Misplaced Pages

Morality: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 22:32, 8 March 2010 editChildofMidnight (talk | contribs)43,041 edits tweak← Previous edit Latest revision as of 14:05, 24 December 2024 edit undoParadoctor (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers33,546 edits Ethics: WP:DUE: not a representative sample 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Differentiation between right and wrong}}
{{Redirect|Appropriate||Appropriation}}
{{hatnote group|
'''Morality''' (from the ] ''{{lang|la|moralitas}}'' "manner, character, proper behavior") is a system of virtuous conduct and character. It can also refer to sexual matters and chastity. It has three principal meanings:
{{redirect-several|dab=off|Morality (novella){{!}}''Morality'' (novella)|Morality (The Armando Iannucci Shows){{!}}Morality (''The Armando Iannucci Shows'')|Morals (film){{!}}''Morals'' (film)|The Immoralist{{!}}''The Immoralist''}}
{{distinguish|Morale|Molarity|Molality}}
}}
], 1585]]


'''Morality''' ({{etymology|la|{{wikt-lang|la|moralitas}}|manner, ], proper behavior}}) is the categorization of ]s, decisions and ] into those that are proper, or ''right'', and those that are improper, or ''wrong''.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Hellenistic Philosophers: Translations of the Principal Sources with Philosophical Commentary|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AfemGeG8SysC|volume=1|first1=A. A.|last1=Long|first2=D. N.|last2=Sedley|publisher=Cambridge University Press|location=Cambridge|year=1987|pages=366–67|isbn=978-0521275569}}</ref> Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a ] from a particular ], ] or ], or it can derive from a standard that is ].<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |url= http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/|title= The Definition of Morality|author= Stanford University|date= 2011|encyclopedia= Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|publisher= Stanford University|access-date= 22 March 2014}}</ref> Morality may also be specifically synonymous with "]ness", "appropriateness" or "rightness".
In its "descriptive" sense, ''morality'' refers to ], ] or social ] that distinguish between right and wrong in the ]. Describing morality in this way is not making a claim about what is objectively right or wrong, but only referring to what is considered right or wrong by ]. For the most part right and wrong acts are classified as such because they are thought to cause benefit or harm, but it is possible that many moral beliefs are based on prejudice, ignorance or even hatred. This sense of term is also addressed by ].


] includes ], which studies abstract issues such as moral ] and moral ], and ], which studies more concrete systems of moral decision-making such as ] and ]. An example of normative ] is the ], which states: "One should treat others as one would like others to treat oneself."<ref name = "Flew">{{Cite encyclopedia |title=golden rule|editor =] | encyclopedia=A Dictionary of Philosophy | publisher = ] in association with ] | year = 1979 | location = London | page = 134 | isbn = 978-0333262047|quote=The maxim 'Treat others how you wish to be treated'. Various expressions of this fundamental moral rule are to be found in tenets of most religions and creeds through the ages, testifying to its universal applicability. }}</ref><ref>] argued that the Golden Rule is much more than simply an ]. He posits that it "express the essence of a universal morality." The rationale for this distinction occupies much of his book ''The Concept of Morals'' (1937). {{cite book | last = Stace | first = Walter T. | title = The Concept of Morals | url = https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.213305 | publisher = The MacMillan Company; reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc, January 1990 | year= 1937 | location = New York | page = | isbn = 978-0-8446-2990-2}}</ref>
In its "]" sense, ''morality'' refers directly to what is right and wrong, regardless of what people think. It could be defined as the conduct of the ideal "moral" person in a certain situation. This usage of the term is characterized by "definitive" statements such as "That act is immoral" rather than descriptive ones such as "Many believe that act is immoral." It is often challenged by a ], in which the unchanging existence of a rigid, universal, objective moral "truth" is rejected.<ref></ref> The normative usage of the term "morality" is also addressed by ].


] is the active opposition to morality (i.e., opposition to that which is ] or right), while ] is variously defined as an unawareness of, indifference toward, or disbelief in any particular set of moral standards or principles.<ref>
''Morality'' may also be defined as synonymous with ], the field that encompasses the above two meanings and others within a systematic philosophical study of the moral domain.<ref></ref> Ethics seeks to address questions such as how a moral outcome can be achieved in a specific situation (]), how moral values should be determined (]), what morals people actually abide by (]), what the fundamental nature of ethics or morality is, including whether it has any objective justification (]), and how moral capacity or moral agency develops and what its nature is (]).<ref></ref>
{{Cite book| last = Johnstone | first = Megan-Jane | title = Bioethics: A Nursing Perspective | journal = Confederation of Australian Critical Care Nurses Journal | publisher = Elsevier Health Sciences | year = 2008 | volume = 3 | issue = 4 | pages = 102–03 | pmid = 2129925 | isbn = 978-0-7295-3873-2}}</ref><ref>
{{Cite book| last = Superson | first = Anita | title = The Moral Skeptic | publisher = Oxford University Press | year = 2009 | pages = 127–59 | isbn = 978-0-19-537662-3}}</ref><ref>{{cite web| url = http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/amorality | title = Amorality | access-date = 2010-06-18 | work = Dictionary.com}} "having no moral standards, restraints, or principles; unaware of or indifferent to questions of right or wrong"</ref>


== History ==
A key issue is the meaning of the terms "moral" or "immoral". ] would hold that there are true moral statements which report objective moral facts, whereas moral ] would hold that morality is derived from any one of the ] prevalent in society (]); the edicts of a god (]); is merely an expression of the speakers' sentiments (]); an implied imperative (]); or falsely presupposes that there are objective moral facts (]). Some thinkers hold that there is no correct definition of right behavior, that morality can only be judged with respect to particular situations, within the standards of particular belief systems and socio-historical contexts. This position, known as ], often cites empirical evidence from anthropology as evidence to support its claims.<ref></ref> The opposite view, that there are universal, eternal moral truths are known as ]. Moral absolutists might concede that forces of social ] significantly shape moral decisions, but deny that cultural ]s and ]s define morally right behavior.
{{See also|Evolution of morality|History of ethics}}


== Ethics<!--'Morality and ethics' redirects here--> ==
== Anthropological perspectives ==
{{Expand section|date=June 2008}}
=== Tribal and territorial moralities ===
] has made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality.<ref name="Green">Green, Celia (2004). ''Letters from Exile: Observations on a Culture in Decline''. Oxford: Oxford Forum. Chapters I-XX. </ref> She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive: it defines a person’s territory, including his or her property and dependents, which is not to be damaged or interfered with. Apart from these proscriptions, territorial morality is permissive, allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another. By contrast, tribal morality is prescriptive, imposing the norms of the collective on the individual. These norms will be arbitrary, culturally dependent and ‘flexible’, whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute, such as ]’s ‘]’. Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property, and the ascendancy of contract over status.


] (also known as moral philosophy) is the branch of ] which addresses questions of morality. The word "ethics" is "commonly used interchangeably with 'morality'{{Nbsp}}... and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group, or individual."<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia |year=2015 |title=ethics |encyclopedia=] |publisher=] |last=Deigh |first=John |editor-last=Audi |editor-first=Robert |editor-link=Robert Audi |edition=3rd |page=328 |doi=10.1017/CBO9781139057509 |isbn=9781139057509}}</ref> Likewise, certain types of ethical theories, especially ], sometimes distinguish between ethics and morality.
=== In-group and out-group ===
{{Expand section|date=June 2008}}


] introduced the ]: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law."]]
some observers hold that individuals apply distinct sets of moral rules to people depending on their membership of an "ingroup" (the individual and those they believe to be of the same culture or race) or an "outgroup" (people not entitled to be treated according to the same rules). Some biologists, anthropologists and ] believe this ingroup-outgroup discrimination has evolved because it enhances group survival. Gary R. Johnson and V.S. Falger have argued that ] and ] are forms of this ingroup/outgroup boundary. Jonathan Haidt has noted<ref>"When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize", Haidt and Graham (<a href="http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z">doi:10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z</a>)</ref> that experimental observation indicates an ingroup criterion provides one moral foundation substantially used by ]s, but far less so by ].
Philosopher ] writes that "Although the morality of people and their ethics amounts to the same thing, there is a usage that restricts morality to systems such as that of ], based on notions such as duty, obligation, and ] of conduct, reserving ethics for the more ] approach to practical reasoning, based on the notion of a ], and generally avoiding the separation of 'moral' considerations from other practical considerations."<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia |year=2008 |title=morality |encyclopedia=] |publisher=] |url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001/acref-9780199541430-e-2075 |last=Blackburn |first=Simon |author-link=Simon Blackburn |edition=2nd |page=241 |doi=10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001 |isbn=9780199541430}}</ref>


=== Comparing cultures === == Descriptive and normative ==
In its descriptive sense, "morality" refers to ], ] or social ] that are observed to be accepted by a significant number of individuals (not necessarily all) in a society. It does not connote objective claims of right or wrong, but only refers to claims of right and wrong that are seen to be made and to conflicts between different claims made. ] is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.<ref name="Gert">{{Cite book|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/|title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|last1=Gert|first1=Bernard|last2=Gert|first2=Joshua|chapter=The Definition of Morality |date=2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2020}}</ref>
Peterson and Seligman <ref>Peterson, Christopher, and Martin E. P. Seligman. ''Character Strengths and Virtues''. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.</ref> approach the anthropological view looking across cultures and across millennia. They conclude that certain virtues have prevailed in all cultures they examined. The major virtues they identified include ''wisdom / knowledge; courage; humanity; justice; temperance; and transcendence''. Each of these includes several divisions. For instance ''humanity'' includes ''love'', ''kindness'', and ''social intelligence''.


In its ] sense, "morality" refers to whatever (if anything) is ''actually'' right or wrong, which may be independent of the values or mores held by any particular peoples or cultures. ] is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.<ref name="Gert"/>
], author of '']'', tested members of different cultures with various ]s. One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend, a passenger riding in the car, lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian. Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations (from none to almost certain)<!-- , and in some cultures it mattered whether the pedestrian had died to how much assistance would be expected -->.


== Realism and anti-realism ==
== Evolutionary perspectives ==
Philosophical theories on the nature and origins of morality (that is, theories of ]) are broadly divided into two classes:
{{Expand section|date=June 2008}}
* ] is the class of theories which hold that there are true moral statements that report objective moral facts. For example, while they might concede that forces of social ] significantly shape individuals' "moral" decisions, they deny that those cultural ] and ] define morally right behavior. This may be the philosophical view propounded by ], but not all moral realists accept that position (e.g. ]).<ref>], "To what extent is moral judgment natural?", ''European Review'' (GB), 2004, 12(2): 179–83</ref>
{{See also|Evolution of morality}}
* Moral ], on the other hand, holds that moral statements either fail or do not even attempt to report objective moral facts. Instead, they hold that moral sentences are either categorically false claims of objective moral facts (]); claims about subjective attitudes rather than objective facts (]); or else do not attempt to describe the world at all but rather something else, like an expression of an emotion or the issuance of a command (]).
:''Further:]


Some forms of non-cognitivism and ethical ], while considered anti-realist in the robust sense used here, are considered realist in the sense synonymous with ]. For example, ] is a universalist form of non-cognitivism which claims that morality is derived from reasoning about implied imperatives, and ] and ] are universalist forms of ethical subjectivism which claim that morality is derived from the edicts of a god or the hypothetical decrees of a perfectly rational being, respectively.
The development of modern morality is a process closely tied to the ] of humanity, however its roots are probably to be found in our very nature. Some evolutionary biologists, particularly sociobiologists, believe that morality is a product of evolutionary forces acting at an individual level and also at the group level through ] (though to what degree this actually occurs is a controversial topic in evolutionary theory). Some sociobiologists contend that the set of behaviors that constitute morality evolved largely because they provided possible survival and/or reproductive benefits (i.e. increased evolutionary success). Humans consequently evolved "pro-social" emotions, such as feelings of empathy or guilt, in response to these moral behaviors.

==Anthropology==
In this respect, morality is not absolute, but relative and constitutes any set of behaviors that encourage human cooperation based on their ideology. Biologists contend that all social animals, from ants to elephants, have modified their behaviors, by restraining selfishness in order to make group living worthwhile. Human morality, though sophisticated and complex relative to other animals, is essentially a natural phenomenon that evolved to restrict excessive individualism and foster human cooperation.

<ref name="shermer">{{cite book
=== Morality with practical reasoning ===
|title=]
Practical reason is necessary for the moral agency but it is not a sufficient condition for moral agency.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Ezedike |first=Edward Uzoma |date=2020-01-02 |title=Morality within the limits of practical reason: a critique of Kant's concept of moral virtue |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/ijoes-11-2018-0171 |journal=International Journal of Ethics and Systems |volume=36 |issue=2 |pages=205–216 |doi=10.1108/ijoes-11-2018-0171 |issn=2514-9369 |s2cid=214501283}}</ref> Real life issues that need solutions do need both rationality and emotion to be sufficiently moral. One uses rationality as a pathway to the ultimate decision, but the environment and emotions towards the environment at the moment must be a factor for the result to be truly moral, as morality is subject to culture. Something can only be morally acceptable if the culture as a whole has accepted this to be true. Both practical reason and relevant emotional factors are acknowledged as significant in determining the morality of a decision.<ref>{{Citation |last=Richardson |first=Henry S. |title=Moral Reasoning |date=2018 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/reasoning-moral/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Fall 2018 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2022-05-04}}</ref>{{POV statement|date=April 2021}}
|isbn=0805075208

===Tribal and territorial===
] made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality.<ref name="Green">Green, Celia (2004). ''Letters from Exile: Observations on a Culture in Decline''. Oxford: Oxford Forum. Chapters I–XX.</ref> She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive: it defines a person's territory, including his or her property and dependents, which is not to be damaged or interfered with. Apart from these proscriptions, territorial morality is permissive, allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another. By contrast, tribal morality is prescriptive, imposing the norms of the collective on the individual. These norms will be arbitrary, culturally dependent and 'flexible', whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute, such as ]'s ']' and ]'s ]. Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property, and the ascendancy of contract over status.

===In-group and out-group===
{{main|In-group and out-group}}
Some observers hold that individuals apply distinct sets of moral rules to people depending on their membership of an "]" (the individual and those they believe to be of the same group) or an "out-group" (people not entitled to be treated according to the same rules). Some biologists, anthropologists and ] believe this in-group/out-group discrimination has evolved because it enhances group survival. This belief has been confirmed by simple computational models of evolution.<ref>T.R. Shultz, M. Hartshorn, and A. Kaznatcheev. {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120327152454/http://141.14.165.6/CogSci09/papers/500/ |date=2012-03-27 }} Proceedings of the 31st annual conference of the cognitive science society, 2009.</ref> In simulations this discrimination can result in both unexpected cooperation towards the in-group and irrational hostility towards the out-group.<ref>Kaznatcheev, A. (2010, March). . In ''Complex Adaptive Systems – AAAI Fall Symposium''. Butiz wintrades</ref> Gary R. Johnson and V.S. Falger have argued that ] and ] are forms of this in-group/out-group boundary. Jonathan Haidt has noted<ref name = haidt>{{cite journal | doi = 10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z | title = When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize | year = 2007 | last1 = Haidt | first1 = Jonathan | last2 = Graham | first2 = Jesse | journal = Social Justice Research | volume = 20 | pages = 98–116 | url = http://faculty.virginia.edu/haidtlab/articles/haidt.graham.2007.when-morality-opposes-justice.pub041.pdf | citeseerx = 10.1.1.385.3650 | s2cid = 6824095| access-date = 2014-09-26 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20140830110131/http://faculty.virginia.edu/haidtlab/articles/haidt.graham.2007.when-morality-opposes-justice.pub041.pdf | archive-date = 2014-08-30 | url-status = dead }}</ref> that experimental observation indicating an in-group criterion provides one moral foundation substantially used by ]s, but far less so by ].

In-group preference is also helpful at the individual level for the passing on of one's genes. For example, a mother who favors her own children more highly than the children of other people will give greater resources to her children than she will to strangers', thus heightening her children's chances of survival and her own gene's chances of being perpetuated. Due to this, within a population, there is substantial ] exerted toward this kind of self-interest, such that eventually, all parents wind up favoring their own children (the in-group) over other children (the out-group).

