Misplaced Pages

Liberal democracy: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 19:29, 27 March 2006 view sourceUltramarine (talk | contribs)33,507 edits Liberal democracies around the world: Irrelevant to modern lists that are highly correlated, see http://www.isanet.org/noarchive/wayman.html← Previous edit Latest revision as of 08:39, 22 November 2024 view source Maggiorana (talk | contribs)314 edits Populism 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{clearright}} {{pp|small=yes}}
{{Short description|Form of government}}
{{unreferenced}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=March 2018}}
{{combi}}
{{Use British English|date=December 2016}}
|{{elections|
{{Democracy}}
image=|
caption=}}
|{{liberalism}}
|}
'''Liberal democracy''' is a form of ] where the ability of elected representatives to exercise ] ] is subject to the ] and moderated by a ] which emphasizes the protection of the ]s and ] of individuals and ] (also called '''constitutional democracy''' and '''constitutional liberalism'''), and which places constraints on the extent to which the ] can be exercised.


]'', the parliament of the ] (then part of ]), had universal suffrage in 1906. ] for being the first with ].]]
These rights and freedoms include the rights to due process, private ownership of property, privacy, and equality before the law, and freedoms of ], ] and ]. In liberal democracies these rights (also known as ‘’liberal rights’’) may sometimes be constitutionally guaranteed, or are otherwise created by ] or ], which may in turn empower various civil institutions to administer or enforce these rights.


'''Liberal democracy''', '''western-style democracy''',<ref name="He 2022 pp. 111–139">{{cite journal | last=He | first=Jiacheng | title=The Patterns of Democracy in Context of Historical Political Science | journal=Chinese Political Science Review | publisher=Springer Science and Business Media LLC | volume=7 | issue=1 | date=Jan 8, 2022 | issn=2365-4244 | doi=10.1007/s41111-021-00201-5 | pages=111–139| s2cid=256470545 | doi-access=free }}</ref> or '''substantive democracy'''<ref name="substantive">{{Cite journal |last1=Jacobs |first1=Lawrence R. |last2=Shapiro |first2=Robert Y. |date=1994 |title=Studying Substantive Democracy |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/420450 |journal=PS: Political Science and Politics |volume=27 |issue=1 |pages=9–17 |doi=10.2307/420450 |jstor=420450 |s2cid=153637162 |issn=1049-0965}}</ref> is a ] that combines the organization of a ] with ideas of ] ].
Liberal democracies also tend to be characterized by ] and ]; widely differing social and political views, even those viewed as extreme or fringe, are permitted to co-exist and compete for political power on a democratic basis. Liberal democracies periodically hold ]s where groups with differing political views have the opportunity to achieve political power.


Common elements within a liberal democracy are: ] between or among ] ], a ] into different ], the ] in everyday life as part of an ], a ] with ], ], and the equal protection of ], ], ], and ]s for all citizens. Substantive democracy refers to ] and ]s, which can include ],<ref name="substantive"/> the ] for subgroups in society.<ref>{{cite report |last1=Cusack |first1=Simone |last2=Ball |first2=Rachel |date=July 2009 |title=Eliminating Discrimination and Ensuring Substantive Equality |publisher=Public Interest Law Clearing House and Human Rights Law Resource Centre Ltd |url=https://www.parliament.vic.gov.au/archive/sarc/EOA_exempt_except/submissions/676%20-%20PILCH%20%26%20HRLRC%20-%2010.07.09.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220606103935/https://www.parliament.vic.gov.au/archive/sarc/EOA_exempt_except/submissions/676%20-%20PILCH%20%26%20HRLRC%20-%2010.07.09.pdf |archive-date=6 June 2022 |access-date=12 June 2024 }}</ref><ref name=":2">"What is substantive equality?". Equal Opportunity Commission, Government of Western Australia. November 2014. Retrieved 28 October 2018</ref> Liberal democracy emphasizes the separation of powers, an ], and a system of checks and balances between branches of government. ]s with at least two persistent, ] are characteristic of liberal democracies.
==Preconditions and structure==
Although they are not a system of government as such, it is now common to include aspects of society among the defining criteria of a liberal democracy. The presence of a ], and a broad and flourishing ] are often seen as pre-conditions for liberal democracy.


Governmental authority is legitimately exercised only in accordance with written, publicly disclosed ] adopted and enforced in accordance with established procedure. To define the system in practice, liberal democracies often draw upon a ], either codified or ], to delineate the powers of government and enshrine the ]. A liberal democracy may take various and mixed constitutional forms: it may be a ] or a ]. It may have a ], ], or ]. Liberal democracies are contrasted with ] and ]s. Some liberal democracies, especially those with large populations, use ] (also known as vertical separation of powers) in order to prevent abuse and increase public input by dividing governing powers between municipal, provincial and national governments. The characteristics of liberal democracies are correlated with increased political stability,<ref name="Carugati2020" /> lower ],<ref name="Lederman2001" /> better management of resources,<ref name="carnegiecouncil1" /> and better health indicators such as ] and ].<ref name="Franco2004" />
Western support for democratisation is almost always associated with support for a ]. In western countries, they do seem inseparable, but that is a geographically and historically limited view. ], which is not a liberal democracy, contains elements of a market economy. Many free-market proponents believe that the emergence of ] pre-dates the emergence of democracy, which leads some theorists to conclude that there is a historical sequence at work, and that market economics is not only a precondition, but will ultimately ''ensure'' the transition to democracy, in countries such as China. However, many ] and ] say that ] and true democracy are at best unrelated and at worst contradictory.
Liberal democracy traces its origins—and its name—to the ]. The conventional views supporting ] and ] were challenged at first by a relatively small group of Enlightenment ]s, who believed that human affairs should be guided by ] and principles of liberty and equality. They argued that ], that governments exist to serve the people—not vice versa—and that laws should apply to those who govern as well as to the governed (a concept known as ]), formulated in Europe as '']''. Some of these ideas began to be expressed in England in the 17th century.<ref name="Kopstein2014" /> By the late 18th century, leading philosophers such as ] had published works that spread around the European continent and beyond. These ideas and beliefs influenced the ] and the ]. After a period of expansion in the second half of the 20th century, liberal democracy became a prevalent political system in the world.<ref name=":0">Anna Lührmann, Seraphine F. Maerz, Sandra Grahn, Nazifa Alizada, Lisa Gastaldi, Sebastian Hellmeier, Garry Hindle and Staffan I. Lindberg. 2020. Autocratization Surges – Resistance Grows. Democracy Report 2020. Varieties of Democracy Institute (V-Dem). {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211218155149/https://www.v-dem.net/media/filer_public/de/39/de39af54-0bc5-4421-89ae-fb20dcc53dba/democracy_report.pdf|date=18 December 2021}}</ref>


== Origins ==
The most ] of the many criteria now used to define liberal democracy, or simply "democracy", is the requirement for political ], which is usually defined as the presence of multiple and distinct ]. The liberal-democratic political process should be ''competitive'', and analogies with economic markets are often used in this context. Therefore liberal democracy is defined by free and fair ].
{{see also|History of liberalism|History of democracy}}
] was the first to develop a liberal philosophy as he coherently described the elementary principles of the liberal movement, such as the ] and the ].]]
] (1647), a manifesto for political change proposed by the ] during the ], called for ], frequent convening of ] and equality under the law]]
Liberal democracy traces its origins—and its name—to 18th-century Europe, during the ]. At the time, the vast majority of European states were ], with political power held either by the ] or the ]. The possibility of democracy had not been a seriously considered political theory since ] and the widely held belief was that democracies would be inherently unstable and chaotic in their policies due to the changing whims of the people. It was further believed that democracy was contrary to ], as human beings were seen to be inherently evil, violent and in need of a strong leader to restrain their destructive impulses. Many European monarchs held that their power had been ] and that questioning their right to rule was tantamount to ].


These conventional views were challenged at first by a relatively small group of Enlightenment ]s, who believed that human affairs should be guided by ] and principles of liberty and equality. They argued that ] and therefore political authority cannot be justified on the basis of noble blood, a supposed privileged connection to God or any other characteristic that is alleged to make one person superior to others. They further argued that governments exist to serve the people—not vice versa—and that laws should apply to those who govern as well as to the governed (a concept known as ]).
The liberal-democratic ] defines the democratic character of the state. In the American political tradition, the purpose of a constitution is often seen as a limit on the authority of the government, and American ideas of liberal democracy are influenced by this. They emphasise the ], an independent judiciary, and a system of ] between branches of government. European constitutional liberalism is more likely to emphasise the ''Rechtsstaat'', usually translated as ], although it implies a specific form of ] or ].


Some of these ideas began to be expressed in England in the 17th century.<ref name="Kopstein2014">{{cite book|editor1-last=Kopstein|editor1-first=Jeffrey|editor2-last=Lichbach|editor2-first=Mark|editor3-last=Hanson|editor3-first=Stephen E.|title=Comparative Politics: Interests, Identities, and Institutions in a Changing Global Order|date=2014|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1139991384|pages=37–39|edition=4, revised|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L2jwAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA38|quote=Britain pioneered the system of liberal democracy that has now spread in one form or another to most of the world's countries|access-date=6 June 2020|archive-date=30 June 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200630231313/https://books.google.com/books?id=L2jwAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA38|url-status=live}}</ref> There was ],<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.bl.uk/magna-carta/videos/from-legal-document-to-public-myth-magna-carta-in-the-17th-century|title=From legal document to public myth: Magna Carta in the 17th century|website=The British Library|access-date=2017-10-16|postscript=none|archive-date=18 October 2017|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171018101349/https://www.bl.uk/magna-carta/videos/from-legal-document-to-public-myth-magna-carta-in-the-17th-century|url-status=live}}; {{Cite web|url=https://www.sal.org.uk/events/2015/06/magna-carta-magna-carta-in-the-17th-century/|title=Magna Carta: Magna Carta in the 17th Century|website=The Society of Antiquaries of London|access-date=2017-10-16|archive-date=25 September 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180925053248/https://www.bl.uk/magna-carta/videos/from-legal-document-to-public-myth-magna-carta-in-the-17th-century|url-status=live}}</ref> and passage of the ] in 1628 and ] in 1679 established certain liberties for subjects. The idea of a political party took form with groups debating rights to political representation during the ] of 1647. After the ]s (1642–1651) and the ] of 1688, the ] was enacted in 1689, which codified certain rights and liberties. The Bill set out the requirement for regular elections, rules for freedom of speech in Parliament and limited the power of the monarch, ensuring that, unlike almost all of Europe at the time, ] would not prevail.<ref name=refNARoP>{{cite web|title=Britain's unwritten constitution|url=http://www.bl.uk/magna-carta/articles/britains-unwritten-constitution|publisher=British Library|access-date=27 November 2015|quote=The key landmark is the Bill of Rights (1689), which established the supremacy of Parliament over the Crown.... The Bill of Rights (1689) then settled the primacy of Parliament over the monarch's prerogatives, providing for the regular meeting of Parliament, free elections to the Commons, free speech in parliamentary debates, and some basic human rights, most famously freedom from 'cruel or unusual punishment'.|archive-date=8 December 2015|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151208232341/http://www.bl.uk/magna-carta/articles/britains-unwritten-constitution|url-status=live}}</ref><ref name=refIIP>{{cite web|title=Constitutionalism: America & Beyond|url=http://www.ait.org.tw/infousa/zhtw/DOCS/Demopaper/dmpaper2.html|publisher=Bureau of International Information Programs (IIP), U.S. Department of State|access-date=30 October 2014|quote=The earliest, and perhaps greatest, victory for liberalism was achieved in England. The rising commercial class that had supported the Tudor monarchy in the 16th century led the revolutionary battle in the 17th, and succeeded in establishing the supremacy of Parliament and, eventually, of the House of Commons. What emerged as the distinctive feature of modern constitutionalism was not the insistence on the idea that the king is subject to law (although this concept is an essential attribute of all constitutionalism). This notion was already well established in the Middle Ages. What was distinctive was the establishment of effective means of political control whereby the rule of law might be enforced. Modern constitutionalism was born with the political requirement that representative government depended upon the consent of citizen subjects.... However, as can be seen through provisions in the 1689 Bill of Rights, the English Revolution was fought not just to protect the rights of property (in the narrow sense) but to establish those liberties which liberals believed essential to human dignity and moral worth. The "rights of man" enumerated in the English Bill of Rights gradually were proclaimed beyond the boundaries of England, notably in the American Declaration of Independence of 1776 and in the French Declaration of the Rights of Man in 1789.|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141024130317/http://www.ait.org.tw/infousa/zhtw/DOCS/Demopaper/dmpaper2.html|archive-date=24 October 2014}}</ref> This led to significant social change in Britain in terms of the position of individuals in society and the growing power of ] in relation to the ].<ref>{{cite web|title=Citizenship 1625–1789|url=http://www.nationalarchives.gov.uk/pathways/citizenship/rise_parliament/citizenship2.htm|publisher=The National Archives|access-date=22 January 2016|postscript=none|archive-date=11 January 2016|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160111215902/http://www.nationalarchives.gov.uk/pathways/citizenship/rise_parliament/citizenship2.htm|url-status=live}}; {{cite web|title=Rise of Parliament|url=http://www.nationalarchives.gov.uk/pathways/citizenship/rise_parliament/making_history_rise.htm|publisher=The National Archives|access-date=22 January 2016|archive-date=17 August 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180817084312/http://www.nationalarchives.gov.uk/pathways/citizenship/rise_parliament/making_history_rise.htm|url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|last1=Heater|first1=Derek|title=Citizenship in Britain: A History|date=2006|publisher=Edinburgh University Press |isbn=978-0748626724|pages=30–42|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=js-qBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA30|chapter=Emergence of Radicalism}}</ref>
]. ] was the first independent state with complete ] in ]]]Liberal democracy is also defined by ], granting all citizens the right to vote regardless of race, gender or property ownership. However, the universality is relative: many countries regarded as democratic have practised various forms of ], or demand further qualifications (except for being a citizen), like a registration procedure to be allowed to vote. Voting rights are limited to those who are above a certain age, typically 18. In any case, decisions taken through elections are taken not by all of the citizens, but rather by those who choose to participate by voting.
:See also ].


By the late 18th century, leading philosophers of the day had published works that spread around the European continent and beyond. One of the most influential of these philosophers was English empiricist ], who refuted ] in his '']''. According to Locke, individuals entered into a ] with a ], surrendering some of their liberties in exchange for the protection of their ]. Locke advanced that governments were only legitimate if they maintained the ] and that citizens had the ] against their government if that government acted against their interests. These ideas and beliefs influenced the ] and the ], which gave birth to the philosophy of ] and instituted forms of government that attempted to put the principles of the Enlightenment philosophers into practice.
==Rights and freedoms==
The most often quoted criteria for liberal democracy take the form of specific rights and freedoms. They were originally considered essential for the functioning of a liberal democracy, but they have acquired such prominence in its definition, that many people now think they are democracy. Since no state wants to admit it is "unfree", and since its enemies may be depicted as 'tyrannies' by its propagandists, they are also usually contested.


When the first prototypical liberal democracies were founded, the liberals themselves were viewed as an extreme and rather dangerous fringe group that threatened international peace and stability. The conservative ] who opposed liberalism and democracy saw themselves as defenders of traditional values and the natural order of things and their criticism of democracy seemed vindicated when ] took control of the young ], reorganized it into the ] and proceeded to conquer most of Europe. Napoleon was eventually defeated and the ] was formed in Europe to prevent any further spread of liberalism or democracy. However, liberal democratic ideals soon became widespread among the general population and over the 19th century traditional monarchy was forced on a continuous defensive and withdrawal. The ]s of the ] became laboratories for liberal democracy from the mid 19th century onward. In Canada, responsible government began in the 1840s and in Australia and New Zealand, parliamentary government elected by ] and ] was established from the 1850s and ] achieved from the 1890s.<ref>Geoffrey Blainey (2004), ''A Very Short History of the World'', Penguin Books, {{ISBN|978-0143005599}}</ref>
In practice, democracies do have specific limits on specific freedoms. In democratic theory, the common justification for these limits is that they are necessary to guarantee the existence of democracy, or the existence of the freedoms themselves. According to this argument, allowing free speech for the opponents of free speech logically undermines free speech. In Europe, this has become a political issue with the rise of ] political argument, which often does explicitly reject such liberal freedoms. Opinion is divided on how far democracy can extend, to include the enemies of democracy in the democratic process.


] (1865–1952), the first ], defined ]'s anchoring as a country defending liberal democracy.<ref>{{Cite web |url=https://trepo.tuni.fi/handle/10024/80491 |title=War or Peace for Finland? Neoclassical Realist Case Study of Finnish Foreign Policy in the Context of the Anti-Bolshevik Intervention in Russia 1918–1920 |access-date=22 July 2020 |archive-date=23 July 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200723024654/https://trepo.tuni.fi/handle/10024/80491 |url-status=live }}</ref> Ståhlberg at his office in 1919.]]
*], including speech, assembly and protest. There are various legal limitations like ] and ], more general restrictions may include restrictions on anti-democratic speech, on attempts to undermine ], on the promotion or justification of ], and in some cases on "anti-western" ideas. In the United States more than in Europe, during the ], such restrictions generally applied to ], now they are mainly applied to Islamists.
Reforms and revolutions helped move most European countries towards liberal democracy. Liberalism ceased being a fringe opinion and joined the political mainstream. At the same time, a number of non-liberal ideologies developed that took the concept of liberal democracy and made it their own. The political spectrum changed; traditional monarchy became more and more a fringe view and liberal democracy became more and more mainstream. By the end of the 19th century, liberal democracy was no longer only a liberal idea, but an idea supported by many different ideologies. After ] and especially after ], liberal democracy achieved a dominant position among theories of government and is now endorsed by the vast majority of the political spectrum.{{Citation needed|date=July 2010}}
*]
*] and access to alternative information sources is considered a characteristic of liberal democracy. For certain groups, however, it may be limited: ] media now face restrictions in many democracies, including ] of satellite broadcasting in France, and proposed bans on Islamist websites in several countries.
*] and ] is also restricted in democracies, for groups considered a threat to state or society. Most democracies have procedures to ban organisations, on suspicion of ], for instance, and usually without a prior judicial procedure. The ] has an official list of banned organisations, overriding the freedom of association in the ] and the national constitutions.
*]
*Equality before the law and ] under the ] is considered a characteristic of liberal democracy. However, if relatively small numbers of people, seen as mortal enemies by the majority of the population, are excluded from legal protections, a country may still be seen as a liberal democracy: it is not qualitatively different from repressive autocracy, but ''quantitatively'' different.


Although liberal democracy was originally put forward by Enlightenment liberals, the relationship between democracy and liberalism has been controversial since the beginning and was problematized in the 20th century.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy|last=Schmitt|first=Carl|publisher=MIT Press|year=1985|isbn= 978-0262192408|location=Cambridge|pages=2, 8 (chapter 1)}}</ref> In his book ''Freedom and Equality in a Liberal Democratic State'', Jasper Doomen posited that freedom and equality are necessary for a liberal democracy.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Freedom and Equality in a Liberal Democratic State|last=Doomen|first=Jasper|publisher=Bruylant|year=2014|isbn= 978-2802746232|location=Brussels|pages=88, 101}}</ref> In his book '']'', ] says that since the ], liberal democracy has repeatedly proven to be a fundamentally better system (ethically, politically, economically) than any of the alternatives, and that democracy will become more and more prevalent in the long term, although it may suffer temporary setbacks.<ref name="endofhistory">{{Cite journal|last=Fukuyama|first=Francis|date=1989|title=The End of History?|journal=The National Interest|issue=16|pages=3–18|issn=0884-9382|jstor=24027184}}</ref><ref>{{cite news|last1=Glaser|first1=Eliane|date=21 March 2014|title=Bring Back Ideology: Fukuyama's 'End of History' 25 years On|work=The Guardian|url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/21/bring-back-ideology-fukuyama-end-history-25-years-on|access-date=18 March 2019|archive-date=17 April 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190417071820/https://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/21/bring-back-ideology-fukuyama-end-history-25-years-on|url-status=live}}</ref> The research institute ] today simply defines liberal democracy as an electoral democracy also protecting ].
==Critique and defense==
Some would argue that 'liberal democracy' is not ] or liberal at all. They would argue that 'liberal democracy' does not respect ] (except when citizens are asked to vote for their representatives), and also that its "liberty" is restricted by the constitution or ] (in the UK) decided by previous generations. They would argue that, by prohibiting citizens the right to cast votes on all issues (especially for serious subjects like going to war, constitutional amendments or constitution abolishment, etc.), this turns 'liberal democracy' into the precursor of ].


== Rights and freedoms ==
Anti-capitalists, which include ], ] and ], argue that liberal democracy is an integral part of the ] and is ]-based and not fully democratic or ]. It is ] democracy where only the most financially powerful people rule. Because of this it is seen as fundamentally un-egalitarian, existing or operating in a way that facilitates economic exploitation.
{{main|Political freedom|Democracy and human rights}}
Others would say that only a liberal democracy can guarantee the individual liberties of its citizens and prevent the development into a dictatorship. Unmoderated majority rule could, in this view, lead to an oppression of minorities. One important aspect of representative democracy is, however, the fact that the real power is actually held by a relatively small representative body. The rule is by no means held by the majority, but rather a small group elected on a popular basis.


Political freedom is a central ] in ] and political thought and one of the most important features of ] societies.<ref name="Arendt1993">Hannah Arendt, "What is Freedom?", ''Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought'', (New York: Penguin, 1993).</ref> Political freedom was described as freedom from oppression<ref>Iris Marion Young, "Five Faces of Oppression", ''Justice and the Politics of Difference'' (Princeton University press, 1990), 39–65.</ref> or coercion,<ref>Michael Sandel, ''Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?'' (Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2010).</ref> the absence of disabling conditions for an individual and the fulfillment of enabling conditions,<ref>Amartya Sen, ''Development as Freedom'' (Anchor Books, 2000).</ref> or the absence of life conditions of compulsion, e.g. economic compulsion, in a society.<ref>], "Alienated Labour" in ''Early Writings''.</ref> Although political freedom is often interpreted ] as the freedom from unreasonable external constraints on action,<ref>], ''Liberty'' (Oxford 2004).</ref> it can also refer to the ] exercise of rights, ] and possibilities for action and the exercise of social or group rights.<ref>], "What's Wrong With Negative Liberty?", ''Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers'' (Cambridge, 1985), 211–229.</ref> The concept can also include freedom from internal constraints on political action or speech (e.g. social ], consistency, or inauthentic behaviour).<ref>Ralph Waldo Emerson, ""; Nikolas Kompridis, "Struggling Over the Meaning of Recognition: A Matter of Identity, Justice or Freedom?" in ''European Journal of Political Theory'' July 2007 vol. 6 no. 3 pp. 277–289.</ref> The concept of political freedom is closely connected with the concepts of ] and ], which in democratic societies are usually afforded legal protection from the ].
No substantial famine has occurred in any independent country with a democratic government and a relatively free press<ref>], </ref>. There is also strong evidence that war between liberal democracies is vanishingly rare and that lesser conflicts between them are less common, including civil wars within a liberal democracy, <ref>The disputed ]; see, for example Håvard Hegre ''et al.'': "": American Political Science Review (March) 95: 1 at]</ref>. There is also research associating democracy, parliamentary systems, political stability, and freedom of the press with lower ]<ref>Lederman, Daniel, Loayza, Norman and Reis Soares, Rodrigo: "Accountability and Corruption: Political Institutions Matter" (November 2001). World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 2708. at </ref>.


Laws in liberal democracies may limit certain freedoms. The common justification for these limits is that they are necessary to guarantee the existence of democracy, or the existence of the freedoms themselves. For example, democratic governments may impose restrictions on free speech, with examples including ] and ]. Some ] behavior may be prohibited. For example, ] may not discriminate on the basis of "race, color, religion, or national origin." There are various legal limitations such as ] and laws against ]. There may be limits on anti-democratic speech, on attempts to undermine ] and on the promotion or justification of ]. In the United States more than in Europe, during the ] such restrictions applied to ]. Now they are more commonly applied to organizations perceived as promoting terrorism or the incitement of group hatred. Examples include ], the shutting down of ] satellite broadcasts and some laws against ]. Critics{{who|date=February 2022}} claim that these limitations may go too far and that there may be no due and fair judicial process. Opinion is divided on how far democracy can extend to include the enemies of democracy in the democratic process.{{citation needed|date=February 2022}} If relatively small numbers of people are excluded from such freedoms for these reasons, a country may still be seen as a liberal democracy. Some argue that this is only quantitatively (not qualitatively) different from autocracies that persecute opponents, since only a small number of people are affected and the restrictions are less severe, but others emphasize that democracies are different. At least in theory, opponents of democracy are also allowed due process under the rule of law.
==Relation to indirect democracy==
Liberal democracies are representative democracies. Some of these democracies have additional systems of ] to give the ] a possibility to overrule decisions of the elected ] or even to make decisions by ] without giving the legislature a say in that decision. ] and ] are some of the liberal democracies with a representative system combined with referenda and plebiscites; so are several of the component states of the ]. Other countries have referenda to a lesser degree in their political system. Adding referenda to a political system could help prevent the evolution of a liberal democracy into an oligarchy.


Since it is possible to disagree over which rights are considered fundamental, different countries may treat particular rights in different ways. For example:
==Liberal democracies around the world==
* The constitutions of Canada, India, Israel, Mexico and the United States guarantee freedom from ], a right not provided in some other legal systems.
* Legal systems that use politically elected court jurors, such as ], view a (partly) politicized court system as a main component of accountable government. Other democracies employ ] with the intent of shielding against the influence of politicians over trials.


Liberal democracies usually have ], granting all ] citizens the right to vote regardless of ], ], property ownership, race, age, sexuality, ], income, social status, or religion. However, historically some countries regarded as liberal democracies have had a more ]. Even today, some countries, considered to be liberal democracies, do not have truly universal suffrage. In some countries, members of political organizations with connections to historical totalitarian governments (for example formerly predominant communist, ] or ] governments in some European countries) may be deprived of the vote and the privilege of holding certain jobs. In the United Kingdom people serving long prison sentences are unable to vote, a policy which has been ruled a human rights violation by the ].<ref> {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200807231112/https://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Prisoners_vote_ENG.pdf |date=7 August 2020 }} European Court of Human Rights, April 2019.</ref> A similar policy is also enacted in most of the United States.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Felon Voting Rights|url=https://www.ncsl.org/research/elections-and-campaigns/felon-voting-rights.aspx|access-date=2021-04-23|website=National Conference of State Legislatures |archive-date=7 March 2016|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160307104713/http://www.ncsl.org/research/elections-and-campaigns/felon-voting-rights.aspx|url-status=live}}</ref> According to a study by Coppedge and Reinicke, at least 85% of democracies provided for ].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Coppedge |first1=Michael |last2=Reinicke |first2=Wolfgang |title=Measuring Polyarchy |date=1991 |publisher=Transaction |location=New Brunswick}}</ref> ] require positive identification before allowing people to vote. For example, in the United States two thirds of the states require their citizens to provide identification to vote, which also provide state IDs for free.<ref>{{cite web |title=Voting requirements |url=https://www.usa.gov/voter-id |website=USA Gov |access-date=21 January 2021 |archive-date=22 January 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210122041827/https://www.usa.gov/voter-id |url-status=live }}</ref> The decisions made through elections are made by those who are members of the electorate and who choose to ] by ].
Several political scientists and think tanks maintain lists of free and unfree states, both in the present and going back a couple centuries. Of these, the best known may be the Polity Data Set, founded by Ted Gurr and that produced by ]. .


In 1971, ] summarized the fundamental rights and freedoms shared by all liberal democracies as eight rights:<ref>{{Cite book|last=Dahl|first=Robert A.|url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/49414698|title=Polyarchy: participation and opposition|date=1971|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=0-585-38576-9|location=New Haven|oclc=49414698|access-date=23 January 2021|archive-date=24 May 2022|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220524115530/http://www.worldcat.org/oclc/49414698|url-status=live}}</ref>
There is general agreement that the states of the ], Japan, the United States, Canada, India, South Africa, Australia and New Zealand are liberal democracies.


# Freedom to form and join organizations.
==References==
# Freedom of expression.
<references/>
# Right to vote.
# Right to run for public office.
# Right of political leaders to compete for support and votes.
# Freedom of alternative sources of information
# Free and fair elections.
# Right to control government policy through votes and other expressions of preference.


==See also== == Preconditions ==
For a political regime to be considered a liberal democracy it must contain in its governing over a nation-state the provision of civil rights- the non-discrimination in the provision of public goods such as justice, security, education and health- in addition to, political rights- the guarantee of free and fair electoral contests, which allow the winners of such contests to determine policy subject to the constraints established by other rights, when these are provided- and property rights- which protect asset holders and investors against expropriation by the state or other groups. In this way, liberal democracy is set apart from electoral democracy, as free and fair elections – the hallmark of electoral democracy – can be separated from equal treatment and non-discrimination – the hallmarks of liberal democracy. In liberal democracy, an elected government cannot discriminate against specific individuals or groups when it administers justice, protects basic rights such as freedom of assembly and free speech, provides for collective security, or distributes economic and social benefits.<ref>Mukand, S. W., & Rodrik, D. (2016). The Political Economy of Liberal Democracy. The Economic Journal, 130(627), 765–792. https://drodrik.scholar.harvard.edu/files/dani-rodrik/files/the_political_economy_of_liberal_democracy_june_2016.pdf {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118213502/https://drodrik.scholar.harvard.edu/files/dani-rodrik/files/the_political_economy_of_liberal_democracy_june_2016.pdf |date=18 November 2022 }}</ref>
*]
According to Seymour Martin Lipset, although they are not part of the system of government as such, a modicum of ] and ]s, which result in the formation of a significant ] and a broad and flourishing ], are seen as pre-conditions for liberal democracy.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Lipset|first=Seymour Martin|date=1959|title=Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1951731|journal=The American Political Science Review|volume=53|issue=1|pages=69–105|doi=10.2307/1951731|jstor=1951731|s2cid=53686238|issn=0003-0554|access-date=25 January 2021|archive-date=9 February 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230209225223/https://www.jstor.org/stable/1951731|url-status=live}}</ref>


For countries without a strong tradition of democratic majority rule, the introduction of free elections alone has rarely been sufficient to achieve a transition from dictatorship to democracy; a wider shift in the political culture and gradual formation of the institutions of democratic government are needed. There are various examples—for instance, in ]—of countries that were able to sustain democracy only temporarily or in a limited fashion until wider cultural changes established the conditions under which democracy could flourish.{{Citation needed|date=October 2014}}
*]
*]
*]
*]
*]
*]


One of the key aspects of democratic culture is the concept of a ], where political competitors may disagree, but they must tolerate one another and acknowledge the legitimate and important roles that each play. This is an especially difficult cultural shift to achieve in nations where transitions of power have historically taken place through violence. The term means in essence that all sides in a democracy share a common commitment to its basic values. The ground rules of the society must encourage tolerance and civility in public debate. In such a society, the losers accept the judgement of the voters when the election is over and allow for the ]. According to Cas Mudde and Cristóbal Rovira, this is tied to another key concept of democratic cultures, the protection of minorities,<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Mudde|first1=Cas|last2=Rovira Kaltwasser|first2=Cristóbal|author-link2=Cristóbal Rovira|url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/795125118|title=Populism in Europe and the Americas: threat or corrective for democracy?|date=2012|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-139-42423-3|location=Cambridge|oclc=795125118}}</ref> where the losers are safe in the knowledge that they will neither lose their lives nor their liberty and will continue to participate in public life. They are loyal not to the specific policies of the government, but to the fundamental legitimacy of the state and to the democratic process itself.
] ] ]


One requirement of liberal democracy is political equality amongst voters (ensuring that all voices and all votes count equally) and that these can properly influence government policy, requiring quality procedure and quality content of debate that provides an accountable result, this may apply within elections or to procedures between elections. This requires universal, adult suffrage; recurring, free elections, competitive and fair elections; multiple political parties and a wide variety of information so that citizens can rationally and effectively put pressure onto the government, including that it can be checked, evaluated and removed. This can include or lead to accountability, responsiveness to the desires of citizens, the rule of law, full respect of rights and implementation of political, social and economic freedom.<ref>Morlino L. (2004) "What is a 'good' democracy?", Demoocratization, 11(5), pp. 10-32. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13510340412331304589</ref> Other liberal democracies consider the requirement of minority rights and preventing tyranny of the majority. One of the most common ways is by actively preventing discrimination by the government (bill of rights) but can also include requiring concurrent majorities in several constituencies (confederalism); guaranteeing regional government (federalism); broad coalition governments (consociationalism) or negotiating with other political actors, such as pressure groups (neocorporatism).<ref>Schmitter P.C. and Karl T.L. (1991) "What Democracy Is...and Is Not", Journal of Democracy, 2(3), pp. 75-88. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.1991.0033.</ref> These split political power amongst many competing and cooperating actors and institutions by requiring the government to respect minority groups and give them their positive freedoms, negotiate across multiple geographical areas, become more centrist among cooperative parties and open up with new social groups.
]

]
In a new study published in ], Damian J. Ruck and his co-authors take a major step toward resolving this long-standing and seemingly irresolvable debate about whether culture shapes regimes or regimes shape culture. This study resolves the debate in favor of culture's causal primacy and shows that it is the civic and emancipative values (], ] and ]) among a country's citizens that give rise to democratic institutions, not vice versa.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Ruck |first1=Damian J. |last2=Matthews |first2=Luke J. |last3=Kyritsis |first3=Thanos |last4=Atkinson |first4=Quentin D. |last5=Bentley |first5=R. Alexander |title=The cultural foundations of modern democracies |journal=] |date=2020 |volume=4 |issue=3 |pages=265–269 |doi=10.1038/s41562-019-0769-1|pmid=31792400 |s2cid=256726148 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Welzel |first1=Christian |title=A cultural theory of regimes |journal=Nature Human Behaviour |date=2020 |volume=4 |issue=3 |pages=231–232 |doi=10.1038/s41562-019-0790-4|pmid=31792403 |s2cid=256707649 |doi-access=free }}</ref>
]

]
== Liberal democracies around the world ==
{{further| List of democracy indices }}
] in Freedom House's ''Freedom in the World 2023'' survey, covering the year 2022<ref> {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230415185547/https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/2023-02/All_data_FIW_2013-2023.xlsx |date=15 April 2023 }} (]), by ]</ref>]]
]'s 2022 survey concerning the state of freedom by country / region in 2021. The concept of freedom used in the survey is closely connected to liberal democracy. {{legend|#16A983|Free}} {{legend|#E5B63B|Partly free}} {{legend|#6973A5|Not free}}]]
[[File:Freedom in the World graph.svg|thumb|upright=1.6|Percentage of countries in each category from Freedom House's 1973 through 2021 reports:
{{center|{{legend inline|#198A8A|Free}} {{legend inline|#FFD320|Partly free}} {{legend inline|#6B4794|Not free}} {{legend-line|red solid 2px|Electoral democracies}}}}]]

Several organizations and political scientists maintain lists of free and unfree states, both in the present and going back a couple centuries. Of these, the best known may be the Polity Data Set<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://www.systemicpeace.org/polity/polity4.htm |title=Policy Data Set |access-date=28 October 2008 |archive-date=4 May 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200504221240/http://www.systemicpeace.org/polity/polity4.htm |url-status=live }}</ref> and that produced by ] and ].

There is agreement amongst several intellectuals and organizations such as Freedom House that the states of the ] (with the exception of ] and ]), ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ],<ref>{{cite book |editor-first =Seyla|editor-last= Benhabib|title= Democracy and difference: contesting the boundaries of the political|url = https://books.google.com/books?id=oUo9px-SL4QC|publisher = Princeton University Press|date = 1996 |isbn = 978-0691044781}}</ref><ref>Alain Gagnon,Intellectuals in liberal democracies: political influence and social involvement
</ref><ref>Yvonne Schmidt, Foundations of Civil and Political Rights in Israel and the Occupied Territories</ref><ref>William S. Livingston, A Prospect of purple and orange democracy</ref><ref>{{cite book|first =Steven V. |last=Mazie|title =Israel's higher law: religion and liberal democracy in the Jewish state|publisher =Lexington Books|date = 2006|isbn =978-0739114858|url =https://books.google.com/books?id=2Y-TVQiDk8IC}}</ref> ], ], ], ], ], and ]<ref>{{Cite book|last=Mulgan|first=Richard|author2=Peter Aimer|title=Politics in New Zealand|publisher=Auckland University Press|year=2004|edition=3rd|chapter=chapter 1|page=17|isbn=1869403185|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ROzyxst0h6gC&q=New+Zealand+liberal+democracy&pg=PA17|access-date=2009-06-26|archive-date=22 September 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200922124657/https://books.google.com/books?id=ROzyxst0h6gC&pg=PA17&lpg=PA17&dq=New+Zealand+liberal+democracy|url-status=live}}</ref> are liberal democracies.
Liberal democracies are susceptible to ] and this is taking place or has taken place in several countries, including, but not limited to, the ], ], ], and ].<ref name=":0" />

Freedom House considers many of the officially democratic governments in ] and the former ] to be undemocratic in practice, usually because the sitting government has a strong influence over election outcomes. Many of these countries are in a state of considerable flux.

Officially non-democratic forms of government, such as single-party states and dictatorships, are more common in ], the ] and ].

The 2019 ] report noted a fall in the number of countries with liberal democracies over the 13 years from 2005 to 2018, citing declines in 'political rights and civil liberties'.<ref>{{cite web |title=Freedom in the World: Democracy in Retreat |url=https://freedomhouse.org/report/freedom-world/freedom-world-2019 |website=freedomhouse.org |publisher=Freedom House |access-date=7 December 2019 |archive-date=5 February 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190205180803/https://freedomhouse.org/report/freedom-world/freedom-world-2019 |url-status=live }}</ref> The 2020 <ref name="FITW-TG-2020">{{cite web | url=https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/2020-02/FIW_2020_REPORT_BOOKLET_Final.pdf | title=Freedom in the World 2020 | publisher=Freedom House | date=4 March 2020 | access-date=4 March 2020 | archive-date=4 March 2020 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200304125426/https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/2020-02/FIW_2020_REPORT_BOOKLET_Final.pdf | url-status=live }}</ref> and 2021 <ref name="FITW-TG-2021">{{cite web | url=https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/2021-02/FIW2021_World_02252021_FINAL-web-upload.pdf | title=Freedom in the World 2021 | publisher=Freedom House | date=3 March 2021 | access-date=3 March 2021 | archive-date=26 December 2021 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211226172012/https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/2021-02/FIW2021_World_02252021_FINAL-web-upload.pdf | url-status=live }}</ref> reports document further reductions in the number of free countries in the world.

== Types ==
{{unreferenced section|date=August 2012}}

=== Proportional vs. plurality representation ===
] award seats according to regional majorities. The political party or individual candidate who receives the most votes, wins the seat which represents that locality. There are other democratic electoral systems, such as the various forms of ], which award seats according to the proportion of individual votes that a party receives nationwide or in a particular region.

One of the main points of contention between these two systems is whether to have representatives who are able to effectively represent specific regions in a country, or to have all citizens' vote count the same, regardless of where in the country they happen to live.

Some countries, such as ] and ], address the conflict between these two forms of representation by having two categories of seats in the ] of their national legislative bodies. The first category of seats is appointed according to regional popularity and the remainder are awarded to give the parties a proportion of seats that is equal—or as equal as practicable—to their proportion of nationwide votes. This system is commonly called ].

The ] incorporates both systems in having the ] system applicable to the ] and ] by state in the ]. This system is argued to result in a more stable government, while having a better diversity of parties to review its actions. The various ] in Australia employ a range of a different electoral systems.

=== Presidential vs. parliamentary systems ===
A ] is a ] of a ] in which the ] is elected separately from the ]. A ] is distinguished by the ] being dependent on the direct or indirect support of the ], often expressed through a ].

The presidential system of democratic government has been adopted in ], ] and parts of the former ], largely by the example of the ]. ] (dominated by elected parliaments) are present in ] and some former ] which peacefully separated, such as ] and ]. Others have also arisen in ], ] and a variety of small nations around the world. Former British territories such as ], ], ] and the ] opted for different forms at the time of independence. The parliamentary system is widely used in the ] and neighbouring countries.

== Impact on economic growth ==

Recent academic studies have found that democratisation is beneficial for national growth. However, the effect of democratisation has not been studied as yet. The most common factors that determine whether a country's economy grows or not are the country's level of development and the educational level of its newly elected democratic leaders. As a result, there is no clear indication of how to determine which factors contribute to economic growth in a democratic country.<ref>The Effects of Democracy on Economic Growth {{cite web|url=https://www.newculturalfrontiers.org/the-effects-of-democracy-on-economic-growth|date=2022|title=The Effects of Democracy on Economic Growth|access-date=8 October 2022|archive-date=26 January 2022|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220126141236/https://www.newculturalfrontiers.org/the-effects-of-democracy-on-economic-growth|url-status=live}}</ref>

However, there is disagreement regarding how much credit the democratic system can take for this growth. One observation is that democracy became widespread only after the ] and the introduction of ]. On the other hand, the Industrial Revolution started in England which was one of the most democratic nations for its time within its own borders, but this democracy was very limited and did not apply to the colonies which contributed significantly to the wealth.<ref>{{cite web|date=2017|url=https://cepr.org/voxeu/columns/economic-impact-colonialism|title=The economic impact of colonialism|access-date=8 October 2022|archive-date=17 August 2022|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220817160154/https://cepr.org/voxeu/columns/economic-impact-colonialism|url-status=live}}</ref>

Several statistical studies support the theory that a higher degree of economic freedom, as measured with one of the several ] which have been used in numerous studies,<ref>Free the World. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110514001203/http://www.freetheworld.com/papers.html |date=14 May 2011 }}. Retrieved 19 February 2006.</ref> increases ] and that this in turn increases general prosperity, reduces poverty and causes ]. This is a statistical tendency and there are individual exceptions like Mali, which is ranked as "Free" by ], but is a ], or Qatar, which has arguably the highest GDP per capita in the world, but has never been democratic. There are also other studies suggesting that more democracy increases economic freedom, although a few find no or even a small negative effect.<ref>{{cite web|first=Niclas|last= Bergren|date=2002 |url = http://www.ratioinstitutet.nu/pdf/wp/nb_efi.pdf |title=The Benefits of Economic Freedom: A Survey |url-status=unfit |archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20070628093441/http://www.ratioinstitutet.nu/pdf/wp/nb_efi.pdf |archive-date=28 June 2007 }}</ref><ref>John W. Dawson, (1998). {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060420160141/http://www.eh.net/bookreviews/library/0102.shtml |date=20 April 2006 }}. ''Economic History Services''. Retrieved 19 February 2006.</ref><ref>W. Ken Farr, Richard A. Lord, J. Larry Wolfenbarger, (1998).{{cite web|url=http://catoinstitute.org/pubs/journal/cj18n2/cj18n2-5.pdf |title=Economic Freedom, Political Freedom, and Economic Well-Being: A Causality Analysis |access-date=11 April 2005 |url-status=unfit |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070203075248/http://catoinstitute.org/pubs/journal/cj18n2/cj18n2-5.pdf |archive-date=3 February 2007 }}. ''Cato Journal'', Vol 18, No 2.</ref><ref>Wenbo Wu, Otto A. Davis, (2003). " {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060524134800/http://www.spp.nus.edu.sg/docs/wp/wp48.pdf |date=24 May 2006 }}", ''Encyclopedia of Public Choice''. ], ].</ref><ref>Ian Vásquez, (2001). {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110524064149/http://www.cato.org/research/articles/vas-0109.html |date=24 May 2011 }}. ]. Retrieved 19 February 2006.</ref><ref>Susanna Lundström, (April 2002). {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060524134800/http://smye2002.univ-paris1.fr/program/paper/b5_lun.pdf |date=24 May 2006 }}. Retrieved 19 February 2006.</ref>

Some argue that economic growth due to its empowerment of citizens will ensure a transition to democracy in countries such as Cuba. However, other dispute this and even if economic growth has caused democratisation in the past, it may not do so in the future. Dictators may now have learned how to have economic growth without this causing more political freedom.<ref>{{cite journal|first1 = Bruce|last1 = Bueno de Mesquita|first2 = George W.|last2 = Downs|date = September–October 2005|url = https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/2005-09-01/development-and-democracy|title = Development and Democracy|journal = Foreign Affairs| volume=84 | issue=September/October 2005 |publisher = Council on Foreign Relations|access-date = 22 October 2018|archive-date = 22 October 2018|archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20181022234013/https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/2005-09-01/development-and-democracy|url-status = live}}</ref><ref>{{cite news|first1= Joseph T.|last1= Single|first2= Michael M.|last2= Weinstein|first3= Morton H.|last3= Halperin|date= 28 September 2004|url= https://www.nytimes.com/cfr/international/20040901facomment_v83n4_siegle-weinstein-halperin.html|title= Why Democracies Excel|work= New York Times|access-date= 2 March 2017|archive-date= 13 November 2016|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20161113004700/http://www.nytimes.com/cfr/international/20040901facomment_v83n4_siegle-weinstein-halperin.html|url-status= live}}</ref>

A high degree of oil or mineral exports is strongly associated with nondemocratic rule. This effect applies worldwide and not only to the Middle East. Dictators who have this form of wealth can spend more on their security apparatus and provide benefits which lessen public unrest. Also, such wealth is not followed by the social and cultural changes that may transform societies with ordinary economic growth.<ref>{{Cite journal|author=Ross, Michael Lewin |title=Does Oil Hinder Democracy? |journal=World Politics |year=2001 |volume=53 |issue=3 |pages=325–61 |doi=10.1353/wp.2001.0011|s2cid=18404 }}</ref>

A 2006 meta-analysis found that democracy has no direct effect on economic growth. However, it has strong and significant indirect effects which contribute to growth. Democracy is associated with higher human ], lower ], lower political instability and higher ]. There is also some evidence that it is associated with larger governments and more restrictions on international trade.<ref>{{Cite journal|author=Doucouliagos, H., Ulubasoglu, M |title=Democracy and Economic Growth: A meta-analysis |journal=School of Accounting, Economics and Finance Deakin University Australia |year=2006}}</ref>

If leaving out ], then during the last forty-five years poor democracies have grown their economies 50% more rapidly than nondemocracies. Poor democracies such as the Baltic countries, Botswana, Costa Rica, Ghana and Senegal have grown more rapidly than nondemocracies such as Angola, Syria, Uzbekistan and Zimbabwe.<ref name="carnegiecouncil1"/>

Of the eighty worst financial catastrophes during the last four decades, only five were in democracies. Similarly, poor democracies are half likely as non-democracies to experience a 10 per cent decline in GDP per capita over the course of a single year.<ref name="carnegiecouncil1"/>

== Justifications and support ==
=== Increased political stability ===
Several key features of liberal democracies are associated with political stability, including economic growth, as well as robust state institutions that guarantee free elections, the ], and individual liberties.<ref name="Carugati2020">{{cite journal|doi=10.1146/annurev-polisci-052918-012050|title=Democratic Stability: A Long View|year=2020|last1=Carugati|first1=Federica|journal=Annual Review of Political Science|volume=23|pages=59–75|doi-access=free|quote=In sum, this literature suggests that stable democracies look very much like liberal democracies, whose critical features are...}}</ref>

One argument for democracy is that by creating a system where the public can remove administrations, without changing the legal basis for government, democracy aims at reducing political uncertainty and instability and assuring citizens that however much they may disagree with present policies, they will be given a regular chance to change those who are in power, or change policies with which they disagree. This is preferable to a system where political change takes place through violence.{{citation needed|date=June 2020}}

One notable feature of liberal democracies is that their opponents (those groups who wish to abolish liberal democracy) rarely win elections. Advocates use this as an argument to support their view that liberal democracy is inherently stable and can usually only be overthrown by external force, while opponents argue that the system is inherently stacked against them despite its claims to impartiality. In the past, it was feared that democracy could be easily exploited by leaders with dictatorial aspirations, who could get themselves elected into power. However, the actual number of liberal democracies that have elected dictators into power is low. When it has occurred, it is usually after a major crisis has caused many people to doubt the system or in young/poorly functioning democracies. Some possible examples include ] during the ] and ], who became first President of the ] and later Emperor.{{citation needed|date=June 2020}}

=== Effective response in wartime ===
By definition, a liberal democracy implies that power is not concentrated. One criticism is that this could be a disadvantage for a state in ]time, when a fast and unified response is necessary. The legislature usually must give consent before the start of an offensive military operation, although sometimes the executive can do this on its own while keeping the legislature informed. If the democracy is attacked, then no consent is usually required for defensive operations. The people may vote against a ] army.

However, actual research shows that democracies are more likely to win wars than non-democracies. One explanation attributes this primarily to "the transparency of the ], and the stability of their preferences, once determined, democracies are better able to cooperate with their partners in the conduct of wars". Other research attributes this to superior mobilisation of resources or selection of wars that the democratic states have a high chance of winning.<ref>Ajin Choi, (2004). "Democratic Synergy and Victory in War, 1816–1992". ''International Studies Quarterly'', Volume 48, Number 3, September 2004, pp. 663–82 (20). {{doi|10.1111/j.0020-8833.2004.00319.x}}</ref>

Stam and ] also note that the emphasis on individuality within democratic societies means that their soldiers fight with greater initiative and superior leadership.<ref>{{Cite book |first1=Reiter |last1=Dan |last2=Stam |first2=Allan C. |year=2002 |title=Democracies at War |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=0691089485 |pages= |url=https://archive.org/details/democraciesatwar00danr/page/64 }}</ref> Officers in dictatorships are often selected for political loyalty rather than military ability. They may be exclusively selected from a small class or religious/ethnic group that support the regime. The leaders in nondemocracies may respond violently to any perceived criticisms or disobedience. This may make the soldiers and officers afraid to raise any objections or do anything without explicit authorisation. The lack of initiative may be particularly detrimental in modern warfare. Enemy soldiers may more easily surrender to democracies since they can expect comparatively good treatment. In contrast, Nazi Germany killed almost 2/3 of the captured Soviet soldiers and 38% of the American soldiers captured by North Korea in the ] were killed.

=== Better information on and corrections of problems ===
A democratic system may provide better information for policy decisions. Undesirable information may more easily be ignored in dictatorships, even if this undesirable or contrarian information provides early warning of problems. ] put forward the argument for ] for this reason in 1776.<ref name=luoma>{{cite web|last=Luoma|first=Jukka|title=Helsingin Sanomat – International Edition|access-date=26 November 2007|url=http://www.hs.fi/english/article/Self-censorship+has+always+encouraged+censorship/1135218861212|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20071120112003/http://www.hs.fi/english/article/Self-censorship+has+always+encouraged+censorship/1135218861212|archive-date=20 November 2007}}</ref> The democratic system also provides a way to replace inefficient leaders and policies, thus problems may continue longer and crises of all kinds may be more common in autocracies.<ref name=carnegiecouncil1>{{cite web|title=The Democracy Advantage: How Democracies Promote Prosperity and Peace |work=Carnegie Council |url=http://carnegiecouncil.org/viewMedia.php/prmTemplateID/9/prmID/5129 |first1=Morton |last1=Halperin |first2=Joseph T. |last2=Siegle |first3=Michael |last3=Weinstein |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060628061201/http://carnegiecouncil.org/viewMedia.php/prmTemplateID/9/prmID/5129 |archive-date=28 June 2006}}</ref>

=== Reduction of corruption ===
Research by the ] suggests that political institutions are extremely important in determining the prevalence of ]: (long term) democracy, parliamentary systems, political stability and freedom of the press are all associated with lower corruption.<ref name="Lederman2001">Daniel Lederman, Normal Loaza, Rodrigo Res Soares (November 2001). . ''World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 2708''. {{SSRN|632777}}. {{Cite web |url=https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=632777 |title=Accountability and Corruption: Political Institutions Matter by Daniel Lederman, Norman Loayza, Rodrigo R. Soares :: SSRN |date=November 2001 |ssrn=632777 |access-date=17 June 2023 |archive-date=19 January 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210119120724/https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=632777 |url-status=bot: unknown }}. Retrieved 19 February 2006.</ref> ] is important for ] and ]. The Indian ] "has already engendered mass movements in the country that is bringing the lethargic, often corrupt bureaucracy to its knees and changing power equations completely".<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.asiamedia.ucla.edu/article.asp?parentid=52046 |title=Right to Information Act India's magic wand against corruption |work=AsiaMedia |access-date=2008-10-28 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080926172330/http://www.asiamedia.ucla.edu/article.asp?parentid=52046 |archive-date=26 September 2008 }}</ref>

=== Better use of resources ===
Democracies can put in place better education, longer life expectancy, lower infant mortality, access to drinking water and better health care than dictatorships. This is not due to higher levels of foreign assistance or spending a larger percentage of GDP on health and education, as instead the available resources are managed better.<ref name="carnegiecouncil1"/>

Prominent economist ] has noted that no functioning democracy has ever suffered a large scale ].<ref>{{cite journal |url-status=dead |author-link1=Amartya Sen |first1=Amartya |last1=Sen |date=1999 |url=http://muse.jhu.edu/demo/jod/10.3sen.html |title=Democracy as a Universal Value |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060427050621/http://muse.jhu.edu/demo/jod/10.3sen.html |archive-date=27 April 2006 |journal=Journal of Democracy |volume=10 |issue=3 |pages=3–17 |doi=10.1353/jod.1999.0055 |via=Johns Hopkins University Press Project MUSE }}</ref> Refugee crises almost always occur in non-democracies. From 1985 to 2008, the eighty-seven largest refugee crises occurred in autocracies.<ref name=carnegiecouncil1/>

=== Health and human development===
Democracy correlates with a higher score on the ] and a lower score on the human poverty index.

Several health indicators (life expectancy and infant and maternal mortality) have a stronger and more significant association with democracy than they have with GDP per capita, rise of the public sector or income inequality.<ref name="Franco2004">{{cite journal|first1=Álvaro |last1=Franco |first2=Carlos |last2=Álvarez-Dardet |first3=Maria Teresa |last3=Ruiz |doi-access=free |title=Effect of democracy on health: ecological study (required) |journal=] |year=2004 |volume=329 |issue=7480 |pages=1421–23 |doi=10.1136/bmj.329.7480.1421 |pmid=15604165 |pmc=535957}}</ref>

In the post-communist nations, after an initial decline those that are the most democratic have achieved the greatest gains in life expectancy.<ref>{{Cite journal|author1=McKee, Marin |author2=Ellen Nolte |title=Lessons from health during the transition from communism |doi-access=free |journal=] |year=2004 |volume=329 |issue=7480 |pages=1428–29 |doi=10.1136/bmj.329.7480.1428 |pmid=15604170 |pmc=535963}}</ref>

=== Democratic peace theory ===
{{main|Democratic peace theory}}
Numerous studies using many different kinds of data, definitions and statistical analyses have found support for the democratic peace theory.{{citation needed|date=August 2016}} The original finding was that liberal democracies have never made war with one another. More recent research has extended the theory and finds that democracies have few ]s causing less than 1,000 battle deaths with one another, that those militarized interstate disputes that have occurred between democracies have caused few deaths and that democracies have few ].<ref>{{cite journal |first1=Håvard |last1=Hegre |first2=Tanja |last2=Ellingsen |first3=Scott |last3=Gates |first4=Nils Petter |last4=Gleditsch |s2cid-access=free |title=Towards A Democratic Civil Peace? Opportunity, Grievance, and Civil War 1816–1992 |journal=American Political Science Review |year=2001 |volume=95 |pages=33–48 |url=http://www.worldbank.org/research/conflict/papers/peace.htm |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060209113811/http://www.worldbank.org/research/conflict/papers/peace.htm |archive-date=9 February 2006 |doi=10.1017/s0003055401000119|s2cid=7521813 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |author=Ray, James Lee |title=A Lakatosian View of the Democratic Peace Research Program From Progress in International Relations Theory, edited by Colin and Miriam Fendius Elman |url=http://sitemason.vanderbilt.edu/files/g/gDf5Ty/6%20ray%20demo%20peace%20FIRST%20PROOFS.pdf |publisher=MIT Press |year=2003 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060625203811/http://sitemason.vanderbilt.edu/files/g/gDf5Ty/6%20ray%20demo%20peace%20FIRST%20PROOFS.pdf |archive-date=25 June 2006 }}</ref> There are various criticisms of the theory, including at least as many refutations as alleged proofs of the theory, some 200 deviant cases, failure to treat democracy as a multidimensional concept and that correlation is not causation.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Haas |first1=Michael |title=Deconstructing the "democratic peace" : how a research agenda boomeranged |year=2014 |publisher=Publishinghouse for Scholars |location=Los Angeles, CA |isbn=9780983962625}}</ref>{{page needed|date=January 2021}}

=== Minimization of political violence ===
]'s ''Power Kills'' says that liberal democracy, among all types of regimes, minimizes political violence and is a method of nonviolence. Rummel attributes this firstly to democracy instilling an attitude of tolerance of differences, an acceptance of losing and a positive outlook towards conciliation and compromise.<ref>], ''Power Kills''. 1997. p. .</ref>

A study published by the British Academy, on ''Violence and Democracy'',<ref>{{Cite web|date=September 2019|title=Violence and Democracy|url=https://www.lse.ac.uk/lacc/publications/PDFs/Violence-and-Democracy.pdf|publisher=]|access-date=25 January 2021|archive-date=7 March 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230307000118/https://www.lse.ac.uk/lacc/publications/PDFs/Violence-and-Democracy.pdf|url-status=live}}</ref> argues that in practice, liberal democracy has not stopped those running the state from exerting acts of violence both within and outside their borders. The paper also argues that police killings, profiling of racial and religious minorities, online surveillance, data collection, or media censorship are a couple of ways in which successful states maintain a monopoly on violence.

== Objections and criticism ==
{{See also|Criticism of democracy}}
=== Campaign costs ===
In Athenian democracy, some public offices were randomly allocated to citizens, in order to inhibit the effects of plutocracy. Aristotle described the law courts in Athens which were selected by lot as democratic<ref>Aristotle, Politics 2.1273b</ref> and described elections as oligarchic.<ref>Aristotle, Politics 4.1294b</ref>

Political campaigning in representative democracies can favor the rich due to campaign costs, a form of ] where only a very small number of wealthy individuals can actually affect government policy in their favor and toward ].<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Draper|first1=Hal|title=Marx on Democratic Forms of Government|date=1974|journal=The Socialist Register|volume=11|url=https://socialistregister.com/index.php/srv/article/view/5326/2227|access-date=22 October 2018|archive-date=5 August 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190805130248/https://socialistregister.com/index.php/srv/article/view/5326/2227|url-status=live}}</ref> Stringent ] laws can correct this perceived problem.{{citation needed|date=September 2021}}

Other studies predicted that the global trend toward plutonomies would continue, for various reasons, including "capitalist-friendly governments and tax regimes".<ref>Kapur, Ajay, Niall Macleod, Narendra Singh: "Plutonomy: Buying Luxury, Explaining Global Imbalances", Citigroup, Equity Strategy, Industry Note: October 16, 2005. p. 9f.</ref> However, they also say that, since "political enfranchisement remains as was—one person, one vote, at some point it is likely that labor will fight back against the rising profit share of the rich and there will be a political backlash against the rising wealth of the rich."<ref>Kapur, Ajay, Niall Macleod, Narendra Singh: "Revisiting Plutonomy: The Rich Getting Richer", Citigroup, Equity Strategy, Industry Note: March 5, 2006. p. 10.</ref>

Economist ] says in his book '']'' that campaign spending is no guarantee of electoral success. He compared electoral success of the same pair of candidates running against one another repeatedly for the same job, as often happens in United States congressional elections, where spending levels varied. He concludes:
:A winning candidate can cut his spending in half and lose only 1 percent of the vote. Meanwhile, a losing candidate who doubles his spending can expect to shift the vote in his favor by only that same 1 percent.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Cta5AAAAIAAJ&q=%22A+winning+candidate+can+cut+his+spending+in+half+and+lose+only+1+percent+of+the+vote.+Meanwhile,+a+losing+candidate+who+doubles+his+spending+can+expect+to+shift+the+vote+in+his+favor+by+only+that+same+1+percent%22|first1=Steven|last1=Levitt|author-link1=Steven Levitt|first2=Stephen J.|last2=Dubner|author-link2=Stephen J. Dubner|title=Freakonomics: A Rogue Economist Explores the Hidden Side of Everything|publisher=]|year=2006|isbn=978-0061245138|page=14|access-date=6 June 2020|archive-date=22 September 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200922124658/https://books.google.com/books?id=Cta5AAAAIAAJ&q=%22A+winning+candidate+can+cut+his+spending+in+half+and+lose+only+1+percent+of+the+vote.+Meanwhile%2C+a+losing+candidate+who+doubles+his+spending+can+expect+to+shift+the+vote+in+his+favor+by+only+that+same+1+percent%22&dq=%22A+winning+candidate+can+cut+his+spending+in+half+and+lose+only+1+percent+of+the+vote.+Meanwhile%2C+a+losing+candidate+who+doubles+his+spending+can+expect+to+shift+the+vote+in+his+favor+by+only+that+same+1+percent%22&cd=1|url-status=live}}</ref>

On September 18, 2014, Martin Gilens and Benjamin I. Page's study concluded "Multivariate analysis indicates that economic elites and organized groups representing business interests have substantial independent impacts on U.S. government policy, while average citizens and mass-based interest groups have little or no independent influence. The results provide substantial support for theories of Economic-Elite Domination and for theories of Biased Pluralism, but not for theories of Majoritarian Electoral Democracy or Majoritarian Pluralism."<ref>Gilens, M., & Page, B. (2014). Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens. ''Perspectives on Politics'', 12(3), 564–81. {{doi|10.1017/S1537592714001595}}</ref>

=== Media ===
Critics of the role of the media in liberal democracies allege that ] leads to major distortions of democratic processes. In '']'', ] and ] argue via their ]<ref>Edward S. Herman {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120106195120/http://www.chomsky.info/onchomsky/199607--.htm |date=6 January 2012 }}, ''Monthly Review'', July 1996, as reproduced on the Chomsky.info website</ref> that the corporate media limits the availability of contesting views and assert this creates a narrow spectrum of elite opinion. This is a natural consequence, they say, of the close ties between powerful ]s and the media and thus limited and restricted to the explicit views of those who can afford it.<ref>James Curran and ] '']'', London: Routledge, 1997, p. 1</ref> Furthermore, the media's negative influence can be seen in social media where vast numbers of individuals seek their political information which is not always correct and may be controlled. For example, as of 2017, two-thirds (67%) of Americans report that they get at least some of their news from social media,<ref>{{Cite web|last1=Shearer|first1=Elisa|last2=Gottfried|first2=Jeffrey|date=2017-09-07|title=News Use Across Social Media Platforms 2017|url=https://www.journalism.org/2017/09/07/news-use-across-social-media-platforms-2017/|access-date=2021-01-14|website=Pew Research Center's Journalism Project|language=en-US|archive-date=16 March 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210316054814/https://www.journalism.org/2017/09/07/news-use-across-social-media-platforms-2017/|url-status=live}}</ref> as well as a rising number of countries are exercising extreme control over the flow of information.<ref>{{Cite web|last=Chapman|first=Terri|date=2019-10-27|title=Liberal democracy is under threat from digitisation as govts, tech firms gain more power|url=https://theprint.in/opinion/liberal-democracy-is-under-threat-from-digitisation-as-govts-tech-firms-gain-more-power/312081/|access-date=2021-01-14|website=ThePrint|language=en-US|archive-date=15 April 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210415154755/https://theprint.in/opinion/liberal-democracy-is-under-threat-from-digitisation-as-govts-tech-firms-gain-more-power/312081/|url-status=live}}</ref> This may contribute to large numbers of individuals using social media platforms but not always gaining correct political information. This may cause conflict with liberal democracy and some of its core principles, such as freedom, if individuals are not entirely free since their governments are seizing that level of control on media sites. The notion that the media is used to indoctrinate the public is also shared by Yascha Mounk's ''The People Vs Democracy'' which states that the government benefits from the public having a relatively similar worldview and that this one-minded ideal is one of the principles in which Liberal Democracy stands.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Girard|first=Raphaël|date=2019|title=Yascha Mounk, The People vs. Democracy: Why Our Freedom Is in Danger and How to Save It, Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 2018, 400 pp, hb £21.95.|url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1468-2230.12397|journal=The Modern Law Review|language=en|volume=82|issue=1|pages=196–200|doi=10.1111/1468-2230.12397|s2cid=149968721|issn=1468-2230|access-date=25 January 2021|archive-date=20 April 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210420225212/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1468-2230.12397|url-status=live}}</ref>

Defenders responding to such arguments say that constitutionally protected ] makes it possible for both for-profit and non-profit organisations to debate the issues. They argue that media coverage in democracies simply reflects public preferences and does not entail censorship. Especially with new forms of media such as the Internet, it is not expensive to reach a wide audience, if an interest in the ideas presented exists.

=== Limited voter turnout ===
{{further|Voter turnout}}
Low voter turnout, whether the cause is disenchantment, indifference or contentment with the status quo, may be seen as a problem, especially if disproportionate in particular segments of the population. Although turnout levels vary greatly among modern democratic countries and in various types and levels of elections within countries, at some point low turnout may prompt questions as to whether the results reflect the will of the people, whether the causes may be indicative of concerns to the society in question, or in extreme cases the ] of the electoral system.

] campaigns, either by governments or private groups, may increase voter turnout, but distinctions must be made between general campaigns to raise the turnout rate and partisan efforts to aid a particular candidate, party or cause. Other alternatives include increased use of ], or other measures to ease or improve the ability to vote, including ].

Several nations have forms of ], with various degrees of enforcement. Proponents argue that this increases the legitimacy—and thus also popular acceptance—of the elections and ensures political participation by all those affected by the political process and reduces the costs associated with encouraging voting. Arguments against include restriction of freedom, economic costs of enforcement, increased number of invalid and blank votes and random voting.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.idea.int/vt/compulsory_voting.cfm |title=International IDEA &#124; Compulsory Voting |publisher=Idea.int |access-date=2008-10-28 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090612191446/http://www.idea.int/vt/compulsory_voting.cfm |archive-date=12 June 2009 }}</ref>

=== Bureaucracy ===
A persistent ] and ] critique of democracy is the claim that it encourages the elected representatives to change the law without necessity and in particular to pour forth a flood of new laws, as described in ]'s '']''.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Spencer |first1=Herbert |last2=Beale|first2=T. | title=The Man Versus the State: A Collection of Essays |publisher=M. Kennerley |year=1916 }}</ref> This is seen as pernicious in several ways. New laws constrict the scope of what were previously private liberties. Rapidly changing laws make it difficult for a willing non-specialist to remain law-abiding. This may be an invitation for law-enforcement agencies to misuse power. The claimed continual complication of the law may be contrary to a claimed simple and eternal ]—although there is no consensus on what this natural law is, even among advocates. Supporters of democracy point to the complex bureaucracy and regulations that has occurred in dictatorships, like many of the former communist states.

The bureaucracy in liberal democracies is often criticised for a claimed slowness and complexity of their decision-making. The term "]" is a synonym of slow bureaucratic functioning that hinders quick results in a liberal democracy.

=== Short-term focus ===
By definition, modern liberal democracies allow for regular changes of government. That has led to a common criticism of their short-term focus. In four or five years the government will face a new election and it must think of how it will win that election. That would encourage a preference for policies that will bring short term benefits to the electorate (or to self-interested politicians) before the next election, rather than unpopular policy with longer term benefits. This criticism assumes that it is possible to make long term predictions for a society, something ] has criticised as ].

Besides the regular review of governing entities, short-term focus in a democracy could also be the result of collective short-term thinking. For example, consider a campaign for policies aimed at reducing environmental damage while causing temporary increase in unemployment. However, this risk applies also to other political systems.

=== Majoritarianism ===
{{main|Majority rule|Tyranny of the majority}}
{{More citations needed|section|date=August 2012}}
The ] is the fear that a direct democratic government, reflecting the majority view, can take action that oppresses a particular minority. For instance, a minority holding wealth, property ownership or power (see ]), or a minority of a certain racial and ethnic origin, class or nationality. Theoretically, the majority is a majority of all citizens. If citizens are not compelled by law to vote, it is usually a majority of those who choose to vote. If such of group constitutes a minority, then it is possible that a minority could in theory oppress another minority in the name of the majority. However, such an argument could apply to both ] or ]. Several ''de facto'' dictatorships also have compulsory, but not "free and fair" voting in order to try to increase the legitimacy of the regime, such as ].<ref name=pk>{{cite web |title=DPRK Holds Election of Local and National Assemblies |work=] |url=http://www1.korea-np.co.jp/pk/195th_issue/2003081602.htm |access-date=2008-06-28 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120510012133/http://www1.korea-np.co.jp/pk/195th_issue/2003081602.htm |archive-date=10 May 2012 |url-status=dead }}</ref><ref name=parlunion4>{{cite web | title=The Parliamentary System of the Democratic People's Republic of Korea | publisher=Association of Secretaries General of Parliaments (ASGP) of the ] | work=Constitutional and Parliamentary Information | url=http://www.asgp.co/sites/default/files/documents//CJOZSZTEPVVOCWJVUPPZVWPAPUOFGF.pdf | access-date=2010-10-01 | page=4 | archive-date=3 March 2012 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120303054935/http://www.asgp.info/Resources/Data/Documents/CJOZSZTEPVVOCWJVUPPZVWPAPUOFGF.pdf | url-status=live }}</ref>

In her book '']'', ] professor ] posits that "when free market democracy is pursued in the presence of a market-dominant minority, the almost invariable result is backlash. This backlash typically takes one of three forms. The first is a backlash against markets, targeting the market-dominant minority's wealth. The second is a backlash against democracy by forces favorable to the market-dominant minority. The third is violence, sometimes ], directed against the market-dominant minority itself".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Chua |first=Amy |author-link=Amy Chua |title=World on Fire |publisher=] |year= 2002 |isbn=0385503024|title-link=World on Fire: How Exporting Free Market Democracy Breeds Ethnic Hatred and Global Instability }}</ref>

Cases that have been cited as examples of a minority being oppressed by or in the name of the majority include{{fact|date=June 2023}} the practice of ] and laws against ], ], and ]. Homosexual acts were widely criminalised in democracies until several decades ago and in some democracies like Ghana, Kenya, Tanzania, Tunisia, Nigeria, and Malaysia, they still are, reflecting the religious or sexual mores of the majority. The Athenian democracy and the early United States practiced ], and even proponents of liberal democracy in the 17th and 18th century were often pro-slavery, which is contradictory of a liberal democracy. Another often quoted example of the "tyranny of the majority" is that ] came to power by "legitimate" democratic procedures. The ] gained the largest share of votes in the democratic ] in 1933. However, his regime's large-scale human rights violations took place after the democratic system had been abolished. Furthermore, the ] in an ].

Proponents of democracy make a number of defenses concerning "tyranny of the majority". One is to argue that the presence of a ] protecting the rights of all citizens in many democratic countries acts as a safeguard. Generally, changes in these constitutions require the agreement of a ] of the elected representatives, or require a judge and jury to agree that evidentiary and procedural standards have been fulfilled by the state, or two different votes by the representatives separated by an election, or sometimes a ]. These requirements are often combined. The ] into ], ] and ] also makes it more difficult for a small majority to impose their will. This means a majority can still legitimately coerce a minority (which is still ethically questionable), but such a minority would be very small and as a practical matter it is harder to get a larger proportion of the people to agree to such actions.

Another argument is that majorities and minorities can take a markedly different shape on different issues. People often agree with the majority view on some issues and agree with a minority view on other issues. One's view may also change, thus the members of a majority may limit oppression of a minority since they may well in the future themselves be in a minority.

A third common argument is that despite the risks majority rule is preferable to other systems and the tyranny of the majority is in any case an improvement on a tyranny of a minority. All the possible problems mentioned above can also occur in non-democracies with the added problem that a minority can oppress the majority. Proponents of democracy argue that empirical statistical evidence strongly shows that more democracy leads to less internal violence and mass murder by the government. This is sometimes formulated as ], which states that the less democratic freedom a people have, the more likely their rulers are to murder them.

=== Socialist and Marxist criticism ===
{{main|Democracy in Marxism}}
{{Multiple issues|section=yes|
{{Original research section|date=July 2022}}
{{More citations needed|section|date=April 2023}}
}}

Some socialists, such as ] party in Germany,<ref>{{cite journal|title=Democracy|journal=Left Party in Germany|url=https://www.linksfraktion.de/themen/a-z/detailansicht/demokratie/|access-date=15 December 2017|archive-date=16 December 2017|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171216091214/https://www.linksfraktion.de/themen/a-z/detailansicht/demokratie/|url-status=live}}</ref> say that liberal democracy is a dishonest farce used to keep the masses from realizing that their will is irrelevant in the political process.

] and ], as well as some non-Marxist ] and ], argue that liberal democracy under ] is constitutively ]-based and therefore can never be democratic or ]. They refer to it as "] democracy" because they say that ultimately, politicians fight mainly for the interests of the bourgeoisie.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Segrillo |first=Angelo |date=2012 |title=Liberalism, Marxism and Democratic Theory Revisited: Proposal of a Joint Index of Political and Economic Democracy |url=https://www.scielo.br/j/bpsr/a/6XjtSXLrNpf7nY7qXPFb6FF/?format=pdf |journal=Brazilianpoliticalsciencereview |pages=15}}</ref> As such, liberal democracy is said to represent "the rule of capital".<ref name="Kuttner">Robert Kuttner, , New York Review of Books, November 21, 2019</ref>

According to ], representation of the interests of different classes is proportional to the influence which a particular class can purchase (through bribes, transmission of propaganda through mass media, economic blackmail, donations for political parties and their campaigns and so on). Thus, the public interest in so-called liberal democracies is systematically corrupted by the wealth of those classes rich enough to gain the appearance of representation. Because of this, he said that ] under capitalism are always distorted and anti-democratic, their operation merely furthering the class interests of the owners of the means of production, and the bourgeois class becomes wealthy through a drive to appropriate the ] of the creative labours of the working class. This drive obliges the bourgeois class to amass ever-larger fortunes by increasing the proportion of surplus-value by exploiting the working class through capping workers' terms and conditions as close to poverty levels as possible. Incidentally, this obligation demonstrates the clear limit to bourgeois freedom even for the bourgeoisie itself. According to Marx, parliamentary elections are no more than a cynical, systemic attempt to deceive the people by permitting them, every now and again, to endorse one or other of the bourgeoisie's predetermined choices of which political party can best advocate the interests of capital. Once elected, he said that this parliament, as a dictatorship of the bourgeoisie, enacts regulations that actively support the interests of its true constituency, the bourgeoisie (such as bailing out Wall St investment banks; direct socialisation/subsidisation of business—GMH, US/European ]; and even wars to guarantee trade in commodities such as oil).

] once argued that liberal democracy had simply been used to give an illusion of democracy whilst maintaining the dictatorship of the ], giving as an example the United States's representative democracy which he said consisted of "spectacular and meaningless duels between two bourgeois parties" led by "multimillionaires".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Christopher|first=Rice|title=Lenin: Portrait of a Professional Revolutionary|publisher=Cassell|year=1990|isbn=978-0-304-31814-8|location=London|pages=121}}</ref>

The ] political concept of ] criticizes liberal democracy for excessively relying on procedural formalities without genuinely reflecting the interests of the people.<ref name=":1">{{Cite book |title=CPC Futures The New Era of Socialism with Chinese Characteristics |date=2022 |publisher=] |isbn=978-981-18-5206-0 |editor-last1=Pieke |editor-first1=Frank N |location=Singapore |pages=60–64 |doi=10.56159/eai.52060 |oclc=1354535847 |editor-last2=Hofman |editor-first2=Bert |doi-access=free}}</ref> Under this primarily consequentialist concept, the most important criteria for a democracy is whether it can "solve the people's real problems", while a system in which "the people are awakened only for voting" is not truly democratic.<ref name=":1" /> For example, the Chinese government's 2021 white paper ] criticizes liberal democracy's shortcoming based on principles of whole process people's democracy.<ref>{{Cite web |date=2021-12-04 |title=China criticises US democracy before Biden summit |url=https://www.hindustantimes.com/world-news/china-criticises-us-democracy-before-biden-summit-101638620354714.html |access-date=2023-01-11 |website=] |language=en |archive-date=7 December 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211207212721/https://www.hindustantimes.com/world-news/china-criticises-us-democracy-before-biden-summit-101638620354714.html |url-status=live }}</ref>

===Religion===
{{See also|Religious democracy}}
] is not compatible with democracy or liberalism.<ref name="b584">{{cite journal | last=Fox | first=Jonathan | title=The correlates of religion and state: an introduction | journal=Religion, State and Society | volume=47 | issue=1 | date=2019 | issn=0963-7494 | doi=10.1080/09637494.2018.1529269 | pages=2–9}}</ref> Religious stances on democracy and liberalism vary and can change.<ref name="c993">{{cite journal | last=Minkenberg | first=Michael | title=Democracy and Religion: Theoretical and Empirical Observations on the Relationship between Christianity, Islam and Liberal Democracy | journal=Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies | volume=33 | issue=6 | date=2007 | issn=1369-183X | doi=10.1080/13691830701432731 | pages=887–909}}</ref> The Catholic church opposed liberal democracy until 1965, when ] endorsed religious freedom.<ref name="c993"/> ] which prioritizes non-liberal religious values over liberal values has been criticized for not being a liberal democracy.<ref name="y092">{{cite journal | last=Bader | first=Veit | title=Religious Pluralism: Secularism or Priority for Democracy? | journal=Political Theory | volume=27 | issue=5 | date=1999 | issn=0090-5917 | doi=10.1177/0090591799027005002 | pages=597–633}}</ref>

== Vulnerabilities ==

===Authoritarianism===

Authoritarianism is perceived by many to be a direct threat to the liberalised democracy practised in many countries. According to American political sociologist and authors ], Marc F. Plattner and Christopher Walker, undemocratic regimes are becoming more assertive.<ref>Diamond, Larry; Plattner, Marc F.; Walker, Christopher (2016) 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, Summary. Available at: https://diamond-democracy.stanford.edu/ {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230520051005/https://diamond-democracy.stanford.edu/ |date=20 May 2023 }} </ref> They suggest that liberal democracies introduce more authoritarian measures to counter authoritarianism itself and cite monitoring elections and more control on media in an effort to stop the agenda of undemocratic views. Diamond, Plattner and Walker uses an example of China using aggressive foreign policy against western countries to suggest that a country's society can force another country to behave in a more authoritarian manner. In their book 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' they claim that Beijing confronts the United States by building its navy and missile force and promotes the creation of global institutions designed to exclude American and European influence; as such authoritarian states pose a threat to liberal democracy as they seek to remake the world in their own image.<ref>Diamond, Larry; Plattner, Marc F.; Walker, Christopher (2016) 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, p.23</ref>

Various authors have also analysed the authoritarian means that are used by liberal democracies to defend economic liberalism and the power of political elites.<ref>See for example, Renato Cristi, ''Carl Schmitt and authoritarian liberalism: strong state, free economy'', Cardiff : Univ. of Wales Press, 1998; Michael A. Wilkinson, 'Authoritarian Liberalism as Authoritarian Constitutionalism', in Helena Alviar García, Günter Frankenberg, ''Authoritarian constitutionalism: comparative analysis and critique'', Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing Limited, 2019.</ref>

=== War ===
There are ongoing debates surrounding the effect that war may have on liberal democracy, and whether it cultivates or inhibits democratization.

War may cultivate democratization by "mobilizing the masses, and creating incentives for the state to bargain with the people it needs to contribute to the war effort".<ref name=krebs>Krebs, Ronald R., and Elizabeth Kier. ''In War's Wake : International Conflict and the Fate of Liberal Democracy''. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.</ref> An example of this may be seen in the extension of ] in the UK after ].

War may however inhibit democratization by "providing an excuse for the curtailment of ]".<ref name=krebs/>

=== Terrorism ===
{{globalize|section|date=January 2014}}
Several studies{{citation needed|date=September 2011}} have concluded that terrorism is most common in nations with intermediate ], meaning countries transitioning from autocratic governance to democracy. Nations with strong autocratic governments and governments that allow for more political freedom experience less terrorism.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.news.harvard.edu/gazette/2004/11.04/05-terror.html |title=Harvard Gazette: Freedom squelches terrorist violence |publisher=News.harvard.edu |access-date=2008-10-28 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150919050732/http://news.harvard.edu/gazette/2004/11.04/05-terror.html |archive-date=19 September 2015 }}</ref>

=== Populism ===
{{POV section|date=May 2024}}
{{main|Populism}}

There is no one agreed upon definition of populism, with a broader definition settled upon following a conference at the London School of Economics in 1967.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Berlin |first1=Isiah |last2=Schapiro |first2=Leonard |last3=Deakin |first3=F.W |last4=Seton-Watson |first4=Hugh |last5=Worsley |first5=Peter |last6=Gellner |first6=Ernest |last7=McRae |first7=Donald |title=Conference on Populism 1967 |journal=The London School of Economics |date=1967 |url=http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/id/eprint/102463}}</ref> Academically, the term "populism" faces criticism that it should be abandoned as a descriptor due to its vagueness.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Serhan |first1=Yasmeen |title=Does anyone know what Populism means? Populism is meaningless |url=https://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2020/03/what-is-populism/607600/ |website=The Atlantic |date=14 March 2020 |access-date=2 February 2021 |archive-date=5 April 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230405044353/https://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2020/03/what-is-populism/607600/ |url-status=live }}</ref> It is typically not fundamentally undemocratic, but it is often anti-liberal. Many will agree on certain features that characterize populism and populists: a conflict between 'the people' and 'the elites', with populists siding with 'the people'<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Mudde|first=Cas|date=2013|title=Are Populists Friends or Foes of Constitutionalism?|url=https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:fc657de0-ab0c-4911-8d2b-646101599b65|journal=The Social and Political Foundations of Constitutions|via=ORA|access-date=7 January 2020|archive-date=6 April 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230406024111/https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:fc657de0-ab0c-4911-8d2b-646101599b65|url-status=live}}</ref> and strong disdain for opposition and negative media using labels such as 'fake news'.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Cooke |first1=Nicole |title=Fake News and Alternative Facts : Information Literacy in a Post-Truth Era |date=2018 |publisher=Chicago: ALA Editions |url=https://eds-b-ebscohost-com.uea.idm.oclc.org/eds/detail/detail?vid=0&sid=4fc04e42-38bd-47d8-9e65-381c99e5daf6%40pdc-v-sessmgr02&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWRzLWxpdmUmc2NvcGU9c2l0ZQ%3d%3d#AN=1867933&db=nlebk}}</ref>

Populism is a form of majoritarianism, threatening some of the core principles of liberal democracy such as the rights of the individual. Examples of these can vary from ] via control on immigration, or opposition to liberal social values such as gay marriage.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Fitzgibbon |first1=John |title=Populists are not anti-democratic, they are anti-liberal democracy |journal=London School of Economics |ref=Populism has long been associated with opposition to immigration and liberal social values such as gay marriage. More recently, as they have grown in influence populists have come to focus their opposition to the 'elite' on the range of ancillary institutions and actors – such as the judiciary, media, academia – at the core of liberal democracy.}}</ref> Populists do this by appealing to the feelings and emotions of the people whilst offering solutions - often vastly simplified - to complex problems.

Populism is a particular threat to liberal democracy because it exploits the weaknesses of the liberal democratic system. A key weakness of liberal democracies highlighted in 'How Democracies Die',<ref>{{Cite book|title=How democracies die|last=Levitsky, Steven|others=Ziblatt, Daniel|year=2019|isbn=978-0241381359|location=London|oclc=1084729957}}</ref> is the conundrum that suppressing populist movements or parties can be seen to be illiberal. Also, populism exploits the inherent differences between 'Democracy' and 'Liberalism'.<ref>{{Cite web|title=The Enduring Vulnerability of Liberal Democracy|url=https://www.journalofdemocracy.com/articles/the-enduring-vulnerability-of-liberal-democracy/|access-date=2021-01-25|website=Journal of Democracy|language=en-US|archive-date=24 January 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210124222600/https://journalofdemocracy.com/articles/the-enduring-vulnerability-of-liberal-democracy/|url-status=live}}</ref> For liberal democracy to be effective, a degree of compromise is required<ref>{{Cite book|title=Anti-pluralism : the populist threat to liberal democracy|last=Galston, William A. (William Arthur)|others=Hunter, James Davison, Owen, John M. (John Malloy)|isbn=978-0300235319|location=New Haven|oclc=1026492265|year=2018}}</ref> as protecting the rights of the individual take precedence if they are threatened by the will of the majority, more commonly known as a tyranny of the majority. Majoritarianism is so ingrained in populism that this core value of a liberal democracy is under threat. This therefore brings into question how effectively liberal democracy can defend itself from populism.

According to Takis Papas in his work ''Populism and Liberal Democracy: A Comparative and Theoretical Analysis'', "democracy has two opposites, one liberal, the other populist". Whereas liberalism accepts a notion of society composed of multiple divisions, populism only acknowledges a society of 'the people' versus 'the elites'. The fundamental beliefs of the populist voter consist of: the belief that oneself is powerless and is a victim of the powerful; a "sense of enmity" rooted in "moral indignation and resentfulness"; and a "longing for future redemption" through the actions of a charismatic leader. Papas says this mindset results in a feeling of victimhood caused by the belief that the society is "made up of victims and perpetrators". Other characteristic of a populist voter is that they are "distinctively irrational" because of the "disproportionate role of emotions and morality" when making a political decision like voting. Moreover, through self-deception they are "wilfully ignorant". In addition, they are "intuitively… and unsettlingly principled" rather than a more "pragmatic" liberal voter.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Pappas |first1=Takis |title=Populism and Liberal Democracy: A Comparative and Theoretical Analysis |date=2019 |publisher=Oxford Scholarship Online |page=219 |ref=You are the famed average voter. If one party leader tells you that democracy is about institutions that serve the public good and another tells you that democracy is about the satisfaction of your own rights without regard to institutions, under what conditions will you prefer to rebuff the first leader and cast a vote for the second one? Answer: Unless of course you are a committed altruist, it is more likely that you will rate your individual rights higher than your preference for general institutional order under two conditions: You either are skeptical about the public utility of institutions or you have become convinced about the righteousness and moral superiority of your own individual claims. In both cases, and provided that a significant populist party exists in your country, it is likely that you feel attracted to it. You have a "populist mindset."}}</ref>

An example of a populist movement is ].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Norris |first1=Pippa |title=] |date=February 2019 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |page=368 |ref=The outcome of the Brexit referenda on 23 June 2016 generated international concern about the effects of populist forces, and stunned disbelief from Berlin to Paris that Britain had voted to withdraw from the European Union after more than four decades of membership.1 Brexit has been widely seen as a watershed signaling an end to the era of faith in the benefits of globalization, open labor markets, and European integration.}}</ref> The role of the 'elite' in this circumstance was played by the EU and 'London-centric liberals',<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Dunin-Wasowicz |first1=Roch |title=London Calling Brexit: How the rest of the UK views the capital |journal=London School of Economics |date=November 2018 |ref=Some have blamed an out of touch 'liberal metropolitan elite', overwhelmingly concentrated in London or Westminster, for Brexit and the climate that led to it. These accusations have been most prominent, perhaps ironically, amongst equally 'elite' politicians and commentators in equally powerful positions, often based in London themselves.....Opinion polling has heavily suggested that the British public think that the UK is too centralised in Westminster and Whitehall – and that London benefits from unfair treatment as a result.}}</ref> while the Brexit campaign appealed to workers in industries such as agriculture who were allegedly worse off due to EU membership. This case study also illustrates the potential threat populism can pose to a liberal democracy with the movement heavily relying on disdain for the media. This was done by labeling criticism of Brexit as 'Project Fear'.

== See also ==
{{Wikiquote}}

{{Portal|Freedom of speech|Liberalism}}

{{Colbegin}}
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
{{Colend}}

== References ==
{{Reflist}}

== Further reading ==
{{Library resources box}}

*{{cite journal |last=Shils |first=Edward |title=Some of the Modern Roots of Liberal Democracy |journal=International Journal on World Peace |publisher=Professors World Peace Academy |volume=12 |issue=3 |year=1995 |issn=0742-3640 |jstor=20752038 |pages=3–37 |url=http://www.jstor.org/stable/20752038}}
*{{cite web |website=academic.oup.com |title= The Oxford Handbook of Political Representation in Liberal Democracies |url=https://academic.oup.com/edited-volume/28169/chapter/213008245}}
* Ghasemi, Mehdi. "." SAGE Open, 2019, April–June: 1–6.
* Haas, Michael (2014). ''Deconstructing the 'Democratic Peace': How a Research Agenda Boomeranged''. Los Angeles, CA: Publishinghouse for Scholars. {{ISBN?}}
* Willard, Charles Arthur (1996). ''Liberalism and the Problem of Knowledge: A New Rhetoric for Modern Democracy''. University of Chicago Press. {{ISBN|0226898458|0226898466}}. {{OCLC|33967621}}.

{{Liberalism}}

]
]

Latest revision as of 08:39, 22 November 2024

Form of government

Part of the Politics series
Democracy
Types
Related topics
Region
icon Politics portal
The Eduskunta, the parliament of the Grand Duchy of Finland (then part of Russia), had universal suffrage in 1906. Several states and territories can present arguments for being the first with universal suffrage.

Liberal democracy, western-style democracy, or substantive democracy is a form of government that combines the organization of a democracy with ideas of liberal political philosophy.

Common elements within a liberal democracy are: elections between or among multiple distinct political parties, a separation of powers into different branches of government, the rule of law in everyday life as part of an open society, a market economy with private property, universal suffrage, and the equal protection of human rights, civil rights, civil liberties, and political freedoms for all citizens. Substantive democracy refers to substantive rights and substantive laws, which can include substantive equality, the equality of outcome for subgroups in society. Liberal democracy emphasizes the separation of powers, an independent judiciary, and a system of checks and balances between branches of government. Multi-party systems with at least two persistent, viable political parties are characteristic of liberal democracies.

Governmental authority is legitimately exercised only in accordance with written, publicly disclosed laws adopted and enforced in accordance with established procedure. To define the system in practice, liberal democracies often draw upon a constitution, either codified or uncodified, to delineate the powers of government and enshrine the social contract. A liberal democracy may take various and mixed constitutional forms: it may be a constitutional monarchy or a republic. It may have a parliamentary system, presidential system, or semi-presidential system. Liberal democracies are contrasted with illiberal democracies and dictatorships. Some liberal democracies, especially those with large populations, use federalism (also known as vertical separation of powers) in order to prevent abuse and increase public input by dividing governing powers between municipal, provincial and national governments. The characteristics of liberal democracies are correlated with increased political stability, lower corruption, better management of resources, and better health indicators such as life expectancy and infant mortality. Liberal democracy traces its origins—and its name—to the Age of Enlightenment. The conventional views supporting monarchies and aristocracies were challenged at first by a relatively small group of Enlightenment intellectuals, who believed that human affairs should be guided by reason and principles of liberty and equality. They argued that all people are created equal, that governments exist to serve the people—not vice versa—and that laws should apply to those who govern as well as to the governed (a concept known as rule of law), formulated in Europe as Rechtsstaat. Some of these ideas began to be expressed in England in the 17th century. By the late 18th century, leading philosophers such as John Locke had published works that spread around the European continent and beyond. These ideas and beliefs influenced the American Revolution and the French Revolution. After a period of expansion in the second half of the 20th century, liberal democracy became a prevalent political system in the world.

Origins

See also: History of liberalism and History of democracy
John Locke was the first to develop a liberal philosophy as he coherently described the elementary principles of the liberal movement, such as the right to private property and the consent of the governed.
The Agreement of the People (1647), a manifesto for political change proposed by the Levellers during the English Civil War, called for freedom of religion, frequent convening of Parliament and equality under the law

Liberal democracy traces its origins—and its name—to 18th-century Europe, during the Age of Enlightenment. At the time, the vast majority of European states were monarchies, with political power held either by the monarch or the aristocracy. The possibility of democracy had not been a seriously considered political theory since classical antiquity and the widely held belief was that democracies would be inherently unstable and chaotic in their policies due to the changing whims of the people. It was further believed that democracy was contrary to human nature, as human beings were seen to be inherently evil, violent and in need of a strong leader to restrain their destructive impulses. Many European monarchs held that their power had been ordained by God and that questioning their right to rule was tantamount to blasphemy.

These conventional views were challenged at first by a relatively small group of Enlightenment intellectuals, who believed that human affairs should be guided by reason and principles of liberty and equality. They argued that all people are created equal and therefore political authority cannot be justified on the basis of noble blood, a supposed privileged connection to God or any other characteristic that is alleged to make one person superior to others. They further argued that governments exist to serve the people—not vice versa—and that laws should apply to those who govern as well as to the governed (a concept known as rule of law).

Some of these ideas began to be expressed in England in the 17th century. There was renewed interest in Magna Carta, and passage of the Petition of Right in 1628 and Habeas Corpus Act in 1679 established certain liberties for subjects. The idea of a political party took form with groups debating rights to political representation during the Putney Debates of 1647. After the English Civil Wars (1642–1651) and the Glorious Revolution of 1688, the Bill of Rights was enacted in 1689, which codified certain rights and liberties. The Bill set out the requirement for regular elections, rules for freedom of speech in Parliament and limited the power of the monarch, ensuring that, unlike almost all of Europe at the time, royal absolutism would not prevail. This led to significant social change in Britain in terms of the position of individuals in society and the growing power of Parliament in relation to the monarch.

By the late 18th century, leading philosophers of the day had published works that spread around the European continent and beyond. One of the most influential of these philosophers was English empiricist John Locke, who refuted monarchical absolutism in his Two Treatises of Government. According to Locke, individuals entered into a social contract with a state, surrendering some of their liberties in exchange for the protection of their natural rights. Locke advanced that governments were only legitimate if they maintained the consent of the governed and that citizens had the right to instigate a rebellion against their government if that government acted against their interests. These ideas and beliefs influenced the American Revolution and the French Revolution, which gave birth to the philosophy of liberalism and instituted forms of government that attempted to put the principles of the Enlightenment philosophers into practice.

When the first prototypical liberal democracies were founded, the liberals themselves were viewed as an extreme and rather dangerous fringe group that threatened international peace and stability. The conservative monarchists who opposed liberalism and democracy saw themselves as defenders of traditional values and the natural order of things and their criticism of democracy seemed vindicated when Napoleon Bonaparte took control of the young French Republic, reorganized it into the first French Empire and proceeded to conquer most of Europe. Napoleon was eventually defeated and the Holy Alliance was formed in Europe to prevent any further spread of liberalism or democracy. However, liberal democratic ideals soon became widespread among the general population and over the 19th century traditional monarchy was forced on a continuous defensive and withdrawal. The Dominions of the British Empire became laboratories for liberal democracy from the mid 19th century onward. In Canada, responsible government began in the 1840s and in Australia and New Zealand, parliamentary government elected by male suffrage and secret ballot was established from the 1850s and female suffrage achieved from the 1890s.

K. J. Ståhlberg (1865–1952), the first President of the Republic of Finland, defined Finland's anchoring as a country defending liberal democracy. Ståhlberg at his office in 1919.

Reforms and revolutions helped move most European countries towards liberal democracy. Liberalism ceased being a fringe opinion and joined the political mainstream. At the same time, a number of non-liberal ideologies developed that took the concept of liberal democracy and made it their own. The political spectrum changed; traditional monarchy became more and more a fringe view and liberal democracy became more and more mainstream. By the end of the 19th century, liberal democracy was no longer only a liberal idea, but an idea supported by many different ideologies. After World War I and especially after World War II, liberal democracy achieved a dominant position among theories of government and is now endorsed by the vast majority of the political spectrum.

Although liberal democracy was originally put forward by Enlightenment liberals, the relationship between democracy and liberalism has been controversial since the beginning and was problematized in the 20th century. In his book Freedom and Equality in a Liberal Democratic State, Jasper Doomen posited that freedom and equality are necessary for a liberal democracy. In his book The End of History and the Last Man, Francis Fukuyama says that since the French Revolution, liberal democracy has repeatedly proven to be a fundamentally better system (ethically, politically, economically) than any of the alternatives, and that democracy will become more and more prevalent in the long term, although it may suffer temporary setbacks. The research institute Freedom House today simply defines liberal democracy as an electoral democracy also protecting civil liberties.

Rights and freedoms

Main articles: Political freedom and Democracy and human rights

Political freedom is a central concept in history and political thought and one of the most important features of democratic societies. Political freedom was described as freedom from oppression or coercion, the absence of disabling conditions for an individual and the fulfillment of enabling conditions, or the absence of life conditions of compulsion, e.g. economic compulsion, in a society. Although political freedom is often interpreted negatively as the freedom from unreasonable external constraints on action, it can also refer to the positive exercise of rights, capacities and possibilities for action and the exercise of social or group rights. The concept can also include freedom from internal constraints on political action or speech (e.g. social conformity, consistency, or inauthentic behaviour). The concept of political freedom is closely connected with the concepts of civil liberties and human rights, which in democratic societies are usually afforded legal protection from the state.

Laws in liberal democracies may limit certain freedoms. The common justification for these limits is that they are necessary to guarantee the existence of democracy, or the existence of the freedoms themselves. For example, democratic governments may impose restrictions on free speech, with examples including Holocaust denial and hate speech. Some discriminatory behavior may be prohibited. For example, public accommodations in the United States may not discriminate on the basis of "race, color, religion, or national origin." There are various legal limitations such as copyright and laws against defamation. There may be limits on anti-democratic speech, on attempts to undermine human rights and on the promotion or justification of terrorism. In the United States more than in Europe, during the Cold War such restrictions applied to communists. Now they are more commonly applied to organizations perceived as promoting terrorism or the incitement of group hatred. Examples include anti-terrorism legislation, the shutting down of Hezbollah satellite broadcasts and some laws against hate speech. Critics claim that these limitations may go too far and that there may be no due and fair judicial process. Opinion is divided on how far democracy can extend to include the enemies of democracy in the democratic process. If relatively small numbers of people are excluded from such freedoms for these reasons, a country may still be seen as a liberal democracy. Some argue that this is only quantitatively (not qualitatively) different from autocracies that persecute opponents, since only a small number of people are affected and the restrictions are less severe, but others emphasize that democracies are different. At least in theory, opponents of democracy are also allowed due process under the rule of law.

Since it is possible to disagree over which rights are considered fundamental, different countries may treat particular rights in different ways. For example:

  • The constitutions of Canada, India, Israel, Mexico and the United States guarantee freedom from double jeopardy, a right not provided in some other legal systems.
  • Legal systems that use politically elected court jurors, such as Sweden, view a (partly) politicized court system as a main component of accountable government. Other democracies employ trial by jury with the intent of shielding against the influence of politicians over trials.

Liberal democracies usually have universal suffrage, granting all adult citizens the right to vote regardless of ethnicity, sex, property ownership, race, age, sexuality, gender, income, social status, or religion. However, historically some countries regarded as liberal democracies have had a more limited franchise. Even today, some countries, considered to be liberal democracies, do not have truly universal suffrage. In some countries, members of political organizations with connections to historical totalitarian governments (for example formerly predominant communist, fascist or Nazi governments in some European countries) may be deprived of the vote and the privilege of holding certain jobs. In the United Kingdom people serving long prison sentences are unable to vote, a policy which has been ruled a human rights violation by the European Court of Human Rights. A similar policy is also enacted in most of the United States. According to a study by Coppedge and Reinicke, at least 85% of democracies provided for universal suffrage. Many nations require positive identification before allowing people to vote. For example, in the United States two thirds of the states require their citizens to provide identification to vote, which also provide state IDs for free. The decisions made through elections are made by those who are members of the electorate and who choose to participate by voting.

In 1971, Robert Dahl summarized the fundamental rights and freedoms shared by all liberal democracies as eight rights:

  1. Freedom to form and join organizations.
  2. Freedom of expression.
  3. Right to vote.
  4. Right to run for public office.
  5. Right of political leaders to compete for support and votes.
  6. Freedom of alternative sources of information
  7. Free and fair elections.
  8. Right to control government policy through votes and other expressions of preference.

Preconditions

For a political regime to be considered a liberal democracy it must contain in its governing over a nation-state the provision of civil rights- the non-discrimination in the provision of public goods such as justice, security, education and health- in addition to, political rights- the guarantee of free and fair electoral contests, which allow the winners of such contests to determine policy subject to the constraints established by other rights, when these are provided- and property rights- which protect asset holders and investors against expropriation by the state or other groups. In this way, liberal democracy is set apart from electoral democracy, as free and fair elections – the hallmark of electoral democracy – can be separated from equal treatment and non-discrimination – the hallmarks of liberal democracy. In liberal democracy, an elected government cannot discriminate against specific individuals or groups when it administers justice, protects basic rights such as freedom of assembly and free speech, provides for collective security, or distributes economic and social benefits. According to Seymour Martin Lipset, although they are not part of the system of government as such, a modicum of individual and economic freedoms, which result in the formation of a significant middle class and a broad and flourishing civil society, are seen as pre-conditions for liberal democracy.

For countries without a strong tradition of democratic majority rule, the introduction of free elections alone has rarely been sufficient to achieve a transition from dictatorship to democracy; a wider shift in the political culture and gradual formation of the institutions of democratic government are needed. There are various examples—for instance, in Latin America—of countries that were able to sustain democracy only temporarily or in a limited fashion until wider cultural changes established the conditions under which democracy could flourish.

One of the key aspects of democratic culture is the concept of a loyal opposition, where political competitors may disagree, but they must tolerate one another and acknowledge the legitimate and important roles that each play. This is an especially difficult cultural shift to achieve in nations where transitions of power have historically taken place through violence. The term means in essence that all sides in a democracy share a common commitment to its basic values. The ground rules of the society must encourage tolerance and civility in public debate. In such a society, the losers accept the judgement of the voters when the election is over and allow for the peaceful transfer of power. According to Cas Mudde and Cristóbal Rovira, this is tied to another key concept of democratic cultures, the protection of minorities, where the losers are safe in the knowledge that they will neither lose their lives nor their liberty and will continue to participate in public life. They are loyal not to the specific policies of the government, but to the fundamental legitimacy of the state and to the democratic process itself.

One requirement of liberal democracy is political equality amongst voters (ensuring that all voices and all votes count equally) and that these can properly influence government policy, requiring quality procedure and quality content of debate that provides an accountable result, this may apply within elections or to procedures between elections. This requires universal, adult suffrage; recurring, free elections, competitive and fair elections; multiple political parties and a wide variety of information so that citizens can rationally and effectively put pressure onto the government, including that it can be checked, evaluated and removed. This can include or lead to accountability, responsiveness to the desires of citizens, the rule of law, full respect of rights and implementation of political, social and economic freedom. Other liberal democracies consider the requirement of minority rights and preventing tyranny of the majority. One of the most common ways is by actively preventing discrimination by the government (bill of rights) but can also include requiring concurrent majorities in several constituencies (confederalism); guaranteeing regional government (federalism); broad coalition governments (consociationalism) or negotiating with other political actors, such as pressure groups (neocorporatism). These split political power amongst many competing and cooperating actors and institutions by requiring the government to respect minority groups and give them their positive freedoms, negotiate across multiple geographical areas, become more centrist among cooperative parties and open up with new social groups.

In a new study published in Nature Human Behaviour, Damian J. Ruck and his co-authors take a major step toward resolving this long-standing and seemingly irresolvable debate about whether culture shapes regimes or regimes shape culture. This study resolves the debate in favor of culture's causal primacy and shows that it is the civic and emancipative values (liberty, impartiality and contractarianism) among a country's citizens that give rise to democratic institutions, not vice versa.

Liberal democracies around the world

Further information: List of democracy indices
  Countries and regions designated electoral democracies in Freedom House's Freedom in the World 2023 survey, covering the year 2022
Map reflecting the findings of Freedom House's 2022 survey concerning the state of freedom by country / region in 2021. The concept of freedom used in the survey is closely connected to liberal democracy.   Free   Partly free   Not free
Percentage of countries in each category from Freedom House's 1973 through 2021 reports:   Free   Partly free   Not free   Electoral democracies

Several organizations and political scientists maintain lists of free and unfree states, both in the present and going back a couple centuries. Of these, the best known may be the Polity Data Set and that produced by Freedom House and Larry Diamond.

There is agreement amongst several intellectuals and organizations such as Freedom House that the states of the European Union (with the exception of Poland and Hungary), United Kingdom, Norway, Iceland, Switzerland, Japan, Argentina, Brazil, Chile, South Korea, Taiwan, United States, India, Canada, Uruguay, Costa Rica, Israel, South Africa, Australia, and New Zealand are liberal democracies. Liberal democracies are susceptible to democratic backsliding and this is taking place or has taken place in several countries, including, but not limited to, the United States, Poland, Hungary, and Israel.

Freedom House considers many of the officially democratic governments in Africa and the former Soviet Union to be undemocratic in practice, usually because the sitting government has a strong influence over election outcomes. Many of these countries are in a state of considerable flux.

Officially non-democratic forms of government, such as single-party states and dictatorships, are more common in East Asia, the Middle East and North Africa.

The 2019 Freedom in the World report noted a fall in the number of countries with liberal democracies over the 13 years from 2005 to 2018, citing declines in 'political rights and civil liberties'. The 2020 and 2021 reports document further reductions in the number of free countries in the world.

Types

This section does not cite any sources. Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (August 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Proportional vs. plurality representation

Plurality voting system award seats according to regional majorities. The political party or individual candidate who receives the most votes, wins the seat which represents that locality. There are other democratic electoral systems, such as the various forms of proportional representation, which award seats according to the proportion of individual votes that a party receives nationwide or in a particular region.

One of the main points of contention between these two systems is whether to have representatives who are able to effectively represent specific regions in a country, or to have all citizens' vote count the same, regardless of where in the country they happen to live.

Some countries, such as Germany and New Zealand, address the conflict between these two forms of representation by having two categories of seats in the lower house of their national legislative bodies. The first category of seats is appointed according to regional popularity and the remainder are awarded to give the parties a proportion of seats that is equal—or as equal as practicable—to their proportion of nationwide votes. This system is commonly called mixed member proportional representation.

The Australian Government incorporates both systems in having the preferential voting system applicable to the lower house and proportional representation by state in the upper house. This system is argued to result in a more stable government, while having a better diversity of parties to review its actions. The various state and territory governments in Australia employ a range of a different electoral systems.

Presidential vs. parliamentary systems

A presidential system is a system of government of a republic in which the executive branch is elected separately from the legislative. A parliamentary system is distinguished by the executive branch of government being dependent on the direct or indirect support of the parliament, often expressed through a vote of confidence.

The presidential system of democratic government has been adopted in Latin America, Africa and parts of the former Soviet Union, largely by the example of the United States. Constitutional monarchies (dominated by elected parliaments) are present in Northern Europe and some former colonies which peacefully separated, such as Australia and Canada. Others have also arisen in Spain, East Asia and a variety of small nations around the world. Former British territories such as South Africa, India, Ireland and the United States opted for different forms at the time of independence. The parliamentary system is widely used in the European Union and neighbouring countries.

Impact on economic growth

Recent academic studies have found that democratisation is beneficial for national growth. However, the effect of democratisation has not been studied as yet. The most common factors that determine whether a country's economy grows or not are the country's level of development and the educational level of its newly elected democratic leaders. As a result, there is no clear indication of how to determine which factors contribute to economic growth in a democratic country.

However, there is disagreement regarding how much credit the democratic system can take for this growth. One observation is that democracy became widespread only after the Industrial Revolution and the introduction of capitalism. On the other hand, the Industrial Revolution started in England which was one of the most democratic nations for its time within its own borders, but this democracy was very limited and did not apply to the colonies which contributed significantly to the wealth.

Several statistical studies support the theory that a higher degree of economic freedom, as measured with one of the several Indices of Economic Freedom which have been used in numerous studies, increases economic growth and that this in turn increases general prosperity, reduces poverty and causes democratisation. This is a statistical tendency and there are individual exceptions like Mali, which is ranked as "Free" by Freedom House, but is a Least Developed Country, or Qatar, which has arguably the highest GDP per capita in the world, but has never been democratic. There are also other studies suggesting that more democracy increases economic freedom, although a few find no or even a small negative effect.

Some argue that economic growth due to its empowerment of citizens will ensure a transition to democracy in countries such as Cuba. However, other dispute this and even if economic growth has caused democratisation in the past, it may not do so in the future. Dictators may now have learned how to have economic growth without this causing more political freedom.

A high degree of oil or mineral exports is strongly associated with nondemocratic rule. This effect applies worldwide and not only to the Middle East. Dictators who have this form of wealth can spend more on their security apparatus and provide benefits which lessen public unrest. Also, such wealth is not followed by the social and cultural changes that may transform societies with ordinary economic growth.

A 2006 meta-analysis found that democracy has no direct effect on economic growth. However, it has strong and significant indirect effects which contribute to growth. Democracy is associated with higher human capital accumulation, lower inflation, lower political instability and higher economic freedom. There is also some evidence that it is associated with larger governments and more restrictions on international trade.

If leaving out East Asia, then during the last forty-five years poor democracies have grown their economies 50% more rapidly than nondemocracies. Poor democracies such as the Baltic countries, Botswana, Costa Rica, Ghana and Senegal have grown more rapidly than nondemocracies such as Angola, Syria, Uzbekistan and Zimbabwe.

Of the eighty worst financial catastrophes during the last four decades, only five were in democracies. Similarly, poor democracies are half likely as non-democracies to experience a 10 per cent decline in GDP per capita over the course of a single year.

Justifications and support

Increased political stability

Several key features of liberal democracies are associated with political stability, including economic growth, as well as robust state institutions that guarantee free elections, the rule of law, and individual liberties.

One argument for democracy is that by creating a system where the public can remove administrations, without changing the legal basis for government, democracy aims at reducing political uncertainty and instability and assuring citizens that however much they may disagree with present policies, they will be given a regular chance to change those who are in power, or change policies with which they disagree. This is preferable to a system where political change takes place through violence.

One notable feature of liberal democracies is that their opponents (those groups who wish to abolish liberal democracy) rarely win elections. Advocates use this as an argument to support their view that liberal democracy is inherently stable and can usually only be overthrown by external force, while opponents argue that the system is inherently stacked against them despite its claims to impartiality. In the past, it was feared that democracy could be easily exploited by leaders with dictatorial aspirations, who could get themselves elected into power. However, the actual number of liberal democracies that have elected dictators into power is low. When it has occurred, it is usually after a major crisis has caused many people to doubt the system or in young/poorly functioning democracies. Some possible examples include Adolf Hitler during the Great Depression and Napoleon III, who became first President of the Second French Republic and later Emperor.

Effective response in wartime

By definition, a liberal democracy implies that power is not concentrated. One criticism is that this could be a disadvantage for a state in wartime, when a fast and unified response is necessary. The legislature usually must give consent before the start of an offensive military operation, although sometimes the executive can do this on its own while keeping the legislature informed. If the democracy is attacked, then no consent is usually required for defensive operations. The people may vote against a conscription army.

However, actual research shows that democracies are more likely to win wars than non-democracies. One explanation attributes this primarily to "the transparency of the polities, and the stability of their preferences, once determined, democracies are better able to cooperate with their partners in the conduct of wars". Other research attributes this to superior mobilisation of resources or selection of wars that the democratic states have a high chance of winning.

Stam and Reiter also note that the emphasis on individuality within democratic societies means that their soldiers fight with greater initiative and superior leadership. Officers in dictatorships are often selected for political loyalty rather than military ability. They may be exclusively selected from a small class or religious/ethnic group that support the regime. The leaders in nondemocracies may respond violently to any perceived criticisms or disobedience. This may make the soldiers and officers afraid to raise any objections or do anything without explicit authorisation. The lack of initiative may be particularly detrimental in modern warfare. Enemy soldiers may more easily surrender to democracies since they can expect comparatively good treatment. In contrast, Nazi Germany killed almost 2/3 of the captured Soviet soldiers and 38% of the American soldiers captured by North Korea in the Korean War were killed.

Better information on and corrections of problems

A democratic system may provide better information for policy decisions. Undesirable information may more easily be ignored in dictatorships, even if this undesirable or contrarian information provides early warning of problems. Anders Chydenius put forward the argument for freedom of the press for this reason in 1776. The democratic system also provides a way to replace inefficient leaders and policies, thus problems may continue longer and crises of all kinds may be more common in autocracies.

Reduction of corruption

Research by the World Bank suggests that political institutions are extremely important in determining the prevalence of corruption: (long term) democracy, parliamentary systems, political stability and freedom of the press are all associated with lower corruption. Freedom of information legislation is important for accountability and transparency. The Indian Right to Information Act "has already engendered mass movements in the country that is bringing the lethargic, often corrupt bureaucracy to its knees and changing power equations completely".

Better use of resources

Democracies can put in place better education, longer life expectancy, lower infant mortality, access to drinking water and better health care than dictatorships. This is not due to higher levels of foreign assistance or spending a larger percentage of GDP on health and education, as instead the available resources are managed better.

Prominent economist Amartya Sen has noted that no functioning democracy has ever suffered a large scale famine. Refugee crises almost always occur in non-democracies. From 1985 to 2008, the eighty-seven largest refugee crises occurred in autocracies.

Health and human development

Democracy correlates with a higher score on the Human Development Index and a lower score on the human poverty index.

Several health indicators (life expectancy and infant and maternal mortality) have a stronger and more significant association with democracy than they have with GDP per capita, rise of the public sector or income inequality.

In the post-communist nations, after an initial decline those that are the most democratic have achieved the greatest gains in life expectancy.

Democratic peace theory

Main article: Democratic peace theory

Numerous studies using many different kinds of data, definitions and statistical analyses have found support for the democratic peace theory. The original finding was that liberal democracies have never made war with one another. More recent research has extended the theory and finds that democracies have few militarized interstate disputes causing less than 1,000 battle deaths with one another, that those militarized interstate disputes that have occurred between democracies have caused few deaths and that democracies have few civil wars. There are various criticisms of the theory, including at least as many refutations as alleged proofs of the theory, some 200 deviant cases, failure to treat democracy as a multidimensional concept and that correlation is not causation.

Minimization of political violence

Rudolph Rummel's Power Kills says that liberal democracy, among all types of regimes, minimizes political violence and is a method of nonviolence. Rummel attributes this firstly to democracy instilling an attitude of tolerance of differences, an acceptance of losing and a positive outlook towards conciliation and compromise.

A study published by the British Academy, on Violence and Democracy, argues that in practice, liberal democracy has not stopped those running the state from exerting acts of violence both within and outside their borders. The paper also argues that police killings, profiling of racial and religious minorities, online surveillance, data collection, or media censorship are a couple of ways in which successful states maintain a monopoly on violence.

Objections and criticism

See also: Criticism of democracy

Campaign costs

In Athenian democracy, some public offices were randomly allocated to citizens, in order to inhibit the effects of plutocracy. Aristotle described the law courts in Athens which were selected by lot as democratic and described elections as oligarchic.

Political campaigning in representative democracies can favor the rich due to campaign costs, a form of plutocracy where only a very small number of wealthy individuals can actually affect government policy in their favor and toward plutonomy. Stringent campaign finance laws can correct this perceived problem.

Other studies predicted that the global trend toward plutonomies would continue, for various reasons, including "capitalist-friendly governments and tax regimes". However, they also say that, since "political enfranchisement remains as was—one person, one vote, at some point it is likely that labor will fight back against the rising profit share of the rich and there will be a political backlash against the rising wealth of the rich."

Economist Steven Levitt says in his book Freakonomics that campaign spending is no guarantee of electoral success. He compared electoral success of the same pair of candidates running against one another repeatedly for the same job, as often happens in United States congressional elections, where spending levels varied. He concludes:

A winning candidate can cut his spending in half and lose only 1 percent of the vote. Meanwhile, a losing candidate who doubles his spending can expect to shift the vote in his favor by only that same 1 percent.

On September 18, 2014, Martin Gilens and Benjamin I. Page's study concluded "Multivariate analysis indicates that economic elites and organized groups representing business interests have substantial independent impacts on U.S. government policy, while average citizens and mass-based interest groups have little or no independent influence. The results provide substantial support for theories of Economic-Elite Domination and for theories of Biased Pluralism, but not for theories of Majoritarian Electoral Democracy or Majoritarian Pluralism."

Media

Critics of the role of the media in liberal democracies allege that concentration of media ownership leads to major distortions of democratic processes. In Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media, Edward S. Herman and Noam Chomsky argue via their Propaganda Model that the corporate media limits the availability of contesting views and assert this creates a narrow spectrum of elite opinion. This is a natural consequence, they say, of the close ties between powerful corporations and the media and thus limited and restricted to the explicit views of those who can afford it. Furthermore, the media's negative influence can be seen in social media where vast numbers of individuals seek their political information which is not always correct and may be controlled. For example, as of 2017, two-thirds (67%) of Americans report that they get at least some of their news from social media, as well as a rising number of countries are exercising extreme control over the flow of information. This may contribute to large numbers of individuals using social media platforms but not always gaining correct political information. This may cause conflict with liberal democracy and some of its core principles, such as freedom, if individuals are not entirely free since their governments are seizing that level of control on media sites. The notion that the media is used to indoctrinate the public is also shared by Yascha Mounk's The People Vs Democracy which states that the government benefits from the public having a relatively similar worldview and that this one-minded ideal is one of the principles in which Liberal Democracy stands.

Defenders responding to such arguments say that constitutionally protected freedom of speech makes it possible for both for-profit and non-profit organisations to debate the issues. They argue that media coverage in democracies simply reflects public preferences and does not entail censorship. Especially with new forms of media such as the Internet, it is not expensive to reach a wide audience, if an interest in the ideas presented exists.

Limited voter turnout

Further information: Voter turnout

Low voter turnout, whether the cause is disenchantment, indifference or contentment with the status quo, may be seen as a problem, especially if disproportionate in particular segments of the population. Although turnout levels vary greatly among modern democratic countries and in various types and levels of elections within countries, at some point low turnout may prompt questions as to whether the results reflect the will of the people, whether the causes may be indicative of concerns to the society in question, or in extreme cases the legitimacy of the electoral system.

Get out the vote campaigns, either by governments or private groups, may increase voter turnout, but distinctions must be made between general campaigns to raise the turnout rate and partisan efforts to aid a particular candidate, party or cause. Other alternatives include increased use of absentee ballots, or other measures to ease or improve the ability to vote, including electronic voting.

Several nations have forms of compulsory voting, with various degrees of enforcement. Proponents argue that this increases the legitimacy—and thus also popular acceptance—of the elections and ensures political participation by all those affected by the political process and reduces the costs associated with encouraging voting. Arguments against include restriction of freedom, economic costs of enforcement, increased number of invalid and blank votes and random voting.

Bureaucracy

A persistent libertarian and monarchist critique of democracy is the claim that it encourages the elected representatives to change the law without necessity and in particular to pour forth a flood of new laws, as described in Herbert Spencer's The Man Versus The State. This is seen as pernicious in several ways. New laws constrict the scope of what were previously private liberties. Rapidly changing laws make it difficult for a willing non-specialist to remain law-abiding. This may be an invitation for law-enforcement agencies to misuse power. The claimed continual complication of the law may be contrary to a claimed simple and eternal natural law—although there is no consensus on what this natural law is, even among advocates. Supporters of democracy point to the complex bureaucracy and regulations that has occurred in dictatorships, like many of the former communist states.

The bureaucracy in liberal democracies is often criticised for a claimed slowness and complexity of their decision-making. The term "red tape" is a synonym of slow bureaucratic functioning that hinders quick results in a liberal democracy.

Short-term focus

By definition, modern liberal democracies allow for regular changes of government. That has led to a common criticism of their short-term focus. In four or five years the government will face a new election and it must think of how it will win that election. That would encourage a preference for policies that will bring short term benefits to the electorate (or to self-interested politicians) before the next election, rather than unpopular policy with longer term benefits. This criticism assumes that it is possible to make long term predictions for a society, something Karl Popper has criticised as historicism.

Besides the regular review of governing entities, short-term focus in a democracy could also be the result of collective short-term thinking. For example, consider a campaign for policies aimed at reducing environmental damage while causing temporary increase in unemployment. However, this risk applies also to other political systems.

Majoritarianism

Main articles: Majority rule and Tyranny of the majority
This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Liberal democracy" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (August 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

The tyranny of the majority is the fear that a direct democratic government, reflecting the majority view, can take action that oppresses a particular minority. For instance, a minority holding wealth, property ownership or power (see Federalist No. 10), or a minority of a certain racial and ethnic origin, class or nationality. Theoretically, the majority is a majority of all citizens. If citizens are not compelled by law to vote, it is usually a majority of those who choose to vote. If such of group constitutes a minority, then it is possible that a minority could in theory oppress another minority in the name of the majority. However, such an argument could apply to both direct democracy or representative democracy. Several de facto dictatorships also have compulsory, but not "free and fair" voting in order to try to increase the legitimacy of the regime, such as North Korea.

In her book World on Fire, Yale Law School professor Amy Chua posits that "when free market democracy is pursued in the presence of a market-dominant minority, the almost invariable result is backlash. This backlash typically takes one of three forms. The first is a backlash against markets, targeting the market-dominant minority's wealth. The second is a backlash against democracy by forces favorable to the market-dominant minority. The third is violence, sometimes genocidal, directed against the market-dominant minority itself".

Cases that have been cited as examples of a minority being oppressed by or in the name of the majority include the practice of conscription and laws against homosexuality, pornography, and recreational drug use. Homosexual acts were widely criminalised in democracies until several decades ago and in some democracies like Ghana, Kenya, Tanzania, Tunisia, Nigeria, and Malaysia, they still are, reflecting the religious or sexual mores of the majority. The Athenian democracy and the early United States practiced slavery, and even proponents of liberal democracy in the 17th and 18th century were often pro-slavery, which is contradictory of a liberal democracy. Another often quoted example of the "tyranny of the majority" is that Adolf Hitler came to power by "legitimate" democratic procedures. The Nazi Party gained the largest share of votes in the democratic Weimar Republic in 1933. However, his regime's large-scale human rights violations took place after the democratic system had been abolished. Furthermore, the Weimar Constitution in an "emergency" allowed dictatorial powers and suspension of the essentials of the constitution itself without any vote or election.

Proponents of democracy make a number of defenses concerning "tyranny of the majority". One is to argue that the presence of a constitution protecting the rights of all citizens in many democratic countries acts as a safeguard. Generally, changes in these constitutions require the agreement of a supermajority of the elected representatives, or require a judge and jury to agree that evidentiary and procedural standards have been fulfilled by the state, or two different votes by the representatives separated by an election, or sometimes a referendum. These requirements are often combined. The separation of powers into legislative branch, executive branch and judicial branch also makes it more difficult for a small majority to impose their will. This means a majority can still legitimately coerce a minority (which is still ethically questionable), but such a minority would be very small and as a practical matter it is harder to get a larger proportion of the people to agree to such actions.

Another argument is that majorities and minorities can take a markedly different shape on different issues. People often agree with the majority view on some issues and agree with a minority view on other issues. One's view may also change, thus the members of a majority may limit oppression of a minority since they may well in the future themselves be in a minority.

A third common argument is that despite the risks majority rule is preferable to other systems and the tyranny of the majority is in any case an improvement on a tyranny of a minority. All the possible problems mentioned above can also occur in non-democracies with the added problem that a minority can oppress the majority. Proponents of democracy argue that empirical statistical evidence strongly shows that more democracy leads to less internal violence and mass murder by the government. This is sometimes formulated as Rummel's Law, which states that the less democratic freedom a people have, the more likely their rulers are to murder them.

Socialist and Marxist criticism

Main article: Democracy in Marxism
This section has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these messages)
This section possibly contains original research. Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations. Statements consisting only of original research should be removed. (July 2022) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Liberal democracy" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (April 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
(Learn how and when to remove this message)

Some socialists, such as The Left party in Germany, say that liberal democracy is a dishonest farce used to keep the masses from realizing that their will is irrelevant in the political process.

Marxists and communists, as well as some non-Marxist socialists and anarchists, argue that liberal democracy under capitalism is constitutively class-based and therefore can never be democratic or participatory. They refer to it as "bourgeois democracy" because they say that ultimately, politicians fight mainly for the interests of the bourgeoisie. As such, liberal democracy is said to represent "the rule of capital".

According to Karl Marx, representation of the interests of different classes is proportional to the influence which a particular class can purchase (through bribes, transmission of propaganda through mass media, economic blackmail, donations for political parties and their campaigns and so on). Thus, the public interest in so-called liberal democracies is systematically corrupted by the wealth of those classes rich enough to gain the appearance of representation. Because of this, he said that multi-party democracies under capitalism are always distorted and anti-democratic, their operation merely furthering the class interests of the owners of the means of production, and the bourgeois class becomes wealthy through a drive to appropriate the surplus-value of the creative labours of the working class. This drive obliges the bourgeois class to amass ever-larger fortunes by increasing the proportion of surplus-value by exploiting the working class through capping workers' terms and conditions as close to poverty levels as possible. Incidentally, this obligation demonstrates the clear limit to bourgeois freedom even for the bourgeoisie itself. According to Marx, parliamentary elections are no more than a cynical, systemic attempt to deceive the people by permitting them, every now and again, to endorse one or other of the bourgeoisie's predetermined choices of which political party can best advocate the interests of capital. Once elected, he said that this parliament, as a dictatorship of the bourgeoisie, enacts regulations that actively support the interests of its true constituency, the bourgeoisie (such as bailing out Wall St investment banks; direct socialisation/subsidisation of business—GMH, US/European agricultural subsidies; and even wars to guarantee trade in commodities such as oil).

Vladimir Lenin once argued that liberal democracy had simply been used to give an illusion of democracy whilst maintaining the dictatorship of the bourgeoisie, giving as an example the United States's representative democracy which he said consisted of "spectacular and meaningless duels between two bourgeois parties" led by "multimillionaires".

The Chinese Communist Party political concept of whole-process people's democracy criticizes liberal democracy for excessively relying on procedural formalities without genuinely reflecting the interests of the people. Under this primarily consequentialist concept, the most important criteria for a democracy is whether it can "solve the people's real problems", while a system in which "the people are awakened only for voting" is not truly democratic. For example, the Chinese government's 2021 white paper China: Democracy that Works criticizes liberal democracy's shortcoming based on principles of whole process people's democracy.

Religion

See also: Religious democracy

Religious supremacism is not compatible with democracy or liberalism. Religious stances on democracy and liberalism vary and can change. The Catholic church opposed liberal democracy until 1965, when Second Vatican Council endorsed religious freedom. Religious democracy which prioritizes non-liberal religious values over liberal values has been criticized for not being a liberal democracy.

Vulnerabilities

Authoritarianism

Authoritarianism is perceived by many to be a direct threat to the liberalised democracy practised in many countries. According to American political sociologist and authors Larry Diamond, Marc F. Plattner and Christopher Walker, undemocratic regimes are becoming more assertive. They suggest that liberal democracies introduce more authoritarian measures to counter authoritarianism itself and cite monitoring elections and more control on media in an effort to stop the agenda of undemocratic views. Diamond, Plattner and Walker uses an example of China using aggressive foreign policy against western countries to suggest that a country's society can force another country to behave in a more authoritarian manner. In their book 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' they claim that Beijing confronts the United States by building its navy and missile force and promotes the creation of global institutions designed to exclude American and European influence; as such authoritarian states pose a threat to liberal democracy as they seek to remake the world in their own image.

Various authors have also analysed the authoritarian means that are used by liberal democracies to defend economic liberalism and the power of political elites.

War

There are ongoing debates surrounding the effect that war may have on liberal democracy, and whether it cultivates or inhibits democratization.

War may cultivate democratization by "mobilizing the masses, and creating incentives for the state to bargain with the people it needs to contribute to the war effort". An example of this may be seen in the extension of suffrage in the UK after World War I.

War may however inhibit democratization by "providing an excuse for the curtailment of liberties".

Terrorism

Globe icon.The examples and perspective in this section may not represent a worldwide view of the subject. You may improve this section, discuss the issue on the talk page, or create a new section, as appropriate. (January 2014) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Several studies have concluded that terrorism is most common in nations with intermediate political freedom, meaning countries transitioning from autocratic governance to democracy. Nations with strong autocratic governments and governments that allow for more political freedom experience less terrorism.

Populism

The neutrality of this section is disputed. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page. Please do not remove this message until conditions to do so are met. (May 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
Main article: Populism

There is no one agreed upon definition of populism, with a broader definition settled upon following a conference at the London School of Economics in 1967. Academically, the term "populism" faces criticism that it should be abandoned as a descriptor due to its vagueness. It is typically not fundamentally undemocratic, but it is often anti-liberal. Many will agree on certain features that characterize populism and populists: a conflict between 'the people' and 'the elites', with populists siding with 'the people' and strong disdain for opposition and negative media using labels such as 'fake news'.

Populism is a form of majoritarianism, threatening some of the core principles of liberal democracy such as the rights of the individual. Examples of these can vary from freedom of movement via control on immigration, or opposition to liberal social values such as gay marriage. Populists do this by appealing to the feelings and emotions of the people whilst offering solutions - often vastly simplified - to complex problems.

Populism is a particular threat to liberal democracy because it exploits the weaknesses of the liberal democratic system. A key weakness of liberal democracies highlighted in 'How Democracies Die', is the conundrum that suppressing populist movements or parties can be seen to be illiberal. Also, populism exploits the inherent differences between 'Democracy' and 'Liberalism'. For liberal democracy to be effective, a degree of compromise is required as protecting the rights of the individual take precedence if they are threatened by the will of the majority, more commonly known as a tyranny of the majority. Majoritarianism is so ingrained in populism that this core value of a liberal democracy is under threat. This therefore brings into question how effectively liberal democracy can defend itself from populism.

According to Takis Papas in his work Populism and Liberal Democracy: A Comparative and Theoretical Analysis, "democracy has two opposites, one liberal, the other populist". Whereas liberalism accepts a notion of society composed of multiple divisions, populism only acknowledges a society of 'the people' versus 'the elites'. The fundamental beliefs of the populist voter consist of: the belief that oneself is powerless and is a victim of the powerful; a "sense of enmity" rooted in "moral indignation and resentfulness"; and a "longing for future redemption" through the actions of a charismatic leader. Papas says this mindset results in a feeling of victimhood caused by the belief that the society is "made up of victims and perpetrators". Other characteristic of a populist voter is that they are "distinctively irrational" because of the "disproportionate role of emotions and morality" when making a political decision like voting. Moreover, through self-deception they are "wilfully ignorant". In addition, they are "intuitively… and unsettlingly principled" rather than a more "pragmatic" liberal voter.

An example of a populist movement is the 2016 Brexit campaign. The role of the 'elite' in this circumstance was played by the EU and 'London-centric liberals', while the Brexit campaign appealed to workers in industries such as agriculture who were allegedly worse off due to EU membership. This case study also illustrates the potential threat populism can pose to a liberal democracy with the movement heavily relying on disdain for the media. This was done by labeling criticism of Brexit as 'Project Fear'.

See also

References

  1. He, Jiacheng (8 January 2022). "The Patterns of Democracy in Context of Historical Political Science". Chinese Political Science Review. 7 (1). Springer Science and Business Media LLC: 111–139. doi:10.1007/s41111-021-00201-5. ISSN 2365-4244. S2CID 256470545.
  2. ^ Jacobs, Lawrence R.; Shapiro, Robert Y. (1994). "Studying Substantive Democracy". PS: Political Science and Politics. 27 (1): 9–17. doi:10.2307/420450. ISSN 1049-0965. JSTOR 420450. S2CID 153637162.
  3. Cusack, Simone; Ball, Rachel (July 2009). Eliminating Discrimination and Ensuring Substantive Equality (PDF) (Report). Public Interest Law Clearing House and Human Rights Law Resource Centre Ltd. Archived from the original (PDF) on 6 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2024.
  4. "What is substantive equality?". Equal Opportunity Commission, Government of Western Australia. November 2014. Retrieved 28 October 2018
  5. ^ Carugati, Federica (2020). "Democratic Stability: A Long View". Annual Review of Political Science. 23: 59–75. doi:10.1146/annurev-polisci-052918-012050. In sum, this literature suggests that stable democracies look very much like liberal democracies, whose critical features are...
  6. ^ Daniel Lederman, Normal Loaza, Rodrigo Res Soares (November 2001). "Accountability and Corruption: Political Institutions Matter". World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 2708. SSRN 632777. "Accountability and Corruption: Political Institutions Matter by Daniel Lederman, Norman Loayza, Rodrigo R. Soares :: SSRN". November 2001. SSRN 632777. Archived from the original on 19 January 2021. Retrieved 17 June 2023.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link). Retrieved 19 February 2006.
  7. ^ Halperin, Morton; Siegle, Joseph T.; Weinstein, Michael. "The Democracy Advantage: How Democracies Promote Prosperity and Peace". Carnegie Council. Archived from the original on 28 June 2006.
  8. ^ Franco, Álvaro; Álvarez-Dardet, Carlos; Ruiz, Maria Teresa (2004). "Effect of democracy on health: ecological study (required)". British Medical Journal. 329 (7480): 1421–23. doi:10.1136/bmj.329.7480.1421. PMC 535957. PMID 15604165.
  9. ^ Kopstein, Jeffrey; Lichbach, Mark; Hanson, Stephen E., eds. (2014). Comparative Politics: Interests, Identities, and Institutions in a Changing Global Order (4, revised ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 37–39. ISBN 978-1139991384. Archived from the original on 30 June 2020. Retrieved 6 June 2020. Britain pioneered the system of liberal democracy that has now spread in one form or another to most of the world's countries
  10. ^ Anna Lührmann, Seraphine F. Maerz, Sandra Grahn, Nazifa Alizada, Lisa Gastaldi, Sebastian Hellmeier, Garry Hindle and Staffan I. Lindberg. 2020. Autocratization Surges – Resistance Grows. Democracy Report 2020. Varieties of Democracy Institute (V-Dem). Archived 18 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine
  11. "From legal document to public myth: Magna Carta in the 17th century". The British Library. Archived from the original on 18 October 2017. Retrieved 16 October 2017; "Magna Carta: Magna Carta in the 17th Century". The Society of Antiquaries of London. Archived from the original on 25 September 2018. Retrieved 16 October 2017.
  12. "Britain's unwritten constitution". British Library. Archived from the original on 8 December 2015. Retrieved 27 November 2015. The key landmark is the Bill of Rights (1689), which established the supremacy of Parliament over the Crown.... The Bill of Rights (1689) then settled the primacy of Parliament over the monarch's prerogatives, providing for the regular meeting of Parliament, free elections to the Commons, free speech in parliamentary debates, and some basic human rights, most famously freedom from 'cruel or unusual punishment'.
  13. "Constitutionalism: America & Beyond". Bureau of International Information Programs (IIP), U.S. Department of State. Archived from the original on 24 October 2014. Retrieved 30 October 2014. The earliest, and perhaps greatest, victory for liberalism was achieved in England. The rising commercial class that had supported the Tudor monarchy in the 16th century led the revolutionary battle in the 17th, and succeeded in establishing the supremacy of Parliament and, eventually, of the House of Commons. What emerged as the distinctive feature of modern constitutionalism was not the insistence on the idea that the king is subject to law (although this concept is an essential attribute of all constitutionalism). This notion was already well established in the Middle Ages. What was distinctive was the establishment of effective means of political control whereby the rule of law might be enforced. Modern constitutionalism was born with the political requirement that representative government depended upon the consent of citizen subjects.... However, as can be seen through provisions in the 1689 Bill of Rights, the English Revolution was fought not just to protect the rights of property (in the narrow sense) but to establish those liberties which liberals believed essential to human dignity and moral worth. The "rights of man" enumerated in the English Bill of Rights gradually were proclaimed beyond the boundaries of England, notably in the American Declaration of Independence of 1776 and in the French Declaration of the Rights of Man in 1789.
  14. "Citizenship 1625–1789". The National Archives. Archived from the original on 11 January 2016. Retrieved 22 January 2016; "Rise of Parliament". The National Archives. Archived from the original on 17 August 2018. Retrieved 22 January 2016.
  15. Heater, Derek (2006). "Emergence of Radicalism". Citizenship in Britain: A History. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 30–42. ISBN 978-0748626724.
  16. Geoffrey Blainey (2004), A Very Short History of the World, Penguin Books, ISBN 978-0143005599
  17. "War or Peace for Finland? Neoclassical Realist Case Study of Finnish Foreign Policy in the Context of the Anti-Bolshevik Intervention in Russia 1918–1920". Archived from the original on 23 July 2020. Retrieved 22 July 2020.
  18. Schmitt, Carl (1985). The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 2, 8 (chapter 1). ISBN 978-0262192408.
  19. Doomen, Jasper (2014). Freedom and Equality in a Liberal Democratic State. Brussels: Bruylant. pp. 88, 101. ISBN 978-2802746232.
  20. Fukuyama, Francis (1989). "The End of History?". The National Interest (16): 3–18. ISSN 0884-9382. JSTOR 24027184.
  21. Glaser, Eliane (21 March 2014). "Bring Back Ideology: Fukuyama's 'End of History' 25 years On". The Guardian. Archived from the original on 17 April 2019. Retrieved 18 March 2019.
  22. Hannah Arendt, "What is Freedom?", Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought, (New York: Penguin, 1993).
  23. Iris Marion Young, "Five Faces of Oppression", Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton University press, 1990), 39–65.
  24. Michael Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do? (Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2010).
  25. Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Anchor Books, 2000).
  26. Karl Marx, "Alienated Labour" in Early Writings.
  27. Isaiah Berlin, Liberty (Oxford 2004).
  28. Charles Taylor, "What's Wrong With Negative Liberty?", Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge, 1985), 211–229.
  29. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Self-Reliance"; Nikolas Kompridis, "Struggling Over the Meaning of Recognition: A Matter of Identity, Justice or Freedom?" in European Journal of Political Theory July 2007 vol. 6 no. 3 pp. 277–289.
  30. Factsheet – Prisoners' right to vote Archived 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine European Court of Human Rights, April 2019.
  31. "Felon Voting Rights". National Conference of State Legislatures. Archived from the original on 7 March 2016. Retrieved 23 April 2021.
  32. Coppedge, Michael; Reinicke, Wolfgang (1991). Measuring Polyarchy. New Brunswick: Transaction.
  33. "Voting requirements". USA Gov. Archived from the original on 22 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
  34. Dahl, Robert A. (1971). Polyarchy: participation and opposition. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-585-38576-9. OCLC 49414698. Archived from the original on 24 May 2022. Retrieved 23 January 2021.
  35. Mukand, S. W., & Rodrik, D. (2016). The Political Economy of Liberal Democracy. The Economic Journal, 130(627), 765–792. https://drodrik.scholar.harvard.edu/files/dani-rodrik/files/the_political_economy_of_liberal_democracy_june_2016.pdf Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
  36. Lipset, Seymour Martin (1959). "Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy". The American Political Science Review. 53 (1): 69–105. doi:10.2307/1951731. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 1951731. S2CID 53686238. Archived from the original on 9 February 2023. Retrieved 25 January 2021.
  37. Mudde, Cas; Rovira Kaltwasser, Cristóbal (2012). Populism in Europe and the Americas: threat or corrective for democracy?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-42423-3. OCLC 795125118.
  38. Morlino L. (2004) "What is a 'good' democracy?", Demoocratization, 11(5), pp. 10-32. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13510340412331304589
  39. Schmitter P.C. and Karl T.L. (1991) "What Democracy Is...and Is Not", Journal of Democracy, 2(3), pp. 75-88. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.1991.0033.
  40. Ruck, Damian J.; Matthews, Luke J.; Kyritsis, Thanos; Atkinson, Quentin D.; Bentley, R. Alexander (2020). "The cultural foundations of modern democracies". Nature Human Behaviour. 4 (3): 265–269. doi:10.1038/s41562-019-0769-1. PMID 31792400. S2CID 256726148.
  41. Welzel, Christian (2020). "A cultural theory of regimes". Nature Human Behaviour. 4 (3): 231–232. doi:10.1038/s41562-019-0790-4. PMID 31792403. S2CID 256707649.
  42. List of Electoral Democracies FIW23 Archived 15 April 2023 at the Wayback Machine (.XLSX), by Freedom House
  43. "Policy Data Set". Archived from the original on 4 May 2020. Retrieved 28 October 2008.
  44. Benhabib, Seyla, ed. (1996). Democracy and difference: contesting the boundaries of the political. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0691044781.
  45. Alain Gagnon,Intellectuals in liberal democracies: political influence and social involvement
  46. Yvonne Schmidt, Foundations of Civil and Political Rights in Israel and the Occupied Territories
  47. William S. Livingston, A Prospect of purple and orange democracy
  48. Mazie, Steven V. (2006). Israel's higher law: religion and liberal democracy in the Jewish state. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-0739114858.
  49. Mulgan, Richard; Peter Aimer (2004). "chapter 1". Politics in New Zealand (3rd ed.). Auckland University Press. p. 17. ISBN 1869403185. Archived from the original on 22 September 2020. Retrieved 26 June 2009.
  50. "Freedom in the World: Democracy in Retreat". freedomhouse.org. Freedom House. Archived from the original on 5 February 2019. Retrieved 7 December 2019.
  51. "Freedom in the World 2020" (PDF). Freedom House. 4 March 2020. Archived (PDF) from the original on 4 March 2020. Retrieved 4 March 2020.
  52. "Freedom in the World 2021" (PDF). Freedom House. 3 March 2021. Archived (PDF) from the original on 26 December 2021. Retrieved 3 March 2021.
  53. The Effects of Democracy on Economic Growth "The Effects of Democracy on Economic Growth". 2022. Archived from the original on 26 January 2022. Retrieved 8 October 2022.
  54. "The economic impact of colonialism". 2017. Archived from the original on 17 August 2022. Retrieved 8 October 2022.
  55. Free the World. Published Work Using Economic Freedom of the World Research Archived 14 May 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Retrieved 19 February 2006.
  56. Bergren, Niclas (2002). "The Benefits of Economic Freedom: A Survey" (PDF). Archived from the original on 28 June 2007.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  57. John W. Dawson, (1998). "Review of Robert J. Barro, Determinants of Economic Growth: A Cross-Country Empirical Study" Archived 20 April 2006 at the Wayback Machine. Economic History Services. Retrieved 19 February 2006.
  58. W. Ken Farr, Richard A. Lord, J. Larry Wolfenbarger, (1998)."Economic Freedom, Political Freedom, and Economic Well-Being: A Causality Analysis" (PDF). Archived from the original on 3 February 2007. Retrieved 11 April 2005.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link). Cato Journal, Vol 18, No 2.
  59. Wenbo Wu, Otto A. Davis, (2003). "Economic Freedom and Political Freedom Archived 24 May 2006 at the Wayback Machine", Encyclopedia of Public Choice. Carnegie Mellon University, National University of Singapore.
  60. Ian Vásquez, (2001). "Ending Mass Poverty" Archived 24 May 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Cato Institute. Retrieved 19 February 2006.
  61. Susanna Lundström, (April 2002). "The Effects of Democracy on Different Categories of Economic Freedom" Archived 24 May 2006 at the Wayback Machine. Retrieved 19 February 2006.
  62. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce; Downs, George W. (September–October 2005). "Development and Democracy". Foreign Affairs. 84 (September/October 2005). Council on Foreign Relations. Archived from the original on 22 October 2018. Retrieved 22 October 2018.
  63. Single, Joseph T.; Weinstein, Michael M.; Halperin, Morton H. (28 September 2004). "Why Democracies Excel". New York Times. Archived from the original on 13 November 2016. Retrieved 2 March 2017.
  64. Ross, Michael Lewin (2001). "Does Oil Hinder Democracy?". World Politics. 53 (3): 325–61. doi:10.1353/wp.2001.0011. S2CID 18404.
  65. Doucouliagos, H., Ulubasoglu, M (2006). "Democracy and Economic Growth: A meta-analysis". School of Accounting, Economics and Finance Deakin University Australia.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  66. Ajin Choi, (2004). "Democratic Synergy and Victory in War, 1816–1992". International Studies Quarterly, Volume 48, Number 3, September 2004, pp. 663–82 (20). doi:10.1111/j.0020-8833.2004.00319.x
  67. Dan, Reiter; Stam, Allan C. (2002). Democracies at War. Princeton University Press. pp. 64–70. ISBN 0691089485.
  68. Luoma, Jukka. "Helsingin Sanomat – International Edition". Archived from the original on 20 November 2007. Retrieved 26 November 2007.
  69. "Right to Information Act India's magic wand against corruption". AsiaMedia. Archived from the original on 26 September 2008. Retrieved 28 October 2008.
  70. Sen, Amartya (1999). "Democracy as a Universal Value". Journal of Democracy. 10 (3): 3–17. doi:10.1353/jod.1999.0055. Archived from the original on 27 April 2006 – via Johns Hopkins University Press Project MUSE.
  71. McKee, Marin; Ellen Nolte (2004). "Lessons from health during the transition from communism". British Medical Journal. 329 (7480): 1428–29. doi:10.1136/bmj.329.7480.1428. PMC 535963. PMID 15604170.
  72. Hegre, Håvard; Ellingsen, Tanja; Gates, Scott; Gleditsch, Nils Petter (2001). "Towards A Democratic Civil Peace? Opportunity, Grievance, and Civil War 1816–1992". American Political Science Review. 95: 33–48. doi:10.1017/s0003055401000119. S2CID 7521813. Archived from the original on 9 February 2006.
  73. Ray, James Lee (2003). A Lakatosian View of the Democratic Peace Research Program From Progress in International Relations Theory, edited by Colin and Miriam Fendius Elman (PDF). MIT Press. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 June 2006.
  74. Haas, Michael (2014). Deconstructing the "democratic peace" : how a research agenda boomeranged. Los Angeles, CA: Publishinghouse for Scholars. ISBN 9780983962625.
  75. R. J. Rummel, Power Kills. 1997. p. 6.
  76. "Violence and Democracy" (PDF). The British Academy. September 2019. Archived (PDF) from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 25 January 2021.
  77. Aristotle, Politics 2.1273b
  78. Aristotle, Politics 4.1294b
  79. Draper, Hal (1974). "Marx on Democratic Forms of Government". The Socialist Register. 11. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 22 October 2018.
  80. Kapur, Ajay, Niall Macleod, Narendra Singh: "Plutonomy: Buying Luxury, Explaining Global Imbalances", Citigroup, Equity Strategy, Industry Note: October 16, 2005. p. 9f.
  81. Kapur, Ajay, Niall Macleod, Narendra Singh: "Revisiting Plutonomy: The Rich Getting Richer", Citigroup, Equity Strategy, Industry Note: March 5, 2006. p. 10.
  82. Levitt, Steven; Dubner, Stephen J. (2006). Freakonomics: A Rogue Economist Explores the Hidden Side of Everything. HarperCollins. p. 14. ISBN 978-0061245138. Archived from the original on 22 September 2020. Retrieved 6 June 2020.
  83. Gilens, M., & Page, B. (2014). Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens. Perspectives on Politics, 12(3), 564–81. doi:10.1017/S1537592714001595
  84. Edward S. Herman "The Propaganda Model Revisited" Archived 6 January 2012 at the Wayback Machine, Monthly Review, July 1996, as reproduced on the Chomsky.info website
  85. James Curran and Jean Seaton Power Without Responsibility: the Press and Broadcasting in Britain, London: Routledge, 1997, p. 1
  86. Shearer, Elisa; Gottfried, Jeffrey (7 September 2017). "News Use Across Social Media Platforms 2017". Pew Research Center's Journalism Project. Archived from the original on 16 March 2021. Retrieved 14 January 2021.
  87. Chapman, Terri (27 October 2019). "Liberal democracy is under threat from digitisation as govts, tech firms gain more power". ThePrint. Archived from the original on 15 April 2021. Retrieved 14 January 2021.
  88. Girard, Raphaël (2019). "Yascha Mounk, The People vs. Democracy: Why Our Freedom Is in Danger and How to Save It, Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 2018, 400 pp, hb £21.95". The Modern Law Review. 82 (1): 196–200. doi:10.1111/1468-2230.12397. ISSN 1468-2230. S2CID 149968721. Archived from the original on 20 April 2021. Retrieved 25 January 2021.
  89. "International IDEA | Compulsory Voting". Idea.int. Archived from the original on 12 June 2009. Retrieved 28 October 2008.
  90. Spencer, Herbert; Beale, T. (1916). The Man Versus the State: A Collection of Essays. M. Kennerley.
  91. "DPRK Holds Election of Local and National Assemblies". People's Korea. Archived from the original on 10 May 2012. Retrieved 28 June 2008.
  92. "The Parliamentary System of the Democratic People's Republic of Korea" (PDF). Constitutional and Parliamentary Information. Association of Secretaries General of Parliaments (ASGP) of the Inter-Parliamentary Union. p. 4. Archived (PDF) from the original on 3 March 2012. Retrieved 1 October 2010.
  93. Chua, Amy (2002). World on Fire. Doubleday. ISBN 0385503024.
  94. "Democracy". Left Party in Germany. Archived from the original on 16 December 2017. Retrieved 15 December 2017.
  95. Segrillo, Angelo (2012). "Liberalism, Marxism and Democratic Theory Revisited: Proposal of a Joint Index of Political and Economic Democracy". Brazilianpoliticalsciencereview: 15.
  96. Robert Kuttner, Blaming Liberalism, New York Review of Books, November 21, 2019
  97. Christopher, Rice (1990). Lenin: Portrait of a Professional Revolutionary. London: Cassell. p. 121. ISBN 978-0-304-31814-8.
  98. ^ Pieke, Frank N; Hofman, Bert, eds. (2022). CPC Futures The New Era of Socialism with Chinese Characteristics. Singapore: National University of Singapore Press. pp. 60–64. doi:10.56159/eai.52060. ISBN 978-981-18-5206-0. OCLC 1354535847.
  99. "China criticises US democracy before Biden summit". Hindustan Times. 4 December 2021. Archived from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 11 January 2023.
  100. Fox, Jonathan (2019). "The correlates of religion and state: an introduction". Religion, State and Society. 47 (1): 2–9. doi:10.1080/09637494.2018.1529269. ISSN 0963-7494.
  101. ^ Minkenberg, Michael (2007). "Democracy and Religion: Theoretical and Empirical Observations on the Relationship between Christianity, Islam and Liberal Democracy". Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies. 33 (6): 887–909. doi:10.1080/13691830701432731. ISSN 1369-183X.
  102. Bader, Veit (1999). "Religious Pluralism: Secularism or Priority for Democracy?". Political Theory. 27 (5): 597–633. doi:10.1177/0090591799027005002. ISSN 0090-5917.
  103. Diamond, Larry; Plattner, Marc F.; Walker, Christopher (2016) 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, Summary. Available at: https://diamond-democracy.stanford.edu/ Archived 20 May 2023 at the Wayback Machine
  104. Diamond, Larry; Plattner, Marc F.; Walker, Christopher (2016) 'Authoritarianism Goes Global: The Challenge to Democracy' Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, p.23
  105. See for example, Renato Cristi, Carl Schmitt and authoritarian liberalism: strong state, free economy, Cardiff : Univ. of Wales Press, 1998; Michael A. Wilkinson, 'Authoritarian Liberalism as Authoritarian Constitutionalism', in Helena Alviar García, Günter Frankenberg, Authoritarian constitutionalism: comparative analysis and critique, Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing Limited, 2019.
  106. ^ Krebs, Ronald R., and Elizabeth Kier. In War's Wake : International Conflict and the Fate of Liberal Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  107. "Harvard Gazette: Freedom squelches terrorist violence". News.harvard.edu. Archived from the original on 19 September 2015. Retrieved 28 October 2008.
  108. Berlin, Isiah; Schapiro, Leonard; Deakin, F.W; Seton-Watson, Hugh; Worsley, Peter; Gellner, Ernest; McRae, Donald (1967). "Conference on Populism 1967". The London School of Economics.
  109. Serhan, Yasmeen (14 March 2020). "Does anyone know what Populism means? Populism is meaningless". The Atlantic. Archived from the original on 5 April 2023. Retrieved 2 February 2021.
  110. Mudde, Cas (2013). "Are Populists Friends or Foes of Constitutionalism?". The Social and Political Foundations of Constitutions. Archived from the original on 6 April 2023. Retrieved 7 January 2020 – via ORA.
  111. Cooke, Nicole (2018). Fake News and Alternative Facts : Information Literacy in a Post-Truth Era. Chicago: ALA Editions.
  112. Fitzgibbon, John. "Populists are not anti-democratic, they are anti-liberal democracy". London School of Economics.
  113. Levitsky, Steven (2019). How democracies die. Ziblatt, Daniel. London. ISBN 978-0241381359. OCLC 1084729957.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  114. "The Enduring Vulnerability of Liberal Democracy". Journal of Democracy. Archived from the original on 24 January 2021. Retrieved 25 January 2021.
  115. Galston, William A. (William Arthur) (2018). Anti-pluralism : the populist threat to liberal democracy. Hunter, James Davison, Owen, John M. (John Malloy). New Haven. ISBN 978-0300235319. OCLC 1026492265.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  116. Pappas, Takis (2019). Populism and Liberal Democracy: A Comparative and Theoretical Analysis. Oxford Scholarship Online. p. 219.
  117. Norris, Pippa (February 2019). Cultural Backlash: Trump, Brexit, and Authoritarian Populism. Cambridge University Press. p. 368.
  118. Dunin-Wasowicz, Roch (November 2018). "London Calling Brexit: How the rest of the UK views the capital". London School of Economics.

Further reading

Library resources about
Liberal democracy
Liberalism
Ideas
Schools
Classical
  • Economic
  • Equity feminism
  • Georgist
  • Radical
  • Whig
  • Physiocratic
  • Encyclopaedist
  • Conservative
    Social
    Other
    By region
    Africa
    Asia
    Europe
    Latin America and
    the Caribbean
    North America
    Oceania
    Philosophers
    Politicians
  • Jefferson
  • Kołłątaj
  • Madison
  • Artigas
  • Bolívar
  • Broglie
  • Lamartine
  • Macaulay
  • Kossuth
  • Deák
  • Cobden
  • Mazzini
  • Juárez
  • Lincoln
  • Gladstone
  • Cavour
  • Sarmiento
  • Mommsen
  • Naoroji
  • Itagaki
  • Levski
  • Kemal
  • Deakin
  • Milyukov
  • Lloyd George
  • Venizelos
  • Ståhlberg
  • Gokhale
  • Rathenau
  • Madero
  • Einaudi
  • King
  • Roosevelt
  • Pearson
  • Ohlin
  • Kennedy
  • Jenkins
  • Balcerowicz
  • Verhofstadt
  • Obama
  • Macron
  • Organisations
  • Africa Liberal Network
  • Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe
  • Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe Party
  • Arab Liberal Federation
  • Council of Asian Liberals and Democrats
  • European Democratic Party
  • European Liberal Youth
  • International Alliance of Libertarian Parties
  • International Federation of Liberal Youth
  • Liberal International
  • Liberal Network for Latin America
  • Liberal parties
  • Liberal South East European Network
  • Related topics
  • Liberalism Portal
  • Categories: