Revision as of 14:21, 26 July 2010 edit71.177.17.107 (talk) →Intersubjectivity in psychoanalysis: I am Robert Stolorow. I fleshed out a little my collaborators and my conception of intersubjectivity.← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 23:03, 13 November 2024 edit undo2601:249:8281:94f0:f90a:754d:72ed:bfb0 (talk) →Definition: Citation needed | ||
(198 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Concept in philosophy and psychology}} | |||
'''Intersubjectivity''' is a term used in philosophy, psychology and sociology to describe a condition somewhere between subjectivity and objectivity, one in which a phenomenon is personally experienced (subjectively) but by more than one ]. | |||
{{Lead too short|date=March 2021}} | |||
In ], ], ], and ], '''intersubjectivity''' is the ] or ] between people's ]s. | |||
==Definition== | ==Definition== | ||
Thomas Scheff defines intersubjectivity as "the sharing of subjective states by two or more individuals." <ref>Scheff, Thomas et al. (2006). ''Goffman Unbound!: A New Paradigm for Social Science (The Sociological Imagination)'', Paradigm Publishers (ISBN 978-1-59451-196-7)</ref> | |||
{{em|Intersubjectivity}} is a term coined by social scientists beginning around 1970{{Citation needed|date=November 2024|reason=Elsewhere, Edmund Husserl (who is discussed later in this article) is credited with coining the term, outside of social science and well before 1970}} to refer to a variety of types of human interaction. The term was introduced to psychoanalysis by ] and ], who consider it a "meta-theory" of psychoanalysis.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Spezzano |first1=C. |title=Textbook of psychoanalysis |date=2012 |publisher=American Psychiatric Publishing |isbn=978-1-58562-410-2 |pages=105–116 |edition=2nd |url=https://www.appi.org/textbook_of_psychoanalysis_second_edition}}</ref> For example, social psychologists ] and ] listed at least seven definitions of intersubjectivity (and other disciplines have additional definitions): | |||
The term is used in three ways: | |||
* people's agreement on the shared definition of a concept; | |||
* people's mutual awareness of agreement or disagreement, or of understanding or misunderstanding each other; | |||
* people's attribution of intentionality, feelings, and beliefs to each other; | |||
* people's implicit or automatic behavioral orientations towards other people; | |||
* people's interactive performance within a situation; | |||
* people's shared and taken-for-granted background assumptions, whether consensual or contested; and | |||
* "the variety of possible relations between people's perspectives".<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gillespie |first1=Alex |last2=Cornish |first2=Flora |date=March 2010 |title=Intersubjectivity: towards a dialogical analysis |journal=] |volume=40 |issue=1 |pages=19–46 |doi=10.1111/j.1468-5914.2009.00419.x |hdl=1893/2576 |citeseerx=10.1.1.724.7095 |url=http://users.utu.fi/freder/gillespie.pdf}}</ref> | |||
{{em|Intersubjectivity}} has been used in social science to refer to agreement. There is intersubjectivity between people if they agree on a given set of meanings or share the same perception of a situation. Similarly, ] defines {{em|intersubjectivity}} as "the sharing of subjective states by two or more individuals".<ref>{{Cite book| publisher = Routledge| isbn = 978-1-315-63435-7| last = Scheff| first = Thomas J. | author-link=Thomas J. Scheff | title = Goffman Unbound!: A New Paradigm for Social Science| location = New York| date = 2015-11-15}}</ref> | |||
#Second, and more subtly intersubjectivity refers to the "]," shared meanings constructed by people in their interactions with each other and used as an everyday resource to interpret the meaning of elements of social and cultural life. If people share common sense, then they share a definition of the situation.<ref>]. , ''Researching Society and Culture''.</ref> | |||
#Third, the term has been used to refer to shared (or partially shared) ''divergences'' of meaning. Self-presentation, lying, practical jokes, and social emotions, for example, all entail not a shared definition of the situation, but partially shared divergences of meaning. Someone who is telling a lie is engaged in an intersubjective act because they are working with two different definitions of the situation. Lying is thus genuinely inter-subjective (in the sense of operating between two subjective definitions of reality). | |||
{{em|Intersubjectivity}} also has been used to refer to the ], shared meanings constructed by people in their interactions with each other and used as an everyday resource to interpret the meaning of elements of social and cultural life. If people share common sense, then they share a definition of the situation.<ref>{{Cite book| publisher = Sage Publications| isbn = 978-0-7619-5276-3| last = Seale| first = Clive| title = Researching society and culture| location = London| date = 1998 | author-link=Clive Seale}}</ref> | |||