===Comparing cultures===
Peterson and Seligman<ref>Peterson, Christopher, and Martin E. P. Seligman. ''Character Strengths and Virtues''. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.</ref> approach the anthropological view looking across cultures, geo-cultural areas and across millennia. They conclude that certain virtues have prevailed in all cultures they examined. The major virtues they identified include ''wisdom / knowledge; courage; ]; justice; temperance; and transcendence''. Each of these include several divisions. For instance ''humanity'' includes '']'', '']'', and ''social intelligence''.

Still, others theorize that morality is not always absolute, contending that moral issues often differ along cultural lines. A 2014 PEW research study among several nations illuminates significant cultural differences among issues commonly related to morality, including divorce, extramarital affairs, homosexuality, gambling, abortion, alcohol use, contraceptive use, and premarital sex. Each of the 40 countries in this study has a range of percentages according to what percentage of each country believes the common moral issues are acceptable, unacceptable, or not moral issues at all. Each percentage regarding the significance of the moral issue varies greatly on the culture in which the moral issue is presented.<ref>{{cite web |website=PewResearch.org |url=http://www.pewglobal.org/2014/04/15/global-morality/table/alcohol-use/ |title=Global Views on Morality|date=15 April 2014 }}</ref>

Advocates of a theory known as moral relativism subscribe to the notion that moral virtues are right or wrong only within the context of a certain standpoint (e.g., cultural community). In other words, what is morally acceptable in one culture may be taboo in another. They further contend that no moral virtue can objectively be proven right or wrong <ref>(Westacott, https://www.iep.utm.edu/moral-re/#SH2g).</ref> Critics of moral relativism point to historical atrocities such as infanticide, slavery, or genocide as counter arguments, noting the difficulty in accepting these actions simply through cultural lenses.

], author of ''Did the Pedestrian Die?'', tested members of different cultures with various ]s. One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend, a passenger riding in the car, lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian. Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations, from none to definite.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=BAYKAQAAMAAJ|title=Did the Pedestrian Die: Insights from the World's Greatest Culture!|last=Trompenaars|first=Fons|date=2003|publisher=Wiley|isbn=978-1841124360|language=en}}</ref>

Anthropologists from Oxford's Institute of Cognitive & Evolutionary Anthropology (part of the School of Anthropology & Museum Ethnography) analysed ethnographic accounts of ethics from 60 societies, comprising over 600,000 words from over 600 sources and discovered what they believe to be seven universal moral rules: help your family, help your group, return favours, be brave, defer to superiors, divide resources fairly, and respect others' property.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Curry |first1=Oliver Scott |last2=Mullins |first2=Daniel Austin |last3=Whitehouse |first3=Harvey |title=Is It Good to Cooperate? Testing the Theory of Morality-as-Cooperation in 60 Societies |journal=] |date=2019 |volume=60 |issue=1 |pages=47–69 |doi=10.1086/701478|s2cid=150324056 |url=https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:8dd8d82d-3829-4857-bcf4-eebf196d11be }}</ref><ref>{{cite news |title=Seven moral rules found all around the world {{!}} University of Oxford |url=https://www.ox.ac.uk/news/2019-02-11-seven-moral-rules-found-all-around-world |work=www.ox.ac.uk |date=11 February 2019 |language=en}}</ref>

==Evolution==
{{See also|Altruism#Evolutionary explanations|Evolution of morality|Evolutionary ethics}}

The development of modern morality is a process closely tied to ]. Some ], particularly ], believe that morality is a product of evolutionary forces acting at an individual level and also at the group level through ] (although to what degree this actually occurs is a controversial topic in evolutionary theory). Some sociobiologists contend that the set of behaviors that constitute morality evolved largely because they provided possible survival or reproductive benefits (i.e. increased evolutionary success). Humans consequently evolved "pro-social" emotions, such as feelings of empathy or guilt, in response to these moral behaviors.

On this understanding, moralities are sets of self-perpetuating and biologically driven behaviors which encourage human ]. Biologists contend that all social animals, from ants to elephants, have modified their behaviors, by restraining immediate ] in order to improve their evolutionary fitness. Human morality, although sophisticated and complex relative to the moralities of other animals, is essentially a natural phenomenon that evolved to restrict excessive individualism that could undermine a group's cohesion and thereby reducing the individuals' fitness.<ref name="shermer">{{Cite book
|title=The Science of Good and Evil
|isbn=978-0-8050-7520-5
|last=Shermer |last=Shermer
|first=Michael |first=Michael
|authorlink=Michael Shermer |author-link=Michael Shermer
|chapter=Transcendent Morality |chapter=Transcendent Morality
|chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=eevvWAcMBaAC&pg=PA19&dq=shermer+exegesis&ei=EIC1SNOiE4uWyATTmaj2Bg&sig=ACfU3U3KFh8kP8Ns8-YgpqBuI03N1JrpEg |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eevvWAcMBaAC&q=shermer+exegesis&pg=PA19
|title-link=The Science of Good and Evil
|date=2004
|publisher=Macmillan
}}</ref> }}</ref>


On this view, moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction (]). Examples: the ] is selected for because it improves the survival of offspring; the ], where close proximity during early years reduces mutual sexual attraction, underpins ] because it decreases the likelihood of genetically risky behaviour such as ]. On this view, moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction (]). Examples: the ] is selected for because it improves the survival of offspring; the ], where close proximity during early years reduces mutual sexual attraction, underpins ] because it decreases the likelihood of genetically risky behaviour such as ].


<!-- kinship altruism theory --> <!-- kinship altruism theory -->
Line 49: Line 85:
<!-- reputation theory --> <!-- reputation theory -->
<!-- reciprocity theory --> <!-- reciprocity theory -->
The phenomenon of ']' in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality. Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources, especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably. For example, some ]s fail to feed on prey on any given night while others consume a surplus. Bats that have successfully fed then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a ] from starvation. Since these animals live in close-knit groups over many years, an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry (Wilkinson, 1984) The phenomenon of ] in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality. Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources, especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably. For example, some ]s fail to feed on prey some nights while others manage to consume a surplus. Bats that did eat will then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a ] from starvation. Since these animals live in close-knit groups over many years, an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry (Wilkinson, 1984)


Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce (2009) have argued that morality is a suite of behavioral capacities likely shared by all mammals living in complex social groups (e.g., wolves, coyotes, elephants, dolphins, rats, chimpanzees). They define morality as "a suite of interrelated other-regarding behaviors that cultivate and regulate complex interactions within social groups." This suite of behaviors includes empathy, reciprocity, altruism, cooperation, and a sense of fairness. <ref>Bekoff, Marc and Jessica Pierce ''Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals'' (Chicago, The University of Chicago Press 2009)</ref> In related work, it has been convincingly demonstrated that chimpanzees show empathy for each other in a wide variety of contexts.<ref>{{cite journal |last=O’Connell |first= Sanjida |authorlink= |coauthors= |year= 1995|month= July|title= Empathy in chimpanzees: Evidence for theory of mind? |journal= Primates|volume= 36|issue= 3|pages= 397–410|issn= 0032-8332 |url= |accessdate= 2007-11-08 |quote=|doi= 10.1007/BF02382862 }}</ref> They also possess the ability to engage in deception, and a level of social 'politics'<ref>.</ref> prototypical of our own tendencies for ] and ] management. Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce (2009) have argued that morality is a suite of behavioral capacities likely shared by all mammals living in complex social groups (e.g., wolves, coyotes, elephants, dolphins, rats, chimpanzees). They define morality as "a suite of interrelated other-regarding behaviors that cultivate and regulate complex interactions within social groups." This suite of behaviors includes empathy, reciprocity, altruism, cooperation, and a sense of fairness.<ref>Bekoff, Marc and Jessica Pierce ''Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals'' (Chicago, The University of Chicago Press 2009)</ref> In related work, it has been convincingly demonstrated that chimpanzees show ] for each other in a wide variety of contexts.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=O'Connell |first= Sanjida |date=July 1995|title= Empathy in chimpanzees: Evidence for theory of mind? |journal= Primates|volume= 36|issue= 3|pages= 397–410|issn= 0032-8332 |doi= 10.1007/BF02382862 |s2cid= 41356986 }}</ref> They also possess the ability to engage in deception, and a level of social politics<ref>{{cite book|title = Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals|last = de Waal|first = Frans|date = 1997|publisher = Harvard University Press |isbn = 978-0674356610}}</ref> prototypical of our own tendencies for ] and ].
<!-- ] Johnathan Haidt --> <!-- ] Johnathan Haidt -->


Christopher Boehm (1982) has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout ] evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons. Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size, and in particular the development of ] abilities. ] in '']'' suggested that our morality is a result of our biological evolutionary history and that the ] helps describe how morality evolves from biological and cultural origins and evolves with time within a culture. Christopher Boehm (1982)<ref>{{cite journal|last=Boehm|first=Christopher|title=The evolutionary development of morality as an effect of dominance behaviour and conflict interference|journal=Journal of Social and Biological Sciences|year=1982|volume=5|issue=4 |pages=413–22|doi= 10.1016/s0140-1750(82)92069-3}}</ref> has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout ] evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons. Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size, and in particular the development of ] abilities.


==Psychology==
== Neuroscientific and psychiatric perspectives ==
{{Main|Moral psychology}}
=== Mirror-neurons ===
{{See also|Kohlberg's stages of moral development|Jean Piaget#Education and development of morality}}
Research on '']s'', since their discovery in 1996<ref>Giacomo Rizzolatti et al. (1996). ''Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions'', Cognitive Brain Research 3 131–141</ref>, suggests that they may have a role to play not only in action understanding, but also in emotion sharing ]. Cognitive neuro-scientist ] thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another individual is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior, and ultimately, morality.<ref></ref> The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristics of ]y, and this would appear to lend support to Decety's view.<ref>{{cite journal |author=de Wied M, Goudena PP, Matthys W |title=Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders |journal=Journal of child psychology and psychiatry, and allied disciplines |volume=46 |issue=8 |pages=867–80 |year=2005 |pmid=16033635 |doi=10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00389.x}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |author=Fernandez YM, Marshall WL |title=Victim empathy, social self-esteem, and psychopathy in rapists |journal=Sexual abuse : a journal of research and treatment |volume=15 |issue=1 |pages=11–26 |year=2003 |pmid=12616926 |doi=10.1023/A:1020611606754}}</ref>
]'s model of moral development]]


In modern ], morality is sometimes considered to change through personal development. Several psychologists have produced theories on the development of morals, usually going through stages of different morals. ], ], and ] have cognitive-developmental approaches to ]; to these theorists morality forms in a series of constructive stages or domains. In the ] approach established by ], moral development occurs in the context of caring, mutually responsive relationships which are based on ], particularly in parenting but also in social relationships generally.<ref>Gilligan and Kohlberg: "Implications for Moral Theory" Author(s): Lawrence A. Blum
===Neuroimaging===
Source: ''Ethics'', Vol. 98, No. 3 (Apr., 1988), pp. 472–91</ref> ] such as ] and ] emphasize social and emotional development based on biology, such as ]. ] theorists, such as ] and ], see moral commitment as arising from the development of a self-identity that is defined by moral purposes: this moral self-identity leads to a sense of responsibility to pursue such purposes. Of historical interest in psychology are the theories of ]s such as ], who believe that moral development is the product of aspects of the ] as guilt-shame avoidance. Theories of moral development therefore tend to regard it as positive moral development: the higher stages are morally higher, though this, naturally, involves a circular argument. The higher stages are better because they are higher, but the better higher because they are better.


As an alternative to viewing morality as an individual trait, some sociologists as well as social- and discursive psychologists have taken upon themselves to study the ''in-vivo'' aspects of morality by examining how persons conduct themselves in social interaction.<ref>{{cite journal | author = Bergmann Jörg | year = 1998 | title = Introduction:Morality in discourse | journal = Research on Language and Social Interaction | volume = 31 | issue = 3/4| pages = 279–74 | doi = 10.1080/08351813.1998.9683594 }}</ref><ref>Jörg Bergmann "Veiled morality: Notes on discretion in psychiatry." In {{cite book |title= Talk at work: Interaction in institutional settings. |editor1-first= Paul|editor1-last= Drew|editor2-first= John | editor2-last= Heritage|year= 1992|publisher= Cambridge University Press|location= Cambridge |pages= 137–62}}</ref><ref>Lena Jayyusi "Values and moral judgment: Communicative praxis as moral order." In {{cite book |title= Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences. |editor1-first= Graham|editor1-last= Button|year= 1991|publisher= Cambridge University Press|location= Cambridge |pages= 227–51}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | author1 = Cromdal Jakob | author2 = Michael Tholander | year = 2014 | title = Morality in professional practice | url = http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:liu:diva-116647| journal = Journal of Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice | volume = 9| issue = 2| pages = 155–64 | doi = 10.1558/japl.v9i2.25734}}</ref>
The explicit making of moral right and wrong judgments links to activation in the ] while as the
intuitive reactions to situations containing implicit moral issues activates the ] area.<ref>Harenski CL, Antonenko O, Shane MS, Kiehl KA. (2010). A functional imaging investigation of moral deliberation and moral intuition. Neuroimage. 49: 2707–2716. {{doi|10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.10.062}} PMID 19878727</ref>


A new study analyses the common perception of a decline in morality in societies worldwide and throughout history. Adam M. Mastroianni and Daniel T. Gilbert present a series of studies indicating that the perception of moral decline is an illusion and easily produced, with implications for misallocation of resources, underuse of social support, and social influence. To begin with, the authors demonstrate that people in no less than 60 nations hold the belief that morality is deteriorating continuously, and this conviction has been present for the last 70 years. Subsequently, they indicate that people ascribe this decay to the declining morality of individuals as they age and the succeeding generations. Thirdly, the authors demonstrate that people's evaluations of the morality of their peers have not decreased over time, indicating that the belief in moral decline is an illusion. Lastly, the authors explain a basic psychological mechanism that uses two well-established phenomena (distorted exposure to information and distorted memory of information) to cause the illusion of moral decline. The authors present studies that validate some of the predictions about the circumstances in which the perception of moral decline is attenuated, eliminated, or reversed (e.g., when participants are asked about the morality of people closest to them or people who lived before they were born).<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Mastroianni |first1=Adam M. |last2=Gilbert |first2=Daniel T. |title=The illusion of moral decline |journal=] |date=2023 |volume=618 |issue=7966 |pages=782–789 |doi=10.1038/s41586-023-06137-x |pmid=37286595 |pmc=10284688 |bibcode=2023Natur.618..782M |doi-access=free}}</ref>
==Psychological perspectives==
{{See|Jean Piaget#Education and development of morality}}
{{See|Kohlberg's stages of moral development}}
{{See|Ethics of care}}


===Moral cognition===
In modern ], morality is considered to change through personal development. A number of psychologists have produced theories on the development of morals, usually going through stages of different morals. ], ], and ] have cognitive-developmental approaches to moral development; to these theorists morality forms in a series of constructive stages or domains. ] such as ] and ] emphasize social and emotional development based on biology, such as ]. Moral identity theorists, such as ] and ], see moral commitment as arising from the development of a self-identity that is defined by moral purposes: this moral self-identity leads to a sense of responsibility to pursue such purposes. Of historical interest in psychology are the theories of ]s such as ], who believe that moral development is the product of aspects of the ] as guilt-shame avoidance.


