Revision as of 23:39, 18 March 2006 editSpace Cadet (talk | contribs)8,095 edits rm double "now"← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 22:47, 14 December 2024 edit undo87.100.216.54 (talk)No edit summary | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|German philosopher (1788–1860)}} | |||
{{Infobox_Philosopher | | |||
{{Redirect|Schopenhauer}} | |||
<!-- Scroll down to edit this page --> | |||
{{Use dmy dates|date=October 2020}} | |||
<!-- Philosopher Category --> | |||
{{Infobox philosopher | |||
region = Western Philosophers | | |||
|region = ] | |||
|era = ] | |||
|image = File:Arthur Schopenhauer by J Schäfer, 1859b.jpg | |||
|caption = Schopenhauer in 1859 | |||
|signature = Arthur Schopenhauer Signature.svg | |||
|name = Arthur Schopenhauer | |||
|birth_date = {{birth date|1788|2|22|df=y}} | |||
|birth_place = ] (Danzig),<!--keep both names as per the Danzig/Gdansk vote (Talk:Gdańsk/Vote): "the first occurrence of the name should be used in the form Gdańsk (Danzig)"--> ], ] | |||
|death_date = {{Death date and age|1860|9|21|1788|2|22|df=y}} | |||
|death_place = ], ] | |||
|education = {{plainlist| | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] (PhD, 1813)}} | |||
|relatives = {{Plainlist| | |||
* ] (mother) | |||
* ] (sister) | |||
}} | |||
|institutions = ] | |||
|school_tradition = {{plainlist| | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] (disputed)<ref name=iep>{{cite web|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/schopenh|title=Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)}}</ref><ref>] reviews the commonly held position that Schopenhauer was a transcendental idealist and he rejects it: "Though it is deeply heretical from the standpoint of transcendental idealism, Schopenhauer's objective standpoint involves a form of '']'', i.e. the assumption of the independent reality of the world of experience." (Beiser 2016, p. 40)</ref> | |||
* ]<ref name=Brit> – ]</ref> | |||
* ] | |||
}} | |||
|main_interests = ], ], ], ], ] | |||
|notable_ideas = {{Plain list| | |||
* ]<ref>Arthur Schopenhauer, ''Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Presentation, Volume 1'', Routledge, 2016, p. 211: "the world mere ''presentation'', object for a subject ..."</ref><ref>Lennart Svensson, ''Borderline: A Traditionalist Outlook for Modern Man'', Numen Books, 2015, p. 71: " said that 'the world is our conception'. A world without a perceiver would in that case be an impossibility. But we can—he said—gain knowledge about Essential Reality for looking into ourselves, by introspection. ... This is one of many examples of the anthropic principle. The world is there for the sake of man."</ref> | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] as ] | |||
* ]<ref name="PhilPapers"/> | |||
* ] | |||
* Criticism of ]<ref name="WWR3">'']'', vol. 3, Ch. 50.</ref><ref name=Jacquette/> | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
}} | |||
}} | |||
'''Arthur Schopenhauer''' ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|ʃ|oʊ|p|ən|h|aʊər}} {{respell|SHOH|pən|how|ər}};<ref>{{citation|last=Wells|first=John C.|year=2008|title=Longman Pronunciation Dictionary|edition=3rd|publisher=Longman|isbn=978-1-4058-8118-0}}</ref> {{IPA|de|ˈaʁtuːɐ̯ ˈʃoːpn̩haʊɐ|lang|De-Arthur Schopenhauer2.ogg}}; 22 February 1788 – 21 September 1860) was a German philosopher. He is known for his 1818 work '']'' (expanded in 1844), which characterizes the ] world as the manifestation of a blind and irrational ] will.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Arthur Schopenhauer|year=2004|url=https://archive.org/details/essaysaphorisms00scho/page/23|title=Essays and Aphorisms|publisher=Penguin Classics|isbn=978-0-14-044227-4|page=}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last=Magee|first=Bryan|title=The Philosophy of Schopenhauer |date=1997-08-14|chapter-url=https://academic.oup.com/book/32819/chapter/275011622|chapter=The World as Will|publisher=Oxford University PressOxford|isbn=978-0-19-823722-8|edition=1|pages=137–163|language=en|doi=10.1093/0198237227.003.0007 |ref=none}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Vandenabeele|first=Bart|date=December 2007|title=Schopenhauer on the Values of Aesthetic Experience|url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2007.tb00065.x|journal=The Southern Journal of Philosophy|language=en|volume=45|issue=4|pages=565–582|doi=10.1111/j.2041-6962.2007.tb00065.x}}</ref> Building on the ] of ] (1724–1804), Schopenhauer developed an ] metaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas of ].<ref name="WWR3"/><ref name=Jacquette>{{cite book|title=Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts|year=2007|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0-521-04406-6|editor=Dale Jacquette|page=162|quote=For Kant, the mathematical sublime, as seen for example in the starry heavens, suggests to imagination the infinite, which in turn leads by subtle turns of contemplation to the concept of God. Schopenhauer's atheism will have none of this, and he rightly observes that despite adopting Kant's distinction between the dynamical and mathematical sublime, his theory of the sublime, making reference to the struggles and sufferings of struggles and sufferings of Will, is unlike Kant's.}}</ref> | |||
<!-- Image and Caption --> | |||
image_name = Schopenhauer.jpg | | |||
image_caption = Arthur Schopenhauer | | |||
Schopenhauer was among the first thinkers in ] to share and affirm significant tenets of ], such as ], denial of the ], and the notion of the ].<ref>See the book-length study about oriental influences on the genesis of Schopenhauer's philosophy by ]: ''Schopenhauer's Compass. An Introduction to Schopenhauer's Philosophy and its Origins''. Wil: UniversityMedia, 2014 ({{ISBN|978-3-906000-03-9}}) | |||
<!-- Information --> | |||
* {{cite book|title=An Introduction to the History of Psychology|edition=6th|year=2009|publisher=Cengage Learning|isbn=978-0-495-50621-8|last=Hergenhahn |first=B. R.|page=216|quote=Although Schopenhauer was an atheist, he realized that his philosophy of denial had been part of several great religions; for example, Christianity, Hinduism, and Buddhism.}}<!--|access-date=2 September 2012--></ref> His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation of ].<ref>{{cite book|title=Essays and Aphorisms|year=2004|publisher=Penguin Classics|isbn=978-0-14-044227-4|author=Arthur Schopenhauer|pages=|quote=...but there has been none who tried with so great a show of learning to demonstrate that the pessimistic outlook is ''justified'', that life itself is really bad. It is to this end that Schopenhauer's metaphysic of will and idea exists.|url=https://archive.org/details/essaysaphorisms00scho/page/22}} | |||
name = Arthur Schopenhauer | | |||
* '''' – audiobook from ]. | |||
birth = ], ] (], ]) | | |||
* {{cite book|title=Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion, Volume 2|year=2009|publisher=Springer|isbn=978-0-387-71801-9|editor1=David A. Leeming |editor2=Kathryn Madden |editor3=Stanton Marlan |page=824|quote=A more accurate statement might be that for a German—rather than a French or British writer of that time—Schopenhauer was an honest and open atheist.}}<!--|access-date=2 September 2012--></ref> Though his work failed to garner substantial attention during his lifetime, he had a posthumous impact across various disciplines, including philosophy, literature, and science. His writing on ], ], and ] have influenced many thinkers and artists. | |||
death = ], ] (], ]) | | |||
school_tradition = ], ] | | |||
main_interests = ], ], ], ], ] | | |||
influences = ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ] | | |||
influenced = ], ], ], ], ], ], ] | | |||
notable_ideas = ], ] | | |||
}} | |||
'''Arthur Schopenhauer''' (], ] – ], ]) was a ] ]. He is most famous for his work '']''. He is commonly known for having espoused a sort of philosophical ] that saw life as being essentially ], futile, and full of suffering. However, upon closer inspection, in accordance with ], especially that of ] and ], he saw ], deliverance, or escape from suffering in ] ], ] for others, and ] living. His ideas profoundly influenced the fields of ], ], ], and ]. | |||
== Life == | == Life == | ||
Schopenhauer was born in ] in ], ] (now ], Poland, near ]). He was the son of Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer and ], a middle class mercantile family of ] heritage, although they had strong feelings against any kind of nationalism. Indeed, the name Arthur was selected by his father especially because it was the same in ], ], and ]. His parents were both from the city, and Johanna was an author as well. After the city was annexed by ] during the second ] in ], the Schopenhauer family fled to ]; in ] Schopenhauer's father died, possibly by ], and Johanna moved to ]. Because of a promise to pursue a business career, Schopenhauer remained in Hamburg. His disgust of this career, however, drove him away to join his mother in Weimar after only a year. He never got along with his mother; when the writer ], who was a friend of Johanna Schopenhauer, told her that he thought her son was destined for great things, Johanna objected: she had never heard there could be ''two'' geniuses in a single family. | |||
=== Family === | |||
Schopenhauer studied at the ] and was awarded a PhD from the ]. In ], Schopenhauer became a lecturer at the ]; it was there that his opposition to ] began. | |||
Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal grandfather, {{ill|Andreas Schopenhauer|de}} (1720–1793), was a wealthy merchant in Danzig. Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal grandmother, Anna Renata Schopenhauer (1726–1804), was the daughter of a Dutch merchant and the Dutch ambassador to the Hanseatic city of Danzig Hendrik Soermans (1700–1775). Arthur Schopenhauer's maternal grandfather, {{ill|Christian Heinrich Trosiener|de}} (1730–1797) was a merchant in Danzig and a councilor from the middle class. Arthur Schopenhauer's maternal grandmother, Elizabeth Trosiener (1745–1818), was daughter of pharmacist Georg Lehmann (died 1762) and his wife Susanna Concordia Lehmann, née Neumann (born 1718). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandfather, {{ill|Johann Schopenhauer|de}} (1670–after 1724), was the mentioned merchant in Gdansk. Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandmother, Marie Elizabeth Schopenhauer, née Lessig, was a daughter of merchant Andreas Lessig (1658–1713). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandfather through paternal grandmother, {{ill|Hendrik Soermans|de}} (1700–1775), was a Dutch merchant, Ambassador of the Netherlands in Gdansk, son of pastor Johannes Soermans (1670–1754) and grandson of Martinus Soermans (1638–1705). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-greatgrandfather, Johann Schopenhauer (1630–1701), was farmer in Petershagen and son of Simon Schopenhauer (1580–1660) and grandson of Salomon Schopenhauer (born 1550). {{Citation needed|date=September 2024}} | |||
=== Early life === | |||
While in Berlin, Schopenhauer was consumed in a lawsuit from a woman named Caroline Marquet. She asked for damages from him, a man of independent means, on the basis that she had been injured when Schopenhauer allegedly pushed her. Marquet had noisily attracted Schopenhauer's attention. Then, Marquet's companion witnessed her as being prostrate outside of his apartment. Marquet claimed that the philosopher had assaulted and battered her after she refused to leave his doorway. In this manner, she succeeded in gaining, through the court, a portion of Schopenhauer's limited wealth; he had to make payments for many years. | |||
] | |||
Arthur Schopenhauer was born on 22 February 1788, in ] (then part of the ]; later in the ] ''Danzig'') on Św. Ducha 47 (in Prussia Heiliggeistgasse), the son of {{ill|Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer|de}} (1747–1805) and his wife ] (née Trosiener; 1766–1838),<ref name="Google Books">{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=fW5Dl-tUS_oC&q=Schopenhauer+%2222+February%22&pg=PR30|title=Chronology|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|author2=Günter Zöller|author3=Eric F. J. Payne|year=1999|series=Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will|publisher=]|page=xxx |isbn=978-0-521-57766-3}}</ref> both descendants of wealthy German ] families. While they came from a ] background, neither of them was very religious;{{r|Cartwright|p=79}}<ref name="Bullock 1920 p. 53">{{cite book | last=Bullock | first=A.B. | title=The Supreme Human Tragedy: And Other Essays | publisher=C.W. Daniel | year=1920 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XipHAAAAMAAJ&pg=PA53 | access-date=2022-10-22 | page=53}}</ref> both supported the ],{{r|Cartwright|p=13}} were ], ] and ].{{r|Cartwright|p=9}} When Gdańsk became part of ] in 1793, Heinrich moved to ]—a free city with a republican constitution. His firm continued trading in Danzig where most of their extended families remained. ], Arthur's only sibling, was born on 12 July 1797.{{Citation needed|date=September 2024}} | |||
In 1797, Arthur was sent to ] to live with the family of his father's business associate, Grégoire de Blésimaire. He seemed to enjoy his two-year stay there, learning to speak French and fostering a life-long friendship with Jean Anthime Grégoire de Blésimaire.{{r|Cartwright|p=18}} As early as 1799, Arthur started playing the flute.{{r|Cartwright|p=30}} | |||
Schopenhauer's health deteriorated during the year of ]. He died of ] on ] of the same year at the age of 72. | |||
In 1803, he accompanied his parents on a European tour of ], Britain, France, ], ] and ]. Viewed as primarily a pleasure tour, Heinrich used the opportunity to visit some of his business associates abroad.{{Citation needed|date=September 2024}} | |||
Schopenhauer called himself a ] and despised Hegel. He formulated a ] ] that gained importance and support after the failure of the German and Austrian ]s of ]. | |||
Heinrich presented Arthur with a choice: he could either stay at home to begin preparations for university or travel with them to further his merchant education. Arthur chose to travel with them. He deeply regretted his choice later because the merchant training was very tedious. He spent twelve weeks of the tour attending school in ], where he was confused by strict and intellectual ] who he described as shallow. He continued to sharply criticize Anglican religiosity later in life despite his general Anglophilia.{{r|Cartwright|p=56}} He was also under pressure from his father, who became very critical of his educational results.{{Citation needed|date=September 2024}} | |||
In 1805, Heinrich drowned in a canal near their home in Hamburg. Although it was possible that his death was accidental, his wife and son believed that it was suicide. He was prone to ] and ], each becoming more pronounced later in his life.<ref>Safranski (1990), p. 12</ref> Heinrich had become so fussy, even his wife started to doubt his mental health.{{r|Cartwright|p=43}} "There was, in the father's life, some dark and vague source of fear which later made him hurl himself to his death from the attic of his house in Hamburg."{{r|Cartwright|p=88}} | |||
Arthur showed similar moodiness during his youth and often acknowledged that he inherited it from his father. There were other instances of serious mental health problems on his father's side of the family.{{r|Cartwright|p=4}} Despite his hardship, Schopenhauer liked his father and later referred to him in a positive light.{{r|Cartwright|p=90}} Heinrich Schopenhauer left the family with a significant inheritance that was split in three among Johanna and the children. Arthur Schopenhauer was entitled to control of his part when he reached the age of majority. He invested it conservatively in government bonds and earned annual interest that was more than double the salary of a university professor.{{r|Cartwright|p=136}} After quitting his merchant apprenticeship, with some encouragement from his mother, he dedicated himself to studies at the ], in ]. While there, he also enjoyed social life among the local nobility, spending large amounts of money, which deeply concerned his frugal mother.{{r|Cartwright|p=128}} He left the Gymnasium after writing a satirical poem about one of the schoolmasters. Although Arthur claimed that he left voluntarily, his mother's letter indicates that he may have been expelled.{{r|Cartwright|p=129}} | |||
] | |||
Arthur spent two years as a merchant in honor of his dead father. During this time, he had doubts about being able to start a new life as a scholar.{{r|Cartwright|p=120}} Most of his prior education was as a practical merchant and he had trouble learning Latin; a prerequisite for an academic career.{{r|Cartwright|p=117}} | |||
His mother moved away, with her daughter Adele, to ]—then the centre of ]—to enjoy social life among writers and artists. Arthur and his mother did not part on good terms. In one letter, she wrote: "You are unbearable and burdensome, and very hard to live with; all your good qualities are overshadowed by your conceit, and made useless to the world simply because you cannot restrain your propensity to pick holes in other people."<ref>{{cite book |last= Wallace|first= W.|date= 2003|title= Life of Arthur Schopenhauer|location= Honolulu|publisher= University Press of the Pacific|page= 59|isbn=978-1-4102-0641-1}}</ref> His mother, Johanna, was generally described as vivacious and sociable.{{r|Cartwright|p=9}} She died 24 years later. Some of Arthur's negative opinions about women may be rooted in his troubled relationship with his mother.<ref>Durant, Will, ''The Story of Philosophy'', Garden City Publishing Co., Inc., New York, p. 350</ref> | |||
Arthur moved to Hamburg to live with his friend Jean Anthime, who was also studying to become a merchant. | |||
=== Education === | |||
He moved to Weimar but did not live with his mother, who even tried to discourage him from coming by explaining that they would not get along very well.{{r|Cartwright|p=131}} Their relationship deteriorated even further due to their temperamental differences. He accused his mother of being financially irresponsible, flirtatious and seeking to remarry, which he considered an insult to his father's memory.{{r|Cartwright|p=116,131}} His mother, while professing her love to him, criticized him sharply for being moody, tactless, and argumentative, and urged him to improve his behavior so that he would not alienate people.{{r|Cartwright|p=129}} Arthur concentrated on his studies, which were now going very well, and he also enjoyed the usual social life such as balls, parties and theater. By that time Johanna's famous salon was well established among local intellectuals and dignitaries, the most celebrated of them being ]. Arthur attended her parties, usually when he knew that Goethe would be there—although the famous writer and statesman seemed not even to notice the young and unknown student. It is possible that Goethe kept a distance because Johanna warned him about her son's depressive and combative nature, or because Goethe was then on bad terms with Arthur's language instructor and roommate, ].{{r|Cartwright|p=134}} Schopenhauer was also captivated by the beautiful ], mistress of ], and he wrote to her his only known love poem.{{r|Cartwright|p=135}} Despite his later celebration of asceticism and negative views of sexuality, Schopenhauer occasionally had sexual affairs—usually with women of lower social status, such as servants, actresses, and sometimes even paid prostitutes.{{r|Cartwright|p=21}} In a letter to his friend Anthime he claims that such affairs continued even in his mature age and admits that he had two out-of-wedlock daughters (born in 1819 and 1836), both of whom died in infancy.{{r|Cartwright|p=25}} In their youthful correspondence Arthur and Anthime were somewhat boastful and competitive about their sexual exploits—but Schopenhauer seemed aware that women usually did not find him very charming or physically attractive, and his desires often remained unfulfilled.{{r|Cartwright|p=22}} | |||
He left Weimar to become a student at the ] in 1809. There are no written reasons about why Schopenhauer chose that university instead of the then more famous ], but Göttingen was known as more modern and scientifically oriented, with less attention given to theology.{{r|Cartwright|p=140}} Law or medicine were usual choices for young men of Schopenhauer's status who also needed career and income; he chose medicine due to his ]. Among his notable professors were ], ], ], ], ], ] and ].{{r|Cartwright|p=141–144}} He studied ], ] and ] under ], the author of '']'', who made a strong impression and advised him to concentrate on ] and ].{{r|Cartwright|p=144}} He decided to switch from medicine to philosophy around 1810–11 and he left Göttingen, which did not have a strong philosophy program: besides Schulze, the only other philosophy professor was ], whom Schopenhauer disliked.{{r|Cartwright|p=150}} He did not regret his medicinal and scientific studies; he claimed that they were necessary for a philosopher, and even in Berlin he attended more lectures in sciences than in philosophy.{{r|Cartwright|p=170}} During his days at Göttingen, he spent considerable time studying, but also continued his flute playing and social life. His friends included ], ], ], and ]{{r|Cartwright|p=151}} | |||
He arrived at the newly founded ] for the winter semester of 1811–12. At the same time, his mother had just begun her literary career; she published her first book in 1810, a biography of her friend ], which was a critical success. Arthur attended lectures by the prominent ] philosopher ], but quickly found many points of disagreement with his {{lang|de|Wissenschaftslehre}}; he also found Fichte's lectures tedious and hard to understand.{{r|Cartwright|p=159}} He later mentioned Fichte only in critical, negative terms{{r|Cartwright|p=159}}—seeing his philosophy as a lower-quality version of Kant's and considering it useful only because Fichte's poor arguments unintentionally highlighted some failings of Kantianism.{{r|Cartwright|pages=165–169}} He also attended the lectures of the famous Protestant theologian ], whom he also quickly came to dislike.{{r|Cartwright|p=174}} His notes and comments on Schleiermacher's lectures show that Schopenhauer was becoming very ] and moving towards ].{{r|Cartwright|p=175}} He learned by self-directed reading; besides Plato, Kant and Fichte he also read the works of ], ], ], ], ], and much current scientific literature.{{r|Cartwright|p=170}} He attended philological courses by ] and ] and continued his naturalistic interests with courses by ], ], ], ], ], ] and ] (Lichtenstein was also a friend whom he met at one of his mother's parties in Weimar).{{r|Cartwright|p=171–174}} | |||
=== Early work === | |||
Schopenhauer left Berlin in a rush in 1813, fearing that the city could be attacked and that he could be pressed into military service as Prussia had just joined the ].{{r|Cartwright|p=179}} He returned to Weimar but left after less than a month, disgusted by the fact that his mother was now living with her supposed lover, {{ill|Georg Friedrich Konrad Ludwig Müller von Gerstenbergk|de|Georg Friedrich von Gerstenbergk}} | |||
(1778–1838), a civil servant twelve years younger than her; he considered the relationship an act of infidelity to his father's memory.{{r|Cartwright|p=188}} He settled for a while in ], hoping that no army would pass through the small town. He spent his time in solitude, hiking in the mountains and the ] and writing his dissertation, '']''. | |||
Schopenhauer completed his dissertation at about the same time as the French army was defeated at the ]. He became irritated by the arrival of soldiers in the town and accepted his mother's invitation to visit her in Weimar. She tried to convince him that her relationship with Gerstenbergk was platonic and that she had no intention of remarrying.{{r|Cartwright|p=230}} But Schopenhauer remained suspicious and often came in conflict with Gerstenbergk because he considered him untalented, pretentious, and ].{{r|Cartwright|p=231}} His mother had just published her second book, ''Reminiscences of a Journey in the Years 1803, 1804, and 1805'', a description of their family tour of Europe, which quickly became a hit. She found his dissertation incomprehensible and said it was unlikely that anyone would ever buy a copy. In a fit of temper Arthur told her that people would read his work long after the "rubbish" she wrote was totally forgotten.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://courseweb.stthomas.edu/paschons/language_http/essays/Schopenhauer.html |title=Schopenhauer: A Pessimist in the Optimistic Month of May |publisher=Germanic American Institute |access-date=12 March 2010 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100611051923/http://courseweb.stthomas.edu/paschons/language_http/essays/schopenhauer.html |archive-date=11 June 2010 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=https://archive.org/stream/selectedessaysof033377mbp/selectedessaysof033377mbp_djvu.txt |title=Full text of "Selected Essays Of Schopenhauer" |access-date=12 March 2010}}</ref> In fact, although they considered her novels of dubious quality, the ] held her in high esteem because they consistently sold well. Hans Brockhaus (1888–1965) later claimed that his predecessors "saw nothing in this manuscript, but wanted to please one of our best-selling authors by publishing her son's work. We published more and more of her son Arthur's work and today nobody remembers Johanna, but her son's works are in steady demand and contribute to Brockhaus' reputation."<ref name=mom>{{citation |last=Fredriksson |first=Einar H. |contribution=The Dutch Publishing Scene: Elsevier and North-Holland |pages=61–76 |title=A Century of Science Publishing: A Collection of Essays |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mwWrRYyck6AC&pg=PA61 |editor-last=Fredriksson |editor-first=Einar H. |display-editors=0 |isbn=978-4-274-90424-0 |publisher=IOS Press |location=Amsterdam |year=2001 }}</ref> He kept large portraits of the pair in his office in ] for the edification of his new editors.<ref name=mom/> | |||
Also contrary to his mother's prediction, Schopenhauer's dissertation made an impression on Goethe, to whom he sent it as a gift.{{r|Cartwright|p=241}} Although it is doubtful that Goethe agreed with Schopenhauer's philosophical positions, he was impressed by his intellect and extensive scientific education.{{r|Cartwright|p=243}} Their subsequent meetings and correspondence were a great honor to a young philosopher, who was finally acknowledged by his intellectual hero. They mostly discussed Goethe's newly published (and somewhat lukewarmly received) work on ]. Schopenhauer soon started writing his own treatise on the subject, '']'', which in many points differed from his teacher's. Although they remained polite towards each other, their growing theoretical disagreements—and especially Schopenhauer's extreme self-confidence and tactless criticisms—soon made Goethe become distant again and after 1816 their correspondence became less frequent.{{r|Cartwright|p=247–265}} Schopenhauer later admitted that he was greatly hurt by this rejection, but he continued to praise Goethe, and considered his color theory a great introduction to his own.{{r|Cartwright|p=252,256,265}} | |||
Another important experience during his stay in Weimar was his acquaintance with Friedrich Majer<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Willson |first=A. Leslie |title=Friedrich Majer: Romantic Indologist |date=1961 |journal=Texas Studies in Literature and Language |volume=3 |issue=1 |pages=40–49 |jstor=40753707 |issn=0040-4691}}</ref>—a ], ] and disciple of ]—who introduced him to ]{{sfn|Clarke|1997|pages=67–68}}{{r|Cartwright|p=266}} (see also ]). Schopenhauer was immediately impressed by the '']'' (he called them "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed that they contained superhuman concepts) and the ],{{sfn|Clarke|1997|pages=67–68}} and put them on a par with Plato and Kant.{{r|Cartwright|p=268,272}} He continued his studies by reading the '']'', an amateurish German journal ''Asiatisches Magazin'', and ''Asiatick Researches'' by ].{{r|Cartwright|p=267,272}} Schopenhauer held a profound respect for ];{{sfn|Clarke|1997|pages=67–69}} and loved ]. Although he never revered a Buddhist text he regarded ] as the most distinguished religion.{{sfn|Clarke|1997|pages=273}}{{r|Cartwright|p=272}} His studies on Hindu and Buddhist texts were constrained by the lack of adequate literature,{{sfn|Clarke|1997|page=69}} and the latter were mostly restricted to ]. He also claimed that he formulated most of his ideas independently,{{sfn|Clarke|1997|pages=67–68}} and only later realized the similarities with Buddhism.{{r|Cartwright|p=274–276}} | |||
Schopenhauer read the Latin translation and praised the Upanishads in his main work, '']'' (1819), as well as in his '']'' (1851), and commented | |||
<blockquote>In the whole world there is no study so beneficial and so elevating as that of the Upanishads. It has been the solace of my life, it will be the solace of my death.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Schopenhauer |first=Arthur |title=The world as will and idea|date=22 April 2019|publisher=Classic Wisdom Reprint |isbn=978-1-950330-23-2|oclc=1229105608}}</ref></blockquote> | |||
] | |||
As the relationship with his mother fell to a new low, in May 1814 he left Weimar and moved to ].{{r|Cartwright|p=265}} He continued his philosophical studies, enjoyed the cultural life, socialized with intellectuals and engaged in sexual affairs.{{r|Cartwright|p=284}} His friends in Dresden were ], ], ] and Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl, a young painter who made a romanticized portrait of him in which he improved some of Schopenhauer's unattractive physical features.{{r|Cartwright|p=278,283}} His criticisms of local artists occasionally caused public quarrels when he ran into them in public.{{r|Cartwright|p=282}} Schopenhauer's main occupation during his stay in Dresden was his seminal philosophical work, '']'', which he started writing in 1814 and finished in 1818.<ref>Although the first volume was published by December 1818, it was printed with a title page erroneously giving the year as 1819 (see {{citation |last=Braunschweig |first=Yael |contribution=Schopenhauer and Rossinian Universiality: On the Italianate in Schopenhauer's Metaphysics of Music <!--|pages=283–304--> |title=The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NQ_3AQAAQBAJ |editor-last=Mathew |editor-first=Nicholas |editor2-last=Walton |editor2-first=Benjamin |display-editors=0 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=] |date=2013 |isbn=978-0-521-76805-4 |page=}}).</ref> He was recommended to the publisher ] by Baron Ferdinand von Biedenfeld, an acquaintance of his mother.{{r|Cartwright|p=285}} Although Brockhaus accepted his manuscript, Schopenhauer made a poor impression because of his quarrelsome and fussy attitude, as well as very poor sales of the book after it was published in December 1818.{{r|Cartwright|p=285–289}} | |||
In September 1818, while waiting for his book to be published and conveniently escaping an affair with a maid that caused an unwanted pregnancy,{{r|Cartwright|p=342}} Schopenhauer left Dresden for a year-long vacation in Italy.{{r|Cartwright|p=346}} He visited ], ], ], ] and ], travelling alone or accompanied by mostly English tourists he met.{{r|Cartwright|p=350}} He spent the winter months in ], where he accidentally met his acquaintance ] and engaged in numerous quarrels with German tourists in the ], among them ], who also mentioned his insulting remarks and unpleasant character.{{r|Cartwright|p=348–349}} He enjoyed art, architecture, and ancient ruins, attended plays and operas, and continued his philosophical contemplation and love affairs.{{r|Cartwright|p=346–350}} One of his affairs supposedly became serious, and for a while he contemplated marriage to a rich Italian noblewoman—but, despite his mentioning this several times, no details are known and it may have been Schopenhauer exaggerating.<ref>Safranski, Rüdiger (1991) '']''. Harvard University Press. p. 244</ref>{{r|Cartwright|p=345}} He corresponded regularly with his sister Adele and became close to her as her relationship with Johanna and Gerstenbergk also deteriorated.{{r|Cartwright|p=344}} She informed him about their financial troubles as the banking house of A. L. Muhl in Danzig—in which her mother invested their whole savings and Arthur a third of his—was near bankruptcy.{{r|Cartwright|p=351}} Arthur offered to share his assets, but his mother refused and became further enraged by his insulting comments.{{r|Cartwright|p=352}} The women managed to receive only thirty percent of their savings while Arthur, using his business knowledge, took a suspicious and aggressive stance towards the banker and eventually received his part in full.{{r|Cartwright|p=354–356}} The affair additionally worsened the relationships among all three members of the Schopenhauer family.{{r|Cartwright|p=352,354}} | |||
He shortened his stay in Italy because of the trouble with Muhl and returned to Dresden.{{r|Cartwright|p=356}} Disturbed by the financial risk and the lack of responses to his book he decided to take an academic position since it provided him with both income and an opportunity to promote his views.{{r|Cartwright|p=358}} He contacted his friends at universities in Heidelberg, Göttingen and Berlin and found ] most attractive.{{r|Cartwright|p=358–362}} He scheduled his lectures to coincide with those of the famous philosopher ], whom Schopenhauer described as a "clumsy charlatan".<ref>Schopenhauer, Arthur. Author's preface to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of sufficient reason", p. 1 (] on Wikisource.)</ref> He was especially appalled by Hegel's supposedly poor knowledge of natural sciences and tried to engage him in a quarrel about it already at his test lecture in March 1820.{{r|Cartwright|p=363}} Hegel was also facing political suspicions at the time, when many progressive professors were ], while Schopenhauer carefully mentioned in his application that he had no interest in politics.{{r|Cartwright|p=362}} Despite their differences and the arrogant request to schedule lectures at the same time as his own, Hegel still voted to accept Schopenhauer to the university.{{r|Cartwright|p=365}} Only five students turned up to Schopenhauer's lectures, and he dropped out of ]. A late essay, "On University Philosophy", expressed his resentment towards the work conducted in academies. | |||
=== Later life === | |||
]]] | |||
After his trying in academia, he continued to travel extensively, visiting ], ], ], ], ], Milan and spending eight months in Florence.{{r|Cartwright|p=411}} Before he left for his three-year travel, Schopenhauer had an incident with his Berlin neighbor, 47-year-old seamstress Caroline Louise Marquet. The details of the August 1821 incident are unknown. He claimed that he had just pushed her from his entrance after she had rudely refused to leave, and that she had purposely fallen to the ground so that she could sue him. She claimed that he had attacked her so violently that she had become paralyzed on her right side and unable to work. She immediately sued him, and the process lasted until May 1827, when a court found Schopenhauer guilty and forced him to pay her an annual pension until her death in 1842.{{r|Cartwright|p=408–411}} | |||