Intersubjectivity emphasizes that shared cognition and consensus is essential in the shaping of our ideas and relations. Language, quintessentially, is viewed as communal rather than private. Therefore, it is problematic to view the individual as partaking in a private world, one which has a meaning defined apart from any other subjects. | |||
Psychoanalyst Jessica Benjamin, in ''The Bonds of Love'', wrote, "The concept of intersubjectivity has its origins in the social theory of ] (1970), who used the expression 'the intersubjectivity of mutual understanding' to designate an individual capacity and a social domain."<ref>{{cite book|last=Benjamin|first=Jessica|title=The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, & the Problem of Domination|date=July 12, 1988 | publisher=Pantheon | isbn=0394757300 | url=https://archive.org/details/bondsoflovetexte00benj_0/page/18/mode/2up|url-access=registration}}</ref>{{rp|19}} Psychoanalyst Molly Macdonald argued in 2011 that a "potential point of origin" for the term was in ]'s use of ''l'inter-subjectivité'' in an essay from 1955 on "The Human Situation in the Hegelian Phenomenology".<ref>Macdonald, M (2011) "Hegel, Psychoanalysis and Intersubjectivity" in ''Philosophy Compass'', 6/7 p449</ref> However, the phenomenologist ], whose work Habermas and Hyppolite draw upon, was the first to develop the term, which was subsequently elaborated upon by other phenomenologists such as ], ], and ]. | |||
==Intersubjectivity in psychoanalysis== | |||
Intersubjectivity is an important concept in modern schools of ], where it has found application to the theory of the interrelations between ] and ]. Adopting an intersubjective perspective in psychoanalysis means, above all, to give up what ] define as "the myth of isolated mind."<ref>http://books.google.com/books?id=EbuJO7ZOHtMC&pg=PA7&lpg=PA7&dq=the+myth+of+isolated+mind&source=web&ots=q8NGjSl1CH&sig=JlbsdG9ldNL_K3yffYPf5waPbmQ</ref> In Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange's "intersubjective-systems theory," "intersubjective" refers not to the sharing of subjective states but to the constitution of psychological systems or fields in the interplay of differently organized experiential worlds. In their view, emotional experience always takes form within such intersubjective systems. | |||
==Philosophy== | |||
Among the early authors who explored this conception in psychoanalysis, in an explicit or implicit way, were ], ], ], ] in the United States and in Italy. | |||
Contemporarily, intersubjectivity is the major topic in both the ] and the ] traditions of philosophy. Intersubjectivity is considered crucial not only at the relational level but also at the epistemological and even metaphysical levels. For example, intersubjectivity is postulated as playing a role in establishing the truth of propositions, and constituting the intersubjective agreement of an experience of an object. | |||
A central concern in consciousness studies of the past 50 years is the so-called problem of ''other minds,'' which asks how we can justify our belief that people have minds much like our own and predict others' mind-states and behavior, as our experience shows we often can.<ref>Hyslop, A (2010). "Other Minds", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.) Accessed from plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/other-minds/>. Section 1.</ref> Contemporary philosophical theories of intersubjectivity need to address the problem of other minds. | |||
Since the late 1980s, a direction in psychoanalysis often referred to as ] or just ]. A central person figure in the theory is ] <ref>{{cite book |title=The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life |last=Stern |first= Daniel |authorlink = Daniel Stern (psychologist) |year=2004 |publisher= ] |location= |isbn= 978-0393704297}}</ref>. Empirically, the intersubjective school is inspired by research on the non-verbal communication of infants, young children, and their parents <ref>{{cite book |title= Infant Research and Adult Treatment. Co-constructing Interactions|last= Beebe |first=Beatrice |coauthors=Frank M Lachmann |year= 2002|publisher= Analytic Press|location=London |isbn= 9780881632453 }}</ref><ref>Schechter DS (2003). Intergenerational communication of maternal violent trauma: Understanding the interplay of reflective functioning and posttraumatic psychopathology. In S.W. Coates, J.L. Rosenthal and D.S. Schechter (eds.) September 11: Trauma and Human Bonds. Hillside, NJ: Analytic Press, Inc. pp. 115-142.</ref>. A central question is how relational issues are communicated at a very fast pace in a non-verbal fashion. Scholars also stress the importance of real relationships between two equivalent partners. The journal ] is devoted to relational psychoanalysis. | |||