Moral cognition refers to cognitive processes implicated in moral judgment and decision making, and moral action. It consists of several domain-general cognitive processes, ranging from perception of a morally salient stimulus to reasoning when faced with a moral dilemma. While it is important to mention that there is not a single cognitive faculty dedicated exclusively to moral cognition,<ref name="Sinnott-Armstrong2012">{{cite journal |last1=Sinnott-Armstrong |first1=Walter |last2=Wheatley |first2=Thalia |title=The Disunity of Morality and Why it Matters to Philosophy |journal=Monist |date=2012 |volume=95 |issue=3 |pages=355–77 |doi=10.5840/monist201295319|doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Sinnott-Armstrong2013">{{cite journal |last1=Sinnott-Armstrong |first1=Walter |last2=Wheatley |first2=Thalia |title=Are moral judgments unified? |journal=Philosophical Psychology |date=13 February 2013 |volume=27 |issue=4 |pages=451–74 |doi=10.1080/09515089.2012.736075|s2cid=143876741 }}</ref> characterizing the contributions of domain-general processes to moral behavior is a critical scientific endeavor to understand how morality works and how it can be improved.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Young |first1=Liane |last2=Dungan |first2=James |title=Where in the brain is morality? Everywhere and maybe nowhere |journal=Social Neuroscience |date=January 2012 |volume=7 |issue=1 |pages=1–10 |doi=10.1080/17470919.2011.569146|pmid=21590587 |s2cid=14074566 }}</ref>
== Morality and politics ==
If morality is the answer to the question 'how ought we to live' at the individual level, politics can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level. It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics. ] and ] have studied the differences between ] and ], in this regard.<ref name="Haidt">] and Graham, Jesse (2006). (DOC) ].</ref><ref></ref><ref></ref> Haidt found that Americans who identified as liberals tended to value care and fairness higher than loyalty, respect and purity. Self-identified conservative Americans valued care and fairness less and the remaining three values more. Both groups gave care the highest over-all weighting, but conservatives valued fairness the lowest, whereas liberals valued purity the lowest. Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geohistorical factors, with conservatism strongest in closely knit, ethnically homogenous communities, in contrast to ]-cities, where the cultural mix is greater, thus requiring more liberalism.


Cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists investigate the inputs to these cognitive processes and their interactions, as well as how these contribute to moral behavior by running controlled experiments.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Yoder |first1=Keith J. |last2=Decety |first2=Jean |title=The neuroscience of morality and social decision-making |journal=Psychology, Crime & Law |date=12 December 2017 |volume=24 |issue=3 |pages=279–95 |doi=10.1080/1068316X.2017.1414817|pmid=30766017 |pmc=6372234 }}</ref> In these experiments putatively moral versus nonmoral stimuli are compared to each other, while controlling for other variables such as content or working memory load. Often, the differential neural response to specifically moral statements or scenes, are examined using functional ] experiments.
Group morality develops from shared ]s and ]s and is often codified to regulate behavior within a ] or community. Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral. Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess "moral fiber", whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially ]. The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality; an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community (a positive example would be the function of ] reform in reviving monasticism; a negative example would be the role of the ] in the subjugation of China to European interests). Within ] movements, there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality, regardless of in what it consists.
Political Morality is also relevant to the behaviour internationally of national governments, and to the support they receive from their host population. ] states that <ref name="Zmag">{{cite web |url=http://www.zmag.org/znet/viewArticle/11934 |title=Terror and Just Response |publisher=ZNet |last=Chomsky |first=Noam |date=2002-07-02}}</ref><ref name="counterpunch">{{cite journal |url=http://www.counterpunch.org/schivone08032007.html <!-- alternate: http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20070803.htm -->|title=On Responsibility, War Guilt and Intellectuals |last=Schivone |first=Gabriel Matthew |date=2007-08-03 |journal=] }} Interview.</ref>


Critically, the specific cognitive processes that are involved depend on the prototypical situation that a person encounters.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Monin |first1=Benoît |last2=Pizarro |first2=David A. |last3=Beer |first3=Jennifer S. |title=Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of moral judgment and the reason-affect debate. |journal=Review of General Psychology |date=2007 |volume=11 |issue=2 |pages=99–111 |doi=10.1037/1089-2680.11.2.99|s2cid=144286153 }}</ref> For instance, while situations that require an active decision on a moral dilemma may require active reasoning, an immediate reaction to a shocking moral violation may involve quick, affect-laden processes. Nonetheless, certain cognitive skills such as being able to attribute mental states—beliefs, intents, desires, emotions to oneself, and others is a common feature of a broad range of prototypical situations. In line with this, a meta-analysis found overlapping activity between ] and ] tasks, suggesting a shared neural network for both tasks.<ref name="ReferenceA">{{cite journal |last1=Sevinc |first1=Gunes |last2=Spreng |first2=R. Nathan |title=Contextual and Perceptual Brain Processes Underlying Moral Cognition: A Quantitative Meta-Analysis of Moral Reasoning and Moral Emotions |journal=PLOS ONE |date=4 February 2014 |volume=9 |issue=2 |page=e87427 |doi=10.1371/journal.pone.0087427|pmid=24503959 |pmc=3913597 |bibcode=2014PLoSO...987427S |doi-access=free }}</ref> The results of this meta-analysis, however, also demonstrated that the processing of moral input is affected by task demands.
{{cquote|... if we adopt the principle of universality : if an action is right (or wrong) for others, it is right (or wrong) for us. Those who do not rise to the minimal moral level of applying to themselves the standards they apply to others -- more stringent ones, in fact -- plainly cannot be taken seriously when they speak of appropriateness of response; or of right and wrong, good and evil.}}


Regarding the issues of morality in video games, some scholars believe that because players appear in video games as actors, they maintain a distance between their sense of self and the role of the game in terms of imagination. Therefore, the decision-making and moral behavior of players in the game are not representing player's Moral dogma.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Bartel|first=Christopher|date=2015|title=Free will and moral responsibility in video games|url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/s10676-015-9383-8|journal=Ethics and Information Technology|language=en|volume=17|issue=4|pages=285–293|doi=10.1007/s10676-015-9383-8|s2cid=15800963|issn=1388-1957}}</ref>
{{cquote|In fact, one of the, maybe the most, elementary of moral principles is that of universality, that is, If something's right for me, it's right for you; if it's wrong for you, it's wrong for me. Any moral code that is even worth looking at has that at its core somehow.}}


It has been recently found that moral judgment consists in concurrent evaluations of three different components that align with precepts from three dominant moral theories (virtue ethics, ], and consequentialism): the character of a person (Agent-component, A); their actions (Deed-component, D); and the consequences brought about in the situation (Consequences-component, C).<ref>{{Cite journal |doi = 10.1371/journal.pone.0204631|title = Deciphering moral intuition: How agents, deeds, and consequences influence moral judgment|year = 2018|last1 = Dubljević|first1 = Veljko|last2 = Sattler|first2 = Sebastian|last3 = Racine|first3 = Eric|journal = PLOS ONE|volume = 13|issue = 10|page = e0204631|pmid = 30273370|pmc = 6166963|bibcode = 2018PLoSO..1304631D|doi-access = free}}</ref> This, implies that various inputs of the situation a person encounters affect moral cognition.
== Moral codes ==
Codified morality is generally distinguished from ], another way for a community to define appropriate activity, by the former's derivation from ] or universal principles. In certain religious communities, the ] is said to provide these principles through ], sometimes in great detail. Such codes may be called laws, as in the ], or community morality may be defined through commentary on the texts of revelation, as in ]. Such codes are distinguished from legal or judicial ], including ], which are based on the accumulated traditions, decrees and legislation of a political authority, though these latter often invoke the authority of the moral law.


] distinguishes between two types of moral cognition: moral intuition and moral reasoning. Moral intuition involves the fast, automatic, and ] processes that result in an evaluative feeling of good-bad or like-dislike, ''without'' awareness of going through any steps. Conversely, moral reasoning does involve conscious mental activity to reach a moral judgment. Moral reasoning is controlled and less affective than moral intuition. When making moral judgments, humans perform moral reasoning to support their initial intuitive feeling. However, there are three ways humans can override their immediate intuitive response. The first way is conscious verbal reasoning (for example, examining costs and benefits). The second way is reframing a situation to see a new perspective or consequence, which triggers a different intuition. Finally, one can talk to other people which illuminates new arguments. In fact, interacting with other people is the cause of most moral change. <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Haidt |first=Jonathan |date=18 May 2007 |title=The New Synthesis in Moral Psychology |journal=Science |volume=316 |issue=5827 |pages=998–1002|doi=10.1126/science.1137651 |pmid=17510357 |bibcode=2007Sci...316..998H }}</ref>
Morality can also be seen as the collection of beliefs as to what constitutes a good life. Since throughout most of ] ], ]s have provided both visions and regulations for an ] life, morality is often confused with religious ]s. In secular communities, ] choices, which represent an ]'s conception of the good life, are often discussed in terms of "morality." Individuals sometimes feel that making an appropriate lifestyle choice invokes a true morality, and that accepted codes of conduct within their chosen community are fundamentally moral, even when such codes deviate from more general social principles.


==Neuroscience==
Moral codes are often complex definitions of moral and immoral that are based upon well-defined ]. Although some people might think that a moral code is simple, rarely is there anything simple about one's ], ], etc. or, for that matter, the judgment of those of others. The difficulty lies in the fact that morals are often part of a ] and more often than not about ] codes. Sometimes, moral codes give way to ]s, which couple penalties or corrective actions with particular practices. Note that while many legal codes are merely built on a foundation of religious and/or cultural moral codes, oftentimes they are one and the same.
{{anchor|Neuroscience of morality}}
{{see also|Science of morality|Neuromorality}}
The brain areas that are consistently involved when humans reason about moral issues have been investigated by multiple quantitative large-scale meta-analyses of the brain activity changes reported in the moral neuroscience literature.<ref name = Bzdok>{{cite journal|title=Bzdok, D. et al. Parsing the neural correlates of moral cognition: ALE meta-analysis on morality, theory of mind, and empathy. Brain Struct Funct, 2011 |date=2012-01-24 |doi=10.1007/s00429-012-0380-y |pmid=22270812 |volume=217 |issue=4 |journal=Brain Structure and Function |pages=783–96|last1=Bzdok |first1=Danilo |last2=Schilbach |first2=Leonhard |last3=Vogeley |first3=Kai |last4=Schneider |first4=Karla |last5=Laird |first5=Angela R |last6=Langner |first6=Robert |last7=Eickhoff |first7=Simon B |pmc=3445793}}</ref><ref name="ReferenceA"/><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Boccia |first1=M. |last2=Dacquino |first2=C. |last3=Piccardi |first3=L. |last4=Cordellieri |first4=P. |last5=Guariglia |first5=C. |last6=Ferlazzo |first6=F. |last7=Ferracuti |first7=S. |last8=Giannini |first8=A. M. |title=Neural foundation of human moral reasoning: an ALE meta-analysis about the role of personal perspective |journal=Brain Imaging and Behavior |date=25 January 2016 |volume=11 |issue=1 |pages=278–92 |doi=10.1007/s11682-016-9505-x |pmid=26809288 |s2cid=3984661 |url=http://www.springer.com/cda/content/document/cda_downloaddocument/Instructions+for+Authors.pdf?SGWID=0-0-45-1658265-p173667707 |access-date=23 September 2019 |archive-date=23 September 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190923130437/https://www.springer.com/cda/content/document/cda_downloaddocument/Instructions+for+Authors.pdf%3FSGWID=0-0-45-1658265-p173667707 |url-status=dead }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Eres |first1=Robert |last2=Louis |first2=Winnifred R. |last3=Molenberghs |first3=Pascal |title=Common and distinct neural networks involved in fMRI studies investigating morality: an ALE meta-analysis |journal=Social Neuroscience |date=27 July 2017 |volume=13 |issue=4 |pages=384–98 |doi=10.1080/17470919.2017.1357657|pmid=28724332 |s2cid=31749926 }}</ref> The neural network underlying moral decisions overlaps with the network pertaining to representing others' intentions (i.e., theory of mind) and the network pertaining to representing others' (vicariously experienced) emotional states (i.e., empathy). This supports the notion that moral reasoning is related to both seeing things from other persons' points of view and to grasping others' feelings. These results provide evidence that the neural network underlying moral decisions is probably domain-global (i.e., there might be no such things as a "moral module" in the human brain) and might be dissociable into cognitive and affective sub-systems.<ref name = Bzdok />


Cognitive neuroscientist ] thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another individual is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior, and ultimately, morality.<ref>{{Cite news| url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/05/27/AR2007052701056_pf.html | newspaper=The Washington Post | title=If It Feels Good to Be Good, It Might Be Only Natural | first=Shankar | last=Vedantam | access-date=2010-05-13}}</ref> The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristics of ]y, and this would appear to lend support to Decety's view.<ref>{{Cite journal|vauthors=de Wied M, Goudena PP, Matthys W |title=Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders |journal=Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, and Allied Disciplines |volume=46 |issue=8 |pages=867–80 |year=2005 |pmid=16033635 |doi=10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00389.x|hdl=1874/11212 |s2cid=45683502 |hdl-access=free }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|vauthors=Fernandez YM, Marshall WL |title=Victim empathy, social self-esteem, and psychopathy in rapists |journal=Sexual Abuse: A Journal of Research and Treatment |volume=15 |issue=1 |pages=11–26 |year=2003 |pmid=12616926 |doi=10.1023/A:1020611606754|s2cid=195293070 |doi-access=free }}</ref> Recently, drawing on empirical research in ], ], ], and psychopathy, Jean Decety argued that empathy and morality are neither systematically opposed to one another, nor inevitably complementary.<ref>{{cite book|last=Decety|first=Jean|series=Research and Perspectives in Neurosciences |title=New Frontiers in Social Neuroscience |date=November 1, 2014|chapter=The Neuroevolution of Empathy and Caring for Others: Why It Matters for Morality|chapter-url=https://www.researchgate.net/publication/287290900|volume=21|pages=127–151|doi=10.1007/978-3-319-02904-7_8|isbn=978-3-319-02903-0}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Decety|first1=J.|last2=Cowell|first2=J. M.|year=2014|title=The complex relation between morality and empathy|url=http://spihub.org/site/resource_files/publications/spi_wp_135_decety.pdf|journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences|volume=18|issue=7|pages=337–339|doi=10.1016/j.tics.2014.04.008|pmid=24972506|s2cid=355141 }}</ref>
Examples of moral codes include the ]; the ] and the ] of ] (''see'' ]); the ancient Egyptian code of ] ;the ] of ], ], and ]; the ] and ] of the ]; the ]; and the principle of the ].


===Brain areas===
Another related concept is the moral core which is assumed to be innate in each individual, to those who accept that differences between individuals are more important than posited Creators or their rules. This, in some religious systems and beliefs (e.g. ], ] and ]), is assumed to be the basis of all ] and thus moral choice. Moral codes as such are therefore seen as coercive—part of human ].