Schopenhauer enjoyed Italy, where he studied art and socialized with Italian and English nobles.{{r|Cartwright|p=411–414}} It was his last visit to the country. He left for ] and stayed there for a year, mostly recuperating from various health issues, some of them possibly caused by venereal diseases (the treatment his doctor used suggests ]).{{r|Cartwright|p=415}} He contacted publishers, offering to translate Hume into German and Kant into English, but his proposals were declined.{{r|Cartwright|p=417,422}} Returning to Berlin, he began to study Spanish so he could read some of his favorite authors in their original language. He liked ], ], ], and especially ].{{r|Cartwright|p=420}} He also made failed attempts to publish his translations of their works. A few attempts to revive his lectures—again scheduled at the same time as Hegel's—also failed, as did his inquiries about relocating to other universities.{{r|Cartwright|p=429–432}} | |||
During his Berlin years, Schopenhauer occasionally mentioned his desire to marry and have a family.{{r|Cartwright|p=404,432}} For a while he was unsuccessfully courting 17-year-old Flora Weiss, who was 22 years younger than himself.{{r|Cartwright|p=433}} His unpublished writings from that time show that he was already very critical of ] but still not advocating ]—instead musing about a ] relationship that he called "tetragamy".{{r|Cartwright|p=404–408}} He had an on-and-off relationship with a young dancer, ] (she also used the surname Medon after one of her ex-lovers).{{r|Cartwright|p=403}} They met when he was 33 and she was 19 and working at the Berlin Opera. She had already had numerous lovers and a son out of wedlock, and later gave birth to another son, this time to an unnamed foreign diplomat (she soon had another pregnancy but the child was stillborn).{{r|Cartwright|p=403–404}} As Schopenhauer was preparing to escape from Berlin in 1831, due to a ] epidemic, he offered to take her with him on the condition that she left her young son behind.{{r|Cartwright|p=404}} She refused and he went alone; in his will he left her a significant sum of money, but insisted that it should not be spent in any way on her second son.{{r|Cartwright|p=404}} | |||
Schopenhauer claimed that, in his last year in Berlin, he had a ] that urged him to escape from the city.{{r|Cartwright|p=436}} As he arrived in his new home in ], he supposedly had another ], an apparition of his dead father and his mother, who was still alive.{{r|Cartwright|p=436}} This experience led him to spend some time investigating ] phenomena and ]. He was quite critical of the available studies and claimed that they were mostly ignorant or fraudulent, but he did believe that there are authentic cases of such phenomena and tried to explain them through his metaphysics as manifestations of the will.{{r|Cartwright|p=437–452}} | |||
Upon his arrival in Frankfurt, he experienced a period of depression and declining health.{{r|Cartwright|p=454}} He renewed his correspondence with his mother, and she seemed concerned that he might commit suicide like his father.{{r|Cartwright|p=454–457}} By now Johanna and Adele were living very modestly. Johanna's writing did not bring her much income, and her popularity was waning.{{r|Cartwright|p=458}} Their correspondence remained reserved, and Arthur seemed undisturbed by her death in 1838.{{r|Cartwright|p=460}} His relationship with his sister grew closer and he corresponded with her until she died in 1849.{{r|Cartwright|p=463}} | |||
In July 1832, Schopenhauer left Frankfurt for ] but returned in July 1833 to remain there for the rest of his life, except for a few short journeys.{{r|Cartwright|p=464}} He lived alone except for a succession of pet ]s named ] and Butz. In 1836, he published ''On the Will in Nature''. In 1838, he sent his essay "]" to the contest of the ] in 1838 and won the prize in 1839. He sent another essay, "]", to the ] in 1839, but did not win the (1840) prize despite being the only contestant.<ref>{{harvnb|Schopenhauer|2010|pages=xxviii, xxxix}}</ref> The Society was appalled that several distinguished contemporary philosophers were mentioned in a very offensive manner, and claimed that the essay missed the point of the set topic and that the arguments were inadequate.{{r|Cartwright|p=483}} Schopenhauer, who had been very confident that he would win, was enraged by this rejection. He published both essays as ''The Two Basic Problems of Ethics''. The first edition, published September 1840 but with an 1841 date, again failed to draw attention to his philosophy. In the preface to the second edition, in 1860, he was still pouring insults on the Royal Danish Society.{{r|Cartwright|p=484}} Two years later, after some negotiations, he managed to convince his publisher, Brockhaus, to print the second, updated edition of ''The World as Will and Representation''. That book was again mostly ignored and the few reviews were mixed or negative. | |||
Schopenhauer began to attract some followers, mostly outside academia, among practical professionals (several of them were lawyers) who pursued private philosophical studies. He jokingly referred to them as "evangelists" and "apostles".{{r|Cartwright|p=504}} One of the most active early followers was ], who wrote numerous articles promoting Schopenhauer's philosophy. He was also instrumental in finding another publisher after Brockhaus declined to publish ''Parerga and Paralipomena'', believing that it would be another failure.{{r|Cartwright|p=506}} Though Schopenhauer later stopped corresponding with him, claiming that he did not adhere closely enough to his ideas, Frauenstädt continued to promote Schopenhauer's work.{{r|Cartwright|p=507–508}} They renewed their communication in 1859 and Schopenhauer named him heir for his literary estate.{{r|Cartwright|p=508}} Frauenstädt also became the editor of the first collected works of Schopenhauer.{{r|Cartwright|p=506}} | |||
In 1848, Schopenhauer witnessed ] in Frankfurt after General ] and Prince ] were murdered. He became worried for his own safety and property.{{r|Cartwright|p=514}} Even earlier in life he had had such worries and kept a sword and loaded pistols near his bed to defend himself from thieves.{{r|Cartwright|p=465}} He gave a friendly welcome to Austrian soldiers who wanted to shoot revolutionaries from his window and as they were leaving he gave one of the officers his opera glasses to help him monitor rebels.{{r|Cartwright|p=514}} The rebellion passed without any loss to Schopenhauer and he later praised ] for restoring order.{{r|Cartwright|p=515}} He even modified his will, leaving a large part of his property to a Prussian fund that helped soldiers who became invalids while fighting rebellion in 1848 or the families of soldiers who died in battle.{{r|Cartwright|p=517}} As ] were advocating change and progress, Schopenhauer claimed that misery is natural for humans and that, even if some utopian society were established, people would still fight each other out of boredom, or would starve due to overpopulation.{{r|Cartwright|p=515}} | |||
]]] | |||
In 1851, Schopenhauer published '']'', which contains essays that are supplementary to his main work. It was his first successful, widely read book, partly due to the work of his disciples who wrote praising reviews.{{r|Cartwright|p=524}} The essays that proved most popular were the ones that actually did not contain the basic philosophical ideas of his system.{{r|Cartwright|p=539}} Many academic philosophers considered him a great stylist and cultural critic but did not take his philosophy seriously.{{r|Cartwright|p=539}} His early critics liked to point out similarities of his ideas to those of Fichte and Schelling,{{r|Cartwright|p=381–386}} or to claim that there were numerous contradictions in his philosophy.{{r|Cartwright|p=381–386, 537}} Both criticisms enraged Schopenhauer. He was becoming less interested in intellectual fights, but encouraged his disciples to do so.{{r|Cartwright|p=525}} His private notes and correspondence show that he acknowledged some of the criticisms regarding contradictions, inconsistencies, and vagueness in his philosophy, but claimed that he was not concerned about harmony and agreement in his propositions{{r|Cartwright|p=394}} and that some of his ideas should not be taken literally but instead as metaphors.{{r|Cartwright|p=510}} | |||
Academic philosophers were also starting to notice his work. In 1856, the University of Leipzig sponsored an essay contest about Schopenhauer's philosophy, which was won by ]'s very critical essay.{{r|Cartwright|p=536}} Schopenhauer's friend ] made the first of his four portraits of him—which Schopenhauer did not particularly like—which was soon sold to a wealthy landowner, Carl Ferdinand Wiesike, who built a house to display it. Schopenhauer seemed flattered and amused by this, and would claim that it was his first chapel.{{r|Cartwright|p=540}} As his fame increased, copies of paintings and photographs of him were being sold and admirers were visiting the places where he had lived and written his works. People visited Frankfurt's ''Englischer Hof'' to observe him dining. Admirers gave him gifts and asked for autographs.{{r|Cartwright|p=541}} He complained that he still felt isolated due to his not very social nature and the fact that many of his good friends had already died from old age.{{r|Cartwright|p=542}} | |||
]'' in ]]] | |||
He remained healthy in his own old age, which he attributed to regular walks no matter the weather and always getting enough sleep.{{r|Cartwright|p=544–545}} He had a great appetite and could read without glasses, but his ] had been declining since his youth and he developed problems with ].{{r|Cartwright|p=545}} He remained active and lucid, continued his reading, writing and correspondence until his death.{{r|Cartwright|p=545}} The numerous notes that he made during these years, amongst others on aging, were published ] under the title ''Senilia''. In the spring of 1860 his health began to decline, and he experienced shortness of breath and heart palpitations; in September he suffered inflammation of the lungs and, although he was starting to recover, he remained very weak.{{r|Cartwright|p=546}} The last friend to visit him was Wilhelm Gwinner; according to him, Schopenhauer was concerned that he would not be able to finish his planned additions to ''Parerga and Paralipomena'' but was at peace with dying.{{r|Cartwright|p=546–547}} He died of ]<ref>Dale Jacquette, ''The Philosophy of Schopenhauer'', Routledge, 2015: "Biographical sketch".</ref> on 21 September 1860 while sitting at home on his couch. He died at the age of 72 and had a funeral conducted by a Lutheran minister.<ref>''Schopenhauer: his life and philosophy'' by H. Zimmern – 1932 – G. Allen & Unwin.</ref><ref>{{Cite book|last=Lewis|first=Peter|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6TBXX9KVtzsC&dq=%22Arthur+Schopenhauer%22+%22lutheran%22&pg=PA167|title=Arthur Schopenhauer, 2013|date=15 February 2013|publisher=Reaktion Books|isbn=978-1-78023-069-6}}</ref> | |||
== Philosophy == | == Philosophy == | ||
Schopenhauer's starting point was ]'s division of the universe into ] and ], claiming that the noumenon was the same as that in us which we call ]. It is the inner content and the driving force of the world. For Schopenhauer, human will had ] primacy over the ]; in other words, desire is understood to be prior to thought, and, in a parallel sense, will is said to be prior to being. In solving/alleviating the fundamental problems of life, Schopenhauer was rare among philosophers in considering ] and ] less important (or less effective) than ], certain types of charitable practice ("loving kindness", in his terms), and certain forms of religious discipline; Schopenhauer concluded that discursive thought (such as philosophy and logic) could neither touch nor transcend the nature of desire— i.e., the will. In '']'', Schopenhauer posited that humans living in the ] are living in the ], and thus are eternally tormented by that desire (his idea of the role of desire in life is similar to that of ] ] and Buddhism, and Schopenhauer draws attention to these similarities himself). | |||
=== Theory of perception === | |||
While Schopenhauer's philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary, his ] was resolutely ], rather than speculative or transcendental: | |||
In November 1813 ] invited Schopenhauer to help him on his ]. Although Schopenhauer considered colour theory a minor matter,<ref>Letter to Goethe on 23 January 1816: "Ich weiß, daß durch mich die Wahrheit geredet hat, – in dieser kleinen Sache, wie dereinst in größern."</ref> he accepted the invitation out of admiration for Goethe. Nevertheless, these investigations led him to his most important discovery in epistemology: finding a demonstration for the ''a priori'' nature of causality. | |||
Kant openly admitted that it was ]'s skeptical assault on causality that motivated the critical investigations in '']'' and gave an elaborate proof to show that causality is ''a priori''. After ] had made it plausible that Kant had not disproven Hume's skepticism, it was up to those loyal to Kant's project to prove this important matter. | |||
{{Quotation|Philosophy... is a science, and as such has no articles of faith; accordingly, in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically, or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions.|Arthur Schopenhauer|''Parerga & Paralipomena'', vol. i, pg. 106., E.F.J. Payne Translation}} | |||
The difference between the approaches of Kant and Schopenhauer was this: Kant simply declared that the empirical content of perception is "given" to us from outside, an expression with which Schopenhauer often expressed his dissatisfaction.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|volume=1. Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy|quote=But the whole teaching of Kant contains really nothing more about this than the oft-repeated meaningless expression: 'The empirical element in perception is given from without.' ... always through the same meaningless metaphorical expression: 'The empirical perception is given us.'}}</ref> He, on the other hand, was occupied with the questions: how do we get this empirical content of perception; how is it possible to comprehend subjective sensations "limited to my skin" as the objective perception of things that lie "outside" of me?<ref>{{Cite book|title=On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=§ 21|quote=For sensation is and remains a process within the organism and is limited, as such, to the region within the skin; it cannot therefore contain any thing which lies beyond that region, or, in other words, anything that is outside us. ... It is only when the Understanding begins to apply its sole form, the causal law, that a powerful transformation takes place, by which subjective sensation becomes objective perception.}}</ref> | |||
{{Quotation|This actual world of what is knowable, in which we are and which is in us, remains both the material and the limit of our consideration.|Arthur Schopenhauer|''World as Will and Representation'', vol. i, pg. 273, E.F.J. Payne Translation}} | |||
{{Quotation|The sensations in the hand of a man born blind, on feeling an object of cubic shape, are quite uniform and the same on all sides and in every direction: the edges, it is true, press upon a smaller portion of his hand, still nothing at all like a cube is contained in these sensations. His Understanding draws the immediate and intuitive conclusion from the resistance felt, that this resistance must have a cause, which then presents itself through that conclusion as a hard body; and through the movements of his arms in feeling the object, while the hand's sensation remains unaltered, he constructs the cubic shape in Space. If the representation of a cause and of Space, together with their laws, had not already existed within him, the image of a cube could never have proceeded from those successive sensations in his hand.<ref>{{Cite book|title=On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=§ 21}}</ref>|sign=|source=}} | |||
Schopenhauer's identification of the Kantian ''noumenon'' (i.e., the actually existing entity) with what we call our will deserves some explanation. The noumenon was what Kant called the ''Ding an Sich'', the "Thing in Itself", the reality that is the foundation of our ] and ] representations of an external world; in Kantian terms, those sensory and mental representations are mere phenomena. Schopenhauer's assertion that what we call our will is the same as this ''noumenon'' might at first instance strike some as oddly as ]'s revelation that everything is made out of ]. | |||
Causality is therefore not an empirical concept drawn from objective perceptions, as Hume had maintained; instead, as Kant had said, objective perception presupposes knowledge of causality.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|volume=1, § 4.|quote=The contrary doctrine that the law of causality results from experience, which was the scepticism of Hume, is first refuted by this. For the independence of the knowledge of causality of all experience,—that is, its a priori character—can only be deduced from the dependence of all experience upon it; and this deduction can only be accomplished by proving, in the manner here indicated, and explained in the passages referred to above, that the knowledge of causality is included in perception in general, to which all experience belongs, and therefore in respect of experience is completely a priori, does not presuppose it, but is presupposed by it as a condition.}}</ref> | |||
But Kant's philosophy was formulated as a response to the radical ] of ] and his fellow ], who claimed that as far as we could tell there was ] beyond our mental representations of it. Schopenhauer begins by arguing that Kant's demarcation between external objects, knowable only as phenomena, and the Thing in Itself of noumenon, contains a significant omission. There is, in fact, one physical object we know more intimately than we know any object of sense perception. It is our own body. | |||
By this intellectual operation, comprehending every effect in our sensory organs as having an external cause, the external world arises. With vision, finding the cause is essentially simplified due to light acting in straight lines. We are seldom conscious of the process that interprets the double sensation in both eyes as coming from one object, that inverts the impressions on the retinas, and that uses the change in the apparent position of an object relative to more distant objects provided by binocular vision to perceive depth and distance. | |||
We know our ] have ], and occupy space, the same way other objects known only through our named senses do. Though we seldom think of our bodies as physical objects, we know even before reflection that it shares some of their properties. We understand that a watermelon cannot successfully occupy the same space as an oncoming truck. We know that if we tried to repeat the experiment with our own bodies, we would obtain similar results. We know this even if we do not understand the ] involved. | |||
Schopenhauer stresses the importance of the intellectual nature of perception; the senses furnish the raw material by which the intellect produces the world as representation. He set out his theory of perception for the first time in '']'',<ref name=":0" /> and, in the subsequent editions of ''Fourfold Root'', an extensive exposition is given in § 21. | |||
We know that our consciousness inhabits a physical body, similar to other physical objects only known as phenomena. Yet, our consciousness is not commensurate with our body. Most of us possess the power of voluntary motion. We usually are not aware of our ]s' breath, or our ]beat, unless our attention is called to it. Our ability to control either is limited. Our ]s command our attention on their schedule rather than one we choose. Few of us have any idea what our ]s are doing right now, though this organ is as needful as lungs, heart, or kidneys. The conscious mind is the servant, not the master, of these and other organs. These organs have an agenda which the conscious mind did not choose, and has limited power over. | |||
=== The world as representation === | |||
When Schopenhauer identifies the ''noumenon'' with the desires, needs, and impulses in us that we name "will," what he is saying is that we participate in the reality of an otherwise unachievable world outside the mind through will. We cannot ''prove'' that our mental picture of an outside world corresponds with a reality by reasoning. Through will, we know—without thinking— that the world can stimulate us. We suffer fear, or desire. These states arise involuntarily. They arise prior to reflection. They arise even when the conscious mind would prefer to hold them at bay. The rational mind is for Schopenhauer a leaf borne along in a stream of pre-reflective and largely unconscious emotion. That stream is will; and through will, if not through logic, we can participate in the underlying reality that lies beyond mere phenomena. It is for this reason that Schopenhauer identifies the ''noumenon'' with what we call our will. | |||
Schopenhauer saw his philosophy as an extension of Kant's, and used the results of Kantian epistemological investigation (]) as starting point for his own. Kant had argued that the ] world is merely a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in our ]s.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics|last=Kant|first=Immanuel|at=§ 52c|translator-last=Paul Carus}}</ref> Schopenhauer did not deny that the external world existed empirically but followed Kant in claiming that our knowledge and experience of the world is always in some sense dependent on ''us''.<ref>See the quotation of Schopenhauer in {{Cite book| publisher = University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0-226-78665-0| last = Storm| first = Jason Josephson| title = Metamodernism: The Future of Theory| location = Chicago| date = 2021|pages=36–37| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=pEQ6EAAAQBAJ}}</ref> For Schopenhauer in particular, the spatiotemporal form and causal structure of the external world are contributed to our experiences of it by the brain as it renders perceptions.<ref name="On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and On the Will in Nature: Two Essays (revised edition)">{{cite web |last1=Schopenhauer |first1=Arthur |title=On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and On the Will in Nature: Two Essays (revised edition) |url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/50966/pg50966-images.html#Pg031 |website=gutenberg.org |publisher=Project Gutenberg |ref=p.65}}</ref> Schopenhauer reiterates this in the first sentence of his main work: "The world is my representation (''Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung'')". Everything that there is for cognition (the entire world) exists simply as an object in relation to a subject—a 'representation' to a subject. Everything that belongs to the world is, therefore, 'subject-dependent'. In Book One of ''The World as Will and Representation'', Schopenhauer considers the world from this angle—that is, insofar as it is representation. | |||
Kant had previously argued that we perceive reality as something spatial and temporal not because reality is inherently spatial and temporal, but because that is how our minds operate in perceiving an object. Therefore, understanding objects in space and time represents our 'contribution' to an experience. For Schopenhauer, Kant's 'greatest service' lay in the 'differentiation between ] and the thing-in-itself (]), based on the proof that between everything and us there is always a perceiving mind.' In other words, Kant's primary achievement is to demonstrate that instead of being a blank slate where reality merely reveals its character, the mind, with sensory support, actively participates in constructing reality. Thus, Schopenhauer believed that Kant had shown that the everyday world of experience, and indeed the entire material world related to space and time, is merely 'appearance' or 'phenomena,' entirely distinct from the thing-in-itself.'<ref>{{Cite book|last=Young|first=Julian|date=2005|url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781134328833|title=Schopenhauer|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-32883-3|edition=1|pages=4–25|language=en|doi=10.4324/9780203022108}}</ref> | |||
Also, Schopenhauer's philosophy could be considered as ] and ], and in some way ]. | |||
=== The world as will === | |||
== Psychology == | |||
{{main|The World as Will and Representation}} | |||
Schopenhauer was perhaps even more influential in his treatment of man's ] than he was in the realm of ]. | |||
In Book Two of ''The World as Will and Representation'', Schopenhauer considers what the world is beyond the aspect of it that appears to us—that is, the aspect of the world beyond representation, the world considered "]" or "]", its inner essence. The very being in-itself of all things, Schopenhauer argues, is will (''Wille''). The empirical world that appears to us as representation has plurality and is ordered in a spatio-temporal framework. The world as thing in-itself must exist outside the subjective forms of space and time. Although the world manifests itself to our experience as a multiplicity of objects (the "objectivation" of the will), each element of this multiplicity has the same blind essence striving towards existence and life. Human rationality is merely a secondary phenomenon that does not distinguish humanity from the rest of nature at the fundamental, essential level. The advanced cognitive abilities of human beings, Schopenhauer argues, serve the ends of willing—an illogical, directionless, ceaseless striving that condemns the human individual to a life of suffering unredeemed by any final purpose. Schopenhauer's philosophy of the will as the essential reality behind the world as representation is often called ].<ref name=Brit/> | |||
Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the tribulations of ]. But Schopenhauer addressed it, and related concepts, forthrightly. | |||
For Schopenhauer, understanding the world as will leads to ethical concerns (see the ] for further detail), which he explores in the Fourth Book of ''The World as Will and Representation'' and again in his two prize essays on ethics, '']'' and '']''. No individual human actions are free, Schopenhauer argues, because they are events in the world of appearance and thus are subject to the principle of sufficient reason: a person's actions are a necessary consequence of motives and the given character of the individual human. Necessity extends to the actions of human beings just as it does to every other appearance, and thus we cannot speak of freedom of individual willing. Albert Einstein quoted the Schopenhauerian idea that "a man can ''do'' as he will, but not ''will'' as he will."<ref>Einstein, Albert (1935). ''The World as I See It'', p. 14. Snowball Publishing. {{ISBN|1-4948-7706-6}}.</ref> Yet the will as thing in-itself is free, as it exists beyond the realm of representation and thus is not constrained by any of the forms of necessity that are part of the principle of sufficient reason. | |||
:"We should be surprised that a matter that generally plays such an important part in the life of man has hitherto been almost entirely disregarded by philosophers, and lies before us as raw and untreated material." | |||
According to Schopenhauer, salvation from our miserable existence can come through the will's being "tranquillized" by the metaphysical insight that reveals individuality to be merely an illusion. The saint or 'great soul' intuitively "recognizes the whole, comprehends its essence, and finds that it is constantly passing away, caught up in vain strivings, inner conflict, and perpetual suffering".<ref>''The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1'', §68</ref> The negation of the will, in other words, stems from the insight that the world in-itself (free from the forms of space and time) is one. ] practices, Schopenhauer remarks, are used to aid the will's "self-abolition", which brings about a blissful, redemptive "will-less" state of emptiness that is free from striving or suffering. | |||
He gave a name to a ] within man which he felt invariably had precedence over reason: the ] (Wille zum Leben), defined as an inherent ] within human beings, and indeed all creatures, to stay alive and to ]. | |||
=== Art and aesthetics === | |||
Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental, but rather understood it to be an immensely powerful force lying unseen within man's ] and dramatically shaping the ]: | |||
{{Main|Arthur Schopenhauer's aesthetics}} | |||
], who "directed such purely objective perception to the most insignificant objects, and set up a lasting monument of their objectivity and spiritual peace in paintings of '']''. The aesthetic beholder does not contemplate this without emotion."<ref>''The World as Will and Representation'', Vol. 1, §38</ref>]] | |||
For Schopenhauer, human "willing"—desiring, craving, etc.—is at the root of ]. A temporary way to escape this pain is through aesthetic contemplation. Here one moves away from ordinary cognizance of individual things to cognizance of eternal Platonic ''Ideas''—in other words, cognizance that is free from the service of will. In aesthetic contemplation, one no longer perceives an object of perception as something from which one is separated; rather "it is as if the object alone existed without anyone perceiving it, and one can thus no longer separate the perceiver from the perception, but the two have become one, the entirety of consciousness entirely filled and occupied by a single perceptual image".<ref>''The World as Will and Representation,'' Vol. 1, §34</ref> Subject and object are no longer distinguishable, and the ''Idea'' comes to the fore. | |||
From this aesthetic immersion, one is no longer an individual who suffers as a result of servitude to one's individual will but, rather, becomes a "pure, will-less, painless, timeless, subject of cognition". The pure, will-less subject of cognition is cognizant only of Ideas, not individual things: this is a kind of cognition that is unconcerned with relations between objects according to the Principle of Sufficient Reason (time, space, cause and effect) and instead involves complete absorption in the object. | |||
:"The ultimate aim of all love affairs ...is more important than all other aims in man's life; and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it." | |||
:"What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation..." | |||
Art is the practical consequence of this brief aesthetic contemplation, since it attempts to depict the essence/pure Ideas of the world. Music, for Schopenhauer, is the purest form of art because it is the one that depicts the will itself without it appearing as subject to the Principle of Sufficient Reason, therefore as an individual object. According to ], "Schopenhauer thought that ] was the only art that did not merely copy ideas, but actually embodied the will itself".<ref>Daniel Albright, ''Modernism and Music'', 2004, p. 39, footnote 34</ref> He deemed music a timeless, universal language comprehended everywhere, that can imbue global enthusiasm, if in possession of a significant melody.<ref name=Music >{{cite book|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|title=Essays and Aphorisms|year=1970|publisher=Penguin Classics |isbn=978-0-14-044227-4|page=|url=https://archive.org/details/essaysaphorisms00scho/page/162}}</ref> | |||
These ideas foreshadowed and laid the groundwork for ]'s ], ]'s ] and ]'s concepts of the ] and the ] ]. | |||
== |
=== Mathematics === | ||
Schopenhauer's ] views on mathematics are evident in his criticism of contemporaneous attempts to prove the ] in ]. Writing shortly before the discovery of ] demonstrated the logical independence of the ]—and long before the ] revealed that it does not necessarily express a property of physical space—Schopenhauer criticized mathematicians for trying to use indirect ]s to prove what he held was directly evident from ]. | |||
:''See main article: ]'' | |||
{{blockquote|text=The Euclidean method of demonstration has brought forth from its own womb its most striking parody and caricature in the famous controversy over the theory of ''parallels'', and in the attempts, repeated every year, to prove the eleventh axiom (also known as the fifth postulate). The axiom asserts, and that indeed through the indirect criterion of a third intersecting line, that two lines inclined to each other (for this is the precise meaning of "less than two right angles"), if produced far enough, must meet. Now this truth is supposed to be too complicated to pass as self-evident, and therefore needs a proof; but no such proof can be produced, just because there is nothing more immediate.<ref name="ReferenceB">'']'', vol. 2, ch. 13</ref>}} | |||
This wild and powerful drive to reproduce, however, caused ] and ] in the world. For Schopenhauer, one way to escape the suffering inherent in a world of Will was through ]. | |||
Throughout his writings,<ref>"I wanted in this way to stress and demonstrate the great difference, indeed opposition, between knowledge of perception and abstract or reflected knowledge. Hitherto this difference has received too little attention, and its establishment is a fundamental feature of my philosophy ..." – ''The World as Will and Representation.'', vol. 2, ch. 7, p. 88 (trans. Payne)</ref> Schopenhauer criticized the logical derivation of philosophies and mathematics from mere concepts, instead of from intuitive perceptions. | |||
Through art, Schopenhauer thought, the thinking subject could be jarred out of their limited, individual ] to feel a sense of the ] directly — the "universal" in question, of course, was the will. The contest of personal ] with a world that was, by nature, inimical to its satisfaction is inevitably tragical; therefore, the highest place in art was given to ]. ] was also given a special status in ] as it did not rely upon the medium of representation to communicate a sense of the universal. Schopenhauer believed the function of art to be a ] on the unity of ], and an attempt to either demonstrate or directly communicate to the ] a certain ] ] for which most forms of entertainment — including bad art — only provided a distraction. A wide range of authors (from ] to ]) and artists have been influenced by this system of ], and in the 20th century this area of Schopenhauer's work garnered more attention and praise than any other. | |||
{{blockquote|text=In fact, it seems to me that the logical method is in this way reduced to an absurdity. But it is precisely through the controversies over this, together with the futile attempts to demonstrate the ''directly'' certain as merely ''indirectly'' certain, that the independence and clearness of intuitive evidence appear in contrast with the uselessness and difficulty of logical proof, a contrast as instructive as it is amusing. The direct certainty will not be admitted here, just because it is no merely logical certainty following from the concept, and thus resting solely on the relation of predicate to subject, according to the principle of contradiction. But that eleventh axiom regarding parallel lines is a ] '']'', and as such has the guarantee of pure, not empirical, perception; this perception is just as immediate and certain as is the ] itself, from which all proofs originally derive their certainty. At bottom this holds good of every geometrical theorem ...}} | |||
According to Daniel Albright (2005), "Schopenhauer thought that ] was the only art that did not merely copy ideas, but actually embodied the will itself." | |||
Although Schopenhauer could see no justification for trying to prove Euclid's parallel postulate, he did see a reason for examining another of Euclid's axioms.<ref>This comment by Schopenhauer was called "an acute observation" by ]. In his translation of ], vol. 1, Book I, "Note on Common Notion 4", Heath made this judgment and also noted that Schopenhauer's remark "was a criticism in advance of ] theory". Helmholtz had "maintained that geometry requires us to assume the actual existence of rigid bodies and their free mobility in space" and is therefore "dependent on mechanics".</ref> | |||
==Politics== | |||
Schopenhauer's ] were, for the most part, a much-diminished echo of his system of ethics (the latter being expressed in '']'', available in English as two separate books, '']'' and '']''; ethics also occupies about one fourth of his central work, '']''). In occasional political comments in his '']'' and '']'', Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent of limited government. What was essential, he thought, was that the state should "leave each man free to work out his own salvation", and so long as government was thus limited, he would "prefer to be ruled by a lion than one of fellow rats" — i.e., a monarch. Schopenhauer did, however, share the view of ] on the necessity of the state, and of state violence, to check the destructive tendencies innate to our species. Schopenhauer, by his own admission, did not give much thought to politics, and several times he writes prideful boasts of how little attention he had paid "to political affairs of day". In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government, and a few continent-shaking wars, he did indeed maintain his aloof position of "minding not the times but the eternities". | |||
{{blockquote|text=It surprises me that the eighth axiom,<ref>What Schopenhauer calls the eighth axiom is Euclid's Common Notion 4.</ref> "Figures that coincide with one another are equal to one another", is not rather attacked. For ''"coinciding with one another"'' is either a mere ], or something quite ], belonging not to pure intuition or perception, but to external sensuous experience. Thus it presupposes mobility of the figures, but ] alone is movable in ]. Consequently, this reference to coincidence with one another forsakes pure space, the sole element of ], in order to pass over to the material and empirical.<ref name="ReferenceB"/>}} | |||
== Schopenhauer on women == | |||
Schopenhauer is also famous for his essay "On Women" (''Über die Weiber''), in which he expressed his opposition to what he called "Teutonico-Christian stupidity" on female affairs. He claimed that "woman is by nature meant to obey", and opposed ]'s poem in honor of women, ''Würde der Frauen''. The essay does give two compliments however: that "women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than are" and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others. However, the latter was discounted as weakness rather than humanitarian virtue. | |||
This follows ]'s reasoning.<ref>"Motion of an ''object'' in space does not belong in a pure science, and consequently not in geometry. For the fact that something is movable cannot be cognized ''a priori'', but can be cognized only through experience." (Kant, '']'', B 155, Note)</ref> | |||
The ultra-intolerant view of women contrasts with Schopenhauer's generally liberal views on other social issues: he was strongly against ]s on issues like ] and ] and condemned the treatment of African ]s. This ] on female nature has since been fiercely attacked as ]. However, he did not hold a universally negative opinion of women in particular; one should note that Schopenhauer had a very high opinion of ], whose writings and biography he highly recommended. | |||
=== Ethics === | |||
In any case, the controversial writing has influenced many, from ] to ] ]. While Schopenhauer's hostility to women may tell us more about his ] than about philosophy, his ] analysis of the difference between the sexes, and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction, anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured by ] and ] in the ]. | |||
{{Main|On the Basis of Morality}} | |||
Schopenhauer asserts that the task of ethics is not to prescribe moral actions that ought to be done, but to investigate moral actions. As such, he states that philosophy is always theoretical: its task to explain what is given.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 1, § 53.}}</ref> | |||
==Schopenhauer on homosexuality== | |||
Schopenhauer was also one of the first philosophers since the days of ] to address the subject of male ]. In the third, expanded edition of ''The World as Will and Representation'' (]), Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on the "Metaphysics of Sexual Love." In it, he develops the idea that since only mature men and fully adult but pre-] women are capable of bearing healthy children, in early adolescence and in late middle age the sexual appetite is susceptible of being turned towards another channel. | |||
According to Kant's transcendental idealism, space and time are forms of our sensibility in which phenomena appear in multiplicity. Reality ] is free from multiplicity, not in the sense that an object is one, but that it is outside the ''possibility'' of multiplicity. Two individuals, though they appear distinct, are in-themselves not distinct.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 1, § 23.}}</ref> | |||
While there may again be more ] than analysis in this hypothesis, it is consistent with the general tenor of Schopenhauer's thought, which gives the Will in nature the position of setting an agenda for individual lives. It is also one of the first attempts at portraying homosexuality as a natural phenomenon, acknowledging its existence in every culture, and seeking to explain its appearance even in those cultures whose moralities sharply condemn homosexual behaviour. | |||
Appearances are entirely subordinated to the ]. The egoistic individual who focuses his aims on his own interests has to deal with empirical laws as well as he can. | |||
==Schopenhauer on Hegel== | |||
Schopenhauer seems to have disliked just about everything concerning his contemporary ]. The following quotation from '']'' (page 15-16) is quite famous: | |||
What is relevant for ethics are individuals who can act against their own self-interest. If we take a man who suffers when he sees his fellow men living in poverty and consequently uses a significant part of his income to support ''their'' needs instead of his ''own'' pleasures, then the simplest way to describe this is that he makes ''less distinction between himself'' and others than is usually made.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 1, § 66.}}</ref> | |||
{{Quotation|If I were to say that the so-called philosophy of this fellow ] is a colossal piece of mystification which will yet provide posterity with an inexhaustible theme for laughter at our times, that it is a ] paralyzing all mental powers, stifling all real thinking, and, by the most outrageous misuse of language, putting in its place the hollowest, most senseless, thoughtless, and, as is confirmed by its success, most stupefying verbiage, I should be quite right.<p> | |||
Further, if I were to say that this summus philosophus scribbled nonsense quite unlike any mortal before him, so that whoever could read his most eulogized work, the so-called ], without feeling as if he were in a madhouse, would qualify as an inmate for ], I should be no less right.|Arthur Schopenhauer|'']'' (page 15-16)}} | |||
Regarding how things ''appear'' to us, the egoist asserts a gap between two individuals, but the altruist experiences the sufferings of others as his own. In the same way a compassionate man cannot hurt animals, though they appear as distinct from himself. | |||
But Schopenhauer had good reason to mistrust the writings of Hegel. In his "Foreword to | |||
the first edition" of his work ], Schopenhauer | |||
had found Hegel to have fallen prey to the '']'' fallacy. | |||
What motivates the altruist is compassion. The suffering of others is for him not a cold matter to which he is indifferent, but he feels connectiveness to all beings. Compassion is thus the basis of morality.<ref>{{Cite book|title=On the Basis of Morality|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=§ 19}}</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer's critique of Hegel is most certainly directed at his perception that Hegel's works use deliberately impressive but ultimately vacuous ] and ]s, and that they contained castles of abstraction that sounded impressive but ultimately contained no verifiable content. He also thought that his glorification of church and state were designed for personal advantage and had little to do with search for philosophical truth. Although Schopenhauer may have appeared vain in his constant attacks on ], they were not necessarily devoid of merit: the ] interpreted Hegel as seeing the Prussian state of his day as perfect and the goal of all history up until then. | |||
==== Eternal justice ==== | |||
==Common Misconceptions== | |||
Schopenhauer calls the principle through which multiplicity appears the '']''. When we behold nature we see that it is a cruel battle for existence. Individual manifestations of the will can maintain themselves only at the expense of others—the will, as the only thing that exists, has no other option but to devour itself to experience pleasure. This is a fundamental characteristic of the will, and cannot be circumvented.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Parerga and Paralipomena|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 2, § 173}}</ref> | |||
Many are put off Schopenhauer by descriptions of him as an obstinate and arrogant man, who did not lead the ascetic life that he glorified in his work. The idea that he made resignation into a command to virtue is inaccurate, as he was merely trying to explain asceticism in terms of ]. He does refer to the asceticism as a state of "inner peace and cheerfulness", but he also clearly states that he was not trying to recommend the denial of the will above the affirmation of the will. Furthermore, the call to asceticism was supposed to come to select individuals as knowledge all of a sudden, rather than being a virtue that can be taught. "In general," he wrote, "it is a strange demand on a moralist that he should commend no other virtue than that which he himself possesses." ('']'', Vol.I, § 68) | |||
Unlike temporal or human justice, which requires time to repay an evil deed and "has its seat in the state, as requiting and punishing",<ref name="World as will and idea Vol. 1 § 63"/> eternal justice "rules not the state but the world, is not dependent upon human institutions, is not subject to chance and deception, is not uncertain, wavering, and erring, but infallible, fixed, and sure".<ref name="World as will and idea Vol. 1 § 63">''The World as Will and Idea'' Vol. 1 § 63</ref> Eternal justice is not retributive, because retribution requires time. There are no delays or reprieves. Instead, punishment is tied to the offence, "to the point where the two become one. ... Tormenter and tormented are one. The errs in that he believes he is not a partaker in the suffering; the , in that he believes he is not a partaker in the guilt."<ref name="World as will and idea Vol. 1 § 63"/> | |||
] seems to have made this misinterpretation, leading some people to a distorted view of Schopenhauer. The following sentence from '']'' is often quoted: | |||
Suffering is the moral outcome of our attachment to pleasure. Schopenhauer deemed that this truth was expressed by the Christian dogma of ] and, in Eastern religions, by the ] | |||
{{Quotation|He has interpreted art, heroism, genius, beauty, great sympathy, knowledge, the will to truth, and tragedy, in turn, as consequences of "negation" or of the "will's" need to negate.|]|'']''}} | |||
==== Quietism ==== | |||
Schopenhauer did see all these things as means to a more peaceful and enlightened way of life, but none of them were "denial of the will-to-live". Only asceticism is referred to in that way. ] also claimed that Schopenhauer did not recognise that suffering had a redemptive quality, yet his recognition of this seems blatantly clear in part 4 of ''The World as Will and Representation''. | |||
He who sees through the ''principium individuationis'' and comprehends suffering ''in general'' as his own will see suffering everywhere and, instead of fighting for the happiness of his individual manifestation, will abhor life itself since he knows that it is inseparably connected with suffering. For him, a happy individual life in a world of suffering is like a beggar who dreams one night that he is a king.<ref name="Ascetic">{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 1, § 68.}}</ref> | |||
Those who have experienced this intuitive knowledge cannot affirm life, but exhibit asceticism and quietism, meaning that they are no longer sensitive to motives, are not concerned about their individual welfare, and accept without resistance the evil that others inflict on them. They welcome poverty and neither seek nor flee death.<ref name="Ascetic"/> Schopenhauer referred to asceticism as the denial of the will to live. | |||
Also, his identification of the ] with the Kantian "thing-in-itself" has been misunderstood. ] defined things-in-themselves as being beyond comprehension and that no-one could know the inner nature of a material thing. It is sometimes thought that Schopenhauer denied this, but he did not. What he did assert was that one could know things about the thing-in-itself. For example, you can know that the will is a striving force, that it is endless, that it causes suffering, that it will produce boredom if unoccupied, etc. However, he did not say that you could directly know the will. In addition, it has sometimes been criticised that he never defined the will, but he explained that it could not be fully defined. | |||
Human life is a ceaseless struggle for satisfaction and, instead of continuing their struggle, ascetics break it. It does not matter if these ascetics adhere to the dogmata of Christianity or to ], since their way of living is the result of intuitive knowledge. | |||
==Influence== | |||
Schopenhauer is thought to have influenced the following intellectual figures and schools of thought: ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ]. | |||
{{Quotation|The ] and the teacher of the ] agree in this respect also, they both regard all outward works and religious exercises as superfluous for him who has attained to perfection. So much agreement in the case of such different ages and nations is a practical proof that what is expressed here is not, as optimistic dullness likes to assert, an eccentricity and perversity of the mind, but an essential side of human nature, which only appears so rarely because of its excellence.<ref name="Ascetic"/>}} | |||
==See also== | |||
*] | |||
== |
=== Psychology === | ||
Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the necessity of sex, but Schopenhauer addressed sex and related concepts forthrightly: | |||
=== Major works === | |||
*''Über die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde'', 1813 ''(On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason)'' | |||
*''Über das Sehen und die Farben'', 1816 ''(On Vision and Colours)'' | |||
*''Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung'', 1818/1819, vol 2 1844 ''(]'', sometimes also known in English as ''The World as Will and Idea'') | |||
**vol. 1 Dover edition 1966, ISBN 0486217612 | |||
**vol. 2 Dover edition 1966, ISBN 0486217620 | |||
**Peter Smith Publisher hardcover set 1969, ISBN 0844628859 | |||
**Everyman Paperback combined abridged edition (290 p.) ISBN 0460875051 | |||
*''Über den Willen in der Natur'', 1836 ''(On the Will in Nature)'' | |||
*''Über die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens'', 1839 ''(On Freedom of the Will)'' | |||
*''Über die Grundlage der Moral'', 1840 ''(On the Basis of Morality)'' | |||
*''Parerga und Paralipomena'', 1851 | |||
{{blockquote|... one ought rather to be surprised that a thing which plays throughout so important a part in human life has hitherto practically been disregarded by philosophers altogether, and lies before us as raw and untreated material.<ref>Schopenhauer, Arthur. ]</ref>}} | |||
=== Online texts === | |||
*'''' (german) | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* {{gutenberg author| id=Arthur+Schopenhauer | name=Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
He named a force within man that he felt took invariable precedence over reason: the Will to Live or Will to Life (''Wille zum Leben''), defined as an inherent drive within human beings, and all creatures, to stay alive; a force that inveigles<ref name="inveigles">{{cite book|title=The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary|year=1991|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Schopenhauer|isbn=978-0-19-861248-3|page=1298}}</ref> us into reproducing. | |||
==Source== | |||
*Albright, Daniel (2004). ''Modernism and Music: An Anthology of Sources'', p.39n34. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226012670. | |||
Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental, but rather understood it as an immensely powerful force that lay unseen within man's ], guaranteeing the quality of the human race: | |||
== External links == | |||
{{commons|Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
{{wikiquote}} | |||
{{Wikisourcelang|de|Arthur Schopenhauer|Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
{{blockquote|The ultimate aim of all love affairs ... is more important than all other aims in man's life; and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it. What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation ...<ref>Schopenhauer, Arthur, ]</ref>}} | |||
* | |||
* (Contains the false view that Schopenhauer was a solipsist) | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* | |||
It has often been argued that Schopenhauer's thoughts on sexuality foreshadowed the ], a claim met with satisfaction by ] as he included a quotation from Schopenhauer in his '']''.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://en.wikisource.org/Page%3ADescent_of_Man_1875.djvu/602|title=The Descent of Man|last=Darwin|first=Charles|page=586}}</ref> This has also been noted about ]'s concepts of the ] and the ], and ] in general.<ref>"Nearly a century before Freud ... in Schopenhauer there is, for the first time, an explicit philosophy of the unconscious and of the body." Safranski p. 345.</ref> | |||
{{Philosophy navigation}} | |||
=== Political and social thought === | |||
==== Politics ==== | |||
]]] | |||
Schopenhauer's politics were an echo of his system of ethics, which he elucidated in detail in his ''Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik'' (the two essays ''On the Freedom of the Will'' and ''On the Basis of Morality''). | |||
In occasional political comments in his '']'' and ''Manuscript Remains'', Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent of ]. Schopenhauer shared the view of ] on the necessity of the state and state action to check the innate destructive tendencies of our species. He also defended the independence of the legislative, judicial and executive branches of power, and a monarch as an impartial element able to practise justice (in a practical and everyday sense, not a cosmological one).<ref>'']'', Vol. 2, Ch. 47</ref> | |||
He declared that monarchy is "natural to man in almost the same way as it is to bees and ants, to cranes in flight, to wandering elephants, to wolves in a pack in search of prey, and to other animals".<ref name="Paralipomena, Vol p. 254">''Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2'', "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 254).</ref> Intellect in monarchies, he writes, always has "much better chances against stupidity, its implacable and ever-present foe, than it has in republics; but this is a great advantage."<ref name="Paralipomena, Vol p. 254"/> On the other hand, Schopenhauer disparaged ] as being "as unnatural to man as it is unfavorable to higher intellectual life and thus to the arts and sciences".<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2'', "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 255).</ref> | |||
By his own admission, Schopenhauer did not give much thought to politics, and several times he wrote proudly of how little attention he paid "to political affairs of day". In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government, and a few continent-shaking wars, he maintained his position of "minding not the times but the eternities". He wrote many disparaging remarks about Germany and the Germans. A typical example is: "For a German it is even good to have somewhat lengthy words in his mouth, for he thinks slowly, and they give him time to reflect."<ref>'']'', Vol. 2, Ch. 12</ref> | |||
==== Punishment ==== | |||
The State, Schopenhauer claimed, punishes criminals to prevent future crimes. It places "beside every possible motive for committing a wrong a more powerful motive for leaving it undone, in the inescapable punishment. Accordingly, the criminal code is as complete a register as possible of counter-motives to all criminal actions that can possibly be imagined ..."<ref name="twwr62">Schopenhauer, '']'', Vol. I, § 62.</ref> He claimed that this doctrine was not original to him but had appeared in the writings of ],<ref>"... he who attempts to punish in accordance with reason does not retaliate on account of the past wrong (for he could not undo something which has been done) but for the future, so that neither the wrongdoer himself, nor others who see him being punished, will do wrong again." Plato, "]", 324 B. Plato wrote that punishment should "be an example to other men not to offend". Plato, "]", Book IX, 863.</ref> ], ], ], and ]. | |||
==== Races and religions ==== | |||
Schopenhauer attributed civilizational primacy to the northern "white races" due to their sensitivity and creativity (except for the ancient Egyptians and Hindus, whom he saw as equal): | |||
<blockquote>The highest civilization and culture, apart from the ] and ], are found exclusively among the white races; and even with many dark peoples, the ruling caste or race is fairer in colour than the rest and has, therefore, evidently immigrated, for example, the ], the ], and the rulers of the ]. All this is due to the fact that necessity is the mother of invention because those tribes that emigrated early to the north, and there gradually became white, had to develop all their intellectual powers and invent and perfect all the arts in their struggle with need, want and misery, which in their many forms were brought about by the climate. This they had to do in order to make up for the parsimony of nature and out of it all came their high civilization.<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena'', Vol. 2, "On Philosophy and Natural Science," §92, trans. Payne (p. 158-159).</ref></blockquote> | |||
Schopenhauer was fervently ]. Speaking of the treatment of slaves in the ], he condemned "those devils in human form, those bigoted, church-going, strict sabbath-observing scoundrels, especially the Anglican parsons among them" for how they "treat their innocent black brothers who through violence and injustice have fallen into their devil's claws". The slave-holding states of North America, Schopenhauer writes, are a "disgrace to the whole of humanity".<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena'', Vol. 2, "On Ethics," §114, trans. Payne (p. 212).</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer also maintained a marked metaphysical and political ]. He argued that Christianity constituted a revolt against what he styled the materialistic basis of Judaism, exhibiting an Indian-influenced ethics reflecting the ]-] theme of spiritual self-conquest. He saw this as opposed to the ignorant drive toward earthly utopianism and superficiality of a worldly "Jewish" spirit: | |||
<blockquote> is, therefore, the crudest and poorest of all religions and consists merely in an absurd and revolting ]. It amounts to this that the ]], who has created the world, desires to be worshipped and adored; and so above all he is jealous, is envious of his colleagues, of all the other gods; if sacrifices are made to them he is furious and his Jews have a bad time ... It is most deplorable that this religion has become the basis of the prevailing religion of Europe; for it is a religion without any metaphysical tendency. While all other religions endeavor to explain to the people by symbols the metaphysical significance of life, the religion of the Jews is entirely immanent and furnishes nothing but a mere war-cry in the struggle with other nations.<ref>"Fragments for the History of Philosophy", ''Parerga and Paralipomena'', Volume I, trans. Payne (p. 126).</ref></blockquote> | |||
==== Women ==== | |||
In his 1851 essay "On Women", Schopenhauer expressed opposition to what he called "Teutonico-Christian stupidity" of "reflexive, unexamined reverence for the female (''abgeschmackten Weiberveneration'')".<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://aboq.org/schopenhauer/parerga2/weiber.htm|title=Arthur Schopenhauer: Ueber die Weiber|website=aboq.org}}</ref> He wrote: "Women are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish, frivolous and short-sighted." He opined that women are deficient in artistic faculties and sense of justice, and expressed his opposition to ].<ref>] (environmentalist) and ] in '']'' call Schopenhauer "a misogynist without rival in ... Western philosophy".</ref> He claimed that "woman is by nature meant to obey". The essay does give some compliments: "women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than are", and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others. | |||
Schopenhauer's writings influenced many, from ] to nineteenth-century ].<ref>''Feminism and the Limits of Equality'' | |||
PA Cain – Ga. L. Rev., 1989</ref> His ] analysis of the difference between the sexes, and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction, anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured by ] and ].<ref name="Young2005">{{cite book|author=Julian Young|title=Schopenhauer|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gfDyeGY0RFMC&pg=PA242|date=23 June 2005|publisher=Psychology Press|isbn=978-0-415-33346-7|page=242}}</ref> | |||
When the elderly Schopenhauer sat for ] by the Prussian sculptor ] in 1859, he was much impressed by the young woman's wit and independence, as well as by her skill as a visual artist.<ref>{{Cite journal|title=Arthur Schopenhauer and Elisabet Ney|first=Sandra Salser|last=Long|journal=]|volume=69|number=2|date=Spring 1984|pages=130–47|jstor=43469632}}</ref> After his time with Ney, he told Richard Wagner's friend ]: "I have not yet spoken my last word about women. I believe that if a woman succeeds in withdrawing from the mass, or rather raising herself above the mass, she grows ceaselessly and more than a man."<ref>Safranski (1990), Chapter 24. p. 348.</ref> | |||
==== Pederasty ==== | |||
In the third, expanded edition of ''The World as Will and Representation'' (1859), Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on the ''Metaphysics of Sexual Love''. He wrote that ] has the benefit of preventing ill-begotten children. Concerning this, he stated that "the vice we are considering appears to work directly against the aims and ends of nature, and that in a matter that is all important and of the greatest concern to her it must in fact serve these very aims, although only indirectly, as a means for preventing greater evils."<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Schopenhauer|1969|p=566}}</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer ends the appendix with the statement that "by expounding these paradoxical ideas, I wanted to grant to the professors of philosophy a small favour. I have done so by giving them the opportunity of slandering me by saying that I defend and commend pederasty."<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Schopenhauer|1969|p=567}}</ref> | |||
==== Heredity and eugenics ==== | |||
] | |||
Schopenhauer viewed personality and ] as inherited. He quotes ]'s saying, "From the brave and good are the brave descended" (''Odes'', iv, 4, 29) and Shakespeare's line from '']'', "Cowards father cowards, and base things sire base" (IV, 2) to reinforce his hereditarian argument.<ref>Payne, ''The World as Will and Representation'', Vol. II, p. 519</ref> | |||
Mechanistically, Schopenhauer believed that a person inherits his intellect through his mother, and personal character through the father.<ref>''On the Suffering of the World'' (1970), p. 35. Penguin Books – Great Ideas.</ref> This belief in heritability of traits informed Schopenhauer's view of love—placing it at the highest level of importance. For Schopenhauer the "final aim of all love intrigues, be they comic or tragic, is really of more importance than all other ends in human life. What it all turns upon is nothing less than the composition of the next generation. ... It is not the weal or woe of any one individual, but that of the human race to come, which is here at stake." This view of the importance for the species of whom we choose to love was reflected in his views on ] or good breeding. Here Schopenhauer wrote: | |||
<blockquote>With our knowledge of the complete unalterability both of character and of mental faculties, we are led to the view that a real and thorough improvement of the human race might be reached not so much from outside as from within, not so much by theory and instruction as rather by the path of generation. Plato had something of the kind in mind when, in the fifth book of his ''Republic'', he explained his plan for increasing and improving his warrior caste. If we could ] all scoundrels and stick all stupid geese in a convent, and give men of noble character a whole ], and procure men, and indeed thorough men, for all girls of intellect and understanding, then a generation would soon arise which would produce a better age than that of ].<ref>{{cite book | last = Schopenhauer | first = Arthur | title = The World as Will and Representation |editor=E. F. J. Payne |volume=II | publisher = Dover Publications | location = New York | year = 1969 |isbn=978-0-486-21762-8 |page=527 }}</ref></blockquote> | |||
In another context, Schopenhauer reiterated his eugenic thesis: "If you want Utopian plans, I would say: the only solution to the problem is the ] of the wise and noble members of a genuine aristocracy, a genuine nobility, achieved by ] the most magnanimous men with the cleverest and most gifted women. This proposal constitutes my Utopia and my Platonic Republic."<ref>''Essays and Aphorisms'', trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Middlesex: London, 1970, p. 154</ref> Analysts (e.g., ]) have suggested that Schopenhauer's anti-] sentiment and his support for eugenics influenced the neo-aristocratic philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, who initially considered Schopenhauer his mentor.<ref>''Nietzsche and Modern German Thought'' by K. Ansell-Pearson – 1991 – Psychology Press.</ref> | |||
==== Animal rights ==== | |||
{{main|Arthur Schopenhauer's view on animal rights}} | |||
As a consequence of his ] philosophy, Schopenhauer was very concerned about animal welfare and rights.<ref>Christina Gerhardt, "Thinking With: Animals in Schopenhauer, Horkheimer and Adorno." ''Critical Theory and Animals''. Ed. John Sanbonmatsu. Lanham: Rowland, 2011. 137–157.</ref><ref name="PhilPapers">Stephen Puryear, .</ref> For him, all individual animals, including humans, are essentially phenomenal manifestations of the one underlying Will. For him the word "will" designates force, power, impulse, energy, and desire; it is the closest word we have that can signify both the essence of all external things and our own direct, inner experience. Since every living thing possesses will, humans and animals are fundamentally the same and can recognize themselves in each other.<ref>"Unlike the intellect, it does not depend on the perfection of the organism, but is essentially the same in all animals as what is known to us so intimately. Accordingly, the animal has all the emotions of humans, such as joy, grief, fear, anger, love, hatred, strong desire, envy, and so on. The great difference between human and animal rests solely on the intellect's degrees of perfection. ''On the Will in Nature'', "Physiology and Pathology".</ref> For this reason, he claimed that a good person would have sympathy for animals, who are our fellow sufferers. | |||
{{blockquote|Compassion for animals is intimately associated with goodness of character, and it may be confidently asserted that he who is cruel to living creatures cannot be a good man.|'']'', § 19}} | |||
{{blockquote|Nothing leads more definitely to a recognition of the identity of the essential nature in animal and human phenomena than a study of zoology and anatomy.|''On the Basis of Morality'', chapter 8<ref>Quoted in {{cite book | last = Schopenhauer | first = Arthur | title = Philosophical Writings | publisher = Continuum | location = London | year = 1994 |isbn=978-0-8264-0729-0 |page=233}}</ref>}} | |||
{{blockquote|The assumption that animals are without rights and the illusion that our treatment of them has no moral significance is a positively outrageous example of Western crudity and barbarity. Universal compassion is the only guarantee of morality.|''On the Basis of Morality'', chapter 8<ref>Quoted in {{cite book | last = Ryder | first = Richard | title = Animal Revolution: Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism | publisher = Berg Publishers | location = Oxford | year = 2000 |isbn=978-1-85973-330-1 |page=57}}</ref>}} | |||
In 1841, he praised the establishment in London of the ], and in Philadelphia of the Animals' Friends Society. Schopenhauer went so far as to protest using the pronoun "it" in reference to animals because that led to treatment of them as though they were inanimate things.<ref>"... in English all animals are of the neuter gender and so are represented by the pronoun 'it,' just as if they were inanimate things. The effect of this artifice is quite revolting, especially in the case of primates, such as dogs, monkeys, and the like...." ''On the Basis of Morality'', § 19.</ref> To reinforce his points, Schopenhauer referred to anecdotal reports of the look in the eyes of a monkey who had been shot<ref>"I recall having read of an Englishman who, while hunting in India, had shot a monkey; he could not forget the look which the dying animal gave him, and since then had never again fired at monkeys." ''On the Basis of Morality'', § 19.</ref> and also the grief of a baby elephant whose mother had been killed by a hunter.<ref>" describes how he shot his first elephant, a female. The next morning he went to look for the dead animal; all the other elephants had fled from the neighborhood except a young one, who had spent the night with its dead mother. Forgetting all fear, he came toward the sportsmen with the clearest and liveliest evidence of inconsolable grief, and put his tiny trunk round them in order to appeal to them for help. Harris says he was then filled with real remorse for what he had done, and felt as if he had committed a murder." ''On the basis of morality'', § 19.</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer was very attached to his succession of pet poodles. He criticized ]'s<ref>"His contempt for animals, who, as mere things for our use, are declared by him to be without rights, ... in conjunction with Pantheism, is at the same time absurd and abominable." ''The World as Will and Representation'', Vol. 2, Chapter 50.</ref> belief that animals are a mere means for the satisfaction of humans.<ref>Spinoza, ''Ethics'', Pt. IV, Prop. XXXVII, Note I.: "Still I do not deny that beasts feel: what I deny is, that we may not consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in a way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours ..." This is the exact opposite of Schopenhauer's doctrine. Also, ''Ethics'', Appendix, 26, "whatsoever there be in nature beside man, a regard for our advantage does not call on us to preserve, but to preserve or destroy according to its various capacities, and to adapt to our use as best we may."</ref><ref>"Such are the matters which I engage to prove in Prop. xviii of this Part, whereby it is plain that the law against the slaughtering of animals is founded rather on vain superstition and womanish pity than on sound reason. The rational quest of what is useful to us further teaches us the necessity of associating ourselves with our fellow-men, but not with beasts, or things, whose nature is different from our own; we have the same rights in respect to them as they have in respect to us. Nay, as everyone's right is defined by his virtue, or power, men have far greater rights over beasts than beasts have over men. Still I affirm that beasts feel. But I also affirm that we may consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in the way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours, and their emotions are naturally different from human emotions." ''Ethics'', Part 4, Prop. 37, Note 1.</ref> Tim Madigan wrote that despite all of his bombast, Schopenhauer was a sympathetic character who had concerns for the suffering of animals. | |||
{{blockquote|The greatest benefit conferred by the railways is that they spare millions of draught-horses their miserable existences.|''Essays and Aphorisms'', p. 171<ref>Quoted in {{Cite web|last=Madigan|first=Tim|title=Schopenhauer's Compassionate Morality {{!}} Issue 52 {{!}} Philosophy Now|url=https://philosophynow.org/issues/52/Schopenhauers_Compassionate_Morality#:~:text=It%20is%20compassion,%20or%20fellow,of%20the%20will%20to%20live.|website=Philosophy Now|access-date=2023-09-16}}</ref>}} | |||
===Intellectual interests and affinities=== | |||
====Indology==== | |||
] | |||
Schopenhauer read the Latin translation of the ], the '']'', translated by French writer ]{{sfn|Clarke|1997|page=68}} from the Persian translation of Prince ] entitled ''Sirre-Akbar'' ("The Great Secret"). He was so impressed by its ] that he called it "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed it contained superhuman concepts. Schopenhauer considered India as "the land of the most ancient and most pristine wisdom, the place from which ] could trace their descent and the tradition by which they had been influenced in so many decisive ways",{{sfn|Clarke|1997|page=68}} and regarded the ''Upanishads'' as "the most profitable and elevating reading which is possible in the world. It has been the solace of my life, and will be the solace of my death."{{sfn|Clarke|1997|page=68}} | |||
Schopenhauer was first introduced to Anquetil du Perron's translation by Friedrich Majer in 1814.{{sfn|Clarke|1997|page=68}} They met during the winter of 1813–1814 in ] at the home of Schopenhauer's mother, according to the biographer Safranski. Majer was a follower of ], and an early ]. Schopenhauer did not begin serious study of the Indic texts until the summer of 1814. Safranski maintains that, between 1815 and 1817, Schopenhauer had another important cross-pollination with Indian thought in ]. This was through his neighbor of two years, ]. Krause was then a minor and rather unorthodox philosopher who attempted to mix his own ideas with ancient Indian wisdom. Krause had also mastered ], unlike Schopenhauer, and they developed a professional relationship. It was from Krause that Schopenhauer learned ] and received the closest thing to expert advice concerning Indian thought.<ref>Christopher McCoy, 3–4</ref> | |||
{{blockquote|The view of things that all plurality is only apparent, that in the endless series of individuals, passing simultaneously and successively into and out of life, generation after generation, age after age, there is but one and the same entity really existing, which is present and identical in all alike;—this theory, I say, was of course known long before Kant; indeed, it may be carried back to the remotest antiquity. It is the alpha and omega of the oldest book in the world, the sacred ], whose dogmatic part, or rather esoteric teaching, is found in the Upanishads. There, in almost every page this profound doctrine lies enshrined; with tireless repetition, in countless adaptations, by many varied parables and similes it is expounded and inculcated.|''On the Basis of Morality'', chapter 4<ref>{{cite book |last=Schopenhauer |first=Arthur |year=1840 |publication-date=1908 |title=] |chapter-url=https://archive.org/stream/basisofmorality00schoiala#page/269/mode/2up |chapter=Part IV |translator-last=Bullock |translator-first=Arthur Brodrick |location=London |publisher=] |pages=269–271 |via=]}}</ref>}} | |||
For Schopenhauer, will had ] primacy over the ]; desire is prior to thought. Schopenhauer felt this was similar to notions of ] or goals of life in ] ]. | |||
In Schopenhauer's philosophy, denial of the will is attained by: | |||
* personal experience of an extremely great suffering that leads to loss of the will to live; or | |||
* knowledge of the essential nature of life in the world through observation of the suffering of other people. | |||
The book ''Oupnekhat'' (Upanishad) always lay open on his table, and he invariably studied it before going to bed. He called the opening up of ] "the greatest gift of our century", and predicted that the philosophy and knowledge of the Upanishads would become the cherished faith of the West.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.philosophy.ru/library/asiatica/indica/authors/motives.html|title=Western Indologists: A Study in Motives|last=Dutt|first=Purohit Bhagavan|access-date=9 May 2009|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100802010348/http://www.philosophy.ru/library/asiatica/indica/authors/motives.html|archive-date=2 August 2010}}</ref> Most noticeable, in the case of Schopenhauer's work, was the significance of the '']'', whose ], ], is mentioned throughout ''The World as Will and Representation''.<ref>Christopher McCoy, 54–56</ref> | |||
==== Buddhism ==== | |||
Schopenhauer noted a correspondence between his doctrines and the ] of ].<ref>Abelson, Peter (April 1993). | |||
{{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110628204330/http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/peter2.htm |date=28 June 2011 }}. ''Philosophy East and West'' Volume 43, Number 2, pp. 255–278. University of Hawaii Press. Retrieved on: 12 April 2008.</ref> Similarities centered on the principles that life involves suffering, that suffering is caused by desire (]), and that the extinction of desire leads to liberation. Thus three of the four "truths of the Buddha" correspond to Schopenhauer's doctrine of the will.<ref>], Christopher, ''Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy'', pp. 28 ff.</ref> In Buddhism, while greed and lust are always unskillful, desire is ethically variable – it can be skillful, unskillful, or neutral.<ref name="David Burton 2004, page 22">David Burton, "Buddhism, Knowledge and Liberation: A Philosophical Study." Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2004, p. 22.</ref> | |||
Buddhist ] is not equivalent to the condition that Schopenhauer described as denial of the will. Nirvāṇa is not the extinguishing of the ''person'' as some Western scholars have thought, but only the "extinguishing" (the literal meaning of nirvana) of the flames of greed, hatred, and delusion that assail a person's character.<ref>John J. Holder, ''Early Buddhist Discourses.'' Hackett Publishing Company, 2006, p. xx.</ref> Schopenhauer made the following statement in his discussion of religions:<ref> | |||
"Schopenhauer is often said to be the first modern Western philosopher to attempt integration of his work with Eastern ways of thinking. That he was the first is true, but the claim that he was ''influenced'' by Indian thought needs qualification. There is a remarkable correspondence in broad terms between some central Schopenhauerian doctrines and Buddhism: notably in the views that empirical existence is suffering, that suffering originates in desires, and that salvation can be attained by the extinction of desires. These three 'truths of the Buddha' are mirrored closely in the essential structure of the doctrine of the will." (On this, see Dorothea W. Dauer, ''Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas''. Note also the discussion by Bryan Magee, ''The Philosophy of Schopenhauer'', pp. 14–15, 316–321). Janaway, Christopher, ''Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy'', p. 28 f. | |||
</ref> | |||
<blockquote>If I wished to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I should have to concede to Buddhism pre-eminence over the others. In any case, it must be a pleasure to me to see my doctrine in such close agreement with a religion that the majority of men on earth hold as their own, for this numbers far more followers than any other. And this agreement must be yet the more pleasing to me, inasmuch as ''in my philosophizing I have certainly not been under its influence'' . For up till 1818, when my work appeared, there was to be found in Europe only a very few accounts of Buddhism.<ref>'']'', Vol. 2, Ch. 17</ref></blockquote> | |||
Buddhist philosopher ] sought to distance Buddhism from Schopenhauer.<ref>''Artistic detachment in Japan and the West: psychic distance in comparative aesthetics'' by S. Odin – 2001 – University of Hawaii Press.</ref> While Schopenhauer's philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary, his ] was resolutely ], rather than speculative or transcendental: | |||
<blockquote>Philosophy ... is a science, and as such has no articles of faith; accordingly, in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically, or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions.<ref>''Parerga & Paralipomena'', vol. I, p. 106., trans. E.F.J. Payne.</ref></blockquote> | |||
Also note: | |||
<blockquote>This actual world of what is knowable, in which we are and which is in us, remains both the material and the limit of our consideration.<ref>''World as Will and Representation'', vol. I, p. 273, trans. E.F.J. Payne.</ref></blockquote> | |||
The argument that Buddhism affected Schopenhauer's philosophy more than any other ] faith loses credence since he did not begin a serious study of Buddhism until after the publication of ''The World as Will and Representation'' in 1818.<ref>Christopher McCoy, 3</ref> Scholars have started to revise earlier views about Schopenhauer's discovery of Buddhism. Proof of early interest and influence appears in Schopenhauer's 1815–16 notes (transcribed and translated by Urs App) about Buddhism. They are included in a recent case study that traces Schopenhauer's interest in Buddhism and documents its influence.<ref>App, Urs (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.; Schopenhauer's early notes on Buddhism reproduced in Appendix). This study provides an overview of the actual discovery of Buddhism by Schopenhauer.</ref> Other scholarly work questions how similar Schopenhauer's philosophy actually is to Buddhism.<ref>Hutton, Kenneth </ref> | |||
====Magic and occultism==== | |||
Some traditions in ] and ] interested Schopenhauer and influenced his philosophical theories. He praised ] as evidence for the reality of magic in his ''On the Will in Nature'', and went so far as to accept the division of magic into ], although he doubted the existence of demons.<ref name="Myth of Disenchantment">{{Cite book | last = Josephson-Storm | first = Jason | title = The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences | location = Chicago | publisher = University of Chicago Press | date = 2017 |pages = 187–188 | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=xZ5yDgAAQBAJ |isbn=978-0-226-40336-6 }}</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer grounded magic in the Will and claimed all forms of magical transformation depended on the human Will, not on ritual. This theory notably parallels ]'s system of magic and its emphasis on human will.<ref name="Myth of Disenchantment" /> Given the importance of the Will to Schopenhauer's overarching system, this amounts to "suggesting his whole philosophical system had magical powers."<ref>Quote from Josephson-Storm (2017), p. 188.</ref> Schopenhauer rejected the theory of ] and claimed philosophy should synthesize itself with magic, which he believed amount to "practical metaphysics".<ref>Josephson-Storm (2017), pp. 188–189.</ref> | |||
], including the traditions of ] and to a lesser extent ], has also been cited as an influence on Schopenhauer.<ref>{{cite book|last=Anderson |first=Mark |title=Pure: Modernity, Philosophy, and the One |chapter=Experimental Subversions of Modernity |date=2009 |publisher=Sophia Perennis |isbn=978-1-59731-094-9}}</ref> | |||
==Interests== | |||
Schopenhauer had a wide range of interests, from science and opera to occultism and literature. | |||
In his student years, Schopenhauer went more often to lectures in the sciences than philosophy. He kept a strong interest as his personal library contained near to 200 books of scientific literature at his death, and his works refer to scientific titles not found in the library.{{r|Cartwright|p=170}} | |||
Many evenings were spent in the theatre, opera and ballet; Schopenhauer especially liked the operas of ], ] and ].<ref>{{Cite book|title=Wagner and the Art of the Theatre|last=Carnegy|first=Patrick|page=51}}</ref> Schopenhauer considered music the highest art, and played the flute during his whole life.{{r|Cartwright|p=30}} | |||
As a polyglot, he knew German, Italian, Spanish, French, English, ] and ], and was an avid reader of poetry and literature. He particularly revered ], ], ] and ]. | |||
<blockquote>If Goethe had not been sent into the world simultaneously with Kant in order to counterbalance him, so to speak, in the spirit of the age, the latter would have been haunted like a nightmare many an aspiring mind and would have oppressed it with great affliction. But now the two have an infinitely wholesome effect from opposite directions and will probably raise the German spirit to a height surpassing even that of antiquity.{{r|Cartwright|p=240}}</blockquote> | |||
In philosophy, his most important influences were, according to himself, Kant, ] and the ]. Concerning the Upanishads and ], he writes in ''The World as Will and Representation'': | |||
<blockquote>If the reader has also received the benefit of the Vedas, the access to which by means of the Upanishads is in my eyes the greatest privilege which this still young century (1818) may claim before all previous centuries, if then the reader, I say, has received his initiation in primeval Indian wisdom, and received it with an open heart, he will be prepared in the very best way for hearing what I have to tell him. It will not sound to him strange, as to many others, much less disagreeable; for I might, if it did not sound conceited, contend that every one of the detached statements which constitute the Upanishads, may be deduced as a necessary result from the fundamental thoughts which I have to enunciate, though those deductions themselves are by no means to be found there.<ref>''The World as Will and Representation'' Preface to the first edition, p. xiii</ref></blockquote> | |||
== Thoughts on other philosophers == | |||
=== Giordano Bruno and Spinoza === | |||
Schopenhauer saw ] and ] as philosophers not bound to their age or nation. "Both were fulfilled by the thought, that as manifold the appearances of the world may be, it is still ''one'' being, that appears in all of them. ... Consequently, there is no place for God as creator of the world in their philosophy, but God is the world itself."<ref name="Spinoza and Bruno">{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|at=Vol. 1, Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. Note 5.}}</ref><ref name="Presentation">{{cite web|url=http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/buch/arthur-schopenhauers-handschriftlicher-nachlass-vorlesungen-und-abhandlungen-4993/3|title=Handschriftlicher, Nachlass, Vorlesungen und Abhandlungen.|website=Gutenberg Spiegel}}</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer expressed regret that Spinoza stuck, for the presentation of his philosophy, with the concepts of ] and ], and tried to use geometrical proofs that do not hold because of vague and overly broad definitions. Bruno on the other hand, who knew much about nature and ancient literature, presented his ideas with Italian vividness, and is amongst philosophers the only one who comes near Plato's poetic and dramatic power of exposition.<ref name="Spinoza and Bruno" /><ref name="Presentation" /> | |||
Schopenhauer noted that their philosophies do not provide any ethics, and it is therefore very remarkable that Spinoza called his main work '']''. In fact, it could be considered complete from the standpoint of life-affirmation, if one completely ignores morality and self-denial.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Abschnitt: Handschriftlicher Nachlaß|at=§ 588|quote=Es kann daher eine vollkommen wahre Philosophie geben, die ganz von der Verneinung des Lebens abstrahirt, diese ganz ignorirt.}}</ref> It is yet even more remarkable that Schopenhauer mentions Spinoza as an example of the denial of the will, if one uses the French biography by Jean Maximilien Lucas<ref>{{cite web|url=https://fr.wikisource.org/Vie_de_Spinoza|title=Vie de Spinoza – Wikisource|website=fr.wikisource.org}}</ref> as the key to '']''.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|at=§ 68|quote=We might to a certain extent regard the well-known French biography of Spinoza as a case in point, if we used as a key to it that noble introduction to his very insufficient essay, "De Emendatione Intellects", a passage which I can also recommend as the most effectual means I know of stilling the storm of the passions.}}</ref> | |||
===Immanuel Kant=== | |||
] | |||
{{See also|Critique of the Kantian philosophy|Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata}} | |||
The importance of Kant for Schopenhauer, in philosophy as well as on a personal level, cannot be overstated. Kant's philosophy was the foundation of Schopenhauer's, and he had high praise for the ] section of Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason''. Schopenhauer maintained that Kant stands in the same relation to philosophers such as Berkeley and ], as Copernicus to ], ], and ]: Kant succeeded in demonstrating what previous philosophers merely asserted. | |||
Schopenhauer writes about Kant's influence on his work in the preface to the second edition of ''The World as Will and Representation'': | |||
{{Quotation|I have already explained in the preface to the first edition, that my philosophy is founded on that of Kant, and therefore presupposes a thorough knowledge of it. I repeat this here. For Kant's teaching produces in the mind of everyone who has comprehended it a fundamental change which is so great that it may be regarded as an intellectual new-birth. It alone is able really to remove the inborn realism which proceeds from the original character of the intellect, which neither ] nor ] succeed in doing, for they remain too much in the universal, while Kant goes into the particular, and indeed in a way that is quite unexampled both before and after him, and which has quite a peculiar, and, we might say, immediate effect upon the mind in consequence of which it undergoes a complete undeception, and forthwith looks at all things in another light. Only in this way can any one become susceptible to the more positive expositions which I have to give. On the other hand, he who has not mastered the Kantian philosophy, whatever else he may have studied, is, as it were, in a state of innocence; that is to say, he remains in the grasp of that natural and childish realism in which we are all born, and which fits us for everything possible, with the single exception of philosophy.<ref>{{Cite book|title=World as Will and Representation|last=Arthur Schopenhauer|volume=1, Preface of the Second Edition}}</ref>}} | |||
In his study room, one bust was of ], the other was of Kant.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Schopenhauer. Pessimist and Pagan.|last=Jerauld McGill|first=Vivian|year=1931|page=320}}</ref> The bond which Schopenhauer felt with the philosopher of Königsberg is demonstrated in an unfinished poem he dedicated to Kant (included in volume 2 of the ''Parerga''): | |||
{{quotation|With my eyes I followed thee into the blue sky,<br />And there thy flight dissolved from view.<br />Alone I stayed in the crowd below,<br />Thy word and thy book my only solace.—<br />Through the strains of thy inspiring words<br />I sought to dispel the dreary solitude.<br />Strangers on all sides surround me.<br />The world is desolate and life interminable.<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays, Volume 2'', trans. Payne, p. 655–656.</ref>}} | |||
Schopenhauer dedicated one fifth of his main work, ''The World as Will and Representation'', to a detailed ]. | |||
Schopenhauer praised Kant for his distinction between appearance and the ], whereas the general consensus in ] was that this was the weakest spot of Kant's theory,<ref name=":0">{{Cite book|title=Introduction to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason"|author1=David E. Cartwright |author2=Edward E. Erdmann|publisher=Cambridge University Press|pages=xvi–xvii|quote=He had also rehearsed for the first time his physiological arguments for the intellectual nature of intuition in his "On Vision and Colours", and he had discussed how his philosophy was corroborated by the sciences in "On Will in Nature". ... Like the German Idealists, Schopenhauer was convinced that Kant's great unknown, the thing in itself, is the weak point of the critical philosophy.}}</ref> since, according to Kant, causality can find application on objects of experience only, and consequently, things-in-themselves cannot be the cause of appearances. The inadmissibility of this reasoning was also acknowledged by Schopenhauer. He insisted that this was a true conclusion, drawn from false premises.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The World as Will and Representation|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|volume=1 Criticism of the Kantian philosophy|translator-last=J. Kemp|quote=With the proof of the thing in itself it has happened to Kant precisely as with that of the a priori nature of the law of causality. Both doctrines are true, but their proof is false. They thus belong to the class of true conclusions from false premises.}}</ref> | |||
===Post-Kantian school=== | |||
The leading figures of ]—], ] and ]—were not respected by Schopenhauer. He argued that they were not philosophers at all, for they lacked "the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of inquiry."<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena,'' Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 21.</ref> Rather, they were merely sophists who, excelling in the art of beguiling the public, pursued their own selfish interests (such as professional advancement within the university system). Diatribes against the alleged vacuity, dishonesty, pomposity, and self-interest of these contemporaries are to be found throughout Schopenhauer's published writings. The following passage is an example: | |||
{{Quotation|All this explains the painful impression with which we are seized when, after studying genuine thinkers, we come to the writings of Fichte and Schelling, or even to the presumptuously scribbled nonsense of Hegel, produced as it was with a boundless, though justified, confidence in German stupidity. With those genuine thinkers one always found an ''honest'' investigation of truth and just as ''honest'' an attempt to communicate their ideas to others. Therefore whoever reads Kant, Locke, Hume, Malebranche, Spinoza, and Descartes feels elevated and agreeably impressed. This is produced through communion with a noble mind which has and awakens ideas and which thinks and sets one thinking. The reverse of all this takes place when we read the above-mentioned three German sophists. An unbiased reader, opening one of their books and then asking himself whether this is the tone of a thinker wanting to instruct or that of a charlatan wanting to impress, cannot be five minutes in any doubt; here everything breathes so much of ''dishonesty''.<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena,'' Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 23.</ref>}} | |||
Schopenhauer deemed Schelling the most talented of the three and wrote that he would recommend his "elucidatory paraphrase of the highly important doctrine of Kant" concerning the intelligible character, if he had been honest enough to admit he was parroting Kant, instead of hiding this relation in a cunning manner.<ref>{{Cite book|title=On the Freedom of the Will|last=Schopenhauer|first=Arthur|page=82}}</ref> | |||
Schopenhauer reserved his most unqualified damning condemnation for Hegel, whom he considered less worthy than Fichte or Schelling. Whereas Fichte was merely a windbag (''Windbeutel''), Hegel was a "commonplace, inane, loathsome, repulsive, and ignorant charlatan."<ref>''Parerga and Paralipomena'', Vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Sec. 13, trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 96.</ref> The philosophers ] and ] agreed with this distinction.<ref>{{Cite journal|title=The Open Society and Her Enemies|journal=Nature|volume=157|issue=3987|last=Popper|first=Karl|year=1946|page=52|bibcode=1946Natur.157..387R|doi=10.1038/157387a0|s2cid=4074331}}</ref><ref name="Bunge1">{{cite web |author=Bunge, Mario | year = 2020 | title = Mario Bunge nos dijo: "Se puede ignorar la filosofía, pero no evitarla" | url = https://www.filco.es/mario-bunge-no-evitar-filosofia/ | publisher = Filosofía&Co}}</ref> Hegel, Schopenhauer wrote in the preface to his ''Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics'', not only "performed no service to philosophy, but he has had a detrimental influence on philosophy, and thereby on German literature in general, really a downright stupefying, or we could even say a pestilential influence, which it is therefore the duty of everyone capable of thinking for himself and judging for himself to counteract in the most express terms at every opportunity."<ref>''The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics'', Preface to the First Edition, trans. Christopher Janaway (Cambridge, 2009), p. 15.</ref> | |||
==Influence and legacy== | |||
] by ]]] | |||
Schopenhauer remained the most influential German philosopher until the ].<ref name=Weltschmerz>{{Cite book|title=Weltschmerz, Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900|last=Beiser|first=Frederick C.|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=2008|isbn=978-0-19-876871-5|location=Oxford|pages=14–16|quote=Arthur Schopenhauer was the most famous and influential philosopher in Germany from 1860 until the First World War. ... Schopenhauer had a profound influence on two intellectual movements of the late 19th century that were utterly opposed to him: neo-Kantianism and positivism. He forced these movements to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly. ... Schopenhauer set the agenda for his age.}}</ref> His philosophy was a starting point for a new generation of philosophers including ], ], Lazar von Hellenbach, ], Ernst Otto Lindner, ], ], ] and ]. His legacy shaped the intellectual debate, and forced movements that were utterly opposed to him, ] and ], to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly.<ref name="Weltschmerz" /> The French writer ] commented that "to-day even those who execrate him seem to carry in their own souls particles of his thought".<ref>Beside Schopenhauer's Corpse</ref> Other philosophers of the 19th century who cited his influence include ], ], ] and ]. | |||
Schopenhauer was well read by physicists, most notably ], ], ],<ref>{{Cite book|title=A Peek behind the Veil of Maya: Einstein, Schopenhauer, and the Historical Background of the Conception of Space as a Ground for the Individuation of Physical Systems|first=Don|last=Howard|publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press|year=1997|quote=Pauli greatly admired Schopenhauer. ... Pauli wrote sympathetically about extrasensory perception, noting approvingly that "even such a thoroughly critical philosopher as Schopenhauer not only regarded parapsychological effects going far beyond what is secured by scientific evidence as possible, but even considered them as a support for his philosophy".}}</ref> and ].<ref name=Majorana>{{Cite book|title=Ettore Majorana: Scientific Papers|last=Bassani|first=Giuseppe-Franco|date=15 December 2006|publisher=Springer|isbn=978-3-540-48091-4|editor-last=Società Italiana di Fisica|page=xl|quote=His interest in philosophy, which had always been great, increased and prompted him to reflect deeply on the works of various philosophers, in particular Schopenhauer.}}</ref> Einstein described Schopenhauer's thoughts as a "continual consolation" and called him a genius.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Einstein: His Life and Universe|last=Isaacson|first=Walter|publisher=Simon & Schuster|year=2007|isbn=978-0-7432-6474-7|location=New York|page=367}}</ref> In his Berlin study three figures hung on the wall: ], ], Schopenhauer.<ref>Howard (1997). p. 87</ref> ] recalled: "He often sat with one of the well-worn Schopenhauer volumes, and as he sat there, he seemed so pleased, as if he were engaged with a serene and cheerful work."<ref>Howard (1997). p. 92</ref> | |||
When ] discovered Schopenhauer ("the greatest savant of the West") he considered switching his study of physics to philosophy.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Einstein's Dice and Schrödinger's Cat: How Two Great Minds Battled Quantum Randomness to Create a Unified Theory of Physics|last=Halpern|first=Paul|year=2015|isbn=978-0-465-04065-0|page=189|publisher=Basic Books }}</ref> He maintained the idealistic views during the rest of his life.<ref>Howard (1997). p. 132</ref> ] accepted the main tenet of Schopenhauer's metaphysics, that the ] is will.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.academia.edu/6149849|title=Schopenhauers Metaphysics and Contemporary Quantum Theory|last=Raymond B. Marcin|quote=David Lindorff referred to Schopenhauer as Pauli's "favorite philosopher", and Pauli himself often expressed his agreement with the main tenet of Schopenhauer's philosophy. ... Suzanne Gieser cited a 1952 letter from Pauli to Carl Jung, in which Pauli indicated that, while he accepted Schopenhauer's main tenet that the thing-in-itself of all reality is will.}}{{Dead link|date=August 2023 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }}</ref> | |||
But most of all Schopenhauer is famous for his influence on artists. ] became one of the earliest and most famous adherents of the Schopenhauerian philosophy.<ref>See e.g. Magee (2000) 276–278.</ref> The admiration was not mutual, and Schopenhauer proclaimed: "I remain faithful to Rossini and Mozart!"<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism|last=Nicholas Mathew, Benjamin Walton|page=296}}</ref> So he has been ] "the artist's philosopher".<ref name=iep/> See also ]. | |||
{{Css Image Crop|Image = DAN-28a-Danzig-500MIL Mark (1923).jpg|bSize = 235|cWidth = 235|cHeight = 133|oTop = 2|oLeft = 0|Location = right|Description= Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzig ] note (1923)}} | |||
Under the influence of Schopenhauer, ] became convinced that the truth of all religions lies in self-renunciation. When he read Schopenhauer's philosophy, Tolstoy exclaimed "at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. ... It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection."<ref>Tolstoy's letter to Afanasy Fet on 30 August 1869. "Do you know what this summer has meant for me? Constant raptures over Schopenhauer and a whole series of spiritual delights as I've never experienced before. I have brought all of his works and read him over and over, Kant too by the way. Assuredly no student has ever learned and discovered so much in one semester as I have during this summer. I do not know if I shall ever change my opinion, but at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. You say he is so-so, he has written a few things on philosophy? What is so-so? It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection. I have started to translate him. Won't you help me? Indeed, I cannot understand how his name can be unknown. The only explanation for this can only be the one he so often repeats, that is, that there is scarcely anyone but idiots in the world."</ref> He said that what he has written in '']'' is also said by Schopenhauer in ''The World as Will and Representation''.<ref>{{cite journal|url=https://muse.jhu.edu/article/316432|title=Quietism from the Side of Happiness: Tolstoy, Schopenhauer, War and Peace|last=Thompson|first=Caleb|journal=Common Knowledge|year=2009|volume=15|issue=3|pages=395–411|doi=10.1215/0961754X-2009-020|s2cid=145535267 }}</ref> | |||
] remarked that the reason he had never attempted to write a systematic account of his world view, despite his penchant for philosophy and metaphysics in particular, was because Schopenhauer had already written it for him.<ref>{{cite book |last=Magee |first=Bryan |title=Confessions of a Philosopher |year=1997 |page=413}}</ref> | |||
Other figures in literature who were strongly influenced by Schopenhauer were ], ], ], ] and ].<ref>{{Cite journal|title=Santayana and Schopenhauer|last=Caleb Flamm|first=Matthew|journal=Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society|volume=38|issue=3|pages=413–431|quote=A thinker of whom it is well known that Santayana had an early, deep admiration, namely, Schopenhauer|jstor = 40320900|year=2002}}</ref> In ] final years, while he wrote '']'', he read Schopenhauer's essays and marked them heavily. Scholar Brian Yothers notes that Melville "marked numerous misanthropic and even suicidal remarks, suggesting an attraction to the most extreme sorts of solitude, but he also made note of Schopenhauer's reflection on the moral ambiguities of genius."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Yothers |first1=Brian |title=Sacred Uncertainty: Religious Difference and The Shape of Melville's Career |date=2015 |publisher=Northwestern University Press |location=Evanston, Illinois |isbn=978-0-8101-3071-5 |page=13}}</ref> Schopenhauer's attraction to and discussions of both Eastern and Western religions in conjunction with each other made an impression on Melville in his final years. | |||
], although initially reluctant to engage with works noted for their pessimism, became fascinated with Schopenhauer after reading ''Aphorisms on the Wisdom of Life'' in ''Parerga and Paralipomena''. "With his truths Schopenhauer gave me a spiritual world and an awareness of happiness."<ref>{{Cite book|title=Sergey Prokofiev and His World|last=Morrison|first=Simon|publisher=Princeton University Press|year=2008|isbn=978-0-691-13895-4|pages=19, 20}}</ref> | |||
] owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading ''The World as Will and Representation'' and admitted that he was one of the few philosophers that he respected, dedicating to him his essay "Schopenhauer als Erzieher",<ref>]</ref> one of his '']''. | |||
] | |||
Early in his career, ] adopted Schopenhauer's epistemological idealism, and some traits of Schopenhauer's influence (particularly Schopenhauerian transcendentalism) can be observed in the '']''.<ref>{{cite book | author = Glock, Hans-Johann | year = 2017 | title = A Companion to Wittgenstein | page = | location = Sussex, UK | publisher = Wiley Blackwell}}</ref><ref>{{cite book | author = Glock, Hans-Johann | year = 2000 | title = The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer | page = | location = New York, NY | publisher = Cambridge University Press}}</ref> Later on, Wittgenstein rejected epistemological ] for ]'s conceptual ]. In later years, Wittgenstein became highly dismissive of Schopenhauer, describing him as an ultimately shallow thinker.<ref name="Culture & Value, p.24, 1933–4">Culture & Value, p. 24, 1933–34</ref><ref>Malcolm, Norman. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press, 1958, p. 6</ref> His friend ] had a low opinion on the philosopher, and even came to attack him in his ] for hypocritically praising asceticism yet not acting upon it.<ref>{{cite book|last=Russell|first=Bertrand|title=History of Western Philosophy|year=1946|publisher=George Allen and Unwin |page=786}}</ref> | |||
Opposite to Russell on the foundations of mathematics, the Dutch mathematician ] incorporated Kant's and Schopenhauer's ideas in the philosophical school of ], where mathematics is considered as a purely mental activity instead of an analytic activity wherein objective properties of reality are revealed. Brouwer was also influenced by Schopenhauer's metaphysics, and wrote an essay on mysticism. | |||
Schopenhauer's philosophy has made its way into a novel, '']'', by American existential psychiatrist and emeritus professor of psychiatry ]. | |||
Schopenhauer's philosophy, and the discussions on ] it has engendered, has been the focus of contemporary thinkers such as ], ], and ]. Their work also served as an inspiration for the popular HBO TV series '']'' as well as '']''.<ref>{{Cite news|title=Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'|url=https://www.wsj.com/articles/BL-SEB-79577|date=2014-02-12|work=The Wall Street Journal}}</ref> In this regard, Schopenhauer is sometimes considered the founding father of today's ].<ref> M.Morioka , pp.8–12.</ref> | |||
Advocates of ] in contemporary ] and ] such as ] and ] owe their philosophical system, in part, to the metaphysics of Schopenhauer. <ref>Kastrup, Bernardo ''Decoding Schopenhauer’s Metaphysics: The Key to Understanding How It Solves the Hard Problem of Consciousness and the Paradoxes of Quantum Mechanics'' Iff Books (July 31, 2020)</ref><ref>Koch, Christof ''Then I Am Myself the World: What Consciousness Is and How to Expand It'' Basic Books (May 7, 2024) pp. 49, 127, 132, 139, 209, 244.</ref> | |||
== Selected bibliography == | |||
<!--older texts use "Ueber" instead of "Über"--> | |||
* '']'' (''Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde''), 1813 | |||
* '']'' (''Ueber das Sehn und die Farben''), 1816 {{ISBN|978-0-85496-988-3}} | |||
* ''Theory of Colors'' (''Theoria colorum physiologica''), 1830. | |||
* '']'' (alternatively translated as ''The World as Will and Idea''; original German is ''Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung''): vol. 1, 1818–1819, vol. 2, 1844 | |||
** Vol. 1 Dover edition 1966, {{ISBN|978-0-486-21761-1}} | |||
** Vol. 2 Dover edition 1966, {{ISBN|978-0-486-21762-8}} | |||
** Peter Smith Publisher hardcover set 1969, {{ISBN|978-0-8446-2885-1}} | |||
** Everyman Paperback combined abridged edition (290 pp.) {{ISBN|978-0-460-87505-9}} | |||
** The Longman Library of Primary Sources in Philosophy, vol. 1, 2008; vol. 2, 2010. Title translated as ''The World as Will and Presentation'', rather than ''Representation''. | |||
* '']'' (''Eristische Dialektik: Die Kunst, Recht zu Behalten''), 1831 | |||
* ''On the Will in Nature'' (''Ueber den Willen in der Natur''), 1836 {{ISBN|978-0-85496-999-9}} | |||
* '']'' (''Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens''), 1838 {{ISBN|978-0-631-14552-3}} | |||
* '']'' (''Ueber die Grundlage der Moral''), 1839 | |||
* {{cite book | last = Schopenhauer | first = Arthur | author-link = Arthur Schopenhauer |translator-last1=Cartwright |translator-first1=David E. |translator-last2=Erdmann |translator-first2=Edward E. | title = The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics | publisher=] | date = 2010| location = London|isbn=9780199297221}} Contains '']'' and ''].'' | |||
* {{cite book |last=Schopenhauer |first=Arthur |author-link=Arthur Schopenhauer |title=Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik, behandelt in zwei akademischen Preisschriften |publisher=Johann Christian Hermannsche Buchandlung |date=September 1840 |orig-date=Stated date: 1841. |location=Frankfurt am Main |language=German |access-date=2024-04-15 |url=https://archive.org/details/diebeidengrundpr00scho/}} Freely ] from ]. Contains ''Preisschrift über die Freiheit des Willens'' and ''Preisschrift über die Grundlage der Moral''. | |||
* '']'' (2 vols., 1851) – Reprint: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) (2 vols., 1974) (English translation by E. F. J. Payne<ref>Eric Francis Jules Payne (17 February 1895 – 12 January 1983)</ref>) | |||
** Printings: | |||
*** 1974 Hardcover, by ISBN | |||
**** Vols. 1 and 2, {{ISBN|978-0-19-519813-3}}, | |||
**** Vol. 1, ISBN | |||
**** Vol. 2, {{ISBN|978-0-19-824527-8}}, | |||
*** 1974–1980 Paperback, Vol. 1, {{ISBN|978-0-19-824634-3}}, Vol. 2, {{ISBN|978-0-19-824635-0}}, | |||
*** 2001 Paperback, Vol. 1, {{ISBN|978-0-19-924220-7}}, Vol. 2, {{ISBN|978-0-19-924221-4}} | |||
** ''Essays and Aphorisms'', being excerpts from Volume 2 of ''Parerga und Paralipomena'', selected and translated by R. J. Hollingdale, with Introduction by R J Hollingdale, Penguin Classics, 1970, Paperback 1973: {{ISBN|978-0-14-044227-4}} | |||
* ''An Enquiry concerning Ghost-seeing, and what is connected therewith (Versuch über das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhangt)'', 1851 | |||
* Arthur Schopenhauer, ''Manuscript Remains'', Volume II, Berg Publishers Ltd., {{ISBN|978-0-85496-539-7}} | |||
=== Online === | |||
* {{gutenberg author|id=Arthur+Schopenhauer | name=Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
* '' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20021215085620/http://www.coolhaus.de/art-of-controversy/ |date=15 December 2002 }}''. (bilingual) ]''] | |||
* '''' – audiobook from ] | |||
* ''The World as Will and Idea'' at the ]: | |||
** '''' | |||
** '''' | |||
** '''' | |||
* "On the fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason" and "On the will in nature". Two essays: | |||
** . Translated by Mrs. Karl Hillebrand (1903). | |||
** . Reprinted by Cornell University Library Digital Collections | |||
* in | |||
* '' '' | |||
== See also == | |||
{{Portal|Philosophy}} | |||
{{cols|colwidth=26em}} | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
{{colend}} | |||
== References == | |||
{{reflist|refs=<ref name=Cartwright>{{cite book|last=Cartwright|first=David E.|year=2010|title=Schopenhauer: A Biography|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=meD1bGAjO6wC&pg=PA30|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0-521-82598-6}}</ref>}} | |||
=== Sources === | |||
{{Refbegin}} | |||
* Albright, Daniel (2004) ''Modernism and Music: An Anthology of Sources''. University of Chicago Press. {{ISBN|978-0-226-01267-4}} | |||
* ], ''Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900'' (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016). | |||
* {{cite book|last=Cartwright|first=David E.|year=2010|title=Schopenhauer: A Biography|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=meD1bGAjO6wC&pg=PA30|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0-521-82598-6}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Clarke |first=John James |year=1997 |title=Oriental Enlightenment: The Encounter Between Asian and Western Thought |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8YOGAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA67 |location=] |publisher=] |isbn=978-0-415-13376-0 }} | |||
* Hannan, Barbara, ''The Riddle of the World: A Reconsideration of Schopenhauer's Philosophy'' (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009). | |||
* ], ''Confessions of a Philosopher'', Random House, 1998, {{ISBN|978-0-375-50028-2}}. Chapters 20, 21. | |||
* ] (1990) '']''. Harvard University Press, {{ISBN|978-0-674-79275-3}}; orig. German ''Schopenhauer und Die wilden Jahre der Philosophie'', Carl Hanser Verlag (1987) | |||
* ] editor, ''The Living Thoughts of Schopenhauer'', Longmans Green & Co., 1939 | |||
{{Refend}} | |||
== Further reading == | |||
=== Biographies === | |||
* ], ''Arthur Schopenhauer, philosopher of pessimism'' (Burns, Oates & Washbourne, 1946) | |||
* Damm, O. F., ''Arthur Schopenhauer – eine Biographie'' (Reclam, 1912) | |||
* Fischer, Kuno, ''Arthur Schopenhauer'' (Heidelberg: Winter, 1893); revised as ''Schopenhauers Leben, Werke und Lehre'' (Heidelberg: Winter, 1898). | |||
* Grisebach, Eduard, ''Schopenhauer – Geschichte seines Lebens'' (Berlin: Hofmann, 1876). | |||
* Hamlyn, D. W., ''Schopenhauer'', London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (1980, 1985) | |||
* Hasse, Heinrich, ''Schopenhauer''. (Reinhardt, 1926) | |||
* Hübscher, Arthur, ''Arthur Schopenhauer – Ein Lebensbild'' (Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1938). | |||
* ], ''Schopenhauer'' (Bermann-Fischer, 1938) | |||
* ], ''Schopenhauer's Will: Das Testament'', Nine Point Publishing, 2015. {{ISBN|978-0-9858278-8-5}}. A recent creative biography by philosophical novelist ]. | |||
* Safranski, Rüdiger, ''Schopenhauer und die wilden Jahre der Philosophie – Eine Biographie'', hard cover Carl Hanser Verlag, München 1987, {{ISBN|978-3-446-14490-3}}, pocket edition Fischer: {{ISBN|978-3-596-14299-6}}. | |||
* Safranski, Rüdiger, '']'', trans. Ewald Osers (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989) | |||
* Schneider, Walther, ''Schopenhauer – Eine Biographie'' (Vienna: Bermann-Fischer, 1937). | |||
* Wallace, William, ''Life of Arthur Schopenhauer'' (London: Scott, 1890; repr., St. Clair Shores, Mich.: Scholarly Press, 1970) | |||
* Zimmern, Helen, '''' (London: Longmans, Green & Co, 1876) | |||
=== Other books === | |||
* ]. (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.). Contains extensive appendixes with transcriptions and English translations of Schopenhauer's early notes about Buddhism and Indian philosophy. | |||
* App, Urs, ''Schopenhauers Kompass. Die Geburt einer Philosophie.'' UniversityMedia, Rorschach/ Kyoto 2011. {{ISBN|978-3-906000-02-2}} | |||
* Atwell, John. ''Schopenhauer on the Character of the World, The Metaphysics of Will''. | |||
* Atwell, John, ''Schopenhauer, The Human Character''. | |||
* Edwards, Anthony. ''An Evolutionary Epistemological Critique of Schopenhauer's Metaphysics''. 123 Books, 2011. | |||
* ], ''Schopenhauer: Philosopher of Pessimism'', 1946 (reprinted London: Search Press, 1975). | |||
* ], 1963. ''Schopenhauer''. Penguin Books. | |||
* Janaway, Christopher, 2002. ''Schopenhauer: A Very Short introduction''. Oxford University Press. {{ISBN|978-0192802590}} | |||
* Janaway, Christopher, 2003. ''Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy''. Oxford University Press. {{ISBN|978-0-19-825003-6}} | |||
* ], ''The Philosophy of Schopenhauer'', Oxford University Press (1988, reprint 1997). {{ISBN|978-0-19-823722-8}} | |||
* Marcin, Raymond B. ''In Search of Schopenhauer's Cat: Arthur Schopenhauer's Quantum-Mystical Theory of Justice''. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2005. {{ISBN|978-0813214306}} | |||
* Neymeyr, Barbara, 1996 (reprint 2011): Ästhetische Autonomie als Abnormität. Kritische Analysen zu Schopenhauers Ästhetik im Horizont seiner Willensmetaphysik. (= Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie. Band 42). Walter de Gruyter, Berlin / New York 1996, {{ISBN|3-11-015229-0}}. (reprint 2011, De Gruyter Berlin / Boston). | |||
* Mannion, Gerard, "Schopenhauer, Religion and Morality – The Humble Path to Ethics", Ashgate Press, New Critical Thinking in Philosophy Series, 2003, 314pp. | |||
* Trottier, Danick. ''L'influence de la philosophie schopenhauerienne dans la vie et l'oeuvre de Richard Wagner; et, Qu'est-ce qui séduit, obsède, magnétise le philosophe dans l'art des sons? deux études en esthétique musicale'', Université du Québec à Montréal, Département de musique, 2000. | |||
* ], '']'', London, ], 1876. | |||
* ]. ''Decoding Schopenhauer's Metaphysics – The key to understanding how it solves the hard problem of consciousness and the paradoxes of quantum mechanics.'' Winchester/Washington, iff Books, 2020. | |||
* ]: '']''. Hamish Hamilton, London 2000. {{ISBN|0-14-027661-0}} (Chapter: ''Consolation for a Broken Heart''). | |||
=== Fiction === | |||
* ]: ''Die Welt ist im Kopf.'' Diogenes, Zürich 2010, {{ISBN|978-3-257-06741-5}} (The novel accompanies Schopenhauer on a trip to Italy). | |||
* ]: ''].'' HarperCollins, New York City 2005, {{ISBN|978-0-06-093810-9}} (The novel switches between the current events happening around a therapy group and the psychobiography of Arthur Schopenhauer). | |||
* ]: ''Happy Hour Schopenhauer. Roman einer Bibliotherapie.'' Turia + Kant, Wien + Berlin 2022, {{ISBN|978-3-98514-030-5}} (In the novel, Schopenhauer lives in the 21st century and comments on current events in original quotations). | |||
* Frederick, J. T.: ''In Arthur's Nature''. Theorism Press 2020, {{ISBN|978-0-6451802-0-6}} (Schopenhauer faces punishment for alleged assault and battery.) | |||
=== Articles === | |||
* {{Cite journal | doi = 10.2307/1399616 | last1 = Abelson | first1 = Peter | year = 1993 | title = Schopenhauer and Buddhism | url = http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/peter2.htm | journal = Philosophy East and West | volume = 43 | issue = 2 | pages = 255–78 | jstor = 1399616 | access-date = 25 October 2007 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20110628204330/http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/peter2.htm | archive-date = 28 June 2011 }} | |||
* Jiménez, Camilo, 2006, "," ''Avinus Magazin'' (in German). | |||
* Luchte, James, 2009, "," ''Heythrop Journal'', Volume 50, Number 2, pp. 228–242. | |||
* Mazard, Eisel, 2005, " {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20081029052835/http://www.pratyeka.org/schopenhauer/ |date=29 October 2008 }}" On Schopenhauer's (debated) place in the history of European philosophy and his relation to his predecessors. | |||
* ], 2004, "" | |||
* {{Cite journal | last1 = Young | first1 = Christopher | last2 = Brook | first2 = Andrew | year = 1994 | title = Schopenhauer and Freud | url = https://carleton.ca/~abrook/SCHOPENY.htm | journal = International Journal of Psychoanalysis | volume = 75 | pages = 101–18 | pmid = 8005756 }} | |||
* | |||
* ], 2020. "A Philosophy in Ruins, An Unquiet Void." Introduction to Arthur Schopenhauer, ''On the Suffering of the World''. Repeater Books. {{ISBN|978-1-913462-03-1}}. | |||
== External links == | |||
{{Sister project links|v=no|n=no|b=no|wikt=no|author=yes}} | |||
* {{Gutenberg author |id=3648 | name=Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
* {{Internet Archive author |sname=Arthur Schopenhauer}} | |||
* {{Librivox author |id=165}} | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia |author-last=Wicks |author-first=Robert |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/schopenhauer/ |title=Arthur Schopenhauer |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |editor-link=Edward N. Zalta |encyclopedia=] |date=Spring 2019 |publisher=] |location=]}} | |||
* "" an article by Mary Troxell in the '']'', 2011 | |||
* {{cite IEP |url-id=schopenhauer-logic-and-dialectic|title=Arthur Schopenhauer: Logic and Dialectic}} | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* | |||
* Ross, Kelley L., 1998, "". Two short essays, on Schopenhauer's life and work, and on his dim view of academia. | |||
{{Schopenhauer|state=uncollapsed}} | |||
{{metaphysics}} | |||
] | |||
{{ethics}} | |||
] | |||
{{Aesthetics}} | |||
] | |||
{{Philosophical pessimism}} | |||
] | |||
{{Animal rights|advocates}} | |||
] | |||
{{Continental philosophy}} | |||
] | |||
{{Authority control}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Schopenhauer, Arthur}} | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 22:47, 14 December 2024
German philosopher (1788–1860) "Schopenhauer" redirects here. For other uses, see Schopenhauer (disambiguation).
Arthur Schopenhauer | |
---|---|
Schopenhauer in 1859 | |
Born | (1788-02-22)22 February 1788 Gdańsk (Danzig), Crown of the Kingdom of Poland, Polish–Lithuanian Commonwealth |
Died | 21 September 1860(1860-09-21) (aged 72) Frankfurt, German Confederation |
Education | |
Relatives |
|
Era | 19th-century philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | |
Institutions | University of Berlin |
Main interests | Metaphysics, aesthetics, ethics, morality, psychology |
Notable ideas | |
Signature | |
Arthur Schopenhauer (/ˈʃoʊpənhaʊər/ SHOH-pən-how-ər; German: [ˈaʁtuːɐ̯ ˈʃoːpn̩haʊɐ] ; 22 February 1788 – 21 September 1860) was a German philosopher. He is known for his 1818 work The World as Will and Representation (expanded in 1844), which characterizes the phenomenal world as the manifestation of a blind and irrational noumenal will. Building on the transcendental idealism of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), Schopenhauer developed an atheistic metaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas of German idealism.
Schopenhauer was among the first thinkers in Western philosophy to share and affirm significant tenets of Indian philosophy, such as asceticism, denial of the self, and the notion of the world-as-appearance. His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation of philosophical pessimism. Though his work failed to garner substantial attention during his lifetime, he had a posthumous impact across various disciplines, including philosophy, literature, and science. His writing on aesthetics, morality, and psychology have influenced many thinkers and artists.
Life
Family
Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal grandfather, Andreas Schopenhauer [de] (1720–1793), was a wealthy merchant in Danzig. Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal grandmother, Anna Renata Schopenhauer (1726–1804), was the daughter of a Dutch merchant and the Dutch ambassador to the Hanseatic city of Danzig Hendrik Soermans (1700–1775). Arthur Schopenhauer's maternal grandfather, Christian Heinrich Trosiener [de] (1730–1797) was a merchant in Danzig and a councilor from the middle class. Arthur Schopenhauer's maternal grandmother, Elizabeth Trosiener (1745–1818), was daughter of pharmacist Georg Lehmann (died 1762) and his wife Susanna Concordia Lehmann, née Neumann (born 1718). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandfather, Johann Schopenhauer [de] (1670–after 1724), was the mentioned merchant in Gdansk. Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandmother, Marie Elizabeth Schopenhauer, née Lessig, was a daughter of merchant Andreas Lessig (1658–1713). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-grandfather through paternal grandmother, Hendrik Soermans [de] (1700–1775), was a Dutch merchant, Ambassador of the Netherlands in Gdansk, son of pastor Johannes Soermans (1670–1754) and grandson of Martinus Soermans (1638–1705). Arthur Schopenhauer's paternal great-greatgrandfather, Johann Schopenhauer (1630–1701), was farmer in Petershagen and son of Simon Schopenhauer (1580–1660) and grandson of Salomon Schopenhauer (born 1550).
Early life
Arthur Schopenhauer was born on 22 February 1788, in Gdańsk (then part of the Polish–Lithuanian Commonwealth; later in the Kingdom of Prussia Danzig) on Św. Ducha 47 (in Prussia Heiliggeistgasse), the son of Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer [de] (1747–1805) and his wife Johanna Schopenhauer (née Trosiener; 1766–1838), both descendants of wealthy German patrician families. While they came from a Protestant background, neither of them was very religious; both supported the French Revolution, were republicans, cosmopolitans and Anglophiles. When Gdańsk became part of Prussia in 1793, Heinrich moved to Hamburg—a free city with a republican constitution. His firm continued trading in Danzig where most of their extended families remained. Adele, Arthur's only sibling, was born on 12 July 1797.
In 1797, Arthur was sent to Le Havre to live with the family of his father's business associate, Grégoire de Blésimaire. He seemed to enjoy his two-year stay there, learning to speak French and fostering a life-long friendship with Jean Anthime Grégoire de Blésimaire. As early as 1799, Arthur started playing the flute.
In 1803, he accompanied his parents on a European tour of Holland, Britain, France, Switzerland, Austria and Prussia. Viewed as primarily a pleasure tour, Heinrich used the opportunity to visit some of his business associates abroad.
Heinrich presented Arthur with a choice: he could either stay at home to begin preparations for university or travel with them to further his merchant education. Arthur chose to travel with them. He deeply regretted his choice later because the merchant training was very tedious. He spent twelve weeks of the tour attending school in Wimbledon, where he was confused by strict and intellectual Anglicans who he described as shallow. He continued to sharply criticize Anglican religiosity later in life despite his general Anglophilia. He was also under pressure from his father, who became very critical of his educational results.
In 1805, Heinrich drowned in a canal near their home in Hamburg. Although it was possible that his death was accidental, his wife and son believed that it was suicide. He was prone to anxiety and depression, each becoming more pronounced later in his life. Heinrich had become so fussy, even his wife started to doubt his mental health. "There was, in the father's life, some dark and vague source of fear which later made him hurl himself to his death from the attic of his house in Hamburg."
Arthur showed similar moodiness during his youth and often acknowledged that he inherited it from his father. There were other instances of serious mental health problems on his father's side of the family. Despite his hardship, Schopenhauer liked his father and later referred to him in a positive light. Heinrich Schopenhauer left the family with a significant inheritance that was split in three among Johanna and the children. Arthur Schopenhauer was entitled to control of his part when he reached the age of majority. He invested it conservatively in government bonds and earned annual interest that was more than double the salary of a university professor. After quitting his merchant apprenticeship, with some encouragement from his mother, he dedicated himself to studies at the Ernestine Gymnasium, Gotha, in Saxe-Gotha-Altenburg. While there, he also enjoyed social life among the local nobility, spending large amounts of money, which deeply concerned his frugal mother. He left the Gymnasium after writing a satirical poem about one of the schoolmasters. Although Arthur claimed that he left voluntarily, his mother's letter indicates that he may have been expelled.
Arthur spent two years as a merchant in honor of his dead father. During this time, he had doubts about being able to start a new life as a scholar. Most of his prior education was as a practical merchant and he had trouble learning Latin; a prerequisite for an academic career.
His mother moved away, with her daughter Adele, to Weimar—then the centre of German literature—to enjoy social life among writers and artists. Arthur and his mother did not part on good terms. In one letter, she wrote: "You are unbearable and burdensome, and very hard to live with; all your good qualities are overshadowed by your conceit, and made useless to the world simply because you cannot restrain your propensity to pick holes in other people." His mother, Johanna, was generally described as vivacious and sociable. She died 24 years later. Some of Arthur's negative opinions about women may be rooted in his troubled relationship with his mother.
Arthur moved to Hamburg to live with his friend Jean Anthime, who was also studying to become a merchant.
Education
He moved to Weimar but did not live with his mother, who even tried to discourage him from coming by explaining that they would not get along very well. Their relationship deteriorated even further due to their temperamental differences. He accused his mother of being financially irresponsible, flirtatious and seeking to remarry, which he considered an insult to his father's memory. His mother, while professing her love to him, criticized him sharply for being moody, tactless, and argumentative, and urged him to improve his behavior so that he would not alienate people. Arthur concentrated on his studies, which were now going very well, and he also enjoyed the usual social life such as balls, parties and theater. By that time Johanna's famous salon was well established among local intellectuals and dignitaries, the most celebrated of them being Goethe. Arthur attended her parties, usually when he knew that Goethe would be there—although the famous writer and statesman seemed not even to notice the young and unknown student. It is possible that Goethe kept a distance because Johanna warned him about her son's depressive and combative nature, or because Goethe was then on bad terms with Arthur's language instructor and roommate, Franz Passow. Schopenhauer was also captivated by the beautiful Karoline Jagemann, mistress of Karl August, Grand Duke of Saxe-Weimar-Eisenach, and he wrote to her his only known love poem. Despite his later celebration of asceticism and negative views of sexuality, Schopenhauer occasionally had sexual affairs—usually with women of lower social status, such as servants, actresses, and sometimes even paid prostitutes. In a letter to his friend Anthime he claims that such affairs continued even in his mature age and admits that he had two out-of-wedlock daughters (born in 1819 and 1836), both of whom died in infancy. In their youthful correspondence Arthur and Anthime were somewhat boastful and competitive about their sexual exploits—but Schopenhauer seemed aware that women usually did not find him very charming or physically attractive, and his desires often remained unfulfilled.
He left Weimar to become a student at the University of Göttingen in 1809. There are no written reasons about why Schopenhauer chose that university instead of the then more famous University of Jena, but Göttingen was known as more modern and scientifically oriented, with less attention given to theology. Law or medicine were usual choices for young men of Schopenhauer's status who also needed career and income; he chose medicine due to his scientific interests. Among his notable professors were Bernhard Friedrich Thibaut, Arnold Hermann Ludwig Heeren, Johann Friedrich Blumenbach, Friedrich Stromeyer, Heinrich Adolf Schrader, Johann Tobias Mayer and Konrad Johann Martin Langenbeck. He studied metaphysics, psychology and logic under Gottlob Ernst Schulze, the author of Aenesidemus, who made a strong impression and advised him to concentrate on Plato and Immanuel Kant. He decided to switch from medicine to philosophy around 1810–11 and he left Göttingen, which did not have a strong philosophy program: besides Schulze, the only other philosophy professor was Friedrich Bouterwek, whom Schopenhauer disliked. He did not regret his medicinal and scientific studies; he claimed that they were necessary for a philosopher, and even in Berlin he attended more lectures in sciences than in philosophy. During his days at Göttingen, he spent considerable time studying, but also continued his flute playing and social life. His friends included Friedrich Gotthilf Osann, Karl Witte, Christian Charles Josias von Bunsen, and William Backhouse Astor Sr.
He arrived at the newly founded University of Berlin for the winter semester of 1811–12. At the same time, his mother had just begun her literary career; she published her first book in 1810, a biography of her friend Karl Ludwig Fernow, which was a critical success. Arthur attended lectures by the prominent post-Kantian philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte, but quickly found many points of disagreement with his Wissenschaftslehre; he also found Fichte's lectures tedious and hard to understand. He later mentioned Fichte only in critical, negative terms—seeing his philosophy as a lower-quality version of Kant's and considering it useful only because Fichte's poor arguments unintentionally highlighted some failings of Kantianism. He also attended the lectures of the famous Protestant theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher, whom he also quickly came to dislike. His notes and comments on Schleiermacher's lectures show that Schopenhauer was becoming very critical of religion and moving towards atheism. He learned by self-directed reading; besides Plato, Kant and Fichte he also read the works of Schelling, Fries, Jacobi, Bacon, Locke, and much current scientific literature. He attended philological courses by August Böckh and Friedrich August Wolf and continued his naturalistic interests with courses by Martin Heinrich Klaproth, Paul Erman, Johann Elert Bode, Ernst Gottfried Fischer, Johann Horkel, Friedrich Christian Rosenthal and Hinrich Lichtenstein (Lichtenstein was also a friend whom he met at one of his mother's parties in Weimar).
Early work
Schopenhauer left Berlin in a rush in 1813, fearing that the city could be attacked and that he could be pressed into military service as Prussia had just joined the war against France. He returned to Weimar but left after less than a month, disgusted by the fact that his mother was now living with her supposed lover, Georg Friedrich Konrad Ludwig Müller von Gerstenbergk [de] (1778–1838), a civil servant twelve years younger than her; he considered the relationship an act of infidelity to his father's memory. He settled for a while in Rudolstadt, hoping that no army would pass through the small town. He spent his time in solitude, hiking in the mountains and the Thuringian Forest and writing his dissertation, On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.
Schopenhauer completed his dissertation at about the same time as the French army was defeated at the Battle of Leipzig. He became irritated by the arrival of soldiers in the town and accepted his mother's invitation to visit her in Weimar. She tried to convince him that her relationship with Gerstenbergk was platonic and that she had no intention of remarrying. But Schopenhauer remained suspicious and often came in conflict with Gerstenbergk because he considered him untalented, pretentious, and nationalistic. His mother had just published her second book, Reminiscences of a Journey in the Years 1803, 1804, and 1805, a description of their family tour of Europe, which quickly became a hit. She found his dissertation incomprehensible and said it was unlikely that anyone would ever buy a copy. In a fit of temper Arthur told her that people would read his work long after the "rubbish" she wrote was totally forgotten. In fact, although they considered her novels of dubious quality, the Brockhaus publishing firm held her in high esteem because they consistently sold well. Hans Brockhaus (1888–1965) later claimed that his predecessors "saw nothing in this manuscript, but wanted to please one of our best-selling authors by publishing her son's work. We published more and more of her son Arthur's work and today nobody remembers Johanna, but her son's works are in steady demand and contribute to Brockhaus' reputation." He kept large portraits of the pair in his office in Leipzig for the edification of his new editors.
Also contrary to his mother's prediction, Schopenhauer's dissertation made an impression on Goethe, to whom he sent it as a gift. Although it is doubtful that Goethe agreed with Schopenhauer's philosophical positions, he was impressed by his intellect and extensive scientific education. Their subsequent meetings and correspondence were a great honor to a young philosopher, who was finally acknowledged by his intellectual hero. They mostly discussed Goethe's newly published (and somewhat lukewarmly received) work on color theory. Schopenhauer soon started writing his own treatise on the subject, On Vision and Colors, which in many points differed from his teacher's. Although they remained polite towards each other, their growing theoretical disagreements—and especially Schopenhauer's extreme self-confidence and tactless criticisms—soon made Goethe become distant again and after 1816 their correspondence became less frequent. Schopenhauer later admitted that he was greatly hurt by this rejection, but he continued to praise Goethe, and considered his color theory a great introduction to his own.
Another important experience during his stay in Weimar was his acquaintance with Friedrich Majer—a historian of religion, orientalist and disciple of Herder—who introduced him to Eastern philosophy (see also Indology). Schopenhauer was immediately impressed by the Upanishads (he called them "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed that they contained superhuman concepts) and the Buddha, and put them on a par with Plato and Kant. He continued his studies by reading the Bhagavad Gita, an amateurish German journal Asiatisches Magazin, and Asiatick Researches by the Asiatic Society. Schopenhauer held a profound respect for Indian philosophy; and loved Hindu texts. Although he never revered a Buddhist text he regarded Buddhism as the most distinguished religion. His studies on Hindu and Buddhist texts were constrained by the lack of adequate literature, and the latter were mostly restricted to Theravada Buddhism. He also claimed that he formulated most of his ideas independently, and only later realized the similarities with Buddhism.
Schopenhauer read the Latin translation and praised the Upanishads in his main work, The World as Will and Representation (1819), as well as in his Parerga and Paralipomena (1851), and commented
In the whole world there is no study so beneficial and so elevating as that of the Upanishads. It has been the solace of my life, it will be the solace of my death.
As the relationship with his mother fell to a new low, in May 1814 he left Weimar and moved to Dresden. He continued his philosophical studies, enjoyed the cultural life, socialized with intellectuals and engaged in sexual affairs. His friends in Dresden were Johann Gottlob von Quandt, Friedrich Laun, Karl Christian Friedrich Krause and Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl, a young painter who made a romanticized portrait of him in which he improved some of Schopenhauer's unattractive physical features. His criticisms of local artists occasionally caused public quarrels when he ran into them in public. Schopenhauer's main occupation during his stay in Dresden was his seminal philosophical work, The World as Will and Representation, which he started writing in 1814 and finished in 1818. He was recommended to the publisher Friedrich Arnold Brockhaus by Baron Ferdinand von Biedenfeld, an acquaintance of his mother. Although Brockhaus accepted his manuscript, Schopenhauer made a poor impression because of his quarrelsome and fussy attitude, as well as very poor sales of the book after it was published in December 1818.
In September 1818, while waiting for his book to be published and conveniently escaping an affair with a maid that caused an unwanted pregnancy, Schopenhauer left Dresden for a year-long vacation in Italy. He visited Venice, Bologna, Florence, Naples and Milan, travelling alone or accompanied by mostly English tourists he met. He spent the winter months in Rome, where he accidentally met his acquaintance Karl Witte and engaged in numerous quarrels with German tourists in the Caffè Greco, among them Johann Friedrich Böhmer, who also mentioned his insulting remarks and unpleasant character. He enjoyed art, architecture, and ancient ruins, attended plays and operas, and continued his philosophical contemplation and love affairs. One of his affairs supposedly became serious, and for a while he contemplated marriage to a rich Italian noblewoman—but, despite his mentioning this several times, no details are known and it may have been Schopenhauer exaggerating. He corresponded regularly with his sister Adele and became close to her as her relationship with Johanna and Gerstenbergk also deteriorated. She informed him about their financial troubles as the banking house of A. L. Muhl in Danzig—in which her mother invested their whole savings and Arthur a third of his—was near bankruptcy. Arthur offered to share his assets, but his mother refused and became further enraged by his insulting comments. The women managed to receive only thirty percent of their savings while Arthur, using his business knowledge, took a suspicious and aggressive stance towards the banker and eventually received his part in full. The affair additionally worsened the relationships among all three members of the Schopenhauer family.
He shortened his stay in Italy because of the trouble with Muhl and returned to Dresden. Disturbed by the financial risk and the lack of responses to his book he decided to take an academic position since it provided him with both income and an opportunity to promote his views. He contacted his friends at universities in Heidelberg, Göttingen and Berlin and found Berlin most attractive. He scheduled his lectures to coincide with those of the famous philosopher G. W. F. Hegel, whom Schopenhauer described as a "clumsy charlatan". He was especially appalled by Hegel's supposedly poor knowledge of natural sciences and tried to engage him in a quarrel about it already at his test lecture in March 1820. Hegel was also facing political suspicions at the time, when many progressive professors were fired, while Schopenhauer carefully mentioned in his application that he had no interest in politics. Despite their differences and the arrogant request to schedule lectures at the same time as his own, Hegel still voted to accept Schopenhauer to the university. Only five students turned up to Schopenhauer's lectures, and he dropped out of academia. A late essay, "On University Philosophy", expressed his resentment towards the work conducted in academies.
Later life
After his trying in academia, he continued to travel extensively, visiting Leipzig, Nuremberg, Stuttgart, Schaffhausen, Vevey, Milan and spending eight months in Florence. Before he left for his three-year travel, Schopenhauer had an incident with his Berlin neighbor, 47-year-old seamstress Caroline Louise Marquet. The details of the August 1821 incident are unknown. He claimed that he had just pushed her from his entrance after she had rudely refused to leave, and that she had purposely fallen to the ground so that she could sue him. She claimed that he had attacked her so violently that she had become paralyzed on her right side and unable to work. She immediately sued him, and the process lasted until May 1827, when a court found Schopenhauer guilty and forced him to pay her an annual pension until her death in 1842.
Schopenhauer enjoyed Italy, where he studied art and socialized with Italian and English nobles. It was his last visit to the country. He left for Munich and stayed there for a year, mostly recuperating from various health issues, some of them possibly caused by venereal diseases (the treatment his doctor used suggests syphilis). He contacted publishers, offering to translate Hume into German and Kant into English, but his proposals were declined. Returning to Berlin, he began to study Spanish so he could read some of his favorite authors in their original language. He liked Pedro Calderón de la Barca, Lope de Vega, Miguel de Cervantes, and especially Baltasar Gracián. He also made failed attempts to publish his translations of their works. A few attempts to revive his lectures—again scheduled at the same time as Hegel's—also failed, as did his inquiries about relocating to other universities.
During his Berlin years, Schopenhauer occasionally mentioned his desire to marry and have a family. For a while he was unsuccessfully courting 17-year-old Flora Weiss, who was 22 years younger than himself. His unpublished writings from that time show that he was already very critical of monogamy but still not advocating polygyny—instead musing about a polyamorous relationship that he called "tetragamy". He had an on-and-off relationship with a young dancer, Caroline Richter (she also used the surname Medon after one of her ex-lovers). They met when he was 33 and she was 19 and working at the Berlin Opera. She had already had numerous lovers and a son out of wedlock, and later gave birth to another son, this time to an unnamed foreign diplomat (she soon had another pregnancy but the child was stillborn). As Schopenhauer was preparing to escape from Berlin in 1831, due to a cholera epidemic, he offered to take her with him on the condition that she left her young son behind. She refused and he went alone; in his will he left her a significant sum of money, but insisted that it should not be spent in any way on her second son.
Schopenhauer claimed that, in his last year in Berlin, he had a prophetic dream that urged him to escape from the city. As he arrived in his new home in Frankfurt, he supposedly had another supernatural experience, an apparition of his dead father and his mother, who was still alive. This experience led him to spend some time investigating paranormal phenomena and magic. He was quite critical of the available studies and claimed that they were mostly ignorant or fraudulent, but he did believe that there are authentic cases of such phenomena and tried to explain them through his metaphysics as manifestations of the will.
Upon his arrival in Frankfurt, he experienced a period of depression and declining health. He renewed his correspondence with his mother, and she seemed concerned that he might commit suicide like his father. By now Johanna and Adele were living very modestly. Johanna's writing did not bring her much income, and her popularity was waning. Their correspondence remained reserved, and Arthur seemed undisturbed by her death in 1838. His relationship with his sister grew closer and he corresponded with her until she died in 1849.
In July 1832, Schopenhauer left Frankfurt for Mannheim but returned in July 1833 to remain there for the rest of his life, except for a few short journeys. He lived alone except for a succession of pet poodles named Atman and Butz. In 1836, he published On the Will in Nature. In 1838, he sent his essay "On the Freedom of the Will" to the contest of the Royal Norwegian Society of Sciences in 1838 and won the prize in 1839. He sent another essay, "On the Basis of Morality", to the Royal Danish Society of Sciences in 1839, but did not win the (1840) prize despite being the only contestant. The Society was appalled that several distinguished contemporary philosophers were mentioned in a very offensive manner, and claimed that the essay missed the point of the set topic and that the arguments were inadequate. Schopenhauer, who had been very confident that he would win, was enraged by this rejection. He published both essays as The Two Basic Problems of Ethics. The first edition, published September 1840 but with an 1841 date, again failed to draw attention to his philosophy. In the preface to the second edition, in 1860, he was still pouring insults on the Royal Danish Society. Two years later, after some negotiations, he managed to convince his publisher, Brockhaus, to print the second, updated edition of The World as Will and Representation. That book was again mostly ignored and the few reviews were mixed or negative.
Schopenhauer began to attract some followers, mostly outside academia, among practical professionals (several of them were lawyers) who pursued private philosophical studies. He jokingly referred to them as "evangelists" and "apostles". One of the most active early followers was Julius Frauenstädt, who wrote numerous articles promoting Schopenhauer's philosophy. He was also instrumental in finding another publisher after Brockhaus declined to publish Parerga and Paralipomena, believing that it would be another failure. Though Schopenhauer later stopped corresponding with him, claiming that he did not adhere closely enough to his ideas, Frauenstädt continued to promote Schopenhauer's work. They renewed their communication in 1859 and Schopenhauer named him heir for his literary estate. Frauenstädt also became the editor of the first collected works of Schopenhauer.
In 1848, Schopenhauer witnessed violent upheaval in Frankfurt after General Hans Adolf Erdmann von Auerswald and Prince Felix Lichnowsky were murdered. He became worried for his own safety and property. Even earlier in life he had had such worries and kept a sword and loaded pistols near his bed to defend himself from thieves. He gave a friendly welcome to Austrian soldiers who wanted to shoot revolutionaries from his window and as they were leaving he gave one of the officers his opera glasses to help him monitor rebels. The rebellion passed without any loss to Schopenhauer and he later praised Alfred I, Prince of Windisch-Grätz for restoring order. He even modified his will, leaving a large part of his property to a Prussian fund that helped soldiers who became invalids while fighting rebellion in 1848 or the families of soldiers who died in battle. As Young Hegelians were advocating change and progress, Schopenhauer claimed that misery is natural for humans and that, even if some utopian society were established, people would still fight each other out of boredom, or would starve due to overpopulation.
In 1851, Schopenhauer published Parerga and Paralipomena, which contains essays that are supplementary to his main work. It was his first successful, widely read book, partly due to the work of his disciples who wrote praising reviews. The essays that proved most popular were the ones that actually did not contain the basic philosophical ideas of his system. Many academic philosophers considered him a great stylist and cultural critic but did not take his philosophy seriously. His early critics liked to point out similarities of his ideas to those of Fichte and Schelling, or to claim that there were numerous contradictions in his philosophy. Both criticisms enraged Schopenhauer. He was becoming less interested in intellectual fights, but encouraged his disciples to do so. His private notes and correspondence show that he acknowledged some of the criticisms regarding contradictions, inconsistencies, and vagueness in his philosophy, but claimed that he was not concerned about harmony and agreement in his propositions and that some of his ideas should not be taken literally but instead as metaphors.
Academic philosophers were also starting to notice his work. In 1856, the University of Leipzig sponsored an essay contest about Schopenhauer's philosophy, which was won by Rudolf Seydel's very critical essay. Schopenhauer's friend Jules Lunteschütz made the first of his four portraits of him—which Schopenhauer did not particularly like—which was soon sold to a wealthy landowner, Carl Ferdinand Wiesike, who built a house to display it. Schopenhauer seemed flattered and amused by this, and would claim that it was his first chapel. As his fame increased, copies of paintings and photographs of him were being sold and admirers were visiting the places where he had lived and written his works. People visited Frankfurt's Englischer Hof to observe him dining. Admirers gave him gifts and asked for autographs. He complained that he still felt isolated due to his not very social nature and the fact that many of his good friends had already died from old age.
He remained healthy in his own old age, which he attributed to regular walks no matter the weather and always getting enough sleep. He had a great appetite and could read without glasses, but his hearing had been declining since his youth and he developed problems with rheumatism. He remained active and lucid, continued his reading, writing and correspondence until his death. The numerous notes that he made during these years, amongst others on aging, were published posthumously under the title Senilia. In the spring of 1860 his health began to decline, and he experienced shortness of breath and heart palpitations; in September he suffered inflammation of the lungs and, although he was starting to recover, he remained very weak. The last friend to visit him was Wilhelm Gwinner; according to him, Schopenhauer was concerned that he would not be able to finish his planned additions to Parerga and Paralipomena but was at peace with dying. He died of pulmonary-respiratory failure on 21 September 1860 while sitting at home on his couch. He died at the age of 72 and had a funeral conducted by a Lutheran minister.
Philosophy
Theory of perception
In November 1813 Goethe invited Schopenhauer to help him on his Theory of Colours. Although Schopenhauer considered colour theory a minor matter, he accepted the invitation out of admiration for Goethe. Nevertheless, these investigations led him to his most important discovery in epistemology: finding a demonstration for the a priori nature of causality.
Kant openly admitted that it was Hume's skeptical assault on causality that motivated the critical investigations in Critique of Pure Reason and gave an elaborate proof to show that causality is a priori. After G. E. Schulze had made it plausible that Kant had not disproven Hume's skepticism, it was up to those loyal to Kant's project to prove this important matter.
The difference between the approaches of Kant and Schopenhauer was this: Kant simply declared that the empirical content of perception is "given" to us from outside, an expression with which Schopenhauer often expressed his dissatisfaction. He, on the other hand, was occupied with the questions: how do we get this empirical content of perception; how is it possible to comprehend subjective sensations "limited to my skin" as the objective perception of things that lie "outside" of me?
The sensations in the hand of a man born blind, on feeling an object of cubic shape, are quite uniform and the same on all sides and in every direction: the edges, it is true, press upon a smaller portion of his hand, still nothing at all like a cube is contained in these sensations. His Understanding draws the immediate and intuitive conclusion from the resistance felt, that this resistance must have a cause, which then presents itself through that conclusion as a hard body; and through the movements of his arms in feeling the object, while the hand's sensation remains unaltered, he constructs the cubic shape in Space. If the representation of a cause and of Space, together with their laws, had not already existed within him, the image of a cube could never have proceeded from those successive sensations in his hand.
Causality is therefore not an empirical concept drawn from objective perceptions, as Hume had maintained; instead, as Kant had said, objective perception presupposes knowledge of causality.
By this intellectual operation, comprehending every effect in our sensory organs as having an external cause, the external world arises. With vision, finding the cause is essentially simplified due to light acting in straight lines. We are seldom conscious of the process that interprets the double sensation in both eyes as coming from one object, that inverts the impressions on the retinas, and that uses the change in the apparent position of an object relative to more distant objects provided by binocular vision to perceive depth and distance.
Schopenhauer stresses the importance of the intellectual nature of perception; the senses furnish the raw material by which the intellect produces the world as representation. He set out his theory of perception for the first time in On Vision and Colors, and, in the subsequent editions of Fourfold Root, an extensive exposition is given in § 21.
The world as representation
Schopenhauer saw his philosophy as an extension of Kant's, and used the results of Kantian epistemological investigation (transcendental idealism) as starting point for his own. Kant had argued that the empirical world is merely a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in our mental representations. Schopenhauer did not deny that the external world existed empirically but followed Kant in claiming that our knowledge and experience of the world is always in some sense dependent on us. For Schopenhauer in particular, the spatiotemporal form and causal structure of the external world are contributed to our experiences of it by the brain as it renders perceptions. Schopenhauer reiterates this in the first sentence of his main work: "The world is my representation (Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung)". Everything that there is for cognition (the entire world) exists simply as an object in relation to a subject—a 'representation' to a subject. Everything that belongs to the world is, therefore, 'subject-dependent'. In Book One of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer considers the world from this angle—that is, insofar as it is representation.
Kant had previously argued that we perceive reality as something spatial and temporal not because reality is inherently spatial and temporal, but because that is how our minds operate in perceiving an object. Therefore, understanding objects in space and time represents our 'contribution' to an experience. For Schopenhauer, Kant's 'greatest service' lay in the 'differentiation between phenomena and the thing-in-itself (noumena), based on the proof that between everything and us there is always a perceiving mind.' In other words, Kant's primary achievement is to demonstrate that instead of being a blank slate where reality merely reveals its character, the mind, with sensory support, actively participates in constructing reality. Thus, Schopenhauer believed that Kant had shown that the everyday world of experience, and indeed the entire material world related to space and time, is merely 'appearance' or 'phenomena,' entirely distinct from the thing-in-itself.'
The world as will
Main article: The World as Will and RepresentationIn Book Two of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer considers what the world is beyond the aspect of it that appears to us—that is, the aspect of the world beyond representation, the world considered "in-itself" or "noumena", its inner essence. The very being in-itself of all things, Schopenhauer argues, is will (Wille). The empirical world that appears to us as representation has plurality and is ordered in a spatio-temporal framework. The world as thing in-itself must exist outside the subjective forms of space and time. Although the world manifests itself to our experience as a multiplicity of objects (the "objectivation" of the will), each element of this multiplicity has the same blind essence striving towards existence and life. Human rationality is merely a secondary phenomenon that does not distinguish humanity from the rest of nature at the fundamental, essential level. The advanced cognitive abilities of human beings, Schopenhauer argues, serve the ends of willing—an illogical, directionless, ceaseless striving that condemns the human individual to a life of suffering unredeemed by any final purpose. Schopenhauer's philosophy of the will as the essential reality behind the world as representation is often called metaphysical voluntarism.
For Schopenhauer, understanding the world as will leads to ethical concerns (see the ethics section below for further detail), which he explores in the Fourth Book of The World as Will and Representation and again in his two prize essays on ethics, On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality. No individual human actions are free, Schopenhauer argues, because they are events in the world of appearance and thus are subject to the principle of sufficient reason: a person's actions are a necessary consequence of motives and the given character of the individual human. Necessity extends to the actions of human beings just as it does to every other appearance, and thus we cannot speak of freedom of individual willing. Albert Einstein quoted the Schopenhauerian idea that "a man can do as he will, but not will as he will." Yet the will as thing in-itself is free, as it exists beyond the realm of representation and thus is not constrained by any of the forms of necessity that are part of the principle of sufficient reason.
According to Schopenhauer, salvation from our miserable existence can come through the will's being "tranquillized" by the metaphysical insight that reveals individuality to be merely an illusion. The saint or 'great soul' intuitively "recognizes the whole, comprehends its essence, and finds that it is constantly passing away, caught up in vain strivings, inner conflict, and perpetual suffering". The negation of the will, in other words, stems from the insight that the world in-itself (free from the forms of space and time) is one. Ascetic practices, Schopenhauer remarks, are used to aid the will's "self-abolition", which brings about a blissful, redemptive "will-less" state of emptiness that is free from striving or suffering.
Art and aesthetics
Main article: Arthur Schopenhauer's aestheticsFor Schopenhauer, human "willing"—desiring, craving, etc.—is at the root of suffering. A temporary way to escape this pain is through aesthetic contemplation. Here one moves away from ordinary cognizance of individual things to cognizance of eternal Platonic Ideas—in other words, cognizance that is free from the service of will. In aesthetic contemplation, one no longer perceives an object of perception as something from which one is separated; rather "it is as if the object alone existed without anyone perceiving it, and one can thus no longer separate the perceiver from the perception, but the two have become one, the entirety of consciousness entirely filled and occupied by a single perceptual image". Subject and object are no longer distinguishable, and the Idea comes to the fore.
From this aesthetic immersion, one is no longer an individual who suffers as a result of servitude to one's individual will but, rather, becomes a "pure, will-less, painless, timeless, subject of cognition". The pure, will-less subject of cognition is cognizant only of Ideas, not individual things: this is a kind of cognition that is unconcerned with relations between objects according to the Principle of Sufficient Reason (time, space, cause and effect) and instead involves complete absorption in the object.
Art is the practical consequence of this brief aesthetic contemplation, since it attempts to depict the essence/pure Ideas of the world. Music, for Schopenhauer, is the purest form of art because it is the one that depicts the will itself without it appearing as subject to the Principle of Sufficient Reason, therefore as an individual object. According to Daniel Albright, "Schopenhauer thought that music was the only art that did not merely copy ideas, but actually embodied the will itself". He deemed music a timeless, universal language comprehended everywhere, that can imbue global enthusiasm, if in possession of a significant melody.
Mathematics
Schopenhauer's realist views on mathematics are evident in his criticism of contemporaneous attempts to prove the parallel postulate in Euclidean geometry. Writing shortly before the discovery of hyperbolic geometry demonstrated the logical independence of the axiom—and long before the general theory of relativity revealed that it does not necessarily express a property of physical space—Schopenhauer criticized mathematicians for trying to use indirect concepts to prove what he held was directly evident from intuitive perception.
The Euclidean method of demonstration has brought forth from its own womb its most striking parody and caricature in the famous controversy over the theory of parallels, and in the attempts, repeated every year, to prove the eleventh axiom (also known as the fifth postulate). The axiom asserts, and that indeed through the indirect criterion of a third intersecting line, that two lines inclined to each other (for this is the precise meaning of "less than two right angles"), if produced far enough, must meet. Now this truth is supposed to be too complicated to pass as self-evident, and therefore needs a proof; but no such proof can be produced, just because there is nothing more immediate.
Throughout his writings, Schopenhauer criticized the logical derivation of philosophies and mathematics from mere concepts, instead of from intuitive perceptions.
In fact, it seems to me that the logical method is in this way reduced to an absurdity. But it is precisely through the controversies over this, together with the futile attempts to demonstrate the directly certain as merely indirectly certain, that the independence and clearness of intuitive evidence appear in contrast with the uselessness and difficulty of logical proof, a contrast as instructive as it is amusing. The direct certainty will not be admitted here, just because it is no merely logical certainty following from the concept, and thus resting solely on the relation of predicate to subject, according to the principle of contradiction. But that eleventh axiom regarding parallel lines is a synthetic proposition a priori, and as such has the guarantee of pure, not empirical, perception; this perception is just as immediate and certain as is the principle of contradiction itself, from which all proofs originally derive their certainty. At bottom this holds good of every geometrical theorem ...
Although Schopenhauer could see no justification for trying to prove Euclid's parallel postulate, he did see a reason for examining another of Euclid's axioms.
It surprises me that the eighth axiom, "Figures that coincide with one another are equal to one another", is not rather attacked. For "coinciding with one another" is either a mere tautology, or something quite empirical, belonging not to pure intuition or perception, but to external sensuous experience. Thus it presupposes mobility of the figures, but matter alone is movable in space. Consequently, this reference to coincidence with one another forsakes pure space, the sole element of geometry, in order to pass over to the material and empirical.
This follows Kant's reasoning.
Ethics
Main article: On the Basis of MoralitySchopenhauer asserts that the task of ethics is not to prescribe moral actions that ought to be done, but to investigate moral actions. As such, he states that philosophy is always theoretical: its task to explain what is given.
According to Kant's transcendental idealism, space and time are forms of our sensibility in which phenomena appear in multiplicity. Reality in itself is free from multiplicity, not in the sense that an object is one, but that it is outside the possibility of multiplicity. Two individuals, though they appear distinct, are in-themselves not distinct.
Appearances are entirely subordinated to the principle of sufficient reason. The egoistic individual who focuses his aims on his own interests has to deal with empirical laws as well as he can.
What is relevant for ethics are individuals who can act against their own self-interest. If we take a man who suffers when he sees his fellow men living in poverty and consequently uses a significant part of his income to support their needs instead of his own pleasures, then the simplest way to describe this is that he makes less distinction between himself and others than is usually made.
Regarding how things appear to us, the egoist asserts a gap between two individuals, but the altruist experiences the sufferings of others as his own. In the same way a compassionate man cannot hurt animals, though they appear as distinct from himself.
What motivates the altruist is compassion. The suffering of others is for him not a cold matter to which he is indifferent, but he feels connectiveness to all beings. Compassion is thus the basis of morality.
Eternal justice
Schopenhauer calls the principle through which multiplicity appears the principium individuationis. When we behold nature we see that it is a cruel battle for existence. Individual manifestations of the will can maintain themselves only at the expense of others—the will, as the only thing that exists, has no other option but to devour itself to experience pleasure. This is a fundamental characteristic of the will, and cannot be circumvented.
Unlike temporal or human justice, which requires time to repay an evil deed and "has its seat in the state, as requiting and punishing", eternal justice "rules not the state but the world, is not dependent upon human institutions, is not subject to chance and deception, is not uncertain, wavering, and erring, but infallible, fixed, and sure". Eternal justice is not retributive, because retribution requires time. There are no delays or reprieves. Instead, punishment is tied to the offence, "to the point where the two become one. ... Tormenter and tormented are one. The errs in that he believes he is not a partaker in the suffering; the , in that he believes he is not a partaker in the guilt."
Suffering is the moral outcome of our attachment to pleasure. Schopenhauer deemed that this truth was expressed by the Christian dogma of original sin and, in Eastern religions, by the dogma of rebirth.
Quietism
He who sees through the principium individuationis and comprehends suffering in general as his own will see suffering everywhere and, instead of fighting for the happiness of his individual manifestation, will abhor life itself since he knows that it is inseparably connected with suffering. For him, a happy individual life in a world of suffering is like a beggar who dreams one night that he is a king.
Those who have experienced this intuitive knowledge cannot affirm life, but exhibit asceticism and quietism, meaning that they are no longer sensitive to motives, are not concerned about their individual welfare, and accept without resistance the evil that others inflict on them. They welcome poverty and neither seek nor flee death. Schopenhauer referred to asceticism as the denial of the will to live.
Human life is a ceaseless struggle for satisfaction and, instead of continuing their struggle, ascetics break it. It does not matter if these ascetics adhere to the dogmata of Christianity or to Dharmic religions, since their way of living is the result of intuitive knowledge.
The Christian mystic and the teacher of the Vedanta philosophy agree in this respect also, they both regard all outward works and religious exercises as superfluous for him who has attained to perfection. So much agreement in the case of such different ages and nations is a practical proof that what is expressed here is not, as optimistic dullness likes to assert, an eccentricity and perversity of the mind, but an essential side of human nature, which only appears so rarely because of its excellence.
Psychology
Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the necessity of sex, but Schopenhauer addressed sex and related concepts forthrightly:
... one ought rather to be surprised that a thing which plays throughout so important a part in human life has hitherto practically been disregarded by philosophers altogether, and lies before us as raw and untreated material.
He named a force within man that he felt took invariable precedence over reason: the Will to Live or Will to Life (Wille zum Leben), defined as an inherent drive within human beings, and all creatures, to stay alive; a force that inveigles us into reproducing.
Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental, but rather understood it as an immensely powerful force that lay unseen within man's psyche, guaranteeing the quality of the human race:
The ultimate aim of all love affairs ... is more important than all other aims in man's life; and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it. What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation ...
It has often been argued that Schopenhauer's thoughts on sexuality foreshadowed the theory of evolution, a claim met with satisfaction by Darwin as he included a quotation from Schopenhauer in his Descent of Man. This has also been noted about Freud's concepts of the libido and the unconscious mind, and evolutionary psychology in general.
Political and social thought
Politics
Schopenhauer's politics were an echo of his system of ethics, which he elucidated in detail in his Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik (the two essays On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality).
In occasional political comments in his Parerga and Paralipomena and Manuscript Remains, Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent of limited government. Schopenhauer shared the view of Thomas Hobbes on the necessity of the state and state action to check the innate destructive tendencies of our species. He also defended the independence of the legislative, judicial and executive branches of power, and a monarch as an impartial element able to practise justice (in a practical and everyday sense, not a cosmological one).
He declared that monarchy is "natural to man in almost the same way as it is to bees and ants, to cranes in flight, to wandering elephants, to wolves in a pack in search of prey, and to other animals". Intellect in monarchies, he writes, always has "much better chances against stupidity, its implacable and ever-present foe, than it has in republics; but this is a great advantage." On the other hand, Schopenhauer disparaged republicanism as being "as unnatural to man as it is unfavorable to higher intellectual life and thus to the arts and sciences".
By his own admission, Schopenhauer did not give much thought to politics, and several times he wrote proudly of how little attention he paid "to political affairs of day". In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government, and a few continent-shaking wars, he maintained his position of "minding not the times but the eternities". He wrote many disparaging remarks about Germany and the Germans. A typical example is: "For a German it is even good to have somewhat lengthy words in his mouth, for he thinks slowly, and they give him time to reflect."
Punishment
The State, Schopenhauer claimed, punishes criminals to prevent future crimes. It places "beside every possible motive for committing a wrong a more powerful motive for leaving it undone, in the inescapable punishment. Accordingly, the criminal code is as complete a register as possible of counter-motives to all criminal actions that can possibly be imagined ..." He claimed that this doctrine was not original to him but had appeared in the writings of Plato, Seneca, Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Anselm Feuerbach.
Races and religions
Schopenhauer attributed civilizational primacy to the northern "white races" due to their sensitivity and creativity (except for the ancient Egyptians and Hindus, whom he saw as equal):
The highest civilization and culture, apart from the ancient Hindus and Egyptians, are found exclusively among the white races; and even with many dark peoples, the ruling caste or race is fairer in colour than the rest and has, therefore, evidently immigrated, for example, the Brahmans, the Incas, and the rulers of the South Sea Islands. All this is due to the fact that necessity is the mother of invention because those tribes that emigrated early to the north, and there gradually became white, had to develop all their intellectual powers and invent and perfect all the arts in their struggle with need, want and misery, which in their many forms were brought about by the climate. This they had to do in order to make up for the parsimony of nature and out of it all came their high civilization.
Schopenhauer was fervently opposed to slavery. Speaking of the treatment of slaves in the slave-holding states of the United States, he condemned "those devils in human form, those bigoted, church-going, strict sabbath-observing scoundrels, especially the Anglican parsons among them" for how they "treat their innocent black brothers who through violence and injustice have fallen into their devil's claws". The slave-holding states of North America, Schopenhauer writes, are a "disgrace to the whole of humanity".
Schopenhauer also maintained a marked metaphysical and political anti-Judaism. He argued that Christianity constituted a revolt against what he styled the materialistic basis of Judaism, exhibiting an Indian-influenced ethics reflecting the Aryan-Vedic theme of spiritual self-conquest. He saw this as opposed to the ignorant drive toward earthly utopianism and superficiality of a worldly "Jewish" spirit:
is, therefore, the crudest and poorest of all religions and consists merely in an absurd and revolting theism. It amounts to this that the κύριος , who has created the world, desires to be worshipped and adored; and so above all he is jealous, is envious of his colleagues, of all the other gods; if sacrifices are made to them he is furious and his Jews have a bad time ... It is most deplorable that this religion has become the basis of the prevailing religion of Europe; for it is a religion without any metaphysical tendency. While all other religions endeavor to explain to the people by symbols the metaphysical significance of life, the religion of the Jews is entirely immanent and furnishes nothing but a mere war-cry in the struggle with other nations.
Women
In his 1851 essay "On Women", Schopenhauer expressed opposition to what he called "Teutonico-Christian stupidity" of "reflexive, unexamined reverence for the female (abgeschmackten Weiberveneration)". He wrote: "Women are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish, frivolous and short-sighted." He opined that women are deficient in artistic faculties and sense of justice, and expressed his opposition to monogamy. He claimed that "woman is by nature meant to obey". The essay does give some compliments: "women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than are", and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others.
Schopenhauer's writings influenced many, from Friedrich Nietzsche to nineteenth-century feminists. His biological analysis of the difference between the sexes, and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction, anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured by sociobiologists and evolutionary psychologists.
When the elderly Schopenhauer sat for a sculpture portrait by the Prussian sculptor Elisabet Ney in 1859, he was much impressed by the young woman's wit and independence, as well as by her skill as a visual artist. After his time with Ney, he told Richard Wagner's friend Malwida von Meysenbug: "I have not yet spoken my last word about women. I believe that if a woman succeeds in withdrawing from the mass, or rather raising herself above the mass, she grows ceaselessly and more than a man."
Pederasty
In the third, expanded edition of The World as Will and Representation (1859), Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on the Metaphysics of Sexual Love. He wrote that pederasty has the benefit of preventing ill-begotten children. Concerning this, he stated that "the vice we are considering appears to work directly against the aims and ends of nature, and that in a matter that is all important and of the greatest concern to her it must in fact serve these very aims, although only indirectly, as a means for preventing greater evils." Schopenhauer ends the appendix with the statement that "by expounding these paradoxical ideas, I wanted to grant to the professors of philosophy a small favour. I have done so by giving them the opportunity of slandering me by saying that I defend and commend pederasty."
Heredity and eugenics
Schopenhauer viewed personality and intellect as inherited. He quotes Horace's saying, "From the brave and good are the brave descended" (Odes, iv, 4, 29) and Shakespeare's line from Cymbeline, "Cowards father cowards, and base things sire base" (IV, 2) to reinforce his hereditarian argument. Mechanistically, Schopenhauer believed that a person inherits his intellect through his mother, and personal character through the father. This belief in heritability of traits informed Schopenhauer's view of love—placing it at the highest level of importance. For Schopenhauer the "final aim of all love intrigues, be they comic or tragic, is really of more importance than all other ends in human life. What it all turns upon is nothing less than the composition of the next generation. ... It is not the weal or woe of any one individual, but that of the human race to come, which is here at stake." This view of the importance for the species of whom we choose to love was reflected in his views on eugenics or good breeding. Here Schopenhauer wrote:
With our knowledge of the complete unalterability both of character and of mental faculties, we are led to the view that a real and thorough improvement of the human race might be reached not so much from outside as from within, not so much by theory and instruction as rather by the path of generation. Plato had something of the kind in mind when, in the fifth book of his Republic, he explained his plan for increasing and improving his warrior caste. If we could castrate all scoundrels and stick all stupid geese in a convent, and give men of noble character a whole harem, and procure men, and indeed thorough men, for all girls of intellect and understanding, then a generation would soon arise which would produce a better age than that of Pericles.
In another context, Schopenhauer reiterated his eugenic thesis: "If you want Utopian plans, I would say: the only solution to the problem is the despotism of the wise and noble members of a genuine aristocracy, a genuine nobility, achieved by mating the most magnanimous men with the cleverest and most gifted women. This proposal constitutes my Utopia and my Platonic Republic." Analysts (e.g., Keith Ansell-Pearson) have suggested that Schopenhauer's anti-egalitarianist sentiment and his support for eugenics influenced the neo-aristocratic philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, who initially considered Schopenhauer his mentor.
Animal rights
Main article: Arthur Schopenhauer's view on animal rightsAs a consequence of his monistic philosophy, Schopenhauer was very concerned about animal welfare and rights. For him, all individual animals, including humans, are essentially phenomenal manifestations of the one underlying Will. For him the word "will" designates force, power, impulse, energy, and desire; it is the closest word we have that can signify both the essence of all external things and our own direct, inner experience. Since every living thing possesses will, humans and animals are fundamentally the same and can recognize themselves in each other. For this reason, he claimed that a good person would have sympathy for animals, who are our fellow sufferers.
Compassion for animals is intimately associated with goodness of character, and it may be confidently asserted that he who is cruel to living creatures cannot be a good man.
— On the Basis of Morality, § 19
Nothing leads more definitely to a recognition of the identity of the essential nature in animal and human phenomena than a study of zoology and anatomy.
— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 8
The assumption that animals are without rights and the illusion that our treatment of them has no moral significance is a positively outrageous example of Western crudity and barbarity. Universal compassion is the only guarantee of morality.
— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 8
In 1841, he praised the establishment in London of the Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals, and in Philadelphia of the Animals' Friends Society. Schopenhauer went so far as to protest using the pronoun "it" in reference to animals because that led to treatment of them as though they were inanimate things. To reinforce his points, Schopenhauer referred to anecdotal reports of the look in the eyes of a monkey who had been shot and also the grief of a baby elephant whose mother had been killed by a hunter.
Schopenhauer was very attached to his succession of pet poodles. He criticized Spinoza's belief that animals are a mere means for the satisfaction of humans. Tim Madigan wrote that despite all of his bombast, Schopenhauer was a sympathetic character who had concerns for the suffering of animals.
The greatest benefit conferred by the railways is that they spare millions of draught-horses their miserable existences.
— Essays and Aphorisms, p. 171
Intellectual interests and affinities
Indology
Schopenhauer read the Latin translation of the ancient Hindu texts, the Upanishads, translated by French writer Anquetil du Perron from the Persian translation of Prince Dara Shukoh entitled Sirre-Akbar ("The Great Secret"). He was so impressed by its philosophy that he called it "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed it contained superhuman concepts. Schopenhauer considered India as "the land of the most ancient and most pristine wisdom, the place from which Europeans could trace their descent and the tradition by which they had been influenced in so many decisive ways", and regarded the Upanishads as "the most profitable and elevating reading which is possible in the world. It has been the solace of my life, and will be the solace of my death."
Schopenhauer was first introduced to Anquetil du Perron's translation by Friedrich Majer in 1814. They met during the winter of 1813–1814 in Weimar at the home of Schopenhauer's mother, according to the biographer Safranski. Majer was a follower of Herder, and an early Indologist. Schopenhauer did not begin serious study of the Indic texts until the summer of 1814. Safranski maintains that, between 1815 and 1817, Schopenhauer had another important cross-pollination with Indian thought in Dresden. This was through his neighbor of two years, Karl Christian Friedrich Krause. Krause was then a minor and rather unorthodox philosopher who attempted to mix his own ideas with ancient Indian wisdom. Krause had also mastered Sanskrit, unlike Schopenhauer, and they developed a professional relationship. It was from Krause that Schopenhauer learned meditation and received the closest thing to expert advice concerning Indian thought.
The view of things that all plurality is only apparent, that in the endless series of individuals, passing simultaneously and successively into and out of life, generation after generation, age after age, there is but one and the same entity really existing, which is present and identical in all alike;—this theory, I say, was of course known long before Kant; indeed, it may be carried back to the remotest antiquity. It is the alpha and omega of the oldest book in the world, the sacred Vedas, whose dogmatic part, or rather esoteric teaching, is found in the Upanishads. There, in almost every page this profound doctrine lies enshrined; with tireless repetition, in countless adaptations, by many varied parables and similes it is expounded and inculcated.
— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 4
For Schopenhauer, will had ontological primacy over the intellect; desire is prior to thought. Schopenhauer felt this was similar to notions of puruṣārtha or goals of life in Vedānta Hinduism.
In Schopenhauer's philosophy, denial of the will is attained by:
- personal experience of an extremely great suffering that leads to loss of the will to live; or
- knowledge of the essential nature of life in the world through observation of the suffering of other people.
The book Oupnekhat (Upanishad) always lay open on his table, and he invariably studied it before going to bed. He called the opening up of Sanskrit literature "the greatest gift of our century", and predicted that the philosophy and knowledge of the Upanishads would become the cherished faith of the West. Most noticeable, in the case of Schopenhauer's work, was the significance of the Chandogya Upanishad, whose Mahāvākya, Tat Tvam Asi, is mentioned throughout The World as Will and Representation.
Buddhism
Schopenhauer noted a correspondence between his doctrines and the Four Noble Truths of Buddhism. Similarities centered on the principles that life involves suffering, that suffering is caused by desire (taṇhā), and that the extinction of desire leads to liberation. Thus three of the four "truths of the Buddha" correspond to Schopenhauer's doctrine of the will. In Buddhism, while greed and lust are always unskillful, desire is ethically variable – it can be skillful, unskillful, or neutral.
Buddhist nirvāṇa is not equivalent to the condition that Schopenhauer described as denial of the will. Nirvāṇa is not the extinguishing of the person as some Western scholars have thought, but only the "extinguishing" (the literal meaning of nirvana) of the flames of greed, hatred, and delusion that assail a person's character. Schopenhauer made the following statement in his discussion of religions:
If I wished to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I should have to concede to Buddhism pre-eminence over the others. In any case, it must be a pleasure to me to see my doctrine in such close agreement with a religion that the majority of men on earth hold as their own, for this numbers far more followers than any other. And this agreement must be yet the more pleasing to me, inasmuch as in my philosophizing I have certainly not been under its influence . For up till 1818, when my work appeared, there was to be found in Europe only a very few accounts of Buddhism.
Buddhist philosopher Keiji Nishitani sought to distance Buddhism from Schopenhauer. While Schopenhauer's philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary, his methodology was resolutely empirical, rather than speculative or transcendental:
Philosophy ... is a science, and as such has no articles of faith; accordingly, in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically, or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions.
Also note:
This actual world of what is knowable, in which we are and which is in us, remains both the material and the limit of our consideration.
The argument that Buddhism affected Schopenhauer's philosophy more than any other Dharmic faith loses credence since he did not begin a serious study of Buddhism until after the publication of The World as Will and Representation in 1818. Scholars have started to revise earlier views about Schopenhauer's discovery of Buddhism. Proof of early interest and influence appears in Schopenhauer's 1815–16 notes (transcribed and translated by Urs App) about Buddhism. They are included in a recent case study that traces Schopenhauer's interest in Buddhism and documents its influence. Other scholarly work questions how similar Schopenhauer's philosophy actually is to Buddhism.
Magic and occultism
Some traditions in Western esotericism and parapsychology interested Schopenhauer and influenced his philosophical theories. He praised animal magnetism as evidence for the reality of magic in his On the Will in Nature, and went so far as to accept the division of magic into left-hand and right-hand magic, although he doubted the existence of demons.
Schopenhauer grounded magic in the Will and claimed all forms of magical transformation depended on the human Will, not on ritual. This theory notably parallels Aleister Crowley's system of magic and its emphasis on human will. Given the importance of the Will to Schopenhauer's overarching system, this amounts to "suggesting his whole philosophical system had magical powers." Schopenhauer rejected the theory of disenchantment and claimed philosophy should synthesize itself with magic, which he believed amount to "practical metaphysics".
Neoplatonism, including the traditions of Plotinus and to a lesser extent Marsilio Ficino, has also been cited as an influence on Schopenhauer.
Interests
Schopenhauer had a wide range of interests, from science and opera to occultism and literature.
In his student years, Schopenhauer went more often to lectures in the sciences than philosophy. He kept a strong interest as his personal library contained near to 200 books of scientific literature at his death, and his works refer to scientific titles not found in the library.
Many evenings were spent in the theatre, opera and ballet; Schopenhauer especially liked the operas of Mozart, Rossini and Bellini. Schopenhauer considered music the highest art, and played the flute during his whole life.
As a polyglot, he knew German, Italian, Spanish, French, English, Latin and ancient Greek, and was an avid reader of poetry and literature. He particularly revered Goethe, Petrarch, Calderón and Shakespeare.
If Goethe had not been sent into the world simultaneously with Kant in order to counterbalance him, so to speak, in the spirit of the age, the latter would have been haunted like a nightmare many an aspiring mind and would have oppressed it with great affliction. But now the two have an infinitely wholesome effect from opposite directions and will probably raise the German spirit to a height surpassing even that of antiquity.
In philosophy, his most important influences were, according to himself, Kant, Plato and the Upanishads. Concerning the Upanishads and Vedas, he writes in The World as Will and Representation:
If the reader has also received the benefit of the Vedas, the access to which by means of the Upanishads is in my eyes the greatest privilege which this still young century (1818) may claim before all previous centuries, if then the reader, I say, has received his initiation in primeval Indian wisdom, and received it with an open heart, he will be prepared in the very best way for hearing what I have to tell him. It will not sound to him strange, as to many others, much less disagreeable; for I might, if it did not sound conceited, contend that every one of the detached statements which constitute the Upanishads, may be deduced as a necessary result from the fundamental thoughts which I have to enunciate, though those deductions themselves are by no means to be found there.
Thoughts on other philosophers
Giordano Bruno and Spinoza
Schopenhauer saw Bruno and Spinoza as philosophers not bound to their age or nation. "Both were fulfilled by the thought, that as manifold the appearances of the world may be, it is still one being, that appears in all of them. ... Consequently, there is no place for God as creator of the world in their philosophy, but God is the world itself."
Schopenhauer expressed regret that Spinoza stuck, for the presentation of his philosophy, with the concepts of scholasticism and Cartesian philosophy, and tried to use geometrical proofs that do not hold because of vague and overly broad definitions. Bruno on the other hand, who knew much about nature and ancient literature, presented his ideas with Italian vividness, and is amongst philosophers the only one who comes near Plato's poetic and dramatic power of exposition.
Schopenhauer noted that their philosophies do not provide any ethics, and it is therefore very remarkable that Spinoza called his main work Ethics. In fact, it could be considered complete from the standpoint of life-affirmation, if one completely ignores morality and self-denial. It is yet even more remarkable that Schopenhauer mentions Spinoza as an example of the denial of the will, if one uses the French biography by Jean Maximilien Lucas as the key to Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione.
Immanuel Kant
See also: Critique of the Kantian philosophy and Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemataThe importance of Kant for Schopenhauer, in philosophy as well as on a personal level, cannot be overstated. Kant's philosophy was the foundation of Schopenhauer's, and he had high praise for the Transcendental Aesthetic section of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Schopenhauer maintained that Kant stands in the same relation to philosophers such as Berkeley and Plato, as Copernicus to Hicetas, Philolaus, and Aristarchus: Kant succeeded in demonstrating what previous philosophers merely asserted.
Schopenhauer writes about Kant's influence on his work in the preface to the second edition of The World as Will and Representation:
I have already explained in the preface to the first edition, that my philosophy is founded on that of Kant, and therefore presupposes a thorough knowledge of it. I repeat this here. For Kant's teaching produces in the mind of everyone who has comprehended it a fundamental change which is so great that it may be regarded as an intellectual new-birth. It alone is able really to remove the inborn realism which proceeds from the original character of the intellect, which neither Berkeley nor Malebranche succeed in doing, for they remain too much in the universal, while Kant goes into the particular, and indeed in a way that is quite unexampled both before and after him, and which has quite a peculiar, and, we might say, immediate effect upon the mind in consequence of which it undergoes a complete undeception, and forthwith looks at all things in another light. Only in this way can any one become susceptible to the more positive expositions which I have to give. On the other hand, he who has not mastered the Kantian philosophy, whatever else he may have studied, is, as it were, in a state of innocence; that is to say, he remains in the grasp of that natural and childish realism in which we are all born, and which fits us for everything possible, with the single exception of philosophy.
In his study room, one bust was of Buddha, the other was of Kant. The bond which Schopenhauer felt with the philosopher of Königsberg is demonstrated in an unfinished poem he dedicated to Kant (included in volume 2 of the Parerga):
With my eyes I followed thee into the blue sky,
And there thy flight dissolved from view.
Alone I stayed in the crowd below,
Thy word and thy book my only solace.—
Through the strains of thy inspiring words
I sought to dispel the dreary solitude.
Strangers on all sides surround me.
The world is desolate and life interminable.
Schopenhauer dedicated one fifth of his main work, The World as Will and Representation, to a detailed criticism of the Kantian philosophy.
Schopenhauer praised Kant for his distinction between appearance and the thing-in-itself, whereas the general consensus in German idealism was that this was the weakest spot of Kant's theory, since, according to Kant, causality can find application on objects of experience only, and consequently, things-in-themselves cannot be the cause of appearances. The inadmissibility of this reasoning was also acknowledged by Schopenhauer. He insisted that this was a true conclusion, drawn from false premises.
Post-Kantian school
The leading figures of post-Kantian philosophy—Johann Gottlieb Fichte, F. W. J. Schelling and G. W. F. Hegel—were not respected by Schopenhauer. He argued that they were not philosophers at all, for they lacked "the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of inquiry." Rather, they were merely sophists who, excelling in the art of beguiling the public, pursued their own selfish interests (such as professional advancement within the university system). Diatribes against the alleged vacuity, dishonesty, pomposity, and self-interest of these contemporaries are to be found throughout Schopenhauer's published writings. The following passage is an example:
All this explains the painful impression with which we are seized when, after studying genuine thinkers, we come to the writings of Fichte and Schelling, or even to the presumptuously scribbled nonsense of Hegel, produced as it was with a boundless, though justified, confidence in German stupidity. With those genuine thinkers one always found an honest investigation of truth and just as honest an attempt to communicate their ideas to others. Therefore whoever reads Kant, Locke, Hume, Malebranche, Spinoza, and Descartes feels elevated and agreeably impressed. This is produced through communion with a noble mind which has and awakens ideas and which thinks and sets one thinking. The reverse of all this takes place when we read the above-mentioned three German sophists. An unbiased reader, opening one of their books and then asking himself whether this is the tone of a thinker wanting to instruct or that of a charlatan wanting to impress, cannot be five minutes in any doubt; here everything breathes so much of dishonesty.
Schopenhauer deemed Schelling the most talented of the three and wrote that he would recommend his "elucidatory paraphrase of the highly important doctrine of Kant" concerning the intelligible character, if he had been honest enough to admit he was parroting Kant, instead of hiding this relation in a cunning manner.
Schopenhauer reserved his most unqualified damning condemnation for Hegel, whom he considered less worthy than Fichte or Schelling. Whereas Fichte was merely a windbag (Windbeutel), Hegel was a "commonplace, inane, loathsome, repulsive, and ignorant charlatan." The philosophers Karl Popper and Mario Bunge agreed with this distinction. Hegel, Schopenhauer wrote in the preface to his Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, not only "performed no service to philosophy, but he has had a detrimental influence on philosophy, and thereby on German literature in general, really a downright stupefying, or we could even say a pestilential influence, which it is therefore the duty of everyone capable of thinking for himself and judging for himself to counteract in the most express terms at every opportunity."
Influence and legacy
Schopenhauer remained the most influential German philosopher until the First World War. His philosophy was a starting point for a new generation of philosophers including Julius Bahnsen, Paul Deussen, Lazar von Hellenbach, Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann, Ernst Otto Lindner, Philipp Mainländer, Friedrich Nietzsche, Olga Plümacher and Agnes Taubert. His legacy shaped the intellectual debate, and forced movements that were utterly opposed to him, neo-Kantianism and positivism, to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly. The French writer Maupassant commented that "to-day even those who execrate him seem to carry in their own souls particles of his thought". Other philosophers of the 19th century who cited his influence include Hans Vaihinger, Volkelt, Solovyov and Weininger.
Schopenhauer was well read by physicists, most notably Einstein, Schrödinger, Wolfgang Pauli, and Majorana. Einstein described Schopenhauer's thoughts as a "continual consolation" and called him a genius. In his Berlin study three figures hung on the wall: Faraday, Maxwell, Schopenhauer. Konrad Wachsmann recalled: "He often sat with one of the well-worn Schopenhauer volumes, and as he sat there, he seemed so pleased, as if he were engaged with a serene and cheerful work."
When Erwin Schrödinger discovered Schopenhauer ("the greatest savant of the West") he considered switching his study of physics to philosophy. He maintained the idealistic views during the rest of his life. Wolfgang Pauli accepted the main tenet of Schopenhauer's metaphysics, that the thing-in-itself is will.
But most of all Schopenhauer is famous for his influence on artists. Richard Wagner became one of the earliest and most famous adherents of the Schopenhauerian philosophy. The admiration was not mutual, and Schopenhauer proclaimed: "I remain faithful to Rossini and Mozart!" So he has been nicknamed "the artist's philosopher". See also Influence of Schopenhauer on Tristan und Isolde.
Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzig papiermark note (1923)Under the influence of Schopenhauer, Leo Tolstoy became convinced that the truth of all religions lies in self-renunciation. When he read Schopenhauer's philosophy, Tolstoy exclaimed "at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. ... It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection." He said that what he has written in War and Peace is also said by Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation.
Jorge Luis Borges remarked that the reason he had never attempted to write a systematic account of his world view, despite his penchant for philosophy and metaphysics in particular, was because Schopenhauer had already written it for him.
Other figures in literature who were strongly influenced by Schopenhauer were Thomas Mann, Thomas Hardy, Afanasy Fet, J.-K. Huysmans and George Santayana. In Herman Melville's final years, while he wrote Billy Budd, he read Schopenhauer's essays and marked them heavily. Scholar Brian Yothers notes that Melville "marked numerous misanthropic and even suicidal remarks, suggesting an attraction to the most extreme sorts of solitude, but he also made note of Schopenhauer's reflection on the moral ambiguities of genius." Schopenhauer's attraction to and discussions of both Eastern and Western religions in conjunction with each other made an impression on Melville in his final years.
Sergei Prokofiev, although initially reluctant to engage with works noted for their pessimism, became fascinated with Schopenhauer after reading Aphorisms on the Wisdom of Life in Parerga and Paralipomena. "With his truths Schopenhauer gave me a spiritual world and an awareness of happiness."
Friedrich Nietzsche owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading The World as Will and Representation and admitted that he was one of the few philosophers that he respected, dedicating to him his essay "Schopenhauer als Erzieher", one of his Untimely Meditations.
Early in his career, Ludwig Wittgenstein adopted Schopenhauer's epistemological idealism, and some traits of Schopenhauer's influence (particularly Schopenhauerian transcendentalism) can be observed in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Later on, Wittgenstein rejected epistemological transcendental idealism for Gottlob Frege's conceptual realism. In later years, Wittgenstein became highly dismissive of Schopenhauer, describing him as an ultimately shallow thinker. His friend Bertrand Russell had a low opinion on the philosopher, and even came to attack him in his History of Western Philosophy for hypocritically praising asceticism yet not acting upon it.
Opposite to Russell on the foundations of mathematics, the Dutch mathematician L. E. J. Brouwer incorporated Kant's and Schopenhauer's ideas in the philosophical school of intuitionism, where mathematics is considered as a purely mental activity instead of an analytic activity wherein objective properties of reality are revealed. Brouwer was also influenced by Schopenhauer's metaphysics, and wrote an essay on mysticism.
Schopenhauer's philosophy has made its way into a novel, The Schopenhauer Cure, by American existential psychiatrist and emeritus professor of psychiatry Irvin Yalom.
Schopenhauer's philosophy, and the discussions on philosophical pessimism it has engendered, has been the focus of contemporary thinkers such as David Benatar, Thomas Ligotti, and Eugene Thacker. Their work also served as an inspiration for the popular HBO TV series True Detective as well as Life Is Beautiful. In this regard, Schopenhauer is sometimes considered the founding father of today's antinatalism.
Advocates of idealism in contemporary analytic philosophy and neuroscience such as Bernardo Kastrup and Christof Koch owe their philosophical system, in part, to the metaphysics of Schopenhauer.
Selected bibliography
- On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde), 1813
- On Vision and Colors (Ueber das Sehn und die Farben), 1816 ISBN 978-0-85496-988-3
- Theory of Colors (Theoria colorum physiologica), 1830.
- The World as Will and Representation (alternatively translated as The World as Will and Idea; original German is Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung): vol. 1, 1818–1819, vol. 2, 1844
- Vol. 1 Dover edition 1966, ISBN 978-0-486-21761-1
- Vol. 2 Dover edition 1966, ISBN 978-0-486-21762-8
- Peter Smith Publisher hardcover set 1969, ISBN 978-0-8446-2885-1
- Everyman Paperback combined abridged edition (290 pp.) ISBN 978-0-460-87505-9
- The Longman Library of Primary Sources in Philosophy, vol. 1, 2008; vol. 2, 2010. Title translated as The World as Will and Presentation, rather than Representation.
- The Art of Being Right (Eristische Dialektik: Die Kunst, Recht zu Behalten), 1831
- On the Will in Nature (Ueber den Willen in der Natur), 1836 ISBN 978-0-85496-999-9
- On the Freedom of the Will (Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens), 1838 ISBN 978-0-631-14552-3
- On the Basis of Morality (Ueber die Grundlage der Moral), 1839
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (2010). The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics. Translated by Cartwright, David E.; Erdmann, Edward E. London: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199297221. Contains On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (September 1840) . Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik, behandelt in zwei akademischen Preisschriften (in German). Frankfurt am Main: Johann Christian Hermannsche Buchandlung. Retrieved 15 April 2024. Freely available from Internet Archive. Contains Preisschrift über die Freiheit des Willens and Preisschrift über die Grundlage der Moral.
- Parerga and Paralipomena (2 vols., 1851) – Reprint: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) (2 vols., 1974) (English translation by E. F. J. Payne)
- Printings:
- 1974 Hardcover, by ISBN
- Vols. 1 and 2, ISBN 978-0-19-519813-3,
- Vol. 1, ISBN
- Vol. 2, ISBN 978-0-19-824527-8,
- 1974–1980 Paperback, Vol. 1, ISBN 978-0-19-824634-3, Vol. 2, ISBN 978-0-19-824635-0,
- 2001 Paperback, Vol. 1, ISBN 978-0-19-924220-7, Vol. 2, ISBN 978-0-19-924221-4
- 1974 Hardcover, by ISBN
- Essays and Aphorisms, being excerpts from Volume 2 of Parerga und Paralipomena, selected and translated by R. J. Hollingdale, with Introduction by R J Hollingdale, Penguin Classics, 1970, Paperback 1973: ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4
- Printings:
- An Enquiry concerning Ghost-seeing, and what is connected therewith (Versuch über das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhangt), 1851
- Arthur Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Volume II, Berg Publishers Ltd., ISBN 978-0-85496-539-7
Online
- Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at Project Gutenberg
- The Art of Controversy (Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten) Archived 15 December 2002 at the Wayback Machine. (bilingual)
- Studies in Pessimism – audiobook from LibriVox
- The World as Will and Idea at the Internet Archive:
- "On the fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason" and "On the will in nature". Two essays:
- Internet Archive. Translated by Mrs. Karl Hillebrand (1903).
- Cornell University Library Historical Monographs Collection. Reprinted by Cornell University Library Digital Collections
- Facsimile edition of Schopenhauer's manuscripts in SchopenhauerSource
- Essays of Schopenhauer
See also
- Antinatalism
- Existential nihilism
- Eye of a needle
- God in Buddhism
- Massacre of the Innocents (Guido Reni)
- Misotheism
- Mortal coil
- Nihilism
- Post-Schopenhauerian pessimism
References
- ^ "Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)".
- Frederick C. Beiser reviews the commonly held position that Schopenhauer was a transcendental idealist and he rejects it: "Though it is deeply heretical from the standpoint of transcendental idealism, Schopenhauer's objective standpoint involves a form of transcendental realism, i.e. the assumption of the independent reality of the world of experience." (Beiser 2016, p. 40)
- ^ Voluntarism (philosophy) – Britannica.com
- Arthur Schopenhauer, Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Presentation, Volume 1, Routledge, 2016, p. 211: "the world mere presentation, object for a subject ..."
- Lennart Svensson, Borderline: A Traditionalist Outlook for Modern Man, Numen Books, 2015, p. 71: " said that 'the world is our conception'. A world without a perceiver would in that case be an impossibility. But we can—he said—gain knowledge about Essential Reality for looking into ourselves, by introspection. ... This is one of many examples of the anthropic principle. The world is there for the sake of man."
- ^ Stephen Puryear, "Schopenhauer on the Rights of Animals." European Journal of Philosophy 25/2 (2017):250–269.
- ^ The World as Will and Representation, vol. 3, Ch. 50.
- ^ Dale Jacquette, ed. (2007). Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts. Cambridge University Press. p. 162. ISBN 978-0-521-04406-6.
For Kant, the mathematical sublime, as seen for example in the starry heavens, suggests to imagination the infinite, which in turn leads by subtle turns of contemplation to the concept of God. Schopenhauer's atheism will have none of this, and he rightly observes that despite adopting Kant's distinction between the dynamical and mathematical sublime, his theory of the sublime, making reference to the struggles and sufferings of struggles and sufferings of Will, is unlike Kant's.
- Wells, John C. (2008), Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (3rd ed.), Longman, ISBN 978-1-4058-8118-0
- Arthur Schopenhauer (2004). Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Classics. p. 23. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4.
- Magee, Bryan (14 August 1997). "The World as Will". The Philosophy of Schopenhauer (1 ed.). Oxford University PressOxford. pp. 137–163. doi:10.1093/0198237227.003.0007. ISBN 978-0-19-823722-8.
- Vandenabeele, Bart (December 2007). "Schopenhauer on the Values of Aesthetic Experience". The Southern Journal of Philosophy. 45 (4): 565–582. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2007.tb00065.x.
- See the book-length study about oriental influences on the genesis of Schopenhauer's philosophy by Urs App: Schopenhauer's Compass. An Introduction to Schopenhauer's Philosophy and its Origins. Wil: UniversityMedia, 2014 (ISBN 978-3-906000-03-9)
- Hergenhahn, B. R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology (6th ed.). Cengage Learning. p. 216. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.
Although Schopenhauer was an atheist, he realized that his philosophy of denial had been part of several great religions; for example, Christianity, Hinduism, and Buddhism.
- Hergenhahn, B. R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology (6th ed.). Cengage Learning. p. 216. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.
- Arthur Schopenhauer (2004). Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Classics. pp. 22–36. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4.
...but there has been none who tried with so great a show of learning to demonstrate that the pessimistic outlook is justified, that life itself is really bad. It is to this end that Schopenhauer's metaphysic of will and idea exists.
- Studies in Pessimism – audiobook from LibriVox.
- David A. Leeming; Kathryn Madden; Stanton Marlan, eds. (2009). Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion, Volume 2. Springer. p. 824. ISBN 978-0-387-71801-9.
A more accurate statement might be that for a German—rather than a French or British writer of that time—Schopenhauer was an honest and open atheist.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur; Günter Zöller; Eric F. J. Payne (1999). Chronology. Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will. Cambridge University Press. p. xxx. ISBN 978-0-521-57766-3.
- ^ Cartwright, David E. (2010). Schopenhauer: A Biography. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82598-6.
- Bullock, A.B. (1920). The Supreme Human Tragedy: And Other Essays. C.W. Daniel. p. 53. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
- Safranski (1990), p. 12
- Wallace, W. (2003). Life of Arthur Schopenhauer. Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific. p. 59. ISBN 978-1-4102-0641-1.
- Durant, Will, The Story of Philosophy, Garden City Publishing Co., Inc., New York, p. 350
- "Schopenhauer: A Pessimist in the Optimistic Month of May". Germanic American Institute. Archived from the original on 11 June 2010. Retrieved 12 March 2010.
- "Full text of "Selected Essays Of Schopenhauer"". Retrieved 12 March 2010.
- ^ Fredriksson, Einar H. (2001), "The Dutch Publishing Scene: Elsevier and North-Holland", A Century of Science Publishing: A Collection of Essays, Amsterdam: IOS Press, pp. 61–76, ISBN 978-4-274-90424-0
- Willson, A. Leslie (1961). "Friedrich Majer: Romantic Indologist". Texas Studies in Literature and Language. 3 (1): 40–49. ISSN 0040-4691. JSTOR 40753707.
- ^ Clarke 1997, pp. 67–68.
- Clarke 1997, pp. 67–69.
- Clarke 1997, pp. 273.
- Clarke 1997, p. 69.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (22 April 2019). The world as will and idea. Classic Wisdom Reprint. ISBN 978-1-950330-23-2. OCLC 1229105608.
- Although the first volume was published by December 1818, it was printed with a title page erroneously giving the year as 1819 (see Braunschweig, Yael (2013), "Schopenhauer and Rossinian Universiality: On the Italianate in Schopenhauer's Metaphysics of Music", The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 297, n. 7, ISBN 978-0-521-76805-4).
- Safranski, Rüdiger (1991) Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Harvard University Press. p. 244
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. Author's preface to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of sufficient reason", p. 1 (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason on Wikisource.)
- Schopenhauer 2010, pp. xxviii, xxxix
- Dale Jacquette, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Routledge, 2015: "Biographical sketch".
- Schopenhauer: his life and philosophy by H. Zimmern – 1932 – G. Allen & Unwin.
- Lewis, Peter (15 February 2013). Arthur Schopenhauer, 2013. Reaktion Books. ISBN 978-1-78023-069-6.
- Letter to Goethe on 23 January 1816: "Ich weiß, daß durch mich die Wahrheit geredet hat, – in dieser kleinen Sache, wie dereinst in größern."
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1. Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy.
But the whole teaching of Kant contains really nothing more about this than the oft-repeated meaningless expression: 'The empirical element in perception is given from without.' ... always through the same meaningless metaphorical expression: 'The empirical perception is given us.'
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. § 21.
For sensation is and remains a process within the organism and is limited, as such, to the region within the skin; it cannot therefore contain any thing which lies beyond that region, or, in other words, anything that is outside us. ... It is only when the Understanding begins to apply its sole form, the causal law, that a powerful transformation takes place, by which subjective sensation becomes objective perception.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. § 21.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 4.
The contrary doctrine that the law of causality results from experience, which was the scepticism of Hume, is first refuted by this. For the independence of the knowledge of causality of all experience,—that is, its a priori character—can only be deduced from the dependence of all experience upon it; and this deduction can only be accomplished by proving, in the manner here indicated, and explained in the passages referred to above, that the knowledge of causality is included in perception in general, to which all experience belongs, and therefore in respect of experience is completely a priori, does not presuppose it, but is presupposed by it as a condition.
- ^ David E. Cartwright; Edward E. Erdmann. Introduction to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason". Cambridge University Press. pp. xvi–xvii.
He had also rehearsed for the first time his physiological arguments for the intellectual nature of intuition in his "On Vision and Colours", and he had discussed how his philosophy was corroborated by the sciences in "On Will in Nature". ... Like the German Idealists, Schopenhauer was convinced that Kant's great unknown, the thing in itself, is the weak point of the critical philosophy.
- Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Translated by Paul Carus. § 52c.
- See the quotation of Schopenhauer in Storm, Jason Josephson (2021). Metamodernism: The Future of Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 36–37. ISBN 978-0-226-78665-0.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and On the Will in Nature: Two Essays (revised edition)". gutenberg.org. Project Gutenberg.
- Young, Julian (2005). Schopenhauer (1 ed.). Routledge. pp. 4–25. doi:10.4324/9780203022108. ISBN 978-1-134-32883-3.
- Einstein, Albert (1935). The World as I See It, p. 14. Snowball Publishing. ISBN 1-4948-7706-6.
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §68
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §38
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §34
- Daniel Albright, Modernism and Music, 2004, p. 39, footnote 34
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (1970). Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Classics. p. 162. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4.
- ^ The World as Will and Representation, vol. 2, ch. 13
- "I wanted in this way to stress and demonstrate the great difference, indeed opposition, between knowledge of perception and abstract or reflected knowledge. Hitherto this difference has received too little attention, and its establishment is a fundamental feature of my philosophy ..." – The World as Will and Representation., vol. 2, ch. 7, p. 88 (trans. Payne)
- This comment by Schopenhauer was called "an acute observation" by Sir Thomas L. Heath. In his translation of The Elements, vol. 1, Book I, "Note on Common Notion 4", Heath made this judgment and also noted that Schopenhauer's remark "was a criticism in advance of Helmholtz' theory". Helmholtz had "maintained that geometry requires us to assume the actual existence of rigid bodies and their free mobility in space" and is therefore "dependent on mechanics".
- What Schopenhauer calls the eighth axiom is Euclid's Common Notion 4.
- "Motion of an object in space does not belong in a pure science, and consequently not in geometry. For the fact that something is movable cannot be cognized a priori, but can be cognized only through experience." (Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B 155, Note)
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 53.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 23.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 66.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Basis of Morality. § 19.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. Parerga and Paralipomena. Vol. 2, § 173.
- ^ The World as Will and Idea Vol. 1 § 63
- ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 68.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation: Supplements to the Fourth Book
- The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary. Schopenhauer: Oxford University Press. 1991. p. 1298. ISBN 978-0-19-861248-3.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur, The World as Will and Representation, Supplements to the Fourth Book
- Darwin, Charles. The Descent of Man. p. 586.
- "Nearly a century before Freud ... in Schopenhauer there is, for the first time, an explicit philosophy of the unconscious and of the body." Safranski p. 345.
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 47
- ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 254).
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 255).
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 12
- Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, § 62.
- "... he who attempts to punish in accordance with reason does not retaliate on account of the past wrong (for he could not undo something which has been done) but for the future, so that neither the wrongdoer himself, nor others who see him being punished, will do wrong again." Plato, "Protagoras", 324 B. Plato wrote that punishment should "be an example to other men not to offend". Plato, "Laws", Book IX, 863.
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Philosophy and Natural Science," §92, trans. Payne (p. 158-159).
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Ethics," §114, trans. Payne (p. 212).
- "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Parerga and Paralipomena, Volume I, trans. Payne (p. 126).
- "Arthur Schopenhauer: Ueber die Weiber". aboq.org.
- Rodgers (environmentalist) and Thompson in Philosophers Behaving Badly call Schopenhauer "a misogynist without rival in ... Western philosophy".
- Feminism and the Limits of Equality PA Cain – Ga. L. Rev., 1989
- Julian Young (23 June 2005). Schopenhauer. Psychology Press. p. 242. ISBN 978-0-415-33346-7.
- Long, Sandra Salser (Spring 1984). "Arthur Schopenhauer and Elisabet Ney". Southwest Review. 69 (2): 130–47. JSTOR 43469632.
- Safranski (1990), Chapter 24. p. 348.
- Schopenhauer 1969, p. 566
- Schopenhauer 1969, p. 567
- Payne, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II, p. 519
- On the Suffering of the World (1970), p. 35. Penguin Books – Great Ideas.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (1969). E. F. J. Payne (ed.). The World as Will and Representation. Vol. II. New York: Dover Publications. p. 527. ISBN 978-0-486-21762-8.
- Essays and Aphorisms, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Middlesex: London, 1970, p. 154
- Nietzsche and Modern German Thought by K. Ansell-Pearson – 1991 – Psychology Press.
- Christina Gerhardt, "Thinking With: Animals in Schopenhauer, Horkheimer and Adorno." Critical Theory and Animals. Ed. John Sanbonmatsu. Lanham: Rowland, 2011. 137–157.
- "Unlike the intellect, it does not depend on the perfection of the organism, but is essentially the same in all animals as what is known to us so intimately. Accordingly, the animal has all the emotions of humans, such as joy, grief, fear, anger, love, hatred, strong desire, envy, and so on. The great difference between human and animal rests solely on the intellect's degrees of perfection. On the Will in Nature, "Physiology and Pathology".
- Quoted in Schopenhauer, Arthur (1994). Philosophical Writings. London: Continuum. p. 233. ISBN 978-0-8264-0729-0.
- Quoted in Ryder, Richard (2000). Animal Revolution: Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism. Oxford: Berg Publishers. p. 57. ISBN 978-1-85973-330-1.
- "... in English all animals are of the neuter gender and so are represented by the pronoun 'it,' just as if they were inanimate things. The effect of this artifice is quite revolting, especially in the case of primates, such as dogs, monkeys, and the like...." On the Basis of Morality, § 19.
- "I recall having read of an Englishman who, while hunting in India, had shot a monkey; he could not forget the look which the dying animal gave him, and since then had never again fired at monkeys." On the Basis of Morality, § 19.
- " describes how he shot his first elephant, a female. The next morning he went to look for the dead animal; all the other elephants had fled from the neighborhood except a young one, who had spent the night with its dead mother. Forgetting all fear, he came toward the sportsmen with the clearest and liveliest evidence of inconsolable grief, and put his tiny trunk round them in order to appeal to them for help. Harris says he was then filled with real remorse for what he had done, and felt as if he had committed a murder." On the basis of morality, § 19.
- "His contempt for animals, who, as mere things for our use, are declared by him to be without rights, ... in conjunction with Pantheism, is at the same time absurd and abominable." The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Chapter 50.
- Spinoza, Ethics, Pt. IV, Prop. XXXVII, Note I.: "Still I do not deny that beasts feel: what I deny is, that we may not consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in a way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours ..." This is the exact opposite of Schopenhauer's doctrine. Also, Ethics, Appendix, 26, "whatsoever there be in nature beside man, a regard for our advantage does not call on us to preserve, but to preserve or destroy according to its various capacities, and to adapt to our use as best we may."
- "Such are the matters which I engage to prove in Prop. xviii of this Part, whereby it is plain that the law against the slaughtering of animals is founded rather on vain superstition and womanish pity than on sound reason. The rational quest of what is useful to us further teaches us the necessity of associating ourselves with our fellow-men, but not with beasts, or things, whose nature is different from our own; we have the same rights in respect to them as they have in respect to us. Nay, as everyone's right is defined by his virtue, or power, men have far greater rights over beasts than beasts have over men. Still I affirm that beasts feel. But I also affirm that we may consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in the way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours, and their emotions are naturally different from human emotions." Ethics, Part 4, Prop. 37, Note 1.
- Quoted in Madigan, Tim. "Schopenhauer's Compassionate Morality | Issue 52 | Philosophy Now". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 16 September 2023.
- ^ Clarke 1997, p. 68.
- Christopher McCoy, 3–4
- Schopenhauer, Arthur (1840). "Part IV". On the Basis of Morality. Translated by Bullock, Arthur Brodrick. London: Swan Sonnenschein (published 1908). pp. 269–271 – via Internet Archive.
- Dutt, Purohit Bhagavan. "Western Indologists: A Study in Motives". Archived from the original on 2 August 2010. Retrieved 9 May 2009.
- Christopher McCoy, 54–56
- Abelson, Peter (April 1993). Schopenhauer and Buddhism Archived 28 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Philosophy East and West Volume 43, Number 2, pp. 255–278. University of Hawaii Press. Retrieved on: 12 April 2008.
- Janaway, Christopher, Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy, pp. 28 ff.
- David Burton, "Buddhism, Knowledge and Liberation: A Philosophical Study." Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2004, p. 22.
- John J. Holder, Early Buddhist Discourses. Hackett Publishing Company, 2006, p. xx.
- "Schopenhauer is often said to be the first modern Western philosopher to attempt integration of his work with Eastern ways of thinking. That he was the first is true, but the claim that he was influenced by Indian thought needs qualification. There is a remarkable correspondence in broad terms between some central Schopenhauerian doctrines and Buddhism: notably in the views that empirical existence is suffering, that suffering originates in desires, and that salvation can be attained by the extinction of desires. These three 'truths of the Buddha' are mirrored closely in the essential structure of the doctrine of the will." (On this, see Dorothea W. Dauer, Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas. Note also the discussion by Bryan Magee, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, pp. 14–15, 316–321). Janaway, Christopher, Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy, p. 28 f.
- The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 17
- Artistic detachment in Japan and the West: psychic distance in comparative aesthetics by S. Odin – 2001 – University of Hawaii Press.
- Parerga & Paralipomena, vol. I, p. 106., trans. E.F.J. Payne.
- World as Will and Representation, vol. I, p. 273, trans. E.F.J. Payne.
- Christopher McCoy, 3
- App, Urs Arthur Schopenhauer and China. Sino-Platonic Papers Nr. 200 (April 2010) (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.; Schopenhauer's early notes on Buddhism reproduced in Appendix). This study provides an overview of the actual discovery of Buddhism by Schopenhauer.
- Hutton, Kenneth Compassion in Schopenhauer and Śāntideva. Journal of Buddhist Ethics Vol. 21 (2014)
- ^ Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 187–188. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
- Quote from Josephson-Storm (2017), p. 188.
- Josephson-Storm (2017), pp. 188–189.
- Anderson, Mark (2009). "Experimental Subversions of Modernity". Pure: Modernity, Philosophy, and the One. Sophia Perennis. ISBN 978-1-59731-094-9.
- Carnegy, Patrick. Wagner and the Art of the Theatre. p. 51.
- The World as Will and Representation Preface to the first edition, p. xiii
- ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. Note 5.
- ^ "Handschriftlicher, Nachlass, Vorlesungen und Abhandlungen". Gutenberg Spiegel.
- Abschnitt: Handschriftlicher Nachlaß. § 588.
Es kann daher eine vollkommen wahre Philosophie geben, die ganz von der Verneinung des Lebens abstrahirt, diese ganz ignorirt.
- "Vie de Spinoza – Wikisource". fr.wikisource.org.
- The World as Will and Representation. § 68.
We might to a certain extent regard the well-known French biography of Spinoza as a case in point, if we used as a key to it that noble introduction to his very insufficient essay, "De Emendatione Intellects", a passage which I can also recommend as the most effectual means I know of stilling the storm of the passions.
- Arthur Schopenhauer. World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, Preface of the Second Edition.
- Jerauld McGill, Vivian (1931). Schopenhauer. Pessimist and Pagan. p. 320.
- Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays, Volume 2, trans. Payne, p. 655–656.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1 Criticism of the Kantian philosophy. Translated by J. Kemp.
With the proof of the thing in itself it has happened to Kant precisely as with that of the a priori nature of the law of causality. Both doctrines are true, but their proof is false. They thus belong to the class of true conclusions from false premises.
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 21.
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 23.
- Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Freedom of the Will. p. 82.
- Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Sec. 13, trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 96.
- Popper, Karl (1946). "The Open Society and Her Enemies". Nature. 157 (3987): 52. Bibcode:1946Natur.157..387R. doi:10.1038/157387a0. S2CID 4074331.
- Bunge, Mario (2020). "Mario Bunge nos dijo: "Se puede ignorar la filosofía, pero no evitarla"". Filosofía&Co.
- The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, Preface to the First Edition, trans. Christopher Janaway (Cambridge, 2009), p. 15.
- ^ Beiser, Frederick C. (2008). Weltschmerz, Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 14–16. ISBN 978-0-19-876871-5.
Arthur Schopenhauer was the most famous and influential philosopher in Germany from 1860 until the First World War. ... Schopenhauer had a profound influence on two intellectual movements of the late 19th century that were utterly opposed to him: neo-Kantianism and positivism. He forced these movements to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly. ... Schopenhauer set the agenda for his age.
- Beside Schopenhauer's Corpse
- Howard, Don (1997). A Peek behind the Veil of Maya: Einstein, Schopenhauer, and the Historical Background of the Conception of Space as a Ground for the Individuation of Physical Systems. University of Pittsburgh Press.
Pauli greatly admired Schopenhauer. ... Pauli wrote sympathetically about extrasensory perception, noting approvingly that "even such a thoroughly critical philosopher as Schopenhauer not only regarded parapsychological effects going far beyond what is secured by scientific evidence as possible, but even considered them as a support for his philosophy".
- Bassani, Giuseppe-Franco (15 December 2006). Società Italiana di Fisica (ed.). Ettore Majorana: Scientific Papers. Springer. p. xl. ISBN 978-3-540-48091-4.
His interest in philosophy, which had always been great, increased and prompted him to reflect deeply on the works of various philosophers, in particular Schopenhauer.
- Isaacson, Walter (2007). Einstein: His Life and Universe. New York: Simon & Schuster. p. 367. ISBN 978-0-7432-6474-7.
- Howard (1997). p. 87
- Howard (1997). p. 92
- Halpern, Paul (2015). Einstein's Dice and Schrödinger's Cat: How Two Great Minds Battled Quantum Randomness to Create a Unified Theory of Physics. Basic Books. p. 189. ISBN 978-0-465-04065-0.
- Howard (1997). p. 132
- Raymond B. Marcin. "Schopenhauers Metaphysics and Contemporary Quantum Theory".
David Lindorff referred to Schopenhauer as Pauli's "favorite philosopher", and Pauli himself often expressed his agreement with the main tenet of Schopenhauer's philosophy. ... Suzanne Gieser cited a 1952 letter from Pauli to Carl Jung, in which Pauli indicated that, while he accepted Schopenhauer's main tenet that the thing-in-itself of all reality is will.
- See e.g. Magee (2000) 276–278.
- Nicholas Mathew, Benjamin Walton. The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism. p. 296.
- Tolstoy's letter to Afanasy Fet on 30 August 1869. "Do you know what this summer has meant for me? Constant raptures over Schopenhauer and a whole series of spiritual delights as I've never experienced before. I have brought all of his works and read him over and over, Kant too by the way. Assuredly no student has ever learned and discovered so much in one semester as I have during this summer. I do not know if I shall ever change my opinion, but at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. You say he is so-so, he has written a few things on philosophy? What is so-so? It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection. I have started to translate him. Won't you help me? Indeed, I cannot understand how his name can be unknown. The only explanation for this can only be the one he so often repeats, that is, that there is scarcely anyone but idiots in the world."
- Thompson, Caleb (2009). "Quietism from the Side of Happiness: Tolstoy, Schopenhauer, War and Peace". Common Knowledge. 15 (3): 395–411. doi:10.1215/0961754X-2009-020. S2CID 145535267.
- Magee, Bryan (1997). Confessions of a Philosopher. p. 413.
- Caleb Flamm, Matthew (2002). "Santayana and Schopenhauer". Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 38 (3): 413–431. JSTOR 40320900.
A thinker of whom it is well known that Santayana had an early, deep admiration, namely, Schopenhauer
- Yothers, Brian (2015). Sacred Uncertainty: Religious Difference and The Shape of Melville's Career. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-8101-3071-5.
- Morrison, Simon (2008). Sergey Prokofiev and His World. Princeton University Press. pp. 19, 20. ISBN 978-0-691-13895-4.
- Schopenhauer as Educator
- Glock, Hans-Johann (2017). A Companion to Wittgenstein. Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell. p. 60.
- Glock, Hans-Johann (2000). The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. p. 424.
- Culture & Value, p. 24, 1933–34
- Malcolm, Norman. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press, 1958, p. 6
- Russell, Bertrand (1946). History of Western Philosophy. George Allen and Unwin. p. 786.
- "Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'". The Wall Street Journal. 12 February 2014.
- M.Morioka What Is Antinatalism? and Other Essays, pp.8–12.
- Kastrup, Bernardo Decoding Schopenhauer’s Metaphysics: The Key to Understanding How It Solves the Hard Problem of Consciousness and the Paradoxes of Quantum Mechanics Iff Books (July 31, 2020)
- Koch, Christof Then I Am Myself the World: What Consciousness Is and How to Expand It Basic Books (May 7, 2024) pp. 49, 127, 132, 139, 209, 244.
- Eric Francis Jules Payne (17 February 1895 – 12 January 1983)
Sources
- Albright, Daniel (2004) Modernism and Music: An Anthology of Sources. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-01267-4
- Beiser, Frederick C., Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016).
- Cartwright, David E. (2010). Schopenhauer: A Biography. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82598-6.
- Clarke, John James (1997). Oriental Enlightenment: The Encounter Between Asian and Western Thought. Abingdon, Oxfordshire: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-13376-0.
- Hannan, Barbara, The Riddle of the World: A Reconsideration of Schopenhauer's Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
- Magee, Bryan, Confessions of a Philosopher, Random House, 1998, ISBN 978-0-375-50028-2. Chapters 20, 21.
- Safranski, Rüdiger (1990) Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Harvard University Press, ISBN 978-0-674-79275-3; orig. German Schopenhauer und Die wilden Jahre der Philosophie, Carl Hanser Verlag (1987)
- Thomas Mann editor, The Living Thoughts of Schopenhauer, Longmans Green & Co., 1939
Further reading
Biographies
- Copleston, Frederick, Arthur Schopenhauer, philosopher of pessimism (Burns, Oates & Washbourne, 1946)
- Damm, O. F., Arthur Schopenhauer – eine Biographie (Reclam, 1912)
- Fischer, Kuno, Arthur Schopenhauer (Heidelberg: Winter, 1893); revised as Schopenhauers Leben, Werke und Lehre (Heidelberg: Winter, 1898).
- Grisebach, Eduard, Schopenhauer – Geschichte seines Lebens (Berlin: Hofmann, 1876).
- Hamlyn, D. W., Schopenhauer, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (1980, 1985)
- Hasse, Heinrich, Schopenhauer. (Reinhardt, 1926)
- Hübscher, Arthur, Arthur Schopenhauer – Ein Lebensbild (Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1938).
- Mann, Thomas, Schopenhauer (Bermann-Fischer, 1938)
- Matthews, Jack, Schopenhauer's Will: Das Testament, Nine Point Publishing, 2015. ISBN 978-0-9858278-8-5. A recent creative biography by philosophical novelist Jack Matthews.
- Safranski, Rüdiger, Schopenhauer und die wilden Jahre der Philosophie – Eine Biographie, hard cover Carl Hanser Verlag, München 1987, ISBN 978-3-446-14490-3, pocket edition Fischer: ISBN 978-3-596-14299-6.
- Safranski, Rüdiger, Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy, trans. Ewald Osers (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989)
- Schneider, Walther, Schopenhauer – Eine Biographie (Vienna: Bermann-Fischer, 1937).
- Wallace, William, Life of Arthur Schopenhauer (London: Scott, 1890; repr., St. Clair Shores, Mich.: Scholarly Press, 1970)
- Zimmern, Helen, Arthur Schopenhauer: His Life and His Philosophy (London: Longmans, Green & Co, 1876)
Other books
- App, Urs. Arthur Schopenhauer and China. Sino-Platonic Papers Nr. 200 (April 2010) (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.). Contains extensive appendixes with transcriptions and English translations of Schopenhauer's early notes about Buddhism and Indian philosophy.
- App, Urs, Schopenhauers Kompass. Die Geburt einer Philosophie. UniversityMedia, Rorschach/ Kyoto 2011. ISBN 978-3-906000-02-2
- Atwell, John. Schopenhauer on the Character of the World, The Metaphysics of Will.
- Atwell, John, Schopenhauer, The Human Character.
- Edwards, Anthony. An Evolutionary Epistemological Critique of Schopenhauer's Metaphysics. 123 Books, 2011.
- Copleston, Frederick, Schopenhauer: Philosopher of Pessimism, 1946 (reprinted London: Search Press, 1975).
- Gardiner, Patrick, 1963. Schopenhauer. Penguin Books.
- Janaway, Christopher, 2002. Schopenhauer: A Very Short introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0192802590
- Janaway, Christopher, 2003. Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-825003-6
- Magee, Bryan, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Oxford University Press (1988, reprint 1997). ISBN 978-0-19-823722-8
- Marcin, Raymond B. In Search of Schopenhauer's Cat: Arthur Schopenhauer's Quantum-Mystical Theory of Justice. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2005. ISBN 978-0813214306
- Neymeyr, Barbara, 1996 (reprint 2011): Ästhetische Autonomie als Abnormität. Kritische Analysen zu Schopenhauers Ästhetik im Horizont seiner Willensmetaphysik. (= Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie. Band 42). Walter de Gruyter, Berlin / New York 1996, ISBN 3-11-015229-0. (reprint 2011, De Gruyter Berlin / Boston).
- Mannion, Gerard, "Schopenhauer, Religion and Morality – The Humble Path to Ethics", Ashgate Press, New Critical Thinking in Philosophy Series, 2003, 314pp.
- Trottier, Danick. L'influence de la philosophie schopenhauerienne dans la vie et l'oeuvre de Richard Wagner; et, Qu'est-ce qui séduit, obsède, magnétise le philosophe dans l'art des sons? deux études en esthétique musicale, Université du Québec à Montréal, Département de musique, 2000.
- Zimmern, Helen, Arthur Schopenhauer, his Life and Philosophy, London, Longman, and Co., 1876.
- Kastrup, Bernardo. Decoding Schopenhauer's Metaphysics – The key to understanding how it solves the hard problem of consciousness and the paradoxes of quantum mechanics. Winchester/Washington, iff Books, 2020.
- de Botton, Alain: The Consolations of Philosophy. Hamish Hamilton, London 2000. ISBN 0-14-027661-0 (Chapter: Consolation for a Broken Heart).
Fiction
- Poschenrieder, Christoph: Die Welt ist im Kopf. Diogenes, Zürich 2010, ISBN 978-3-257-06741-5 (The novel accompanies Schopenhauer on a trip to Italy).
- Yalom, Irvin D.: The Schopenhauer Cure. HarperCollins, New York City 2005, ISBN 978-0-06-093810-9 (The novel switches between the current events happening around a therapy group and the psychobiography of Arthur Schopenhauer).
- Kortmann, Christian: Happy Hour Schopenhauer. Roman einer Bibliotherapie. Turia + Kant, Wien + Berlin 2022, ISBN 978-3-98514-030-5 (In the novel, Schopenhauer lives in the 21st century and comments on current events in original quotations).
- Frederick, J. T.: In Arthur's Nature. Theorism Press 2020, ISBN 978-0-6451802-0-6 (Schopenhauer faces punishment for alleged assault and battery.)
Articles
- Abelson, Peter (1993). "Schopenhauer and Buddhism". Philosophy East and West. 43 (2): 255–78. doi:10.2307/1399616. JSTOR 1399616. Archived from the original on 28 June 2011. Retrieved 25 October 2007.
- Jiménez, Camilo, 2006, "Tagebuch eines Ehrgeizigen: Arthur Schopenhauers Studienjahre in Berlin," Avinus Magazin (in German).
- Luchte, James, 2009, "The Body of Sublime Knowledge: The Aesthetic Phenomenology of Arthur Schopenhauer," Heythrop Journal, Volume 50, Number 2, pp. 228–242.
- Mazard, Eisel, 2005, "Schopenhauer and the Empirical Critique of Idealism in the History of Ideas. Archived 29 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine" On Schopenhauer's (debated) place in the history of European philosophy and his relation to his predecessors.
- Sangharakshita, 2004, "Schopenhauer and aesthetic appreciation."
- Young, Christopher; Brook, Andrew (1994). "Schopenhauer and Freud". International Journal of Psychoanalysis. 75: 101–18. PMID 8005756.
- Oxenford's "Iconoclasm in German Philosophy," (See p. 388)
- Thacker, Eugene, 2020. "A Philosophy in Ruins, An Unquiet Void." Introduction to Arthur Schopenhauer, On the Suffering of the World. Repeater Books. ISBN 978-1-913462-03-1.
External links
- Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at Project Gutenberg
- Works by or about Arthur Schopenhauer at the Internet Archive
- Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- Wicks, Robert (Spring 2019). "Arthur Schopenhauer". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University: Center for the Study of Language and Information.
- "Arthur Schopenhauer" an article by Mary Troxell in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011
- "Arthur Schopenhauer: Logic and Dialectic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Kant's philosophy as rectified by Schopenhauer
- Timeline of German Philosophers
- A Quick Introduction to Schopenhauer
- Ross, Kelley L., 1998, "Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860)". Two short essays, on Schopenhauer's life and work, and on his dim view of academia.
Arthur Schopenhauer | ||
---|---|---|
Books | ||
Philosophy | ||
Family |
| |
Works about | ||
Related |
Philosophical pessimism | |
---|---|
Philosophers | |
Concepts | |
Related articles |
Continental philosophy | |
---|---|
Philosophers |
|
Theories |
|
Concepts |
|
- Arthur Schopenhauer
- 1788 births
- 1860 deaths
- 19th-century atheists
- 19th-century German essayists
- 19th-century German male writers
- 19th-century German philosophers
- 19th-century German writers
- Abolitionists
- Academic staff of the Humboldt University of Berlin
- Animal rights scholars
- Anti-natalists
- Aphorists
- Atheist philosophers
- Burials at Frankfurt Main Cemetery
- Critical theorists
- Critics of Judaism
- Critics of religions
- German epistemologists
- German writers on atheism
- German atheists
- German critics of Christianity
- German ethicists
- German eugenicists
- German flautists
- German logicians
- German male essayists
- German male non-fiction writers
- German monarchists
- German people of Dutch descent
- German philologists
- German scholars of Buddhism
- Idealists
- Kantian philosophers
- Logicians
- Metaphilosophers
- Ontologists
- Phenomenologists
- German philosophers of art
- German philosophers of culture
- German philosophers of education
- German philosophers of history
- German philosophers of language
- Philosophers of literature
- Philosophers of logic
- Philosophers of love
- German philosophers of mind
- Philosophers of pessimism
- Philosophers of psychology
- German philosophers of religion
- German philosophers of science
- Philosophy writers
- German political philosophers
- Simple living advocates
- Theorists on Western civilization
- University of Göttingen alumni
- Writers from Gdańsk