In the debate between cognitive individualism and cognitive universalism, some aspects of thinking are neither solely personal nor fully universal. Cognitive sociology proponents argue for ''intersubjectivity''—an intermediate perspective of social cognition that provides a balanced view between personal and universal views of our social cognition. This approach suggests that, instead of being individual or universal thinkers, human beings subscribe to "thought communities"—communities of differing beliefs. Thought community examples include churches, professions, scientific beliefs, generations, nations, and political movements.<ref name="Zerubavel 1997">{{cite book|last=Zerubavel|first=Eviatar|title=Social Mindscapes: An Invitation to Cognitive Sociology|year=1997|publisher=Harvard University Press|location=Cambridge, Massachusetts}}</ref> This perspective explains why each individual thinks differently from another (individualism): person A may choose to adhere to expiry dates on foods, but person B may believe that expiry dates are only guidelines and it is still safe to eat the food days past the expiry date. But not all human beings think the same way (universalism). | |||
==Intersubjectivity in philosophy== | |||
=== Phenomenology === | |||
Intersubjectivity argues that each thought community shares social experiences that are different from the social experiences of other thought communities, creating differing beliefs among people who subscribe to different thought communities. These experiences transcend our subjectivity, which explains why they can be shared by the entire thought community.<ref name="Zerubavel 1997"/> Proponents of intersubjectivity support the view that individual beliefs are often the result of thought community beliefs, not just personal experiences or universal and objective human beliefs. Beliefs are recast in terms of standards, which are set by thought communities. | |||
In ], intersubjectivity performs many functions. It allows ], which in phenomenology involves experiencing another person as a subject rather than just as an object among objects. In so doing, one experiences oneself as seen by ], and the world in general as a shared world instead of one only available to oneself. | |||
===Phenomenology=== | |||
Early studies on the phenomenology of intersubjectivity were done by ], the founder of phenomenology. His student, ], extended the concept and its basis in empathy in her 1917 doctoral dissertation ''On the Problem of Empathy'' (''Zum Problem der Einfühlung''). | |||
], the founder of ], recognized the importance of intersubjectivity, and wrote extensively on the topic. In German, his writings on intersubjectivity are gathered in volumes 13–15 of the '']''. In English, his best-known text on intersubjectivity is the '']'' (it is this text that features solely in the Husserl reader entitled ''The Essential Husserl''). Although Husserlian phenomenology is often charged with methodological ], in the fifth Cartesian Meditation, Husserl attempts to grapple with the problem of intersubjectivity and puts forward his theory of transcendental, monadological intersubjectivity.<ref>E. Husserl, ''Cartesian Meditations'', Klumer Academic Publishers. Translated by Dorion Cairns.</ref> | |||
Husserl's student ] extended intersubjectivity's basis in empathy in her 1917 doctoral dissertation, ''On the Problem of Empathy'' (''Zum Problem der Einfühlung''). | |||
Intersubjectivity also helps in the constitution of objectivity: in the experience of the world as available not only to oneself, but also to the Other, there is a bridge between the personal and the shared, the self and the Others. | |||
== |
==Psychology== | ||
Discussions and theories of intersubjectivity are prominent and of importance in contemporary psychology, theory of mind, and consciousness studies. Three major contemporary theories of intersubjectivity are theory theory, simulation theory, and interaction theory. | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
Shannon Spaulding, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at ], wrote: {{Blockquote|Theory theorists argue that we explain and predict behaviour by employing folk psychological theories about how mental states inform behaviour. With our folk psychological theories, we infer from a target's behaviour what his or her mental states probably are. And from these inferences, plus the psychological principles in the theory connecting mental states to behavior, we predict the target's behaviour (Carruthers and Smith 1996; Davies and Stone 1995a; Gopnik and Wellman 1992; Nichols and Stich 2003).<ref name="Spaulding">{{cite journal |title=Introduction to debates on Social Cognition |journal=Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences |date=2012-09-05 |last=Spaulding |first=Shannon |volume=11 |issue=4 |pages=431–448 (432, 433) |issn=1568-7759 |doi=10.1007/s11097-012-9275-x |doi-access=free }}<!--|access-date=2015-11-23 --></ref>}} | |||
Intersubjectivity and philosophy: | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
], on the other hand, claim that we explain and predict others' behaviour by using our own minds as a model and "putting ourselves in another's shoes"—that is, by imagining what our mental states would be and how we would behave if we were in the other's situation. More specifically, we simulate what the other's mental states could have been to cause the observed behaviour, then use the simulated mental states, pretend beliefs, and pretend desires as input, running them through our own decision-making mechanism. We then take the resulting conclusion and attribute it to the other person.<ref name="Spaulding"/> Authors like ] have proposed a theory of embodied simulation that refers to neuroscientific research on mirror neurons and phenomenological research.<ref>Gallese, V & Sinigaglia, C. (2011) What is so special about embodied simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol. 15, No. 11.</ref> | |||