An essential, shared component of moral judgment involves the capacity to detect morally salient content within a given social context. Recent research implicated the ] in this initial detection of moral content.<ref name="ReferenceB">{{cite journal |last1=Sevinc |first1=Gunes |last2=Gurvit |first2=Hakan |last3=Spreng |first3=R. Nathan |title=Salience network engagement with the detection of morally laden information |journal=Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience |date=July 2017 |volume=12 |issue=7 |pages=1118–27 |doi=10.1093/scan/nsx035|pmid=28338944 |pmc=5490682 }}</ref> The salience network responds to behaviorally salient events <ref>{{cite journal |last1=Seeley |first1=W. W. |last2=Menon |first2=V. |last3=Schatzberg |first3=A. F. |last4=Keller |first4=J. |author5-link=Gary H. Glover |last5=Glover |first5=G. H. |last6=Kenna |first6=H. |last7=Reiss |first7=A. L. |last8=Greicius |first8=M. D. |title=Dissociable Intrinsic Connectivity Networks for Salience Processing and Executive Control |journal=Journal of Neuroscience |date=28 February 2007 |volume=27 |issue=9 |pages=2349–56 |doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5587-06.2007|pmid=17329432 |pmc=2680293 }}</ref> and may be critical to modulate downstream default and frontal control network interactions in the service of complex moral reasoning and decision-making processes.
== Moral psychology ==
=== Religiosity and morality ===
{{See also|Morality without religion}}
In the scientific literature, the degree of religiosity is generally found to be associated with higher ethical attitudes.<ref>As is expressed in the review of literature on this topic by: {{cite journal |author=Conroy, S.J. and Emerson, T.L.N. |title= | journal=Journal of Business Ethics |year=2004 | volume=50 | number=4 |pages=383--396 | doi = 10.1023/B:BUSI.0000025040.41263.09}} DOI:10.1023/B:BUSI.0000025040.41263.09</ref> Although a recent study by ] published in the ''Journal of Religion and Society'' argues for a positive ] between the degree of ''public religiosity'' in a society and certain measures of dysfunction <ref>{{cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html| journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look|first=Gregory S.|last=Paul |location=Baltimore, Maryland|year=2005| volume=7}}</ref>, an analysis published later in the same journal contends that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions to be taken from the research.<ref>{{cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2006/2006-1.html| journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Religiosity, Secularism, and Social Health|author=Gerson Moreno-Riaño| coauthors=Mark Caleb Smith, Thomas Mach|location=Cedarville University|year=2006| volume=8}}</ref> In another response, Gary Jensen builds on and refines Paul's study.<ref name="Jensen">Gary F. Jensen (2006) Department of Sociology, Vanderbilt University ''Religious Cosmologies and Homicide Rates among Nations: A Closer Look'' http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2006/2006-7.html http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/pdf/2006-7.pdf Journal of Religion and Society, Volume 8, ISSN 1522-5658 http://purl.org/JRS </ref> His conclusion, after carrying out elaborate multivariate statistical studies, is that a complex relationship exists between religiosity and homicide with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it." Meanwhile, other studies seem to show positive links in the relationship between ]<ref>KERLEY, KENT R., MATTHEWS, TODD L. & BLANCHARD, TROY C. (2005) Religiosity, Religious Participation, and Negative Prison Behaviors. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion '''44''' (4), 443–457. {{doi|10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00296.x}}</ref><ref>SAROGLOU, VASSILIS, PICHON, ISABELLE, TROMPETTE, LAURENCE, VERSCHUEREN, MARIJKE & DERNELLE, REBECCA (2005) Prosocial Behavior and Religion: New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion '''44''' (3), 323–348. {{doi|10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00289.x}}</ref><ref>Regnerus, Mark D. & Burdette, Amy (2006)
RELIGIOUS CHANGE AND ADOLESCENT FAMILY DYNAMICS. The Sociological Quarterly '''47''' (1), 175–194. {{doi|10.1111/j.1533-8525.2006.00042.x}}</ref>—for example, surveys suggesting a positive connection between faith and altruism.<ref>eg by ] showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations</ref> Modern research in ] also acknowledges an ''inverse'' relationship between religion and crime,<ref>As is stated in: Doris C. Chu (2007). Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 2007; 34; 661 originally published online Mar 7, 2007; DOI: 10.1177/0093854806293485</ref> with many studies establishing this beneficial connection (though some claim it is a modest one).<ref>
For example:


The explicit making of moral right and wrong judgments coincides with activation in the ] (VMPC), a region involved in valuation, while intuitive reactions to situations containing implicit moral issues activates the ] area, a region that plays a key role in understanding intentions and beliefs.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Harenski | first1 = CL | last2 = Antonenko | first2 = O | last3 = Shane | first3 = MS | last4 = Kiehl | first4 = KA. | year = 2010 | title = A functional imaging investigation of moral deliberation and moral intuition | journal = NeuroImage | volume = 49 | issue = 3| pages = 2707–16 | doi = 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.10.062 | pmid = 19878727 | pmc = 4270295 }}</ref><ref name="ReferenceB"/>
* Albrecht, S. I., Chadwick, B. A., & Alcorn, D. S. (1977). Religiosity and deviance:Application of an attitude-behavior contingent consistency model. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 16, 263–274.
* Burkett, S.,& White, M. (1974). Hellfire and delinquency:Another look. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion,13,455–462.
* Chard-Wierschem, D. (1998). In pursuit of the “true” relationship: A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse. Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Dissertation.
* Cochran, J. K.,& Akers, R. L. (1989). Beyond hellfire:An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 26, 198–225.
* Evans, T. D.,Cullen, F. T.,Burton, V. S.,Jr.,Dunaway, R. G.,Payne, G. L.,& Kethineni, S. R. (1996). Religion, social bonds, and delinquency. Deviant Behavior, 17, 43–70.
* Grasmick, H. G., Bursik, R. J., & Cochran, J. K. (1991). “Render unto Caesar what is Caesar’s”: Religiosity and taxpayer’s inclinations to cheat. The Sociological Quarterly, 32, 251–266.
* Higgins, P. C., & Albrecht, G. L. (1977). Hellfire and delinquency revisited. Social Forces, 55, 952–958.
* Johnson, B. R.,Larson, D. B.,DeLi,S.,& Jang, S. J. (2000). Escaping from the crime of inner cities:Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth. Justice Quarterly, 17, 377–391.
* Johnson, R. E., Marcos, A. C., & Bahr, S. J. (1987). The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use. Criminology, 25, 323–340.
* Powell, K. (1997). Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner-city youths. Family and Community Health, 20, 38–47.


Stimulation of the VMPC by ], or neurological lesion, has been shown to inhibit the ability of human subjects to take into account intent when forming a moral judgment. According to such investigations, TMS did not disrupt participants' ability to make any moral judgment. On the contrary, moral judgments of intentional harms and non-harms were unaffected by TMS to either the RTPJ or the control site; presumably, however, people typically make moral judgments of intentional harms by considering not only the action's harmful outcome but the agent's intentions and beliefs. So why were moral judgments of intentional harms not affected by TMS to the RTPJ? One possibility is that moral judgments typically reflect a weighted function of any morally relevant information that is available at the time. Based on this view, when information concerning the agent's belief is unavailable or degraded, the resulting moral judgment simply reflects a higher weighting of other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). Alternatively, following TMS to the RTPJ, moral judgments might be made via an abnormal processing route that does not take belief into account. On either account, when belief information is degraded or unavailable, moral judgments are shifted toward other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). For intentional harms and non-harms, however, the outcome suggests the same moral judgment as to the intention. Thus, the researchers suggest that TMS to the RTPJ disrupted the processing of negative beliefs for both intentional harms and attempted harms, but the current design allowed the investigators to detect this effect only in the case of attempted harms, in which the neutral outcomes did not afford harsh moral judgments on their own.<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Young |first1= Liane |last2= Camprodon |first2= Joan Albert |last3= Hauser |first3= Marc |last4= Pascual-Leone |first4= Alvaro |last5= Saxe |first5= Rebecca |year= 2010 |title= Disruption of the right temporoparietal junction with transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the role of beliefs in moral judgments |journal= ] |volume= 107 |issue= 15 |pages= 6753–58 |doi= 10.1073/pnas.0914826107 |pmid=20351278 |pmc=2872442|bibcode= 2010PNAS..107.6753Y |doi-access= free }}</ref>
</ref> Indeed, a meta-analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded, “religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals’ criminal behavior”.<ref>Baier, C. J.,& Wright, B. R. (2001). “If you love me, keep my commandments”:A meta-analysis of the effect of religion on crime. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency,38,3–21.</ref>


Similarly, individuals with a lesion of the VMPC judge an action purely on its outcome and are unable to take into account the intent of that action.<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Young |first1= Liane |last2= Bechara |first2= Antoine |last3= Tranel |first3= Daniel |last4= Damasio |first4= Hanna |last5= Hauser |first5= Marc |last6= Damasio |first6= Antonio |year= 2010 |title= Damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex impairs judgment of harmful intent |journal= Neuron |volume= 65 |issue= 6 |pages= 845–51 |doi= 10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.003 |pmid=20346759 |pmc=3085837}}</ref>
=== Religion as a source of moral authority ===
{{Expand section|date=June 2008}}


==Genetics==
{{Main|Euthyphro dilemma|Divine command theory}}
{{expand section|date=May 2022}}
{{See also|Argument from inconsistent revelations|Criticism of religion}}
Moral intuitions may have genetic bases. A 2022 study conducted by scholars Michael Zakharin and ], and published by the '']'', found that moral foundations have significant genetic bases.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Zakharin |first1=Michael |last2=Bates |first2=Timothy C |date=2022-05-26 |title=Testing heritability of moral foundations: Common pathway models support strong heritability for the five moral foundations |url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/08902070221103957 |journal=European Journal of Personality |volume=37 |issue=4 |language=en |pages=485–497 |doi=10.1177/08902070221103957 |s2cid=249115484 |issn=0890-2070}}</ref> Another study, conducted by Smith and Hatemi, similarly found significant evidence in support of moral heritability by looking at and comparing the answers of moral dilemmas between twins.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Smith |first1=Kevin |last2=Hatemi |first2=Peter K. |date=December 2020 |title=Are Moral Intuitions Heritable? |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/s12110-020-09380-7 |journal=Human Nature |language=en |volume=31 |issue=4 |pages=406–420 |doi=10.1007/s12110-020-09380-7 |pmid=33420605 |s2cid=231202698 |issn=1045-6767}}</ref>


Genetics play a role in influencing prosocial behaviors and moral decision-making. Genetics contribute to the development and expression of certain traits and behaviors, including those related to morality. However, it is important to note that while genetics play a role in shaping certain aspects of moral behavior, morality itself is a multifaceted concept that encompasses cultural, societal, and personal influences as well.
Many religions provide moral guidelines for their followers. They believe that God has instructed them with a way to live, and that following these "rules" will lead to oneness with God.

==Politics==
If morality is the answer to the question 'how ought we to live' at the individual level, ] can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level, though the political sphere raises additional problems and challenges.<ref>See Weber, Eric Thomas. 2011. '''' (London: Continuum).</ref> It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics. ], authored by ] and colleagues,<ref name="Haidt2004">{{cite journal |last1=Haidt |first1=Jonathan |last2=Joseph |first2=Craig |title=Intuitive ethics: how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues |journal=Daedalus |date=September 2004 |volume=133 |issue=4 |pages=55–66 |doi=10.1162/0011526042365555|s2cid=1574243 |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Graham2013">{{cite book | last1=Graham | first1=J. | last2=Haidt | first2=J. | last3=Koleva | first3=S. | last4=Motyl | first4=M. | last5=Iyer | first5=R. | last6=Wojcik | first6=S. | last7=Ditto | first7=P.H. | title=Moral Foundations Theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism | journal=Advances in Experimental Social Psychology | volume=47 | year=2013 | pages=55–130 | url=http://www-bcf.usc.edu/~jessegra/papers/GHKMIWD.inpress.MFT.AESP.pdf | doi=10.1016/b978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4 | isbn=978-0124072367 | s2cid=2570757 | access-date=2019-07-22 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170731065520/http://www-bcf.usc.edu/~jessegra/papers/GHKMIWD.inpress.MFT.AESP.pdf | archive-date=2017-07-31 | url-status=dead }}</ref> has been used to study the differences between ] and ], in this regard.<ref name=haidt/><ref>{{cite magazine|url=http://www.newyorker.com/online/video/conference/2007/haidt |title=Morality: 2012: Online Only Video |magazine=]|access-date=2012-05-06}}</ref> Haidt found that Americans who identified as liberals tended to value care and fairness higher than loyalty, respect and purity. Self-identified conservative Americans valued care and fairness less and the remaining three values more. Both groups gave care the highest over-all weighting, but conservatives valued fairness the lowest, whereas liberals valued purity the lowest. Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geo-historical factors, with conservatism strongest in closely knit, ethnically homogeneous communities, in contrast to ]-cities, where the cultural mix is greater, thus requiring more liberalism.

Group morality develops from shared ]s and ]s and is often codified to regulate behavior within a ] or community. Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral. Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess "moral fiber", whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially degenerate. The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality; an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community (a positive example would be the function of ] reform in reviving monasticism; a negative example would be the role of the ] in the subjugation of China to European interests). Within ] movements, there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality, regardless of its content.

Political morality is also relevant to the behavior internationally of national governments, and to the support they receive from their host population. The ], co-founded by ], analyzes the trajectory of moral progress in society via the framework of an expanding moral circle.<ref name="introducing">{{cite web|url = https://www.sentienceinstitute.org/blog/introducing-sentience-institute|title = Introducing Sentience Institute|date = 2 June 2017|access-date = 2019-08-05|publisher = ]}}</ref> ] states that
<blockquote>... if we adopt the principle of universality: if an action is right (or wrong) for others, it is right (or wrong) for us. Those who do not rise to the minimal moral level of applying to themselves the standards they apply to others—more stringent ones, in fact—plainly cannot be taken seriously when they speak of appropriateness of response; or of right and wrong, good and evil.

In fact, one of them, maybe the most, elementary of moral principles is that of universality, that is, If something's right for me, it's right for you; if it's wrong for you, it's wrong for me. Any moral code that is even worth looking at has that at its core somehow.<ref name="Zmag">{{cite web |url=http://www.znetwork.org/znet/viewArticle/11934 |archive-url=https://archive.today/20130113102044/http://www.znetwork.org/znet/viewArticle/11934 |url-status=dead |archive-date=2013-01-13 |title=Terror and Just Response |publisher=ZNet |last=Chomsky |first=Noam |date=2002-07-02 }}</ref></blockquote>

==Religion==
{{Main|Ethics in religion|Morality and religion}}
{{See also|Divine command theory|Divine law|Religious law|Secular ethics|Secular morality}}

Religion and morality are not synonymous. Morality does not depend upon religion although for some this is "an almost automatic assumption".<ref>{{cite book|editor1-last=Rachels|editor1-first=James|editor2-last=Rachels|editor2-first=Stuart|title=The Elements of Moral Philosophy|publisher=McGraw-Hill|edition=7th|year=2011|location=New York|page={{page needed|date=December 2019}}|isbn=978-0-078-03824-2}}</ref> According to ''The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics'', religion and morality "are to be defined differently and have no definitional connections with each other. Conceptually and in principle, morality and a religious value system are two distinct kinds of value systems or action guides."<ref>{{cite book|editor1-last=Childress|editor1-first=James F.|editor2-last= Macquarrie|editor2-first=John|title=The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics|publisher=The Westminster Press|year=1986|location=Philadelphia|page=401|isbn=978-0-664-20940-7}}</ref>

=== Positions ===
Within the wide range of moral traditions, religious value-systems co-exist with contemporary secular frameworks such as ], ], ], ], and others. There are many types of religious value-systems. Modern ] religions, such as ], ], ], and to a certain degree others such as ] and ], define right and wrong by the laws and rules as set forth by their respective ] and as interpreted by ]s within each respective faith. Other religions spanning ] to ] tend to be less absolute. For example, within ], the intention of the individual and the circumstances should be accounted for in the form of ], to determine if an action is termed right or wrong.<ref>Peggy Morgan, "Buddhism". In {{cite book |title= Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions | edition= Second |editor1-first= Peggy |editor1-last= Morgan |editor2-first= Clive A. | editor2-last= Lawton |year= 2007 |publisher= Columbia University Press |isbn= 978-0-7486-2330-3 | pages= 61, 88–89}}</ref> ] points out a further disparity between the values of religious traditions, stating that in ], "practically, right and wrong are decided according to the categories of social rank, kinship, and stages of life. For modern Westerners, who have been raised on ideals of universality and ], this relativity of values and obligations is the aspect of Hinduism most difficult to understand".<ref>{{cite book | title= The Bhagavad Gita: Krishna's Counsel in Time of War | last= Miller |first = Barbara Stoler| year = 2004 |publisher= Random House | location= New York|isbn= 978-0-553-21365-2 |page= 3}}</ref>

Religions provide different ways of dealing with moral dilemmas. For example, Hinduism lacks any absolute prohibition on killing, recognizing that it "may be inevitable and indeed necessary" in certain circumstances.<ref>Werner Menski, "Hinduism". In {{cite book | title= Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions | edition= Second |editor1-first= Peggy |editor1-last= Morgan |editor2-first= Clive A. | editor2-last= Lawton |year= 2007 |publisher= Columbia University Press |isbn= 978-0-7486-2330-3 | page= 5}}</ref> Monotheistic traditions view certain acts—such as ] or ]—in more absolute terms.{{Ref label|A|a|none}} Religion is not always positively associated with morality. Philosopher ] stated that "the greatest crimes have been found, in many instances, to be compatible with a ] ] and devotion; Hence it is justly regarded as unsafe to draw any inference in favor of a man's morals, from the fervor or strictness of his religious exercises, even though he himself believe them sincere."<ref>], "The Natural History of Religion". In {{cite book|title= The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever|title-link= The Portable Atheist|editor-last= Hitchens|editor-first= Christopher|editor-link= Christopher Hitchens |year= 2007|publisher= Da Capo Press|location= Philadelphia|isbn= 978-0-306-81608-6|page= 30}}</ref>

Religious value-systems can be used to justify acts that are contrary to general contemporary morality, such as ]s, ] and ]. For example, ] states that "apologists for Hinduism defend or explain away its involvement with the ], and apologists for Islam defend or explain away its harsh penal code or its attitude to women and infidels".<ref>{{cite book | title= Ethics: A Very Short Introduction |last= Blackburn |first= Simon|author-link= Simon Blackburn |year= 2001 |publisher= Oxford University Press |location= Oxford |isbn= 978-0-19-280442-6 |page= 13}}</ref> In regard to Christianity, he states that the "] can be read as giving us a carte blanche for harsh attitudes to children, the mentally handicapped, animals, the environment, the divorced, unbelievers, people with various sexual habits, and elderly women",<ref>{{cite book | title= Ethics: A Very Short Introduction |last= Blackburn |first= Simon |author-link= Simon Blackburn |year= 2001 |publisher= Oxford University Press |location= Oxford |isbn= 978-0-19-280442-6 |page= 12}}</ref> and notes morally-suspect themes in the Bible's ] as well.<ref>{{cite book | title= Ethics: A Very Short Introduction |last= Blackburn |first= Simon|author-link= Simon Blackburn |year= 2001 |publisher= Oxford University Press |location= Oxford |isbn= 978-0-19-280442-6 |pages= 11–12}}</ref>{{Ref label|E|e|none}} ] likewise holds that "the Bible contains both good and evil teachings", and it is "morally inconsistent".<ref>], "If God is Dead, Is Everything Permitted?" In {{cite book|title= The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever|title-link= The Portable Atheist|publisher= Da Capo Press|year= 2007|isbn= 978-0-306-81608-6|editor-last= Hitchens|editor-first= Christopher|editor-link= Christopher Hitchens|location= Philadelphia|page= 336}}</ref> Christian ] address Blackburn's viewpoints<ref name="colley1">{{cite web|last= Colley|first= Caleb|title= Is Christianity a Threat to Ethics?|url= http://espanol.apologeticspress.org/articles/240427|publisher= Apologetics Press|access-date= 3 May 2012}}</ref> and construe that ] in the ] showed the evolution of moral standards towards protecting the vulnerable, imposing a death penalty on those pursuing slavery and treating slaves as persons and not as property.<ref name="enrichmentjournal1">{{cite web |url= http://enrichmentjournal.ag.org/201102/201102_108_slavery.htm.cfm |title= Does the Old Testament Endorse Slavery? An Overview |publisher= Enrichmentjournal.ag.org |access-date=2012-05-06 |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20181005034831/http://enrichmentjournal.ag.org/201102/201102_108_slavery.htm.cfm |archive-date= 2018-10-05 |url-status= dead }}</ref> Humanists like ] believe that we can identify ]s across cultures, even if we do not appeal to a supernatural or universalist understanding of principles – values including integrity, trustworthiness, benevolence, and fairness. These values can be resources for finding common ground between believers and nonbelievers.<ref>See Weber, Eric Thomas. " {{webarchive|url= https://web.archive.org/web/20131014235128/http://www.ericthomasweber.org/Weber-RPRH.pdf |date=2013-10-14 }}." ''Contemporary Pragmatism'' 5, Issue 2 (2008): 131–47.</ref>

=== Empirical analyses ===
Several studies have been conducted on the empirics of morality in various countries, and the overall relationship between faith and ] is unclear.{{Ref label|B|b|none}} A 2001 review of studies on this topic found "The existing evidence surrounding the effect of religion on crime is varied, contested, and inconclusive, and currently, no persuasive answer exists as to the empirical relationship between religion and crime."<ref name = baier/> Phil Zuckerman's 2008 book, ''Society without God'', based on studies conducted during 14 months in Scandinavia in 2005–2006, notes that ] and ], "which are probably the least religious countries in the world, and possibly in the history of the world", enjoy "among the lowest violent crime rates in the world the lowest levels of corruption in the world".<ref>{{cite book |title= Society Without God: What the Least Religious Nations Can Tell Us about Contentment|last= Zuckerman|first= Phil|publisher= New York University Press|location= New York|isbn= 978-0-8147-9714-3|page= 2|date= October 2008}}</ref>{{Ref label|C|c|none}}

Dozens of studies have been conducted on this topic since the twentieth century. A 2005 study by ] published in the ''Journal of Religion and Society'' stated that, "In general, higher rates of belief in and worship of a creator correlate with higher rates of homicide, juvenile and early adult mortality, STD infection rates, teen pregnancy, and abortion in the prosperous democracies," and "In all secular developing democracies a centuries long-term trend has seen homicide rates drop to historical lows" with the exceptions being the United States (with a high religiosity level) and "theistic" Portugal.<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html |journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look|first=Gregory S.|last=Paul|location=Baltimore, MD|year =2005 |volume =7|pages=4–5, 8, 10|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111214113448/http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html |archive-date=2011-12-14}}</ref>{{Ref label|D|d|none}} In a response, Gary Jensen builds on and refines Paul's study.<ref name="Jensen">Gary F. Jensen (2006) Department of Sociology, Vanderbilt University , ''Journal of Religion and Society'', Vol. 8, {{ISSN|1522-5658}}</ref> he concludes that a "complex relationship" exists between religiosity and homicide "with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it". In April 2012, the results of a study which tested their subjects' ] sentiments were published in the '']'' journal in which non-religious people had higher scores showing that they were more motivated by their own compassion to perform pro-social behaviors. Religious people were found to be less motivated by compassion to be charitable than by an inner sense of moral obligation.<ref>. ''Science Daily''</ref><ref>Laura R. Saslow, Robb Willer, Matthew Feinberg, Paul K. Piff, Katharine Clark, Dacher Keltner and Sarina R. Saturn
</ref>


==See also== ==See also==
{{div col|colwidth=25em}}
* ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ''The Concept of Morals'' (book)<ref name="Stace">{{cite book
* ]
| last = Stace
* ]
| first = Walter T.
* ]
| authorlink =
* ]
| coauthors =
* ]
| title = The Concept of Morals
* ]
| publisher = The MacMillan Company
* ]
| date = 1937, Reprinted 1975 by permission of MacMillan Publishing Co. Inc.
* ]
| location = New York
* ]
| pages =
* ]
| url =
* ]
| doi =
* ]
| id =
* ]
| isbn = 0-8446-2990-1
* ]
}}
* ]
</ref>
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]


{{div col end}}
== References ==
{{reflist|2}}


== Bibliography == ==Notes==
{{refbegin|45em}}
:'''a.'''{{Note label|A|a|none}} Studies on divorce in the ] done by the Barna Group suggested that ] and ] have lower divorce rates than faith groups on average (though some faith groups had ] still).<ref name="barna1">{{cite web|url= http://www.barna.org/barna-update/article/15-familykids/42-new-marriage-and-divorce-statistics-released|title= New Marriage and Divorce Statistics Released|author= Barna Group|date= 31 March 2008|publisher= Barna Group|access-date= 19 November 2011|url-status= dead|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20141219120231/http://www.barna.org/barna-update/article/15-familykids/42-new-marriage-and-divorce-statistics-released|archive-date= 19 December 2014}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url= http://www.adherents.com/largecom/baptist_divorce.html |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20020328084636/http://www.adherents.com/largecom/baptist_divorce.html |url-status= usurped |archive-date= March 28, 2002 |title= Survey Inspires Debate Over Why Faith Isn't a Bigger Factor in Marriage |first= Christine |last= Wicker|year= 2000|publisher= www.adherents.com|access-date= 1 April 2012}}</ref> The study notes that fewer atheists and agnostics enter into marriage relative to faith-based individuals.
:'''b.'''{{Note label|B|b|none}} Some studies appear to show positive links in the relationship between religiosity and moral behavior<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Kerley | first1 = Kent R. | last2 = Matthews | last3 = Blanchard | first3 = Troy C. | year = 2005 | title = Religiosity, Religious Participation, and Negative Prison Behaviors | journal = Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion | volume = 44 | issue = 4| pages = 443–57 | doi = 10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00296.x }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Saroglou | first1 = Vassilis | last2 = Pichon | last3 = Dernelle | first3 = Rebecca | year = 2005 | title = Prosocial Behavior and Religion: New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings | url = http://www.uclouvain.be/cps/ucl/doc/psyreli/documents/2005.JSSR.pdf| journal = Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion | volume = 44 | issue = 3| pages = 323–48 | doi = 10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00289.x | citeseerx = 10.1.1.503.7559 }}</ref><ref>e.g. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20071008201939/http://www.ropercenter.uconn.edu/data_access/data/datasets/social_capital_community_survey.html |date=2007-10-08 }} by ] showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations</ref> Modern research in ] also suggests an inverse relationship between religion and crime,<ref>As is stated in: {{cite journal | last1 = Chu | first1 = Doris C. | year = 2007 | title = Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use | journal = Criminal Justice and Behavior | volume = 34 | issue = 5| pages = 661–79 | doi = 10.1177/0093854806293485 | s2cid = 145491534 }}</ref> with some studies establishing this connection.<ref>
For example:
* {{cite journal | last1 = Albrecht | first1 = S. I. | last2 = Chadwick | first2 = B. A. | last3 = Alcorn | first3 = D. S. | year = 1977 | title = Religiosity and deviance:Application of an attitude-behavior contingent consistency model | journal = Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion | volume = 16 | issue = 3| pages = 263–74 | doi=10.2307/1385697| jstor = 1385697 }}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Burkett | first1 = S. | last2 = White | first2 = M. | year = 1974 | title = Hellfire and delinquency:Another look | journal = Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion | volume = 13 | issue = 4| pages = 455–62 | doi=10.2307/1384608| jstor = 1384608 }}
* Chard-Wierschem, D. (1998). In pursuit of the "true" relationship: A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse. Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Dissertation.
* {{cite journal | last1 = Cochran | first1 = J. K. | last2 = Akers | first2 = R. L. | year = 1989 | title = Beyond Hellfire:An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use | journal = Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency | volume = 26 | issue = 3| pages = 198–225 | doi=10.1177/0022427889026003002| s2cid = 145479350 }}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Evans | first1 = T. D. | last2 = Cullen | first2 = F. T. | last3 = Burton | first3 = V. S. Jr.| last4 = Dunaway | first4 = R. G. | last5 = Payne | first5 = G. L. | last6 = Kethineni | first6 = S. R. | year = 1996 | title = Religion, social bonds, and delinquency | journal = Deviant Behavior | volume = 17 | pages = 43–70 | doi=10.1080/01639625.1996.9968014}}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Grasmick | first1 = H. G. | last2 = Bursik | first2 = R. J. | last3 = Cochran | first3 = J. K. | year = 1991 | title = Render unto Caesar what is Caesar's": Religiosity and taxpayer's inclinations to cheat | journal = The Sociological Quarterly | volume = 32 | issue = 2| pages = 251–66 | doi=10.1111/j.1533-8525.1991.tb00356.x}}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Higgins | first1 = P. C. | last2 = Albrecht | first2 = G. L. | year = 1977 | title = Hellfire and delinquency revisited | journal = Social Forces | volume = 55 | issue = 4| pages = 952–58 | doi=10.1093/sf/55.4.952}}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Johnson | first1 = B. R. | last2 = Larson | first2 = D. B. | last3 = DeLi | first3 = S. | last4 = Jang | first4 = S. J. | year = 2000 | title = Escaping from the crime of inner cities:Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth | journal = Justice Quarterly | volume = 17 | issue = 2| pages = 377–91 | doi=10.1080/07418820000096371| s2cid = 144816590 }}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Johnson | first1 = R. E. | last2 = Marcos | first2 = A. C. | last3 = Bahr | first3 = S. J. | year = 1987 | title = The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use | journal = Criminology | volume = 25 | issue = 2| pages = 323–40 | doi=10.1111/j.1745-9125.1987.tb00800.x}}
* {{cite journal | last1 = Powell | first1 = K. | year = 1997 | title = Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner-city youths | journal = Family and Community Health | volume = 20 | issue = 2| pages = 38–47 | doi=10.1097/00003727-199707000-00006}}
</ref> A meta-analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded, "religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals' criminal behavior".<ref name = baier>{{cite journal | last1 = Baier | first1 = C. J. | last2 = Wright | first2 = B. R. | year = 2001 | title = If you love me, keep my commandments":A meta-analysis of the effect of religion on crime | journal = Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency | volume = 38 | pages = 3–21 | doi=10.1177/0022427801038001001| s2cid = 145779667 }}</ref>
:'''c.'''{{Note label|C|c|none}} Zuckerman identifies that Scandinavians have "relatively high rates of petty crime and burglary", but "their overall rates of violent crime—such as murder, aggravated assault, and rape—are among the lowest on earth" (Zuckerman 2008, pp. 5–6).
:'''d.'''{{Note label|D|d|none}} The authors also state that "A few hundred years ago rates of homicide were astronomical in Christian Europe and the American colonies,"<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look|first=Gregory S.|last=Paul|location=Baltimore, MD|year=2005|volume=7|pages=4–5, 8|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111214113448/http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|archive-date=2011-12-14}}</ref> and "the least theistic secular developing democracies such as Japan, France, and Scandinavia have been most successful in these regards."<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look|first=Gregory S.|last=Paul|location=Baltimore, MD|year=2005|volume=7|page=11|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111214113448/http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|archive-date=2011-12-14}}</ref> They argue for a positive ] between the degree of public religiosity in a society and certain measures of dysfunction,<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look|first=Gregory S.|last=Paul|location=Baltimore, MD|year=2005|volume=7|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111214113448/http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html|archive-date=2011-12-14}}</ref> an analysis published later in the same journal argues that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions in the research.<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2006/2006-1.html|journal=Journal of Religion and Society|title=Religiosity, Secularism, and Social Health|author=Gerson Moreno-Riaño|author2=Mark Caleb Smith|author3=Thomas Mach|publisher=Cedarville University|year=2006|volume=8|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111028205639/http://moses.creighton.edu/jrs/2006/2006-1.html|archive-date=2011-10-28}}</ref>
:'''e.'''{{Note label|E|e|none}} Blackburn provides examples such as the phrase in ] 22:18 that has "helped to burn alive tens or hundreds of thousands of women in Europe and America": "Thou shalt not suffer a witch to live," and notes that the ] God apparently has "no problems with a slave-owning society", considers birth control a crime punishable by death, and "is keen on child abuse".<ref>{{cite book |title= Ethics: A Very Short Introduction|last= Blackburn|first= Simon|author-link=Simon Blackburn|year= 2001|publisher= Oxford University Press|location= Oxford|isbn= 978-0-19-280442-6|pages= 10, 12}}</ref> Others interpret these passages differently, arguing for example that Jewish laws show the evolution of moral standards in society: that Jews actually threatened those who pursued forced slavery with the death penalty, held that slaves were persons instead of property, and protected them in several ways.<ref name="colley1"/><ref name="enrichmentjournal1"/><ref name="Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy">{{cite web |last1=Westacott |first1=Emrys |title=Moral Relativism |url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/moral-re/#SH2g |website=iep.utm.edu |access-date=12 May 2018}}</ref>
{{refend}}


==References==
* Walker, Martin G. ''LIFE! Why We Exist...And What We Must Do to Survive'' (] Wiki Book Page) ( Web Site), Dog Ear Publishing, 2006, ISBN 1-59858-243-7
{{Reflist}}
* Trompenaars, Fons. ''Did the Pedestrian Die?'' ISBN 1-84112-436-2


==Further reading==
== External links ==
* {{cite book|last=Churchland|first=Patricia Smith|author-link=Patricia Churchland|title=Braintrust : What Neuroscience Tells Us about Morality|publisher=]|location=Princeton, NJ|isbn=978-0-691-13703-2|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tLsIzyFR08IC|year=2011}} (Reviewed in )
{{wikiquote}}
* ], "The roots of morality: why are we good?", in '']'', Black Swan, 2007 ({{ISBN|978-0-552-77429-1}}).
*
* {{cite book|last=Harris|first=Sam|author-link=Sam Harris|title=The Moral Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values|year=2010|publisher=Free Press|location=New York|isbn=978-1-4391-7121-9|title-link=The Moral Landscape}}
*
* Lunn, Arnold, and Garth Lean (1964). ''The New Morality''. London: Blandford Press.
* chabad.org
* John Newton, ''Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century'', 2000. {{ISBN|0967370574}}.
*
* {{cite journal
*
| last = Prinz
| first = Jesse
| author-link = Jesse Prinz
|date=Jan–Feb 2013
| title = Morality is a Culturally Conditioned Response
| journal = ]
| url = http://philosophynow.org/issues/82/Morality_is_a_Culturally_Conditioned_Response
}}
*{{cite book|chapter=]|title=A manual of moral theology for English-speaking countries|year=1925|publisher=Burns Oates & Washbourne Ltd.|first=Thomas|last=Slater S.J.}}
* {{cite book|last=Stace|first=Walter Terence|author-link=Walter Terence Stace|title=The Concept of Morals|year=1937|publisher=The MacMillan Company; Reprinted 1975 by permission of Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc., and also reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc, January 1990|location=New York|isbn=978-0-8446-2990-2|url=https://archive.org/details/conceptofmorals029360mbp}}
* {{cite book|last=Trompenaars|first=Fons|author-link=Fons Trompenaars|title=Did the Pedestrian Die?: Insights from the World's Greatest Culture Guru|year=2003|publisher=Capstone|location=Oxford|isbn=978-1-84112-436-0|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=BAYKAQAAMAAJ}}
* {{cite book|last=Yandell|first=Keith E.|title=God, man, and religion: readings in the philosophy of religion|year=1973|publisher=McGraw-Hill|url=https://archive.org/details/godmanreligionre0000yand|url-access=registration}} containing articles by Paterson Brown:
** , (from ''Mind'', 1963).
** , (from ''Mind'', 1964).
** , (from '']'', 1967).
* Ashley Welch, March 4, 2012.
* ], ''Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics'', 2012, 21(4), 457–65.

==External links==
{{Wiktionary}}
{{Wikiquote}}
{{Commons category|Morality}}
* , '']''
*
* , ]
* by ], '']'', 13 January 2008


{{Philosophy topics}}
{{Ethics}} {{Ethics}}
{{Social philosophy}}
{{sociobiology}}
{{Portal bar|Philosophy}}
{{Authority control}}


]
] ]
] ]
] ]

]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]

Latest revision as of 14:05, 24 December 2024

Differentiation between right and wrong Several terms redirect here. For other uses, see Morality (novella), Morality (The Armando Iannucci Shows), Morals (film), and The Immoralist. Not to be confused with Morale, Molarity, or Molality.
Allegory with a portrait of a Venetian senator (Allegory of the morality of earthly things), attributed to Tintoretto, 1585

Morality (from Latin moralitas 'manner, character, proper behavior') is the categorization of intentions, decisions and actions into those that are proper, or right, and those that are improper, or wrong. Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a code of conduct from a particular philosophy, religion or culture, or it can derive from a standard that is understood to be universal. Morality may also be specifically synonymous with "goodness", "appropriateness" or "rightness".

Moral philosophy includes meta-ethics, which studies abstract issues such as moral ontology and moral epistemology, and normative ethics, which studies more concrete systems of moral decision-making such as deontological ethics and consequentialism. An example of normative ethical philosophy is the Golden Rule, which states: "One should treat others as one would like others to treat oneself."

Immorality is the active opposition to morality (i.e., opposition to that which is good or right), while amorality is variously defined as an unawareness of, indifference toward, or disbelief in any particular set of moral standards or principles.

History

See also: Evolution of morality and History of ethics

Ethics

Ethics (also known as moral philosophy) is the branch of philosophy which addresses questions of morality. The word "ethics" is "commonly used interchangeably with 'morality' ... and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group, or individual." Likewise, certain types of ethical theories, especially deontological ethics, sometimes distinguish between ethics and morality.

Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law."

Philosopher Simon Blackburn writes that "Although the morality of people and their ethics amounts to the same thing, there is a usage that restricts morality to systems such as that of Immanuel Kant, based on notions such as duty, obligation, and principles of conduct, reserving ethics for the more Aristotelian approach to practical reasoning, based on the notion of a virtue, and generally avoiding the separation of 'moral' considerations from other practical considerations."

Descriptive and normative

In its descriptive sense, "morality" refers to personal or cultural values, codes of conduct or social mores that are observed to be accepted by a significant number of individuals (not necessarily all) in a society. It does not connote objective claims of right or wrong, but only refers to claims of right and wrong that are seen to be made and to conflicts between different claims made. Descriptive ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.

In its normative sense, "morality" refers to whatever (if anything) is actually right or wrong, which may be independent of the values or mores held by any particular peoples or cultures. Normative ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.

Realism and anti-realism

Philosophical theories on the nature and origins of morality (that is, theories of meta-ethics) are broadly divided into two classes:

  • Moral realism is the class of theories which hold that there are true moral statements that report objective moral facts. For example, while they might concede that forces of social conformity significantly shape individuals' "moral" decisions, they deny that those cultural norms and customs define morally right behavior. This may be the philosophical view propounded by ethical naturalists, but not all moral realists accept that position (e.g. ethical non-naturalists).
  • Moral anti-realism, on the other hand, holds that moral statements either fail or do not even attempt to report objective moral facts. Instead, they hold that moral sentences are either categorically false claims of objective moral facts (error theory); claims about subjective attitudes rather than objective facts (ethical subjectivism); or else do not attempt to describe the world at all but rather something else, like an expression of an emotion or the issuance of a command (non-cognitivism).

Some forms of non-cognitivism and ethical subjectivism, while considered anti-realist in the robust sense used here, are considered realist in the sense synonymous with moral universalism. For example, universal prescriptivism is a universalist form of non-cognitivism which claims that morality is derived from reasoning about implied imperatives, and divine command theory and ideal observer theory are universalist forms of ethical subjectivism which claim that morality is derived from the edicts of a god or the hypothetical decrees of a perfectly rational being, respectively.

Anthropology

Morality with practical reasoning

Practical reason is necessary for the moral agency but it is not a sufficient condition for moral agency. Real life issues that need solutions do need both rationality and emotion to be sufficiently moral. One uses rationality as a pathway to the ultimate decision, but the environment and emotions towards the environment at the moment must be a factor for the result to be truly moral, as morality is subject to culture. Something can only be morally acceptable if the culture as a whole has accepted this to be true. Both practical reason and relevant emotional factors are acknowledged as significant in determining the morality of a decision.

Tribal and territorial

Celia Green made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality. She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive: it defines a person's territory, including his or her property and dependents, which is not to be damaged or interfered with. Apart from these proscriptions, territorial morality is permissive, allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another. By contrast, tribal morality is prescriptive, imposing the norms of the collective on the individual. These norms will be arbitrary, culturally dependent and 'flexible', whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute, such as Kant's 'categorical imperative' and Geisler's graded absolutism. Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property, and the ascendancy of contract over status.

In-group and out-group

Main article: In-group and out-group

Some observers hold that individuals apply distinct sets of moral rules to people depending on their membership of an "in-group" (the individual and those they believe to be of the same group) or an "out-group" (people not entitled to be treated according to the same rules). Some biologists, anthropologists and evolutionary psychologists believe this in-group/out-group discrimination has evolved because it enhances group survival. This belief has been confirmed by simple computational models of evolution. In simulations this discrimination can result in both unexpected cooperation towards the in-group and irrational hostility towards the out-group. Gary R. Johnson and V.S. Falger have argued that nationalism and patriotism are forms of this in-group/out-group boundary. Jonathan Haidt has noted that experimental observation indicating an in-group criterion provides one moral foundation substantially used by conservatives, but far less so by liberals.

In-group preference is also helpful at the individual level for the passing on of one's genes. For example, a mother who favors her own children more highly than the children of other people will give greater resources to her children than she will to strangers', thus heightening her children's chances of survival and her own gene's chances of being perpetuated. Due to this, within a population, there is substantial selection pressure exerted toward this kind of self-interest, such that eventually, all parents wind up favoring their own children (the in-group) over other children (the out-group).

Comparing cultures

Peterson and Seligman approach the anthropological view looking across cultures, geo-cultural areas and across millennia. They conclude that certain virtues have prevailed in all cultures they examined. The major virtues they identified include wisdom / knowledge; courage; humanity; justice; temperance; and transcendence. Each of these include several divisions. For instance humanity includes love, kindness, and social intelligence.

Still, others theorize that morality is not always absolute, contending that moral issues often differ along cultural lines. A 2014 PEW research study among several nations illuminates significant cultural differences among issues commonly related to morality, including divorce, extramarital affairs, homosexuality, gambling, abortion, alcohol use, contraceptive use, and premarital sex. Each of the 40 countries in this study has a range of percentages according to what percentage of each country believes the common moral issues are acceptable, unacceptable, or not moral issues at all. Each percentage regarding the significance of the moral issue varies greatly on the culture in which the moral issue is presented.

Advocates of a theory known as moral relativism subscribe to the notion that moral virtues are right or wrong only within the context of a certain standpoint (e.g., cultural community). In other words, what is morally acceptable in one culture may be taboo in another. They further contend that no moral virtue can objectively be proven right or wrong Critics of moral relativism point to historical atrocities such as infanticide, slavery, or genocide as counter arguments, noting the difficulty in accepting these actions simply through cultural lenses.

Fons Trompenaars, author of Did the Pedestrian Die?, tested members of different cultures with various moral dilemmas. One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend, a passenger riding in the car, lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian. Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations, from none to definite.

Anthropologists from Oxford's Institute of Cognitive & Evolutionary Anthropology (part of the School of Anthropology & Museum Ethnography) analysed ethnographic accounts of ethics from 60 societies, comprising over 600,000 words from over 600 sources and discovered what they believe to be seven universal moral rules: help your family, help your group, return favours, be brave, defer to superiors, divide resources fairly, and respect others' property.

Evolution

See also: Altruism § Evolutionary explanations, Evolution of morality, and Evolutionary ethics

The development of modern morality is a process closely tied to sociocultural evolution. Some evolutionary biologists, particularly sociobiologists, believe that morality is a product of evolutionary forces acting at an individual level and also at the group level through group selection (although to what degree this actually occurs is a controversial topic in evolutionary theory). Some sociobiologists contend that the set of behaviors that constitute morality evolved largely because they provided possible survival or reproductive benefits (i.e. increased evolutionary success). Humans consequently evolved "pro-social" emotions, such as feelings of empathy or guilt, in response to these moral behaviors.

On this understanding, moralities are sets of self-perpetuating and biologically driven behaviors which encourage human cooperation. Biologists contend that all social animals, from ants to elephants, have modified their behaviors, by restraining immediate selfishness in order to improve their evolutionary fitness. Human morality, although sophisticated and complex relative to the moralities of other animals, is essentially a natural phenomenon that evolved to restrict excessive individualism that could undermine a group's cohesion and thereby reducing the individuals' fitness.

On this view, moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction (inclusive fitness). Examples: the maternal bond is selected for because it improves the survival of offspring; the Westermarck effect, where close proximity during early years reduces mutual sexual attraction, underpins taboos against incest because it decreases the likelihood of genetically risky behaviour such as inbreeding.

The phenomenon of reciprocity in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality. Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources, especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably. For example, some vampire bats fail to feed on prey some nights while others manage to consume a surplus. Bats that did eat will then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a conspecific from starvation. Since these animals live in close-knit groups over many years, an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry (Wilkinson, 1984)

Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce (2009) have argued that morality is a suite of behavioral capacities likely shared by all mammals living in complex social groups (e.g., wolves, coyotes, elephants, dolphins, rats, chimpanzees). They define morality as "a suite of interrelated other-regarding behaviors that cultivate and regulate complex interactions within social groups." This suite of behaviors includes empathy, reciprocity, altruism, cooperation, and a sense of fairness. In related work, it has been convincingly demonstrated that chimpanzees show empathy for each other in a wide variety of contexts. They also possess the ability to engage in deception, and a level of social politics prototypical of our own tendencies for gossip and reputation management.

Christopher Boehm (1982) has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout hominid evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons. Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size, and in particular the development of theory of mind abilities.

Psychology

Main article: Moral psychology See also: Kohlberg's stages of moral development and Jean Piaget § Education and development of morality
Kohlberg's model of moral development

In modern moral psychology, morality is sometimes considered to change through personal development. Several psychologists have produced theories on the development of morals, usually going through stages of different morals. Lawrence Kohlberg, Jean Piaget, and Elliot Turiel have cognitive-developmental approaches to moral development; to these theorists morality forms in a series of constructive stages or domains. In the Ethics of care approach established by Carol Gilligan, moral development occurs in the context of caring, mutually responsive relationships which are based on interdependence, particularly in parenting but also in social relationships generally. Social psychologists such as Martin Hoffman and Jonathan Haidt emphasize social and emotional development based on biology, such as empathy. Moral identity theorists, such as William Damon and Mordechai Nisan, see moral commitment as arising from the development of a self-identity that is defined by moral purposes: this moral self-identity leads to a sense of responsibility to pursue such purposes. Of historical interest in psychology are the theories of psychoanalysts such as Sigmund Freud, who believe that moral development is the product of aspects of the super-ego as guilt-shame avoidance. Theories of moral development therefore tend to regard it as positive moral development: the higher stages are morally higher, though this, naturally, involves a circular argument. The higher stages are better because they are higher, but the better higher because they are better.

As an alternative to viewing morality as an individual trait, some sociologists as well as social- and discursive psychologists have taken upon themselves to study the in-vivo aspects of morality by examining how persons conduct themselves in social interaction.

A new study analyses the common perception of a decline in morality in societies worldwide and throughout history. Adam M. Mastroianni and Daniel T. Gilbert present a series of studies indicating that the perception of moral decline is an illusion and easily produced, with implications for misallocation of resources, underuse of social support, and social influence. To begin with, the authors demonstrate that people in no less than 60 nations hold the belief that morality is deteriorating continuously, and this conviction has been present for the last 70 years. Subsequently, they indicate that people ascribe this decay to the declining morality of individuals as they age and the succeeding generations. Thirdly, the authors demonstrate that people's evaluations of the morality of their peers have not decreased over time, indicating that the belief in moral decline is an illusion. Lastly, the authors explain a basic psychological mechanism that uses two well-established phenomena (distorted exposure to information and distorted memory of information) to cause the illusion of moral decline. The authors present studies that validate some of the predictions about the circumstances in which the perception of moral decline is attenuated, eliminated, or reversed (e.g., when participants are asked about the morality of people closest to them or people who lived before they were born).

Moral cognition

Moral cognition refers to cognitive processes implicated in moral judgment and decision making, and moral action. It consists of several domain-general cognitive processes, ranging from perception of a morally salient stimulus to reasoning when faced with a moral dilemma. While it is important to mention that there is not a single cognitive faculty dedicated exclusively to moral cognition, characterizing the contributions of domain-general processes to moral behavior is a critical scientific endeavor to understand how morality works and how it can be improved.

Cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists investigate the inputs to these cognitive processes and their interactions, as well as how these contribute to moral behavior by running controlled experiments. In these experiments putatively moral versus nonmoral stimuli are compared to each other, while controlling for other variables such as content or working memory load. Often, the differential neural response to specifically moral statements or scenes, are examined using functional neuroimaging experiments.

Critically, the specific cognitive processes that are involved depend on the prototypical situation that a person encounters. For instance, while situations that require an active decision on a moral dilemma may require active reasoning, an immediate reaction to a shocking moral violation may involve quick, affect-laden processes. Nonetheless, certain cognitive skills such as being able to attribute mental states—beliefs, intents, desires, emotions to oneself, and others is a common feature of a broad range of prototypical situations. In line with this, a meta-analysis found overlapping activity between moral emotion and moral reasoning tasks, suggesting a shared neural network for both tasks. The results of this meta-analysis, however, also demonstrated that the processing of moral input is affected by task demands.

Regarding the issues of morality in video games, some scholars believe that because players appear in video games as actors, they maintain a distance between their sense of self and the role of the game in terms of imagination. Therefore, the decision-making and moral behavior of players in the game are not representing player's Moral dogma.

It has been recently found that moral judgment consists in concurrent evaluations of three different components that align with precepts from three dominant moral theories (virtue ethics, deontology, and consequentialism): the character of a person (Agent-component, A); their actions (Deed-component, D); and the consequences brought about in the situation (Consequences-component, C). This, implies that various inputs of the situation a person encounters affect moral cognition.

Jonathan Haidt distinguishes between two types of moral cognition: moral intuition and moral reasoning. Moral intuition involves the fast, automatic, and affective processes that result in an evaluative feeling of good-bad or like-dislike, without awareness of going through any steps. Conversely, moral reasoning does involve conscious mental activity to reach a moral judgment. Moral reasoning is controlled and less affective than moral intuition. When making moral judgments, humans perform moral reasoning to support their initial intuitive feeling. However, there are three ways humans can override their immediate intuitive response. The first way is conscious verbal reasoning (for example, examining costs and benefits). The second way is reframing a situation to see a new perspective or consequence, which triggers a different intuition. Finally, one can talk to other people which illuminates new arguments. In fact, interacting with other people is the cause of most moral change.

Neuroscience

See also: Science of morality and Neuromorality

The brain areas that are consistently involved when humans reason about moral issues have been investigated by multiple quantitative large-scale meta-analyses of the brain activity changes reported in the moral neuroscience literature. The neural network underlying moral decisions overlaps with the network pertaining to representing others' intentions (i.e., theory of mind) and the network pertaining to representing others' (vicariously experienced) emotional states (i.e., empathy). This supports the notion that moral reasoning is related to both seeing things from other persons' points of view and to grasping others' feelings. These results provide evidence that the neural network underlying moral decisions is probably domain-global (i.e., there might be no such things as a "moral module" in the human brain) and might be dissociable into cognitive and affective sub-systems.

Cognitive neuroscientist Jean Decety thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another individual is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior, and ultimately, morality. The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristics of psychopathy, and this would appear to lend support to Decety's view. Recently, drawing on empirical research in evolutionary theory, developmental psychology, social neuroscience, and psychopathy, Jean Decety argued that empathy and morality are neither systematically opposed to one another, nor inevitably complementary.

Brain areas

An essential, shared component of moral judgment involves the capacity to detect morally salient content within a given social context. Recent research implicated the salience network in this initial detection of moral content. The salience network responds to behaviorally salient events and may be critical to modulate downstream default and frontal control network interactions in the service of complex moral reasoning and decision-making processes.

The explicit making of moral right and wrong judgments coincides with activation in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPC), a region involved in valuation, while intuitive reactions to situations containing implicit moral issues activates the temporoparietal junction area, a region that plays a key role in understanding intentions and beliefs.

Stimulation of the VMPC by transcranial magnetic stimulation, or neurological lesion, has been shown to inhibit the ability of human subjects to take into account intent when forming a moral judgment. According to such investigations, TMS did not disrupt participants' ability to make any moral judgment. On the contrary, moral judgments of intentional harms and non-harms were unaffected by TMS to either the RTPJ or the control site; presumably, however, people typically make moral judgments of intentional harms by considering not only the action's harmful outcome but the agent's intentions and beliefs. So why were moral judgments of intentional harms not affected by TMS to the RTPJ? One possibility is that moral judgments typically reflect a weighted function of any morally relevant information that is available at the time. Based on this view, when information concerning the agent's belief is unavailable or degraded, the resulting moral judgment simply reflects a higher weighting of other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). Alternatively, following TMS to the RTPJ, moral judgments might be made via an abnormal processing route that does not take belief into account. On either account, when belief information is degraded or unavailable, moral judgments are shifted toward other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). For intentional harms and non-harms, however, the outcome suggests the same moral judgment as to the intention. Thus, the researchers suggest that TMS to the RTPJ disrupted the processing of negative beliefs for both intentional harms and attempted harms, but the current design allowed the investigators to detect this effect only in the case of attempted harms, in which the neutral outcomes did not afford harsh moral judgments on their own.

Similarly, individuals with a lesion of the VMPC judge an action purely on its outcome and are unable to take into account the intent of that action.

Genetics

This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (May 2022)

Moral intuitions may have genetic bases. A 2022 study conducted by scholars Michael Zakharin and Timothy C. Bates, and published by the European Journal of Personality, found that moral foundations have significant genetic bases. Another study, conducted by Smith and Hatemi, similarly found significant evidence in support of moral heritability by looking at and comparing the answers of moral dilemmas between twins.

Genetics play a role in influencing prosocial behaviors and moral decision-making. Genetics contribute to the development and expression of certain traits and behaviors, including those related to morality. However, it is important to note that while genetics play a role in shaping certain aspects of moral behavior, morality itself is a multifaceted concept that encompasses cultural, societal, and personal influences as well.

Politics

If morality is the answer to the question 'how ought we to live' at the individual level, politics can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level, though the political sphere raises additional problems and challenges. It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics. Moral foundations theory, authored by Jonathan Haidt and colleagues, has been used to study the differences between liberals and conservatives, in this regard. Haidt found that Americans who identified as liberals tended to value care and fairness higher than loyalty, respect and purity. Self-identified conservative Americans valued care and fairness less and the remaining three values more. Both groups gave care the highest over-all weighting, but conservatives valued fairness the lowest, whereas liberals valued purity the lowest. Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geo-historical factors, with conservatism strongest in closely knit, ethnically homogeneous communities, in contrast to port-cities, where the cultural mix is greater, thus requiring more liberalism.

Group morality develops from shared concepts and beliefs and is often codified to regulate behavior within a culture or community. Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral. Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess "moral fiber", whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially degenerate. The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality; an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community (a positive example would be the function of Cistercian reform in reviving monasticism; a negative example would be the role of the Dowager Empress in the subjugation of China to European interests). Within nationalist movements, there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality, regardless of its content.

Political morality is also relevant to the behavior internationally of national governments, and to the support they receive from their host population. The Sentience Institute, co-founded by Jacy Reese Anthis, analyzes the trajectory of moral progress in society via the framework of an expanding moral circle. Noam Chomsky states that

... if we adopt the principle of universality: if an action is right (or wrong) for others, it is right (or wrong) for us. Those who do not rise to the minimal moral level of applying to themselves the standards they apply to others—more stringent ones, in fact—plainly cannot be taken seriously when they speak of appropriateness of response; or of right and wrong, good and evil. In fact, one of them, maybe the most, elementary of moral principles is that of universality, that is, If something's right for me, it's right for you; if it's wrong for you, it's wrong for me. Any moral code that is even worth looking at has that at its core somehow.

Religion

Main articles: Ethics in religion and Morality and religion See also: Divine command theory, Divine law, Religious law, Secular ethics, and Secular morality

Religion and morality are not synonymous. Morality does not depend upon religion although for some this is "an almost automatic assumption". According to The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics, religion and morality "are to be defined differently and have no definitional connections with each other. Conceptually and in principle, morality and a religious value system are two distinct kinds of value systems or action guides."

Positions

Within the wide range of moral traditions, religious value-systems co-exist with contemporary secular frameworks such as consequentialism, freethought, humanism, utilitarianism, and others. There are many types of religious value-systems. Modern monotheistic religions, such as Islam, Judaism, Christianity, and to a certain degree others such as Sikhism and Zoroastrianism, define right and wrong by the laws and rules as set forth by their respective scriptures and as interpreted by religious leaders within each respective faith. Other religions spanning pantheistic to nontheistic tend to be less absolute. For example, within Buddhism, the intention of the individual and the circumstances should be accounted for in the form of merit, to determine if an action is termed right or wrong. Barbara Stoler Miller points out a further disparity between the values of religious traditions, stating that in Hinduism, "practically, right and wrong are decided according to the categories of social rank, kinship, and stages of life. For modern Westerners, who have been raised on ideals of universality and egalitarianism, this relativity of values and obligations is the aspect of Hinduism most difficult to understand".

Religions provide different ways of dealing with moral dilemmas. For example, Hinduism lacks any absolute prohibition on killing, recognizing that it "may be inevitable and indeed necessary" in certain circumstances. Monotheistic traditions view certain acts—such as abortion or divorce—in more absolute terms. Religion is not always positively associated with morality. Philosopher David Hume stated that "the greatest crimes have been found, in many instances, to be compatible with a superstitious piety and devotion; Hence it is justly regarded as unsafe to draw any inference in favor of a man's morals, from the fervor or strictness of his religious exercises, even though he himself believe them sincere."

Religious value-systems can be used to justify acts that are contrary to general contemporary morality, such as massacres, misogyny and slavery. For example, Simon Blackburn states that "apologists for Hinduism defend or explain away its involvement with the caste system, and apologists for Islam defend or explain away its harsh penal code or its attitude to women and infidels". In regard to Christianity, he states that the "Bible can be read as giving us a carte blanche for harsh attitudes to children, the mentally handicapped, animals, the environment, the divorced, unbelievers, people with various sexual habits, and elderly women", and notes morally-suspect themes in the Bible's New Testament as well. Elizabeth Anderson likewise holds that "the Bible contains both good and evil teachings", and it is "morally inconsistent". Christian apologists address Blackburn's viewpoints and construe that Jewish laws in the Hebrew Bible showed the evolution of moral standards towards protecting the vulnerable, imposing a death penalty on those pursuing slavery and treating slaves as persons and not as property. Humanists like Paul Kurtz believe that we can identify moral values across cultures, even if we do not appeal to a supernatural or universalist understanding of principles – values including integrity, trustworthiness, benevolence, and fairness. These values can be resources for finding common ground between believers and nonbelievers.

Empirical analyses

Several studies have been conducted on the empirics of morality in various countries, and the overall relationship between faith and crime is unclear. A 2001 review of studies on this topic found "The existing evidence surrounding the effect of religion on crime is varied, contested, and inconclusive, and currently, no persuasive answer exists as to the empirical relationship between religion and crime." Phil Zuckerman's 2008 book, Society without God, based on studies conducted during 14 months in Scandinavia in 2005–2006, notes that Denmark and Sweden, "which are probably the least religious countries in the world, and possibly in the history of the world", enjoy "among the lowest violent crime rates in the world the lowest levels of corruption in the world".

Dozens of studies have been conducted on this topic since the twentieth century. A 2005 study by Gregory S. Paul published in the Journal of Religion and Society stated that, "In general, higher rates of belief in and worship of a creator correlate with higher rates of homicide, juvenile and early adult mortality, STD infection rates, teen pregnancy, and abortion in the prosperous democracies," and "In all secular developing democracies a centuries long-term trend has seen homicide rates drop to historical lows" with the exceptions being the United States (with a high religiosity level) and "theistic" Portugal. In a response, Gary Jensen builds on and refines Paul's study. he concludes that a "complex relationship" exists between religiosity and homicide "with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it". In April 2012, the results of a study which tested their subjects' pro-social sentiments were published in the Social Psychological and Personality Science journal in which non-religious people had higher scores showing that they were more motivated by their own compassion to perform pro-social behaviors. Religious people were found to be less motivated by compassion to be charitable than by an inner sense of moral obligation.

See also

Notes

a. Studies on divorce in the United States done by the Barna Group suggested that atheists and agnostics have lower divorce rates than faith groups on average (though some faith groups had lower rates still). The study notes that fewer atheists and agnostics enter into marriage relative to faith-based individuals.
b. Some studies appear to show positive links in the relationship between religiosity and moral behavior Modern research in criminology also suggests an inverse relationship between religion and crime, with some studies establishing this connection. A meta-analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded, "religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals' criminal behavior".
c. Zuckerman identifies that Scandinavians have "relatively high rates of petty crime and burglary", but "their overall rates of violent crime—such as murder, aggravated assault, and rape—are among the lowest on earth" (Zuckerman 2008, pp. 5–6).
d. The authors also state that "A few hundred years ago rates of homicide were astronomical in Christian Europe and the American colonies," and "the least theistic secular developing democracies such as Japan, France, and Scandinavia have been most successful in these regards." They argue for a positive correlation between the degree of public religiosity in a society and certain measures of dysfunction, an analysis published later in the same journal argues that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions in the research.
e. Blackburn provides examples such as the phrase in Exodus 22:18 that has "helped to burn alive tens or hundreds of thousands of women in Europe and America": "Thou shalt not suffer a witch to live," and notes that the Old Testament God apparently has "no problems with a slave-owning society", considers birth control a crime punishable by death, and "is keen on child abuse". Others interpret these passages differently, arguing for example that Jewish laws show the evolution of moral standards in society: that Jews actually threatened those who pursued forced slavery with the death penalty, held that slaves were persons instead of property, and protected them in several ways.

References

  1. Long, A. A.; Sedley, D. N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers: Translations of the Principal Sources with Philosophical Commentary. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 366–67. ISBN 978-0521275569.
  2. Stanford University (2011). "The Definition of Morality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 22 March 2014.
  3. Antony Flew, ed. (1979). "golden rule". A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books in association with The MacMillan Press. p. 134. ISBN 978-0333262047. The maxim 'Treat others how you wish to be treated'. Various expressions of this fundamental moral rule are to be found in tenets of most religions and creeds through the ages, testifying to its universal applicability.
  4. Walter Terence Stace argued that the Golden Rule is much more than simply an ethical code. He posits that it "express the essence of a universal morality." The rationale for this distinction occupies much of his book The Concept of Morals (1937). Stace, Walter T. (1937). The Concept of Morals. New York: The MacMillan Company; reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc, January 1990. p. 136. ISBN 978-0-8446-2990-2.
  5. Johnstone, Megan-Jane (2008). Bioethics: A Nursing Perspective. Vol. 3. Elsevier Health Sciences. pp. 102–03. ISBN 978-0-7295-3873-2. PMID 2129925. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  6. Superson, Anita (2009). The Moral Skeptic. Oxford University Press. pp. 127–59. ISBN 978-0-19-537662-3.
  7. "Amorality". Dictionary.com. Retrieved 2010-06-18. "having no moral standards, restraints, or principles; unaware of or indifferent to questions of right or wrong"
  8. Deigh, John (2015). "ethics". In Audi, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 328. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139057509. ISBN 9781139057509.
  9. Blackburn, Simon (2008). "morality". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 241. doi:10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001. ISBN 9780199541430.
  10. ^ Gert, Bernard; Gert, Joshua (2020). "The Definition of Morality". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  11. Chapouthier, Georges, "To what extent is moral judgment natural?", European Review (GB), 2004, 12(2): 179–83
  12. Ezedike, Edward Uzoma (2020-01-02). "Morality within the limits of practical reason: a critique of Kant's concept of moral virtue". International Journal of Ethics and Systems. 36 (2): 205–216. doi:10.1108/ijoes-11-2018-0171. ISSN 2514-9369. S2CID 214501283.
  13. Richardson, Henry S. (2018), "Moral Reasoning", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-05-04
  14. Green, Celia (2004). Letters from Exile: Observations on a Culture in Decline. Oxford: Oxford Forum. Chapters I–XX.
  15. T.R. Shultz, M. Hartshorn, and A. Kaznatcheev. Why is ethnocentrism more common than humanitarianism? Archived 2012-03-27 at the Wayback Machine Proceedings of the 31st annual conference of the cognitive science society, 2009.
  16. Kaznatcheev, A. (2010, March). Robustness of ethnocentrism to changes in inter-personal interactions. In Complex Adaptive Systems – AAAI Fall Symposium. Butiz wintrades
  17. ^ Haidt, Jonathan; Graham, Jesse (2007). "When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize" (PDF). Social Justice Research. 20: 98–116. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.385.3650. doi:10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z. S2CID 6824095. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-08-30. Retrieved 2014-09-26.
  18. Peterson, Christopher, and Martin E. P. Seligman. Character Strengths and Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
  19. "Global Views on Morality". PewResearch.org. 15 April 2014.
  20. (Westacott, https://www.iep.utm.edu/moral-re/#SH2g).
  21. Trompenaars, Fons (2003). Did the Pedestrian Die: Insights from the World's Greatest Culture!. Wiley. ISBN 978-1841124360.
  22. Curry, Oliver Scott; Mullins, Daniel Austin; Whitehouse, Harvey (2019). "Is It Good to Cooperate? Testing the Theory of Morality-as-Cooperation in 60 Societies". Current Anthropology. 60 (1): 47–69. doi:10.1086/701478. S2CID 150324056.
  23. "Seven moral rules found all around the world | University of Oxford". www.ox.ac.uk. 11 February 2019.
  24. Shermer, Michael (2004). "Transcendent Morality". The Science of Good and Evil. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-8050-7520-5.
  25. Bekoff, Marc and Jessica Pierce Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals (Chicago, The University of Chicago Press 2009)
  26. O'Connell, Sanjida (July 1995). "Empathy in chimpanzees: Evidence for theory of mind?". Primates. 36 (3): 397–410. doi:10.1007/BF02382862. ISSN 0032-8332. S2CID 41356986.
  27. de Waal, Frans (1997). Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674356610.
  28. Boehm, Christopher (1982). "The evolutionary development of morality as an effect of dominance behaviour and conflict interference". Journal of Social and Biological Sciences. 5 (4): 413–22. doi:10.1016/s0140-1750(82)92069-3.
  29. Gilligan and Kohlberg: "Implications for Moral Theory" Author(s): Lawrence A. Blum Source: Ethics, Vol. 98, No. 3 (Apr., 1988), pp. 472–91
  30. Bergmann Jörg (1998). "Introduction:Morality in discourse". Research on Language and Social Interaction. 31 (3/4): 279–74. doi:10.1080/08351813.1998.9683594.
  31. Jörg Bergmann "Veiled morality: Notes on discretion in psychiatry." In Drew, Paul; Heritage, John, eds. (1992). Talk at work: Interaction in institutional settings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 137–62.
  32. Lena Jayyusi "Values and moral judgment: Communicative praxis as moral order." In Button, Graham, ed. (1991). Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 227–51.
  33. Cromdal Jakob; Michael Tholander (2014). "Morality in professional practice". Journal of Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice. 9 (2): 155–64. doi:10.1558/japl.v9i2.25734.
  34. Mastroianni, Adam M.; Gilbert, Daniel T. (2023). "The illusion of moral decline". Nature. 618 (7966): 782–789. Bibcode:2023Natur.618..782M. doi:10.1038/s41586-023-06137-x. PMC 10284688. PMID 37286595.
  35. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Wheatley, Thalia (2012). "The Disunity of Morality and Why it Matters to Philosophy". Monist. 95 (3): 355–77. doi:10.5840/monist201295319.
  36. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Wheatley, Thalia (13 February 2013). "Are moral judgments unified?". Philosophical Psychology. 27 (4): 451–74. doi:10.1080/09515089.2012.736075. S2CID 143876741.
  37. Young, Liane; Dungan, James (January 2012). "Where in the brain is morality? Everywhere and maybe nowhere". Social Neuroscience. 7 (1): 1–10. doi:10.1080/17470919.2011.569146. PMID 21590587. S2CID 14074566.
  38. Yoder, Keith J.; Decety, Jean (12 December 2017). "The neuroscience of morality and social decision-making". Psychology, Crime & Law. 24 (3): 279–95. doi:10.1080/1068316X.2017.1414817. PMC 6372234. PMID 30766017.
  39. Monin, Benoît; Pizarro, David A.; Beer, Jennifer S. (2007). "Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of moral judgment and the reason-affect debate". Review of General Psychology. 11 (2): 99–111. doi:10.1037/1089-2680.11.2.99. S2CID 144286153.
  40. ^ Sevinc, Gunes; Spreng, R. Nathan (4 February 2014). "Contextual and Perceptual Brain Processes Underlying Moral Cognition: A Quantitative Meta-Analysis of Moral Reasoning and Moral Emotions". PLOS ONE. 9 (2): e87427. Bibcode:2014PLoSO...987427S. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0087427. PMC 3913597. PMID 24503959.
  41. Bartel, Christopher (2015). "Free will and moral responsibility in video games". Ethics and Information Technology. 17 (4): 285–293. doi:10.1007/s10676-015-9383-8. ISSN 1388-1957. S2CID 15800963.
  42. Dubljević, Veljko; Sattler, Sebastian; Racine, Eric (2018). "Deciphering moral intuition: How agents, deeds, and consequences influence moral judgment". PLOS ONE. 13 (10): e0204631. Bibcode:2018PLoSO..1304631D. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0204631. PMC 6166963. PMID 30273370.
  43. Haidt, Jonathan (18 May 2007). "The New Synthesis in Moral Psychology". Science. 316 (5827): 998–1002. Bibcode:2007Sci...316..998H. doi:10.1126/science.1137651. PMID 17510357.
  44. ^ Bzdok, Danilo; Schilbach, Leonhard; Vogeley, Kai; Schneider, Karla; Laird, Angela R; Langner, Robert; Eickhoff, Simon B (2012-01-24). "Bzdok, D. et al. Parsing the neural correlates of moral cognition: ALE meta-analysis on morality, theory of mind, and empathy. Brain Struct Funct, 2011". Brain Structure and Function. 217 (4): 783–96. doi:10.1007/s00429-012-0380-y. PMC 3445793. PMID 22270812.
  45. Boccia, M.; Dacquino, C.; Piccardi, L.; Cordellieri, P.; Guariglia, C.; Ferlazzo, F.; Ferracuti, S.; Giannini, A. M. (25 January 2016). "Neural foundation of human moral reasoning: an ALE meta-analysis about the role of personal perspective". Brain Imaging and Behavior. 11 (1): 278–92. doi:10.1007/s11682-016-9505-x. PMID 26809288. S2CID 3984661. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 September 2019. Retrieved 23 September 2019.
  46. Eres, Robert; Louis, Winnifred R.; Molenberghs, Pascal (27 July 2017). "Common and distinct neural networks involved in fMRI studies investigating morality: an ALE meta-analysis". Social Neuroscience. 13 (4): 384–98. doi:10.1080/17470919.2017.1357657. PMID 28724332. S2CID 31749926.
  47. Vedantam, Shankar. "If It Feels Good to Be Good, It Might Be Only Natural". The Washington Post. Retrieved 2010-05-13.
  48. de Wied M, Goudena PP, Matthys W (2005). "Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders". Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, and Allied Disciplines. 46 (8): 867–80. doi:10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00389.x. hdl:1874/11212. PMID 16033635. S2CID 45683502.
  49. Fernandez YM, Marshall WL (2003). "Victim empathy, social self-esteem, and psychopathy in rapists". Sexual Abuse: A Journal of Research and Treatment. 15 (1): 11–26. doi:10.1023/A:1020611606754. PMID 12616926. S2CID 195293070.
  50. Decety, Jean (November 1, 2014). "The Neuroevolution of Empathy and Caring for Others: Why It Matters for Morality". New Frontiers in Social Neuroscience. Research and Perspectives in Neurosciences. Vol. 21. pp. 127–151. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-02904-7_8. ISBN 978-3-319-02903-0.
  51. Decety, J.; Cowell, J. M. (2014). "The complex relation between morality and empathy" (PDF). Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 18 (7): 337–339. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2014.04.008. PMID 24972506. S2CID 355141.
  52. ^ Sevinc, Gunes; Gurvit, Hakan; Spreng, R. Nathan (July 2017). "Salience network engagement with the detection of morally laden information". Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience. 12 (7): 1118–27. doi:10.1093/scan/nsx035. PMC 5490682. PMID 28338944.
  53. Seeley, W. W.; Menon, V.; Schatzberg, A. F.; Keller, J.; Glover, G. H.; Kenna, H.; Reiss, A. L.; Greicius, M. D. (28 February 2007). "Dissociable Intrinsic Connectivity Networks for Salience Processing and Executive Control". Journal of Neuroscience. 27 (9): 2349–56. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5587-06.2007. PMC 2680293. PMID 17329432.
  54. Harenski, CL; Antonenko, O; Shane, MS; Kiehl, KA. (2010). "A functional imaging investigation of moral deliberation and moral intuition". NeuroImage. 49 (3): 2707–16. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.10.062. PMC 4270295. PMID 19878727.
  55. Young, Liane; Camprodon, Joan Albert; Hauser, Marc; Pascual-Leone, Alvaro; Saxe, Rebecca (2010). "Disruption of the right temporoparietal junction with transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the role of beliefs in moral judgments". PNAS. 107 (15): 6753–58. Bibcode:2010PNAS..107.6753Y. doi:10.1073/pnas.0914826107. PMC 2872442. PMID 20351278.
  56. Young, Liane; Bechara, Antoine; Tranel, Daniel; Damasio, Hanna; Hauser, Marc; Damasio, Antonio (2010). "Damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex impairs judgment of harmful intent". Neuron. 65 (6): 845–51. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.003. PMC 3085837. PMID 20346759.
  57. Zakharin, Michael; Bates, Timothy C (2022-05-26). "Testing heritability of moral foundations: Common pathway models support strong heritability for the five moral foundations". European Journal of Personality. 37 (4): 485–497. doi:10.1177/08902070221103957. ISSN 0890-2070. S2CID 249115484.
  58. Smith, Kevin; Hatemi, Peter K. (December 2020). "Are Moral Intuitions Heritable?". Human Nature. 31 (4): 406–420. doi:10.1007/s12110-020-09380-7. ISSN 1045-6767. PMID 33420605. S2CID 231202698.
  59. See Weber, Eric Thomas. 2011. Morality, Leadership, and Public Policy (London: Continuum).
  60. Haidt, Jonathan; Joseph, Craig (September 2004). "Intuitive ethics: how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues". Daedalus. 133 (4): 55–66. doi:10.1162/0011526042365555. S2CID 1574243.
  61. Graham, J.; Haidt, J.; Koleva, S.; Motyl, M.; Iyer, R.; Wojcik, S.; Ditto, P.H. (2013). Moral Foundations Theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism (PDF). Vol. 47. pp. 55–130. doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4. ISBN 978-0124072367. S2CID 2570757. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-07-31. Retrieved 2019-07-22. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  62. "Morality: 2012: Online Only Video". The New Yorker. Retrieved 2012-05-06.
  63. "Introducing Sentience Institute". Sentience Institute. 2 June 2017. Retrieved 2019-08-05.
  64. Chomsky, Noam (2002-07-02). "Terror and Just Response". ZNet. Archived from the original on 2013-01-13.
  65. Rachels, James; Rachels, Stuart, eds. (2011). The Elements of Moral Philosophy (7th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. p. . ISBN 978-0-078-03824-2.
  66. Childress, James F.; Macquarrie, John, eds. (1986). The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press. p. 401. ISBN 978-0-664-20940-7.
  67. Peggy Morgan, "Buddhism". In Morgan, Peggy; Lawton, Clive A., eds. (2007). Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions (Second ed.). Columbia University Press. pp. 61, 88–89. ISBN 978-0-7486-2330-3.
  68. Miller, Barbara Stoler (2004). The Bhagavad Gita: Krishna's Counsel in Time of War. New York: Random House. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-553-21365-2.
  69. Werner Menski, "Hinduism". In Morgan, Peggy; Lawton, Clive A., eds. (2007). Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions (Second ed.). Columbia University Press. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-7486-2330-3.
  70. David Hume, "The Natural History of Religion". In Hitchens, Christopher, ed. (2007). The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever. Philadelphia: Da Capo Press. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-306-81608-6.
  71. Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  72. Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  73. Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 11–12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  74. Elizabeth Anderson, "If God is Dead, Is Everything Permitted?" In Hitchens, Christopher, ed. (2007). The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever. Philadelphia: Da Capo Press. p. 336. ISBN 978-0-306-81608-6.
  75. ^ Colley, Caleb. "Is Christianity a Threat to Ethics?". Apologetics Press. Retrieved 3 May 2012.
  76. ^ "Does the Old Testament Endorse Slavery? An Overview". Enrichmentjournal.ag.org. Archived from the original on 2018-10-05. Retrieved 2012-05-06.
  77. See Weber, Eric Thomas. "Religion, Public Reason, and Humanism: Paul Kurtz on Fallibilism and Ethics Archived 2013-10-14 at the Wayback Machine." Contemporary Pragmatism 5, Issue 2 (2008): 131–47.
  78. ^ Baier, C. J.; Wright, B. R. (2001). "If you love me, keep my commandments":A meta-analysis of the effect of religion on crime". Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency. 38: 3–21. doi:10.1177/0022427801038001001. S2CID 145779667.
  79. Zuckerman, Phil (October 2008). Society Without God: What the Least Religious Nations Can Tell Us about Contentment. New York: New York University Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-8147-9714-3.
  80. Paul, Gregory S. (2005). "Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look". Journal of Religion and Society. 7. Baltimore, MD: 4–5, 8, 10. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  81. Gary F. Jensen (2006) Department of Sociology, Vanderbilt University "Religious Cosmologies and Homicide Rates among Nations: A Closer Look'", Journal of Religion and Society, Vol. 8, ISSN 1522-5658
  82. "Highly Religious People Are Less Motivated by Compassion Than Are Non-Believers". Science Daily
  83. Laura R. Saslow, Robb Willer, Matthew Feinberg, Paul K. Piff, Katharine Clark, Dacher Keltner and Sarina R. Saturn "My Brother's Keeper? Compassion Predicts Generosity More Among Less Religious Individuals"
  84. Barna Group (31 March 2008). "New Marriage and Divorce Statistics Released". Barna Group. Archived from the original on 19 December 2014. Retrieved 19 November 2011.
  85. Wicker, Christine (2000). "Survey Inspires Debate Over Why Faith Isn't a Bigger Factor in Marriage". www.adherents.com. Archived from the original on March 28, 2002. Retrieved 1 April 2012.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  86. Kerley, Kent R.; Matthews; Blanchard, Troy C. (2005). "Religiosity, Religious Participation, and Negative Prison Behaviors". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 44 (4): 443–57. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00296.x.
  87. Saroglou, Vassilis; Pichon; Dernelle, Rebecca (2005). "Prosocial Behavior and Religion: New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings" (PDF). Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 44 (3): 323–48. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.503.7559. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00289.x.
  88. e.g. a survey Archived 2007-10-08 at the Wayback Machine by Robert Putnam showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations
  89. As is stated in: Chu, Doris C. (2007). "Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use". Criminal Justice and Behavior. 34 (5): 661–79. doi:10.1177/0093854806293485. S2CID 145491534.
  90. For example:
    • Albrecht, S. I.; Chadwick, B. A.; Alcorn, D. S. (1977). "Religiosity and deviance:Application of an attitude-behavior contingent consistency model". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 16 (3): 263–74. doi:10.2307/1385697. JSTOR 1385697.
    • Burkett, S.; White, M. (1974). "Hellfire and delinquency:Another look". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 13 (4): 455–62. doi:10.2307/1384608. JSTOR 1384608.
    • Chard-Wierschem, D. (1998). In pursuit of the "true" relationship: A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse. Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Dissertation.
    • Cochran, J. K.; Akers, R. L. (1989). "Beyond Hellfire:An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use". Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency. 26 (3): 198–225. doi:10.1177/0022427889026003002. S2CID 145479350.
    • Evans, T. D.; Cullen, F. T.; Burton, V. S. Jr.; Dunaway, R. G.; Payne, G. L.; Kethineni, S. R. (1996). "Religion, social bonds, and delinquency". Deviant Behavior. 17: 43–70. doi:10.1080/01639625.1996.9968014.
    • Grasmick, H. G.; Bursik, R. J.; Cochran, J. K. (1991). "Render unto Caesar what is Caesar's": Religiosity and taxpayer's inclinations to cheat". The Sociological Quarterly. 32 (2): 251–66. doi:10.1111/j.1533-8525.1991.tb00356.x.
    • Higgins, P. C.; Albrecht, G. L. (1977). "Hellfire and delinquency revisited". Social Forces. 55 (4): 952–58. doi:10.1093/sf/55.4.952.
    • Johnson, B. R.; Larson, D. B.; DeLi, S.; Jang, S. J. (2000). "Escaping from the crime of inner cities:Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth". Justice Quarterly. 17 (2): 377–91. doi:10.1080/07418820000096371. S2CID 144816590.
    • Johnson, R. E.; Marcos, A. C.; Bahr, S. J. (1987). "The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use". Criminology. 25 (2): 323–40. doi:10.1111/j.1745-9125.1987.tb00800.x.
    • Powell, K. (1997). "Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner-city youths". Family and Community Health. 20 (2): 38–47. doi:10.1097/00003727-199707000-00006.
  91. Paul, Gregory S. (2005). "Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look". Journal of Religion and Society. 7. Baltimore, MD: 4–5, 8. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  92. Paul, Gregory S. (2005). "Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look". Journal of Religion and Society. 7. Baltimore, MD: 11. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  93. Paul, Gregory S. (2005). "Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look". Journal of Religion and Society. 7. Baltimore, MD. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  94. Gerson Moreno-Riaño; Mark Caleb Smith; Thomas Mach (2006). "Religiosity, Secularism, and Social Health". Journal of Religion and Society. 8. Cedarville University. Archived from the original on 2011-10-28.
  95. Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 10, 12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  96. Westacott, Emrys. "Moral Relativism". iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 12 May 2018.

Further reading

External links

Ethics
Normative
Applied
Meta
Schools
Concepts
Ethicists
Works
Related
Social philosophy
Concepts
Schools
Philosophers
Ancient
Medieval
Early modern
18th and 19th
centuries
20th and 21st
centuries
Works
See also
Portal: Categories: