkers such as Georg Simmel and Michel Foucault. Foucault was a great reader of Kierkegaard even though he almost never refers to this author, who nonetheless had for him an importance as secret as it was decisive.
An early contributor to existentialist psychology in the United States was Rollo May, who was strongly influenced by Kierkegaard and Otto Rank. One of the most prolific writers on techniques and theory of existentialist psychology in the US is Irvin D. Yalom. Yalom states that
Aside from their reaction against Freud's mechanistic, deterministic model of the mind and their assumption of a phenomenological approach in therapy, the existentialist analysts have little in common and have never been regarded as a cohesive ideological school. These thinkers—who include Ludwig Binswanger, Medard Boss, Eugène Minkowski, V. E. Gebsattel, Roland Kuhn, G. Caruso, F. T. Buytendijk, G. Bally, and Victor Frankl—were almost entirely unknown to the American psychotherapeutic community until Rollo May's highly influential 1958 book Existence—and especially his introductory essay—introduced their work into this country.
A more recent contributor to the development of a European version of existentialist psychotherapy is the British-based Emmy van Deurzen.
Anxiety's importance in existentialism makes it a popular topic in psychotherapy. Therapists often offer existentialist philosophy as an explanation for anxiety. The assertion is that anxiety is manifested of an individual's complete freedom to decide, and complete responsibility for the outcome of such decisions. Psychotherapists using an existentialist approach believe that a patient can harness his anxiety and use it constructively. Instead of suppressing anxiety, patients are advised to use it as grounds for change. By embracing anxiety as inevitable, a person can use it to achieve his full potential in life. Humanistic psychology also had major impetus from existentialist psychology and shares many of the fundamental tenets. Terror management theory, based on the writings of Ernest Becker and Otto Rank, is a developing area of study within the academic study of psychology. It looks at what researchers claim are implicit emotional reactions of people confronted with the knowledge that they will eventually die.
Also, Gerd B. Achenbach has refreshed the Socratic tradition with his own blend of philosophical counseling; as did Michel Weber with his Chromatiques Center in Belgium.
Criticisms
General criticisms
Walter Kaufmann criticized "the profoundly unsound methods and the dangerous contempt for reason that have been so prominent in existentialism." Logical positivist philosophers, such as Rudolf Carnap and A. J. Ayer, assert that existentialists are often confused about the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being". Specifically, they argue that the verb "is" is transitive and pre-fixed to a predicate (e.g., an apple is red) (without a predicate, the word "is" is meaningless), and that existentialists frequently misuse the term in this manner. Wilson has stated in his book The Angry Years that existentialism has created many of its own difficulties: "We can see how this question of freedom of the will has been vitiated by post-romantic philosophy, with its inbuilt tendency to laziness and boredom, we can also see how it came about that existentialism found itself in a hole of its own digging, and how the philosophical developments since then have amounted to walking in circles round that hole."
Sartre's philosophy
Many critics argue Sartre's philosophy is contradictory. Specifically, they argue that Sartre makes metaphysical arguments despite his claiming that his philosophical views ignore metaphysics. Herbert Marcuse criticized Being and Nothingness for projecting anxiety and meaninglessness onto the nature of existence itself: "Insofar as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it hypostatizes specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics. Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory."
In Letter on Humanism, Heidegger criticized Sartre's existentialism:
Existentialism says existence precedes essence. In this statement he is taking existentia and essentia according to their metaphysical meaning, which, from Plato's time on, has said that essentia precedes existentia. Sartre reverses this statement. But the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement. With it, he stays with metaphysics, in oblivion of the truth of Being.
See also
- Abandonment (existentialism)
- Disenchantment
- Existential phenomenology
- Existential risk
- Existentiell
- List of existentialists
- Meaning (existential)
- Meaning-making
- Philosophical pessimism
- Self-reflection
References
Citations
- "existentialism". Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary. Merriam-Webster.
- "existentialism". Dictionary.com Unabridged (Online). n.d.
- "existentialism". Cambridge Dictionaries (Online). Cambridge University Press. n.d.
- Solomon 1974, pp. 1–2.
- ^ Crowell 2020.
- Macquarrie, John (1972). Existentialism. New York: Penguin. pp. 14–15.
- Honderich, Ted, ed. (1995). Oxford Companion to Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 259. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
- Breisach, Ernst (1962). Introduction to Modern Existentialism. New York: Grove Press. p. 5.
- Kaufmann, Walter (1956). Existentialism: From Dostoyevesky to Sartre. New York: Meridian. p. 12.
- Flynn 2006, p. xi.
- Guignon, Charles B.; Pereboom, Derk (2001). Existentialism: Basic Writings. Hackett Publishing. p. xiii. ISBN 978-0-87220-595-6 – via Google Books.
- Kleinman, Paul (2013). Philosophy 101: from Plato and Socrates to ethics and metaphysics, an essential primer on the history of thought. Adams Media. ISBN 978-1-4405-6767-4. OCLC 869368682.
- Cooper 1990, p. 1.
- Flynn 2006, p. 89.
- Daigle, Christine (2006). Existentialist Thinkers and Ethics. McGill-Queen's University Press. p. 5.
- Ann Fulton, Apostles of Sartre: Existentialism in America, 1945–1963, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1999, p. 12-13 & 18–19.
- L'Existentialisme est un Humanisme (Editions Nagel, 1946); English Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Humanism (Eyre Methuen, 1948).
- Crowell, Steven (2011). The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism. Cambridge. p. 316.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - Copleston, F. C. (January 1948). "Existentialism". Philosophy. 23 (84): 19–37. doi:10.1017/S0031819100065955. ISSN 0031-8191. JSTOR 3747384. S2CID 262276911.
- See James Wood's introduction to Sartre, Jean-Paul (2000). Nausea. London: Penguin Classics. p. vii. ISBN 978-0-141-18549-1.
- Abulof, Uriel. "Episode 1: The Jumping Off Place [MOOC lecture]". Uriel Abulof, Human Odyssey to Political Existentialism (HOPE). edX/Princeton. Archived from the original on 5 August 2021. Retrieved 12 January 2021.
- Klempe, Hroar (October 2008). "Welhaven og psykologien: Del 2. Welhaven peker fremover" [Welhaven and psychology: Part 2. Welhaven points forward]. Tidsskrift for Norsk Psykologforening (in Norwegian Bokmål). 45 (10). Retrieved 2022-07-14.
- Lundestad, 1998, p. 169.
- Slagstad, 2001, p. 89.
- (Dictionary) "L'existencialisme" – see "l'identité de la personne" (in French).
- "Aquinas: Metaphysics | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2022-11-10.
- Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008). From Plato to Derrida. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-158591-1.
- ^ Webber, Jonathan (2018). Rethinking Existentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Burnham, Douglas. "Existentialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 16 November 2020.
- Cox, Gary (2008). The Sartre Dictionary. Continuum. pp. 41–42.
- Heidegger, Martin (1993). David Farrell Krell (ed.). Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to The Task of Thinking (1964) (Revised and expanded ed.). San Francisco, California: Harper San Francisco. ISBN 0-06-063763-3. OCLC 26355951.
- Heidegger, Martin (1993). David Farrell Krell (ed.). Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to The Task of thinking (1964) (Revised and expanded ed.). San Francisco, California: Harper San Francisco. pp. 243. ISBN 0-06-063763-3. OCLC 26355951.
- ^ Wartenberg 2008.
- Michelman, Stephen (2010). The A to Z of Existentialism. Lanham, Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, Inc. p. 27. ISBN 978-0-8108-7589-0.
- Crowell 2020, 3.1 Anxiety, Nothingness, the Absurd.
- ^ Bassnett, Susan; Lorch, Jennifer (March 18, 2014). Luigi Pirandello in the Theatre. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-35114-5. Retrieved 26 March 2015 – via Google Books.
- ^ Thompson, Mel; Rodgers, Nigel (2010). Understanding Existentialism: Teach Yourself. Hodder & Stoughton. ISBN 978-1-4441-3421-6 – via Google Books.
- Caputi, Anthony Francis (1988). Pirandello and the Crisis of Modern Consciousness. University of Illinois Press. ISBN 978-0-252-01468-0 – via Google Books.
- ^ Mariani, Umberto (2010). Living Masks: The Achievement of Pirandello. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-1-4426-9314-2. Retrieved 26 March 2015 – via Google Books.
- Sartre, Jean-Paul (1946). Existentialism is a Humanism. Retrieved 2010-03-08 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
- Keen, E. (1973). "Suicide and Self-Deception". Psychoanalytic Review. 60 (4): 575–85. PMID 4772778.
- ^ Crowell 2020, 2.1 Facticity and Transcendence.
- Crowell 2020, 3. Freedom and Value.
- Crowell 2020, 3.2 The Ideality of Values.
- Crowell 2020, 2.3 Authenticity.
- ^ Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, Routledge Classics (2003).
- "Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2022-11-10.
- Crowell 2020, 2.2 Alienation.
- Sartre, Jean Paul (1992). "Chapter 1". Being and Nothingness. Translated by Barnes, Hazel E. New York: Washington Square Press. ISBN 978-0-230-00673-7.
- "Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2024-06-14.
- Plesa, Patric (2021-07-14). "Reassessing Existential Constructs and Subjectivity: Freedom and Authenticity in Neoliberalism". Journal of Humanistic Psychology: 002216782110320. doi:10.1177/00221678211032065. ISSN 0022-1678.
- Aho 2023.
- "Soren Kierkegaard and The Psychology of Anxiety". 2018-02-20. Retrieved 2024-05-07.
- "despair – definition of despair by the Free Online Dictionary, Thesaurus and Encyclopedia". Tfd.com. Retrieved 2010-03-08.
- Either/Or Part II p. 188 Hong.
- Søren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers Vol. 5, p. 5.
- "Ethics - Existentialism". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2020-05-28.
- Kierkegaard, Soren. Works of Love. Harper & Row, Publishers. New York, N.Y. 1962. p. 62.
- Sariel, Aviram. "Jonasian Gnosticism." Harvard Theological Review 116.1 (2023): 91-122.
- Alan Pratt (April 23, 2001). "Nihilism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Embry–Riddle University. Retrieved November 18, 2018.
- Camus, Albert. "The Myth of Sisyphus". NYU.edu.
- Barrett 1958, pp. 97, 133–157.
- Wahl, Jean André (1949). A Short History of Existentialism. New York: Philosophical Library. pp. 32–33.
- Marino 2004, p. ix.
- ^ McDonald, Lippitt & Evans 2017.
- Watts, Michael (2003). Kierkegaard. Oneworld. pp. 4–6. ISBN 978-1-85168-317-8.
- Lowrie, Walter (1969). Kierkegaard's attack upon "Christendom". Princeton. pp. 37–40.
- Luper 2000, pp. 4–5, 11.
- Nietzsche, Friedrich; Kaufmann, Walter (1994). The portable Nietzsche. Penguin books (Repr. of the 1954 ed. publ. by The Viking Press, New York ed.). New York: Penguin. ISBN 978-0-14-015062-9.
- Hubben, William. Dostoyevsky, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Kafka, Jabber-wacky, Scribner, 1997.
- ^ Rukhsana, Akhter (June 2014). Existentialism and Its Relevance to the Contemporary System of Education in India: Existentialism and Present Educational Scenario. Hamburg: Anchor Academic. ISBN 978-3-95489-277-8. OCLC 911266433.
- Pitari, Paolo (7 August 2020). "The Influence of Sartre's "What Is Literature?" on David Foster Wallace's Literary Project". Critique: Studies in Contemporary Fiction. 61 (4): 423–439. doi:10.1080/00111619.2020.1729690. hdl:10278/3730293. Retrieved 22 December 2024.
- Buber, Martin (1970). I and Thou. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. United States: Charles Scribner's Sons. ISBN 978-0-684-71725-8.
- Maurice S. Friedman, Martin Buber. The Life of Dialogue, University of Chicago Press, 1955, p. 85.
- Ernst Breisach, Introduction to Modern Existentialism, New York (1962), pp. 173–76.
- ^ Samuel M. Keen, "Gabriel Marcel" in Paul Edwards (ed.) The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Macmillan Publishing Co, 1967.
- John Macquarrie, Existentialism, Pelican, 1973, p. 110.
- John Macquarrie, Existentialism, Pelican, 1973, p. 96.
- Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 75/11.
- Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 40.
- Karl Jaspers, "Philosophical Autobiography" in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Jaspers The Library of Living Philosophers IX, Tudor Publishing Company, 1957, p. 75/2 and following.
- Baert, Patrick (2015). The Existentialist Moment: The Rise of Sartre as a Public Intellectual. Polity Press.
- ^ Ronald Aronson, Camus and Sartre, University of Chicago Press, 2004, Chapter 3 passim.
- Ronald Aronson, Camus and Sartre, University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 44.
- Simone de Beauvoir, Force of Circumstance, quoted in Ronald Aronson, Camus and Sartre, University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 48.
- Ronald Aronson, Camus and Sartre, University of Chicago Press, 2004, p. 48.
- Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 343.
- Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics (Hodder Arnold, 2006, p. 158); see also Alexandre Kojève, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit (Cornell University Press, 1980).
- Entry on Kojève in Martin Cohen (editor), The Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics (Hodder Arnold, 2006, p. 158).
- Martin Heidegger, letter, quoted in Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger – Between Good and Evil (Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 349).
- Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger – Between Good and Evil (Harvard University Press, 1998, p. 356).
- William J. Richardson, Martin Heidegger: From Phenomenology to Thought (Martjinus Nijhoff, 1967, p. 351).
- Messud, Claire (2014). "A New 'L'Étranger'". The New York Review of Books. 61 (10). Retrieved 1 June 2014.
- Camus 1968.
- Bergoffen, Debra (September 2010). "Simone de Beauvoir". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Madison, G. B., in Robert Audi's The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 559).
- K. Gunnar Bergström, An Odyssey to Freedom University of Uppsala, 1983, p. 92. Colin Stanley, Colin Wilson, a Celebration: Essays and Recollections Cecil Woolf, 1988, p. 43.
- ^ Holt, Jason. "Existential Ethics: Where do the Paths of Glory Lead?". In The Philosophy of Stanley Kubrick. By Jerold J. Abrams. Published 2007. University Press of Kentucky. SBN 0-8131-2445-X
- "Existential & Psychological Movie Recommendations". Existential-therapy.com. Archived from the original on 2010-01-07. Retrieved 2010-03-08.
- "Existentialism in Film". Uhaweb.hartford.edu. Archived from the original on 2010-01-13. Retrieved 2010-03-08.
- "Existentialist Adaptations – Harvard Film Archive". Hcl.harvard.edu. Archived from the original on 2011-01-27. Retrieved 2010-03-08.
- Chocano, Carina (2008-10-24). "Review: 'Synecdoche, New York'". Los Angeles Times. Retrieved 2008-11-17.
- For an examination of the existentialist elements within the film, see Philosophy Now, issue 102, accessible here (link), accessed 3 June 2014.
- Sartre, Jean-Paul (2000) . Nausea. Translated by Baldick, Robert. London: Penguin.
- Earnshaw, Steven (2006). Existentialism: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Continuum. p. 75. ISBN 0-8264-8530-8.
- Cincotta, Madeleine Strong (1989). Luigi Pirandello: The Humorous Existentialist. University of Wollongong Press. ISBN 978-0-86418-090-2. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Bassanese, Fiora A. (Jan 1, 1997). Understanding Luigi Pirandello. University of South Carolina Press. ISBN 978-0-585-33727-2. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
existential.
- DiGaetani, John Louis (Jan 25, 2008). Stages of Struggle: Modern Playwrights and Their Psychological Inspirations. McFarland. ISBN 978-0-7864-8259-7. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Graham, Maryemma; Singh, Amritjit (1995). Conversations with Ralph Ellison. University of Mississippi Press. ISBN 978-0-87805-781-8. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Cotkin, George (2005). Existential American. JHU Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-8200-5. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Thomas, Paul Lee (2008). Reading, Learning, Teach Ralph Ellison. Peter Lang. ISBN 978-1-4331-0090-1. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Jackson, Lawrence Patrick (2007). Ralph Ellison: Emergence of Genius. University of Georgia Press. ISBN 978-0-8203-2993-2. Retrieved 26 March 2015.
- Gurnow, Michael (2008-10-15). "Zarathustra . . . Cthulhu . Meursault: Existential Futility in H.P. Lovecraft's 'The Call of Cthulhu'". The Horror Review. Archived from the original on October 6, 2014. Retrieved 2015-02-17.
- The Times, 31 December 1964. Quoted in Knowlson, J., Damned to Fame: The Life of Samuel Beckett (London: Bloomsbury, 1996), p. 57
- Cronin, A., Samuel Beckett The Last Modernist (London: Flamingo, 1997), p. 391
- Michael H. Hutchins (14 August 2006). "A Tom Stoppard Bibliography: Chronology". The Stephen Sondheim Reference Guide. Retrieved 2008-06-23.
- Wren, Celia (12 December 2007). "From Forum, an Earnest and Painstaking 'Antigone'". Washington Post. Retrieved 2008-04-07.
- Kernan, Alvin B. The Modern American Theater: A Collection of Critical Essays. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1967.
- Bassey, Magnus O. (2007). "What is Africana Critical Theory or Black Existential Philosophy?". Journal of Black Studies. 37 (6): 914–935. doi:10.1177/0021934705285563. ISSN 0021-9347. JSTOR 40034961. S2CID 145250815.
- Gordon, Lewis R. (2000-04-11). Existentia Africana: Understanding Africana Existential Thought. New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203900758. ISBN 978-0-203-90075-8.
- Frankl, Viktor (2000). Recollections: An Autobiography. Massachusetts: Perseus Publishing. p. 51.
- Šajda 2011, p. 38.
- Flynn, Thomas R. Sartre, Foucault, and Historical Reason. p. 323.
- Yalom, Irvin D. (1980). Existential Psychotherapy. New York: Basic Books (Subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. p. 17. ISBN 0-465-02147-6. Note: The copyright year has not changed, but the book remains in print.
- Kass, Sarah A. (April 2014). "Don't Fall Into Those Stereotype Traps: Women and the Feminine in Existential Therapy". Journal of Humanistic Psychology. 54 (2) (published 11 March 2013): 131–157. doi:10.1177/0022167813478836.
- "Terror Management Theory – Ernest Becker Foundation". ernestbecker.org. Retrieved 2022-11-10.
- Kaufmann, Walter Arnold, From Shakespeare To Existentialism (Princeton University Press 1979), p. xvi.
- Carnap, Rudolf, Uberwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache , Erkenntnis (1932), pp. 219–41. Carnap's critique of Heidegger's "What is Metaphysics."
- Colin, Wilson, The Angry Years (2007), p. 214
- Marcuse, Herbert. "Sartre's Existentialism". Printed in Studies in Critical Philosophy. Translated by Joris De Bres. London: NLB, 1972. p. 161.
- Martin Heidegger, "Letter on Humanism", in Basic Writings: Nine Key Essays, plus the Introduction to Being and Time , trans. David Farrell Krell (London, Routledge; 1978), p. 208. Google Books.
Bibliography
- Aho, Kevin (6 January 2023). "Existentialism". In Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-11-18.
- Barrett, William (1958). Irrational Man: A Study in Existential Philosophy (1st ed.). Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor Books. OCLC 14597959. OL 6247210M.
- Camus, Albert (1968). "No, I am not an existentialist . . . ". In Thody, Philip (ed.). Lyrical and Critical Essays. Translated by Kennedy, Ellen Conroy. New York: Vintage Books. pp. 345–348. OCLC 160250.
- Cooper, David E. (1990). Existentialism: A Reconstruction (1st ed.). Oxford, England & Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-16191-2.
- Crowell, Steven (9 June 2020) . "Existentialism". In Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-11-18.
- Flynn, Thomas R. (2006). Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford, England & New York, NY: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-280428-0.
- Luper, Steven (2000). Luper, Steven (ed.). Existing: An Introduction to Existential Thought. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-7674-0587-4.
- Marino, Gordon (2004). "Introduction". In Marino, Gordon (ed.). Basic Writings of Existentialism. New York: Modern Library. pp. ix–xvi. ISBN 978-0-375-75989-5.
- McDonald, William; Lippitt, John; Evans, C. Stephen (10 November 2017) . "Søren Kierkegaard". In Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-11-18.
- Šajda, Peter (2011). "Martin Buber: "No-One Can so Refute Kierkegaard as Kierkegaard Himself"". In Stewart, Jon (ed.). Kierkegaard and Existentialism. Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources. Vol. 9. Farnham, England & Burlington, VT: Ashgate. pp. 33–62. ISBN 978-1-4094-2641-7.
- Solomon, Robert C., ed. (1974). Existentialism (1st ed.). New York: Modern Library. ISBN 978-0-394-31704-5.
- Wartenberg, Thomas E. (2008). Existentialism: A Beginner's Guide (ebook ed.). Oxford, England: Oneworld (published 2011). ISBN 978-1-78074-020-1.
External links
- "Existentialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Existentialism on In Our Time at the BBC
- The Existential Primer
- Introducing Existentialism by Richard Appignanesi & Oscar Zárate (Icon Books, 2001)
Existentialism | |||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Variants | |||||
Concepts | |||||
People |
| ||||
Related |