Intersubjectivity in psychoanalysis: | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
Spaulding noted that this debate has stalled in the past few years, with progress limited to articulating various hybrid simulation theories—"theory theory" accounts.<ref name="Spaulding"/> To resolve this impasse, authors like ] put forward interaction theory. Gallagher writes that an "... important shift is taking place in social cognition research, away from a focus on the individual mind and toward ... participatory aspects of social understanding...." Interaction theory is put forward to "galvanize" the interactive turn in explanations of intersubjectivity.<ref>De Jaeger, H., Di Paulo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010) Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol. 14, No. 10. Pg 441. {{doi|10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009}}</ref> Gallagher defines an interaction as two or more autonomous agents engaged in co-regulated coupling behavior. For example, when walking a dog, both the owner's behavior is regulated by the dog stopping and sniffing, and the dog's behavior is regulated by the lead and the owner's commands. Ergo, walking the dog is an example of an interactive process. For Gallagher, interaction and direct perception constitute what he terms "primary" (or basic) intersubjectivity. | |||
== References == | |||
<references/> | |||
Studies of dialogue and ] reveal how language is deeply intersubjective. When we speak, we always address our interlocutors, taking their perspective and orienting to what we think they think (or, more often, don't think).<ref>Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking language, mind and world dialogically. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing</ref> Within this tradition of research, it has been argued that the structure of individual signs or symbols, the basis of language, is intersubjective<ref>Gillespie, A. (2009). . In ] (Ed), Symbolic transformations. London: Routledge</ref> and that the psychological process of self-reflection entails intersubjectivity.<ref>Gillespie, A. (2007). . In Valsiner and Rosa (Eds), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University press</ref> Recent research on ] provides evidence for the deeply intersubjective basis of human psychology,<ref>Rizzolatti, G. & Arbib, M. A. (1998). . Trends in neurosciences, 21, 188-194.</ref> and arguably much of the literature on ] and ] relates directly to intersubjectivity. | |||
==Further reading== | |||
==In child development== | |||
===Intersubjectivity in psychoanalysis=== | |||
] has applied intersubjectivity to the very rapid cultural development of new born infants.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Trevarthen |first=Colwyn |date=January 2011 |title=What is it like to be a person who knows nothing? Defining the active intersubjective mind of a newborn human being |journal=Infant and Child Development |volume=20 |issue=1 |pages=119–135 |doi=10.1002/icd.689 |citeseerx=10.1.1.475.9911}}</ref> Research suggests that as babies, humans are biologically wired to "coordinate their actions with others".<ref name=Stone>{{cite journal|last1=Stone|first1=Lynda|last2=Underwood|first2=Charles|last3=Hotchkiss|first3=Jacqueline|title=The Relational Habitus: Intersubjective Processes in Learning Settings|journal=Human Development |year=2012 |volume=55 |issue=2 |pages=65–91 |doi=10.1159/000337150 |s2cid=144722047 |url=http://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/337150|access-date=10 December 2014|ref=Stone}}</ref> This ability to coordinate and sync with others facilitates cognitive and emotional learning through social interaction. Additionally, the most socially productive relationship between children and adults is bidirectional, where both parties actively define a shared culture.<ref name=Stone /> The bidirectional aspect lets the active parties organize the relationship how they see fit—what they see as important receives the most focus. Emphasis is placed on the idea that children are actively involved in how they learn, using intersubjectivity.<ref name=Stone /> | |||
* ] & Pontalis, J. B. (1974). ''The Language of Psycho-Analysis'', Edited by W. W. Norton & Company, ISBN 0-393-01105-4 | |||
===Across cultures=== | |||
The ways intersubjectivity occurs varies across cultures. In certain Indigenous American communities, ] is so prevalent that intersubjectivity may occur regularly amongst all members of the community, in part perhaps due to a "joint cultural understanding" and a history of shared endeavors.<ref name="Correa-Chavez">Correa-Chávez, M., & Roberts, A. (2012). A cultural analysis is necessary in understanding intersubjectivity. Culture & Psychology, 18(1), 99-108. doi: 10.1177/1354067X11427471</ref> This "joint cultural understanding" may develop in small, Indigenous American communities where children have grown up embedded in their community's values, expectations, and livelihoods—learning through participation with adults rather than through intent verbal instruction—working in cohesion with one another in shared endeavors on a daily basis. Having grown up within this context may have led to members of this community to have what is described by some as a "blending of agendas",<ref name="Correa-Chavez" /> or by others as a "dovetailing of motives".<ref>Danziger, E., & Rumsey, A. (2013). Introduction: From Opacity to intersubjectivity across languages and cultures. Language & Communication, 33(3), 247-250.</ref> If community or family members have the same general goals in mind they may thus act cohesively within an overlapping state of mind. Whether persons are in each other's presence or merely within the same community this blending of agendas or dovetailing of motives enables intersubjectivity to occur within these shared endeavors.<ref name="Correa-Chavez" /> | |||
The cultural value of ''respeto'' may also contribute to intersubjectivity in some communities; unlike the English definition of 'respect', ''respeto'' refers loosely to a mutual consideration for others' activities, needs, wants, etc.<ref name="Correa-Chavez" /> Similar to "putting yourself in another's shoes" the prevalence of ''respeto'' in certain Indigenous American communities in Mexico and South America may promote intersubjectivity as persons act in accordance with one another within consideration for the community or the individual's current needs or state of mind. | |||
Shared reference during an activity facilitates learning. Adults either teach by doing the task with children, or by directing attention toward experts. Children that had to ask questions in regard to how to perform a task were scolded for not learning by another's example, as though they were ignoring the available resources to learn a task, as seen in ] parents who scolded questioning children and asking "if they had eyes".<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Paradise|first1=Ruth|last2=Rogoff|first2=Barbara|title=Side by Side: Learning by Observing and Pitching In|journal=Ethos|date=2009|volume=37|issue=1|pages=102–138|doi=10.1111/j.1548-1352.2009.01033.x|ref=ParadiseRuth}}</ref> | |||
Children from the ] village in the Andean mountains learned to ] without explicit instruction. They learned the basic technique from others by observing, eager to participate in their community. The learning process was facilitated by watching adults and by being allowed to play and experiment using tools to create their own weaving techniques.<ref name=Bolin>{{cite book|last1=Bolin|first1=Inge|title=Growing Up in a Culture of Respect: Childrearing in highland Peru|date=2006|publisher=University of Texas|location=Austin|isbn=978-0-292-71298-0|pages=90–99|edition=2}}</ref> | |||
==See also== | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
==References== | |||
{{reflist}} | |||
==Further reading== | |||
===Psychoanalysis=== | |||
* Brandchaft, Doctors & Sorter (2010). Toward an Emancipatory Psychoanalysis. Routledge: New York. | |||
* ] & Pontalis, J. B. (1974). ''The Language of Psycho-Analysis'', Edited by W. W. Norton & Company, {{ISBN|0-393-01105-4}} | |||
* Orange, Atwood & Stolorow (1997). Working Intersubjectively. The Analytic Press: Hillsdale, NJ. | |||
* Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Orange, D. M. (2002). Worlds of Experience: Interweaving Philosophical and Clinical Dimensions in Psychoanalysis. New York: Basic Books. | * Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Orange, D. M. (2002). Worlds of Experience: Interweaving Philosophical and Clinical Dimensions in Psychoanalysis. New York: Basic Books. | ||
* Stolorow & Atwood (1992). Contexts of Being. The Analytic Press: Hillsdale, NJ. | |||
* Stolorow, Brandchaft & Atwood (1987). Psychoanalytic Treatment: An Intersubjective Approach. The Analytic Press:Hillsdale, NJ. | |||
===Philosophy=== | |||
===Intersubjectivity and philosophy=== | |||
* ] '' |
* ] ''Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1905-1920'' | ||
* ] '' Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1921-1928 |
* ] '' Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1921-1928'' | ||
* ] ''Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1929-1935 |
* ] ''Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1929-1935'' | ||
* ] ''], Edited by S. Strasser, 1950. ISBN |
* ] '']'', Edited by S. Strasser, 1950. {{ISBN|978-90-247-0068-4}} | ||
==External links== | ==External links== | ||
{{Wikiquote}} | |||
* Article by Mats Winther | |||
* Article by Mats Winther | |||
*, ] | *, ] | ||
{{Authority control}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 23:03, 13 November 2024
Concept in philosophy and psychologyThis article's lead section may be too short to adequately summarize the key points. Please consider expanding the lead to provide an accessible overview of all important aspects of the article. (March 2021) |
In philosophy, psychology, sociology, and anthropology, intersubjectivity is the relation or intersection between people's cognitive perspectives.
Definition
Intersubjectivity is a term coined by social scientists beginning around 1970 to refer to a variety of types of human interaction. The term was introduced to psychoanalysis by George E. Atwood and Robert Stolorow, who consider it a "meta-theory" of psychoanalysis. For example, social psychologists Alex Gillespie and Flora Cornish listed at least seven definitions of intersubjectivity (and other disciplines have additional definitions):
- people's agreement on the shared definition of a concept;
- people's mutual awareness of agreement or disagreement, or of understanding or misunderstanding each other;
- people's attribution of intentionality, feelings, and beliefs to each other;
- people's implicit or automatic behavioral orientations towards other people;
- people's interactive performance within a situation;
- people's shared and taken-for-granted background assumptions, whether consensual or contested; and
- "the variety of possible relations between people's perspectives".
Intersubjectivity has been used in social science to refer to agreement. There is intersubjectivity between people if they agree on a given set of meanings or share the same perception of a situation. Similarly, Thomas Scheff defines intersubjectivity as "the sharing of subjective states by two or more individuals".
Intersubjectivity also has been used to refer to the common-sense, shared meanings constructed by people in their interactions with each other and used as an everyday resource to interpret the meaning of elements of social and cultural life. If people share common sense, then they share a definition of the situation.
Psychoanalyst Jessica Benjamin, in The Bonds of Love, wrote, "The concept of intersubjectivity has its origins in the social theory of Jürgen Habermas (1970), who used the expression 'the intersubjectivity of mutual understanding' to designate an individual capacity and a social domain." Psychoanalyst Molly Macdonald argued in 2011 that a "potential point of origin" for the term was in Jean Hyppolite's use of l'inter-subjectivité in an essay from 1955 on "The Human Situation in the Hegelian Phenomenology". However, the phenomenologist Edmund Husserl, whose work Habermas and Hyppolite draw upon, was the first to develop the term, which was subsequently elaborated upon by other phenomenologists such as Edith Stein, Emmanuel Levinas, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty.
Philosophy
Contemporarily, intersubjectivity is the major topic in both the analytic and the continental traditions of philosophy. Intersubjectivity is considered crucial not only at the relational level but also at the epistemological and even metaphysical levels. For example, intersubjectivity is postulated as playing a role in establishing the truth of propositions, and constituting the intersubjective agreement of an experience of an object.
A central concern in consciousness studies of the past 50 years is the so-called problem of other minds, which asks how we can justify our belief that people have minds much like our own and predict others' mind-states and behavior, as our experience shows we often can. Contemporary philosophical theories of intersubjectivity need to address the problem of other minds.
In the debate between cognitive individualism and cognitive universalism, some aspects of thinking are neither solely personal nor fully universal. Cognitive sociology proponents argue for intersubjectivity—an intermediate perspective of social cognition that provides a balanced view between personal and universal views of our social cognition. This approach suggests that, instead of being individual or universal thinkers, human beings subscribe to "thought communities"—communities of differing beliefs. Thought community examples include churches, professions, scientific beliefs, generations, nations, and political movements. This perspective explains why each individual thinks differently from another (individualism): person A may choose to adhere to expiry dates on foods, but person B may believe that expiry dates are only guidelines and it is still safe to eat the food days past the expiry date. But not all human beings think the same way (universalism).
Intersubjectivity argues that each thought community shares social experiences that are different from the social experiences of other thought communities, creating differing beliefs among people who subscribe to different thought communities. These experiences transcend our subjectivity, which explains why they can be shared by the entire thought community. Proponents of intersubjectivity support the view that individual beliefs are often the result of thought community beliefs, not just personal experiences or universal and objective human beliefs. Beliefs are recast in terms of standards, which are set by thought communities.
Phenomenology
Edmund Husserl, the founder of phenomenology, recognized the importance of intersubjectivity, and wrote extensively on the topic. In German, his writings on intersubjectivity are gathered in volumes 13–15 of the Husserliana. In English, his best-known text on intersubjectivity is the Cartesian Meditations (it is this text that features solely in the Husserl reader entitled The Essential Husserl). Although Husserlian phenomenology is often charged with methodological solipsism, in the fifth Cartesian Meditation, Husserl attempts to grapple with the problem of intersubjectivity and puts forward his theory of transcendental, monadological intersubjectivity.
Husserl's student Edith Stein extended intersubjectivity's basis in empathy in her 1917 doctoral dissertation, On the Problem of Empathy (Zum Problem der Einfühlung).
Psychology
Discussions and theories of intersubjectivity are prominent and of importance in contemporary psychology, theory of mind, and consciousness studies. Three major contemporary theories of intersubjectivity are theory theory, simulation theory, and interaction theory.
Shannon Spaulding, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Oklahoma State University, wrote:
Theory theorists argue that we explain and predict behaviour by employing folk psychological theories about how mental states inform behaviour. With our folk psychological theories, we infer from a target's behaviour what his or her mental states probably are. And from these inferences, plus the psychological principles in the theory connecting mental states to behavior, we predict the target's behaviour (Carruthers and Smith 1996; Davies and Stone 1995a; Gopnik and Wellman 1992; Nichols and Stich 2003).
Simulation theorists, on the other hand, claim that we explain and predict others' behaviour by using our own minds as a model and "putting ourselves in another's shoes"—that is, by imagining what our mental states would be and how we would behave if we were in the other's situation. More specifically, we simulate what the other's mental states could have been to cause the observed behaviour, then use the simulated mental states, pretend beliefs, and pretend desires as input, running them through our own decision-making mechanism. We then take the resulting conclusion and attribute it to the other person. Authors like Vittorio Gallese have proposed a theory of embodied simulation that refers to neuroscientific research on mirror neurons and phenomenological research.
Spaulding noted that this debate has stalled in the past few years, with progress limited to articulating various hybrid simulation theories—"theory theory" accounts. To resolve this impasse, authors like Shaun Gallagher put forward interaction theory. Gallagher writes that an "... important shift is taking place in social cognition research, away from a focus on the individual mind and toward ... participatory aspects of social understanding...." Interaction theory is put forward to "galvanize" the interactive turn in explanations of intersubjectivity. Gallagher defines an interaction as two or more autonomous agents engaged in co-regulated coupling behavior. For example, when walking a dog, both the owner's behavior is regulated by the dog stopping and sniffing, and the dog's behavior is regulated by the lead and the owner's commands. Ergo, walking the dog is an example of an interactive process. For Gallagher, interaction and direct perception constitute what he terms "primary" (or basic) intersubjectivity.
Studies of dialogue and dialogism reveal how language is deeply intersubjective. When we speak, we always address our interlocutors, taking their perspective and orienting to what we think they think (or, more often, don't think). Within this tradition of research, it has been argued that the structure of individual signs or symbols, the basis of language, is intersubjective and that the psychological process of self-reflection entails intersubjectivity. Recent research on mirror neurons provides evidence for the deeply intersubjective basis of human psychology, and arguably much of the literature on empathy and theory of mind relates directly to intersubjectivity.
In child development
Colwyn Trevarthen has applied intersubjectivity to the very rapid cultural development of new born infants. Research suggests that as babies, humans are biologically wired to "coordinate their actions with others". This ability to coordinate and sync with others facilitates cognitive and emotional learning through social interaction. Additionally, the most socially productive relationship between children and adults is bidirectional, where both parties actively define a shared culture. The bidirectional aspect lets the active parties organize the relationship how they see fit—what they see as important receives the most focus. Emphasis is placed on the idea that children are actively involved in how they learn, using intersubjectivity.
Across cultures
The ways intersubjectivity occurs varies across cultures. In certain Indigenous American communities, nonverbal communication is so prevalent that intersubjectivity may occur regularly amongst all members of the community, in part perhaps due to a "joint cultural understanding" and a history of shared endeavors. This "joint cultural understanding" may develop in small, Indigenous American communities where children have grown up embedded in their community's values, expectations, and livelihoods—learning through participation with adults rather than through intent verbal instruction—working in cohesion with one another in shared endeavors on a daily basis. Having grown up within this context may have led to members of this community to have what is described by some as a "blending of agendas", or by others as a "dovetailing of motives". If community or family members have the same general goals in mind they may thus act cohesively within an overlapping state of mind. Whether persons are in each other's presence or merely within the same community this blending of agendas or dovetailing of motives enables intersubjectivity to occur within these shared endeavors.
The cultural value of respeto may also contribute to intersubjectivity in some communities; unlike the English definition of 'respect', respeto refers loosely to a mutual consideration for others' activities, needs, wants, etc. Similar to "putting yourself in another's shoes" the prevalence of respeto in certain Indigenous American communities in Mexico and South America may promote intersubjectivity as persons act in accordance with one another within consideration for the community or the individual's current needs or state of mind.
Shared reference during an activity facilitates learning. Adults either teach by doing the task with children, or by directing attention toward experts. Children that had to ask questions in regard to how to perform a task were scolded for not learning by another's example, as though they were ignoring the available resources to learn a task, as seen in Tz'utujil Maya parents who scolded questioning children and asking "if they had eyes".
Children from the Chillihuani village in the Andean mountains learned to weave without explicit instruction. They learned the basic technique from others by observing, eager to participate in their community. The learning process was facilitated by watching adults and by being allowed to play and experiment using tools to create their own weaving techniques.
See also
References
- Spezzano, C. (2012). Textbook of psychoanalysis (2nd ed.). American Psychiatric Publishing. pp. 105–116. ISBN 978-1-58562-410-2.
- Gillespie, Alex; Cornish, Flora (March 2010). "Intersubjectivity: towards a dialogical analysis" (PDF). Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour. 40 (1): 19–46. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.724.7095. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5914.2009.00419.x. hdl:1893/2576.
- Scheff, Thomas J. (2015-11-15). Goffman Unbound!: A New Paradigm for Social Science. New York: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-63435-7.
- Seale, Clive (1998). Researching society and culture. London: Sage Publications. ISBN 978-0-7619-5276-3.
- Benjamin, Jessica (July 12, 1988). The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, & the Problem of Domination. Pantheon. ISBN 0394757300.
- Macdonald, M (2011) "Hegel, Psychoanalysis and Intersubjectivity" in Philosophy Compass, 6/7 p449
- Hyslop, A (2010). "Other Minds", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.) Accessed from plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/other-minds/>. Section 1.
- ^ Zerubavel, Eviatar (1997). Social Mindscapes: An Invitation to Cognitive Sociology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
- E. Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, Klumer Academic Publishers. Translated by Dorion Cairns.
- ^ Spaulding, Shannon (2012-09-05). "Introduction to debates on Social Cognition". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 11 (4): 431–448 (432, 433). doi:10.1007/s11097-012-9275-x. ISSN 1568-7759.
- Gallese, V & Sinigaglia, C. (2011) What is so special about embodied simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol. 15, No. 11.
- De Jaeger, H., Di Paulo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010) Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences. Vol. 14, No. 10. Pg 441. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009
- Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking language, mind and world dialogically. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing
- Gillespie, A. (2009). The intersubjective nature of symbols. In Brady Wagoner (Ed), Symbolic transformations. London: Routledge
- Gillespie, A. (2007). The social basis of self-reflection. In Valsiner and Rosa (Eds), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University press
- Rizzolatti, G. & Arbib, M. A. (1998). Language within our grasp. Trends in neurosciences, 21, 188-194.
- Trevarthen, Colwyn (January 2011). "What is it like to be a person who knows nothing? Defining the active intersubjective mind of a newborn human being". Infant and Child Development. 20 (1): 119–135. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.475.9911. doi:10.1002/icd.689.
- ^ Stone, Lynda; Underwood, Charles; Hotchkiss, Jacqueline (2012). "The Relational Habitus: Intersubjective Processes in Learning Settings". Human Development. 55 (2): 65–91. doi:10.1159/000337150. S2CID 144722047. Retrieved 10 December 2014.
- ^ Correa-Chávez, M., & Roberts, A. (2012). A cultural analysis is necessary in understanding intersubjectivity. Culture & Psychology, 18(1), 99-108. doi: 10.1177/1354067X11427471
- Danziger, E., & Rumsey, A. (2013). Introduction: From Opacity to intersubjectivity across languages and cultures. Language & Communication, 33(3), 247-250.
- Paradise, Ruth; Rogoff, Barbara (2009). "Side by Side: Learning by Observing and Pitching In". Ethos. 37 (1): 102–138. doi:10.1111/j.1548-1352.2009.01033.x.
- Bolin, Inge (2006). Growing Up in a Culture of Respect: Childrearing in highland Peru (2 ed.). Austin: University of Texas. pp. 90–99. ISBN 978-0-292-71298-0.
Further reading
Psychoanalysis
- Brandchaft, Doctors & Sorter (2010). Toward an Emancipatory Psychoanalysis. Routledge: New York.
- Laplanche, J. & Pontalis, J. B. (1974). The Language of Psycho-Analysis, Edited by W. W. Norton & Company, ISBN 0-393-01105-4
- Orange, Atwood & Stolorow (1997). Working Intersubjectively. The Analytic Press: Hillsdale, NJ.
- Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Orange, D. M. (2002). Worlds of Experience: Interweaving Philosophical and Clinical Dimensions in Psychoanalysis. New York: Basic Books.
- Stolorow & Atwood (1992). Contexts of Being. The Analytic Press: Hillsdale, NJ.
- Stolorow, Brandchaft & Atwood (1987). Psychoanalytic Treatment: An Intersubjective Approach. The Analytic Press:Hillsdale, NJ.
Philosophy
- Edmund Husserl Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1905-1920
- Edmund Husserl Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1921-1928
- Edmund Husserl Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1929-1935
- Edmund Husserl Cartesian Meditations, Edited by S. Strasser, 1950. ISBN 978-90-247-0068-4
External links
- Critique of intersubjectivity Article by Mats Winther
- Edmund Husserl: Empathy, intersubjectivity and lifeworld, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy