Revision as of 20:02, 27 August 2013 view sourceFavonian (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Administrators287,587 editsm Reverted edits by 64.197.225.97 (talk) to last version by Yobot← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 09:29, 14 December 2024 view source Outcome0970 (talk | contribs)102 edits Undid revision 1263036308 by Outcome0970 (talk)Tags: Undo Mobile edit Mobile web edit | ||
(349 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Process of repeating items in a self-similar way}} | |||
{{Other uses}} | {{Other uses}} | ||
{{pp-vandalism|small=yes}} | |||
<!-- Making the Recursion article link to itself will not display correctly, and is considered to break ]. The joke itself is already featured in the "Recursive humor" section. See discussion on the talk page. --> | <!-- Making the Recursion article link to itself will not display correctly, and is considered to break ]. The joke itself is already featured in the "Recursive humor" section. See discussion on the talk page. --> | ||
{{Refimprove|date=June 2012}} | |||
]''. The woman in this image holds an object that contains a smaller image of her holding an identical object, which in turn contains a smaller image of herself holding an identical object, and so forth.]] | |||
'''Recursion''' is the process of repeating items in a ] way. For instance, when the surfaces of two mirrors are exactly parallel with each other the nested images that occur are a form of infinite recursion. The term has a variety of meanings specific to a variety of disciplines ranging from ] to ]. The most common application of recursion is in ] and ], in which it refers to a method of defining ] in which the function being defined is applied within its own definition. Specifically this defines an infinite number of instances (function values), using a finite expression that for some instances may refer to other instances, but in such a way that no loop or infinite chain of references can occur. The term is also used more generally to describe a process of repeating objects in a self-similar way. | |||
]. The woman in this image holds an object that contains a smaller image of her holding an identical object, which in turn contains a smaller image of herself holding an identical object, and so forth. 1904 Droste ] tin, designed by Jan Misset.]] | |||
==Formal definitions of recursion== | |||
] | |||
In ] and ], a class of objects or methods exhibit recursive behavior when they can be defined by two properties: | |||
'''Recursion''' occurs when the definition of a concept or process depends on a simpler or previous version of itself.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Causey |first=Robert L. |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/62093042 |title=Logic, sets, and recursion |date=2006 |publisher=Jones and Bartlett Publishers |isbn=0-7637-3784-4 |edition=2nd|location=Sudbury, Mass. |oclc=62093042}}</ref> Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from ] to ]. The most common application of recursion is in ] and ], where a ] being defined is applied within its own definition. While this apparently defines an infinite number of instances (function values), it is often done in such a way that no infinite loop or infinite chain of references can occur. | |||
# A simple base case (or cases) | |||
# A set of rules that reduce all other cases toward the base case | |||
A process that exhibits recursion is ''recursive''. ] displays recursive images, as does an ]. | |||
For example, the following is a recursive definition of a person's ancestors: | |||
*One's ]s are one's ]s (''base case''). | |||
*The ancestors of one's ancestors are also one's ancestors (''recursion step''). | |||
==Formal definitions== | |||
The ] is a classic example of recursion: | |||
], an ancient symbol depicting a serpent or dragon eating its own tail]] | |||
In mathematics and computer science, a class of objects or methods exhibits recursive behavior when it can be defined by two properties: | |||
* {{anchor|base case}}A simple ''base case'' (or cases) — a terminating scenario that does not use recursion to produce an answer | |||
* {{anchor|recursive step}}A ''recursive step'' — a set of rules that reduces all successive cases toward the base case. | |||
For example, the following is a recursive definition of a person's ''ancestor''. One's ancestor is either: | |||
* Fib(0) is 0 | |||
* |
*One's parent (''base case''), ''or'' | ||
*One's parent's ancestor (''recursive step''). | |||
* For all integers n > 1: Fib(n) is (Fib(n − 1) + Fib(n − 2)) | |||
The ] is another classic example of recursion: | |||
Many mathematical axioms are based upon recursive rules. For example, the formal definition of the ]s by the ] can be described as: ''0 is a natural number, and each natural number has a successor, which is also a natural number.'' By this base case and recursive rule, one can generate the set of all natural numbers. | |||
:{{math|1=Fib(0) = 0}} as base case 1, | |||
Recursively defined mathematical objects include ]s, ], and especially ]s. | |||
:{{math|1=Fib(1) = 1}} as base case 2, | |||
There are various more tongue-in-cheek "definitions" of recursion; see ]. | |||
:For all ]s {{math|''n'' > 1}}, {{math|1=Fib(''n'') = Fib(''n'' − 1) + Fib(''n'' − 2)}}. | |||
Many mathematical axioms are based upon recursive rules. For example, the formal definition of the ]s by the ] can be described as: "Zero is a natural number, and each natural number has a successor, which is also a natural number."<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/science/Peano-axioms|title=Peano axioms {{!}} mathematics|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> By this base case and recursive rule, one can generate the set of all natural numbers. | |||
Other recursively defined mathematical objects include ]s, ]s (e.g., ]s), ] (e.g., ]), and ]s. | |||
There are various more tongue-in-cheek definitions of recursion; see ]. | |||
==Informal definition== | ==Informal definition== | ||
] being stirred into flour to produce sourdough: the recipe calls for some sourdough left over from the last time the same recipe was made.]] | |||
Recursion is the process a procedure goes through when one of the steps of the procedure involves invoking the procedure itself. A procedure that goes through recursion is said to be 'recursive'. | |||
Recursion is the process a procedure goes through when one of the steps of the procedure involves invoking the procedure itself. A procedure that goes through recursion is said to be 'recursive'.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/recursive|title=Definition of RECURSIVE|website=www.merriam-webster.com|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> | |||
To understand recursion, one must recognize the distinction between a procedure and the running of a procedure. A procedure is a set of steps based on a set of rules, while the running of a procedure involves actually following the rules and performing the steps. | |||
Recursion is related to, but not the same as, a reference within the specification of a procedure to the execution of some other procedure. | |||
When a procedure is thus defined, this immediately creates the possibility of an endless loop; recursion can only be properly used in a definition if the step in question is skipped in certain cases so that the procedure can complete. | |||
Even if it is properly defined, a recursive procedure is not easy for humans to perform, as it requires distinguishing the new from the old, partially executed invocation of the procedure; this requires some administration as to how far various simultaneous instances of the procedures have progressed. For this reason, recursive definitions are very rare in everyday situations. | |||
==In language== | |||
Linguist ], among many others, has argued that the lack of an upper bound on the number of grammatical sentences in a language, and the lack of an upper bound on grammatical sentence length (beyond practical constraints such as the time available to utter one), can be explained as the consequence of recursion in natural language.<ref>{{cite book|last=Pinker|first=Steven|title=The Language Instinct|year=1994|publisher=William Morrow}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | doi = 10.1016/j.cognition.2004.08.004 | title = The faculty of language: What's so special about it? | year = 2005 | last1 = Pinker | first1=Steven | last2 = Jackendoff | first2=Ray | journal = Cognition | volume = 95 | issue = 2 | pages = 201–236 | pmid=15694646| citeseerx = 10.1.1.116.7784 | s2cid = 1599505 }}</ref> | |||
This can be understood in terms of a recursive definition of a syntactic category, such as a sentence. A sentence can have a structure in which what follows the verb is another sentence: ''Dorothy thinks witches are dangerous'', in which the sentence ''witches are dangerous'' occurs in the larger one. So a sentence can be defined recursively (very roughly) as something with a structure that includes a noun phrase, a verb, and optionally another sentence. This is really just a special case of the mathematical definition of recursion. | |||
To understand recursion, one must recognize the distinction between a procedure and the running of a procedure. A procedure is a set of steps based on a set of rules. The running of a procedure involves actually following the rules and performing the steps. An analogy: a procedure is like a written recipe; running a procedure is like actually preparing the meal. | |||
This provides a way of understanding the creativity of language—the unbounded number of grammatical sentences—because it immediately predicts that sentences can be of arbitrary length: ''Dorothy thinks that Toto suspects that Tin Man said that...''. There are many structures apart from sentences that can be defined recursively, and therefore many ways in which a sentence can embed instances of one category inside another.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.thoughtco.com/recursion-grammar-1691901|title=What Is Recursion in English Grammar?|last=Nordquist|first=Richard|website=ThoughtCo|language=en|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> Over the years, languages in general have proved amenable to this kind of analysis. | |||
Recursion is related to, but not the same as, a reference within the specification of a procedure to the execution of some other procedure. For instance, a recipe might refer to cooking vegetables, which is another procedure that in turn requires heating water, and so forth. However, a recursive procedure is where (at least) one of its steps calls for a new instance of the very same procedure, like a ] recipe calling for some dough left over from the last time the same recipe was made. This of course immediately creates the possibility of an endless loop; recursion can only be properly used in a definition if the step in question is skipped in certain cases so that the procedure can complete, like a sourdough recipe that also tells you how to get some starter dough in case you've never made it before. Even if properly defined, a recursive procedure is not easy for humans to perform, as it requires distinguishing the new from the old (partially executed) invocation of the procedure; this requires some administration of how far various simultaneous instances of the procedures have progressed. For this reason recursive definitions are very rare in everyday situations. An example could be the following procedure to find a way through a ]. Proceed forward until reaching either an exit or a branching point (a dead end is considered a branching point with 0 branches). If the point reached is an exit, terminate. Otherwise try each branch in turn, using the procedure recursively; if every trial fails by reaching only dead ends, return on the path that led to this branching point and report failure. Whether this actually defines a terminating procedure depends on the nature of the maze: it must not allow loops. In any case, executing the procedure requires carefully recording all currently explored branching points, and which of their branches have already been exhaustively tried. | |||
The generally accepted idea that recursion is an essential property of human language has been challenged by ] on the basis of his claims about the ]. Andrew Nevins, David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues are among many who have argued against this.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1353/lan.0.0140 |title=Evidence and argumentation: A reply to Everett (2009) |url=http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/Nevins_Pesetsky_Rodrigues_2_Evidence_and_Argumentation_Reply_to_Everett.pdf |year=2009 |last1=Nevins |first1=Andrew |last2=Pesetsky |first2=David |last3=Rodrigues |first3=Cilene |journal=Language |volume=85 |issue=3 |pages=671–681 |s2cid=16915455 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120106154616/http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/Nevins_Pesetsky_Rodrigues_2_Evidence_and_Argumentation_Reply_to_Everett.pdf |archive-date=2012-01-06}}</ref> Literary ] can in any case be argued to be different in kind from mathematical or logical recursion.<ref name="Drucker2008">{{cite book |last=Drucker|first=Thomas |title=Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R70M4zsVgREC&pg=PA110 |date=4 January 2008 |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |isbn=978-0-8176-4768-1 |page=110}}</ref> | |||
==Recursion in language== | |||
Linguist ] theorizes that unlimited extension of any ] is possible using the recursive device of embedding clauses within sentences (Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. 1965). For example, two simple sentences—''"Dorothy met the Wicked Witch of the West in Munchkin Land"'' and ''"The Wicked Witch's sister was killed in Munchkin Land"''—can be embedded in a third sentence, ''"Dorothy liquidated the Wicked Witch with a pail of water,"'' to obtain a recursive sentence: ''"Dorothy, who met the Wicked Witch of the West in Munchkin Land where her sister was killed, liquidated her with a pail of water."'' | |||
Recursion plays a crucial role not only in syntax, but also in ]. The word ''and'', for example, can be construed as a function that can apply to sentence meanings to create new sentences, and likewise for noun phrase meanings, verb phrase meanings, and others. It can also apply to intransitive verbs, transitive verbs, or ditransitive verbs. In order to provide a single denotation for it that is suitably flexible, ''and'' is typically defined so that it can take any of these different types of meanings as arguments. This can be done by defining it for a simple case in which it combines sentences, and then defining the other cases recursively in terms of the simple one.<ref>Barbara Partee and Mats Rooth. 1983. In Rainer Bäuerle et al., ''Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language''. Reprinted in Paul Portner and Barbara Partee, eds. 2002. ''Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings''. Blackwell.</ref> | |||
The idea that recursion is an essential property of human language (as Chomsky suggests) is challenged by ] ] in his work ''Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Pirahã: Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language'', in which he hypothesizes that cultural factors made recursion unnecessary in the development of the ]. This concept, which challenges Chomsky's idea that recursion is the only trait that differentiates human and animal communication, is currently under debate. | |||
Andrew Nevins, David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues provide a debate against this proposal.<ref>{{cite journal | doi = 10.1353/lan.0.0140 | title = Evidence and argumentation: A reply to Everett (2009) |url=http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/pesetsky/Nevins_Pesetsky_Rodrigues_2_Evidence_and_Argumentation_Reply_to_Everett.pdf | format=PDF| year = 2009 | last1 = Nevins | first1=Andrew | last2 = Pesetsky | first2=David | last3 = Rodrigues | first3=Cilene | journal = Language | volume = 85 | issue = 3 | pages = 671–681 }}</ref> | |||
A ] is a ] that contains recursive ].<ref name="ns02">{{citation | |||
Recursion in linguistics enables 'discrete infinity' by embedding phrases within phrases of the same type in a hierarchical structure. Without recursion, language does not have 'discrete infinity' and cannot embed sentences into infinity (with a ']' effect). Everett contests that language must have discrete infinity, and asserts that the Pirahã language—which he claims lacks recursion—is in fact finite. He likens it to the finite game of ], which has a finite number of moves but is nevertheless very productive, with novel moves being discovered throughout history. | |||
| last1 = Nederhof | first1 = Mark-Jan | |||
| last2 = Satta | first2 = Giorgio | |||
| contribution = Parsing Non-recursive Context-free Grammars | |||
| doi = 10.3115/1073083.1073104 | |||
| location = Stroudsburg, PA, USA | |||
| pages = 112–119 | |||
| publisher = Association for Computational Linguistics | |||
| title = Proceedings of the 40th Annual Meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics (ACL '02) | |||
| year = 2002| doi-access = free | |||
}}.</ref> | |||
===Recursive humor=== | ===Recursive humor=== | ||
Recursion is sometimes used humorously in computer science, programming, philosophy, or mathematics textbooks, generally by giving a ] or self-reference, in which the putative recursive step does not get closer to a base case, but instead leads to an ]. It is not unusual for such books to include a joke entry in their |
Recursion is sometimes used humorously in computer science, programming, philosophy, or mathematics textbooks, generally by giving a ] or ], in which the putative recursive step does not get closer to a base case, but instead leads to an ]. It is not unusual for such books to include a joke entry in their glossary along the lines of: | ||
:Recursion, ''see Recursion''.<ref name=Hunter>{{cite book|last=Hunter|first=David|title=Essentials of Discrete Mathematics|year=2011|publisher=Jones and Bartlett|pages=494|url= |
:Recursion, ''see Recursion''.<ref name=Hunter>{{cite book|last=Hunter|first=David|title=Essentials of Discrete Mathematics|year=2011|publisher=Jones and Bartlett|pages=494|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kuwhTxCVovQC&q=recursion+joke|isbn=9781449604424}}</ref> | ||
A variation is found on page 269 in the ] of some editions of Kernighan and Ritchie's book '']''; the index entry recursively references itself ("recursion 86, 139, 141, 182, 202, 269"). |
A variation is found on page 269 in the ] of some editions of ] and ]'s book '']''; the index entry recursively references itself ("recursion 86, 139, 141, 182, 202, 269"). Early versions of this joke can be found in ''Let's talk Lisp'' by Laurent Siklóssy (published by Prentice Hall PTR on December 1, 1975, with a copyright date of 1976) and in ''Software Tools'' by Kernighan and Plauger (published by Addison-Wesley Professional on January 11, 1976). The joke also appears in ''The UNIX Programming Environment'' by Kernighan and Pike. It did not appear in the first edition of ''The C Programming Language''. The joke is part of the ] folklore and was already widespread in the functional programming community before the publication of the aforementioned books. <ref name="Grainger College">{{cite web |last1=Shaffer |first1=Eric |title=CS 173:Discrete Structures |url=https://courses.engr.illinois.edu/cs173/sp2009/Lectures/lect_19.pdf |publisher=University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign |access-date=7 July 2023}}</ref> <ref name="Columbia University">{{cite web |title=Introduction to Computer Science and Programming in C; Session 8: September 25, 2008 |url=http://www.cs.columbia.edu/~bert/courses/1003/lecture8.pdf |publisher=Columbia University |access-date=7 July 2023}}</ref> | ||
] | |||
Another joke is that "To understand recursion, you must understand recursion."<ref name=Hunter/> In the English-language version of the ] web search engine, when a search for "recursion" is made, the site suggests "Did you mean: ''recursion''." An alternative form is the following, from ]: ''"If you already know what recursion is, just remember the answer. Otherwise, find someone who is standing closer to ] than you are; then ask him or her what recursion is."'' | |||
Another joke is that "To understand recursion, you must understand recursion."<ref name=Hunter/> In the English-language version of the Google web search engine, when a search for "recursion" is made, the site suggests "Did you mean: ''recursion''."<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.google.com/search?q=recursion|title=recursion - Google Search|website=www.google.com|access-date=2019-10-24}}</ref> An alternative form is the following, from ]: ''"If you already know what recursion is, just remember the answer. Otherwise, find someone who is standing closer to ] than you are; then ask him or her what recursion is."'' | |||
]s can also be examples of recursive humor. ], for example, stands for "PHP Hypertext Preprocessor", ] stands for "Wine Is Not an Emulator." and ] stands for "GNU's not Unix". | |||
]s are other examples of recursive humor. ], for example, stands for "PHP Hypertext Preprocessor", ] stands for "WINE Is Not an Emulator", ] stands for "GNU's not Unix", and ] denotes the "SPARQL Protocol and RDF Query Language". | |||
==Recursion in mathematics== | |||
]—a confined recursion of triangles to form a geometric ]]] | |||
==In mathematics== | |||
]—a confined recursion of triangles that form a fractal]] | |||
===Recursively defined sets=== | ===Recursively defined sets=== | ||
Line 60: | Line 89: | ||
====Example: the natural numbers==== | ====Example: the natural numbers==== | ||
{{ |
{{See also|Closure (mathematics)}} | ||
The canonical example of a recursively defined set is given by the ]: | The canonical example of a recursively defined set is given by the ]: | ||
Line 67: | Line 96: | ||
:The set of natural numbers is the smallest set satisfying the previous two properties. | :The set of natural numbers is the smallest set satisfying the previous two properties. | ||
In mathematical logic, the ] (or Peano postulates or Dedekind–Peano axioms), are axioms for the natural numbers presented in the 19th century by the German mathematician ] and by the Italian mathematician ]. The Peano Axioms define the natural numbers referring to a recursive successor function and addition and multiplication as recursive functions. | |||
====Example: The set of true reachable propositions==== | |||
Another interesting example is the set of all "true reachable" propositions in an ]. | |||
====Example: Proof procedure ==== | |||
*if a proposition is an axiom, it is a true reachable proposition. | |||
Another interesting example is the set of all "provable" propositions in an ] that are defined in terms of a ] which is inductively (or recursively) defined as follows: | |||
*if a proposition can be obtained from true reachable propositions by means of inference rules, it is a true reachable proposition. | |||
*The set of true reachable propositions is the smallest set of propositions satisfying these conditions. | |||
*If a proposition is an axiom, it is a provable proposition. | |||
This set is called 'true reachable propositions' because in non-constructive approaches to the foundations of mathematics, the set of true propositions may be larger than the set recursively constructed from the axioms and rules of inference. See also ]. | |||
*If a proposition can be derived from true reachable propositions by means of inference rules, it is a provable proposition. | |||
*The set of provable propositions is the smallest set of propositions satisfying these conditions. | |||
===Finite subdivision rules=== | |||
{{Main|Finite subdivision rule}} | |||
Finite subdivision rules are a geometric form of recursion, which can be used to create fractal-like images. A subdivision rule starts with a collection of polygons labelled by finitely many labels, and then each polygon is subdivided into smaller labelled polygons in a way that depends only on the labels of the original polygon. This process can be iterated. The standard `middle thirds' technique for creating the ] is a subdivision rule, as is ]. | |||
===Functional recursion=== | ===Functional recursion=== | ||
A ] may be |
A ] may be recursively defined in terms of itself. A familiar example is the ] sequence: ''F''(''n'') = ''F''(''n'' − 1) + ''F''(''n'' − 2). For such a definition to be useful, it must be reducible to non-recursively defined values: in this case ''F''(0) = 0 and ''F''(1) = 1. | ||
A famous recursive function is the ], which—unlike the Fibonacci sequence—cannot easily be expressed without recursion. | |||
===Proofs involving recursive definitions=== | ===Proofs involving recursive definitions=== | ||
Applying the standard technique of ] to recursively defined sets or functions, as in the preceding sections, yields ] |
Applying the standard technique of ] to recursively defined sets or functions, as in the preceding sections, yields ] — a powerful generalization of ] widely used to derive proofs in ] and computer science. | ||
===Recursive optimization=== | ===Recursive optimization=== | ||
] is an approach to ] that restates a multiperiod or multistep optimization problem in recursive form. The key result in dynamic programming is the ], which writes the value of the optimization problem at an earlier time (or earlier step) | ] is an approach to ] that restates a multiperiod or multistep optimization problem in recursive form. The key result in dynamic programming is the ], which writes the value of the optimization problem at an earlier time (or earlier step) in terms of its value at a later time (or later step). | ||
in terms of its value at a later time (or later step). | |||
===The recursion theorem=== | |||
In ], this is a theorem guaranteeing that recursively defined functions exist. Given a set {{mvar|X}}, an element {{mvar|a}} of {{mvar|X}} and a function {{math|''f'': ''X'' → ''X''}}, the theorem states that there is a unique function <math>F: \N \to X</math> (where <math>\N</math> denotes the set of natural numbers including zero) such that | |||
:<math>F(0) = a</math> | |||
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math> | |||
for any natural number {{mvar|n}}. | |||
Dedekind was the first to pose the problem of unique definition of set-theoretical functions on <math>\mathbb N</math> by recursion, and gave a sketch of an argument in the 1888 essay "Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?" <ref>A. Kanamori, "", pp.50--52. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 18, no. 1 (2012). Accessed 21 August 2023.</ref> | |||
====Proof of uniqueness==== | |||
Take two functions <math>F: \N \to X</math> and <math>G: \N \to X</math> such that: | |||
:<math>F(0) = a</math> | |||
:<math>G(0) = a</math> | |||
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math> | |||
:<math>G(n + 1) = f(G(n))</math> | |||
where {{mvar|a}} is an element of {{mvar|X}}. | |||
It can be proved by ] that {{math|1=''F''(''n'') = ''G''(''n'')}} for all natural numbers | |||
{{mvar|n}}: | |||
:'''Base Case''': {{math|1=''F''(0) = ''a'' = ''G''(0)}} so the equality holds for {{math|1=''n'' = 0}}. | |||
:'''Inductive Step''': Suppose {{math|1=''F''(''k'') = ''G''(''k'')}} for some {{nowrap|<math>k \in \N</math>.}} Then {{math|1=''F''(''k'' + 1) = ''f''(''F''(''k'')) = ''f''(''G''(''k'')) = ''G''(''k'' + 1)}}. | |||
::Hence {{math|1=''F''(''k'') = ''G''(''k'')}} implies {{math|1=''F''(''k'' + 1) = ''G''(''k'' + 1)}}. | |||
By induction, {{math|1=''F''(''n'') = ''G''(''n'')}} for all <math>n \in \N</math>. | |||
== |
==In computer science== | ||
{{Main|Recursion (computer science)}} | {{Main|Recursion (computer science)}} | ||
A common method of simplification is to divide a problem into subproblems of the same type. As a ] technique, this is called ] and is key to the design of many important algorithms. Divide and conquer serves as a top-down approach to problem solving, where problems are solved by solving smaller and smaller instances. A contrary approach is ]. This approach serves as a bottom-up approach, where problems are solved by solving larger and larger instances, until the desired size is reached. | A common method of simplification is to divide a problem into subproblems of the same type. As a ] technique, this is called ] and is key to the design of many important algorithms. Divide and conquer serves as a top-down approach to problem solving, where problems are solved by solving smaller and smaller instances. A contrary approach is ]. This approach serves as a bottom-up approach, where problems are solved by solving larger and larger instances, until the desired size is reached. | ||
A classic example of recursion is the definition of the ] function, given here in |
A classic example of recursion is the definition of the ] function, given here in ] code: | ||
< |
<syntaxhighlight lang="python3">def factorial(n): | ||
if |
if n > 0: | ||
return 1 |
return n * factorial(n - 1) | ||
|
else: | ||
return |
return 1 | ||
</syntaxhighlight> | |||
} | |||
}</source> | |||
The function calls itself recursively on a smaller version of the input (n - 1) and multiplies the result of the recursive call by n, until reaching the ], analogously to the mathematical definition of factorial. | The function calls itself recursively on a smaller version of the input {{code|(n - 1)}} and multiplies the result of the recursive call by {{code|n}}, until reaching the ], analogously to the mathematical definition of factorial. | ||
Recursion in computer programming is exemplified when a function is defined in terms of simpler, often smaller versions of itself. The solution to the problem is then devised by combining the solutions obtained from the simpler versions of the problem. One example application of recursion is in ]s for programming languages. The great advantage of recursion is that an infinite set of possible sentences, designs or other data can be defined, parsed or produced by a finite computer program. | Recursion in computer programming is exemplified when a function is defined in terms of simpler, often smaller versions of itself. The solution to the problem is then devised by combining the solutions obtained from the simpler versions of the problem. One example application of recursion is in ]s for programming languages. The great advantage of recursion is that an infinite set of possible sentences, designs or other data can be defined, parsed or produced by a finite computer program. | ||
]s are equations |
]s are equations which define one or more sequences recursively. Some specific kinds of recurrence relation can be "solved" to obtain a non-recursive definition (e.g., a ]). | ||
Use of recursion in an algorithm has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is usually simplicity |
Use of recursion in an algorithm has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is usually the simplicity of instructions. The main disadvantage is that the memory usage of recursive algorithms may grow very quickly, rendering them impractical for larger instances. | ||
==In biology== | |||
==The recursion theorem== | |||
Shapes that seem to have been created by recursive processes sometimes appear in plants and animals, such as in branching structures in which one large part branches out into two or more similar smaller parts. One example is ].<ref>{{cite web |title=Picture of the Day: Fractal Cauliflower |date=28 December 2012 |url=https://twistedsifter.com/2012/12/fractal-cauliflower-romanesco-broccoli/ |access-date=19 April 2020}}</ref> | |||
In ], this is a theorem guaranteeing that recursively defined functions exist. Given a set ''X'', an element ''a'' of ''X'' and a function <math>f: X \rightarrow X</math>, the theorem states that there is a unique function <math>F: \mathbb{N} \rightarrow X</math> (where <math>\mathbb{N}</math> denotes the set of natural numbers including zero) such that | |||
:<math>F(0) = a</math> | |||
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math> | |||
for any natural number ''n''. | |||
== In the social sciences == | |||
===Proof of uniqueness=== | |||
Authors use the concept of ''recursivity'' to foreground the situation in which specifically ''social'' scientists find themselves when producing knowledge about the world they are always already part of.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Bourdieu |first=Pierre |year=1992 |title=Double Bind et Conversion |journal=Pour Une Anthropologie Réflexive |publisher=Le Seuil |publication-place=Paris}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Giddens |first=Anthony |title=Social Theory and Modern Sociology |publisher=Polity Press |year=1987}}</ref> According to Audrey Alejandro, “as social scientists, the recursivity of our condition deals with the fact that we are both subjects (as discourses are the medium through which we analyse) and objects of the academic discourses we produce (as we are social agents belonging to the world we analyse).”<ref name="Alejandro2021">{{Cite journal |last=Alejandro |first=Audrey |date=2021 |title=Reflexive discourse analysis: A methodology for the practice of reflexivity |journal=] |language=en |volume=27 |issue=1 |page=171 |doi=10.1177/1354066120969789 |s2cid=229461433 |issn=1354-0661|doi-access=free }}</ref> From this basis, she identifies in recursivity a fundamental challenge in the production of emancipatory knowledge which calls for the exercise of ] efforts:{{quote|we are socialised into discourses and dispositions produced by the socio-political order we aim to challenge, a socio-political order that we may, therefore, reproduce unconsciously while aiming to do the contrary. The recursivity of our situation as scholars – and, more precisely, the fact that the dispositional tools we use to produce knowledge about the world are themselves produced by this world – both evinces the vital necessity of implementing reflexivity in practice and poses the main challenge in doing so.|Audrey Alejandro| {{Harvp|Alejandro|2021}}}} | |||
Take two functions <math>F: \mathbb{N} \rightarrow X</math> and <math>G: \mathbb{N} \rightarrow X</math> such that: | |||
==In business== | |||
:<math>F(0) = a</math> | |||
{{Further information|Management cybernetics}} | |||
:<math>G(0) = a</math> | |||
:<math>F(n + 1) = f(F(n))</math> | |||
:<math>G(n + 1) = f(G(n))</math> | |||
Recursion is sometimes referred to in ] as the process of iterating through levels of abstraction in large business entities.<ref>{{cite journal |title=The Canadian Small Business–Bank Interface: A Recursive Model |date=1994 |url=https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/104225879401800401 |publisher=SAGE Journals|doi=10.1177/104225879401800401 |last1=Riding |first1=Allan |last2=Haines |first2=George H. |last3=Thomas |first3=Roland |journal=Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice |volume=18 |issue=4 |pages=5–24 }}</ref> A common example is the recursive nature of management ], ranging from ] to ] via ]. It also encompasses the larger issue of ] in ].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Beer |first1=Stafford |title=Brain Of The Firm |date=1972 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-0471948391}}</ref> | |||
where ''a'' is an element of ''X''. | |||
==In art== | |||
It can be proved by ] that <math>F(n) = G(n)</math> for all natural numbers ''n'': | |||
]s by ] and ], 1892]] | |||
]'s '']'', 1320, recursively contains an image of itself (held up by the kneeling figure in the central panel).]] | |||
{{See also|Mathematics and art|Infinity mirror}} | |||
The ] is a physical artistic example of the recursive concept.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Tang |first1=Daisy |title=Recursion |url=http://www.cpp.edu/~ftang/courses/CS240/lectures/recursion.htm |access-date=24 September 2015 |quote=More examples of recursion: Russian Matryoshka dolls. Each doll is made of solid wood or is hollow and contains another Matryoshka doll inside it.}}</ref> | |||
:'''Base Case''': <math>F(0) = a = G(0)</math> so the equality holds for <math>n = 0</math>. | |||
Recursion has been used in paintings since ]'s '']'', made in 1320. Its central panel contains the kneeling figure of Cardinal Stefaneschi, holding up the triptych itself as an offering.<ref>{{cite web |title=Giotto di Bondone and assistants: Stefaneschi triptych |url=http://mv.vatican.va/3_EN/pages/PIN/PIN_Sala02_03.html |publisher=The Vatican |access-date=16 September 2015}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |title=Physical (A)Causality: Determinism, Randomness and Uncaused Events |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gxBMDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 |first=Karl |last=Svozil |year=2018 |publisher=Springer |pages=12| isbn=9783319708157 }}</ref> This practice is more generally known as the ], an example of the ] technique. | |||
:'''Inductive Step''': Suppose <math>F(k) = G(k)</math> for some <math>k \in \mathbb{N}</math>. Then <math>F(k+1) = f(F(k)) = f(G(k)) = G(k+1).</math> | |||
::Hence F(k) = G(k) implies F(k+1) = G(k+1). | |||
]'s '']'' (1956) is a print which depicts a distorted city containing a gallery which ]ly contains the picture, and so '']''.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Cooper |first1=Jonathan |title=Art and Mathematics |url=https://unwrappingart.com/art/art-and-mathematics/ |access-date=5 July 2020 |date=5 September 2007}}</ref> | |||
By Induction, <math>F(n) = G(n)</math> for all <math>n \in \mathbb{N}</math>. | |||
{{Clear}} | |||
== |
== In culture == | ||
The film '']'' has colloquialized the appending of the suffix '']'' to a noun to jokingly indicate the recursion of something.<ref>{{cite web |title=-ception – The Rice University Neologisms Database |url=http://neologisms.rice.edu/index.php?a=term&d=1&t=17573 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170705153941/http://neologisms.rice.edu/index.php?a=term&d=1&t=17573 |archive-date=July 5, 2017 |access-date=December 23, 2016 |publisher=Rice University}}</ref> | |||
Some common recurrence relations are: | |||
{{col-begin}} | |||
{{col-break}} | |||
*]: <math>\phi = 1 + (1/\phi) = 1 + (1/(1 + (1/(1 + 1/...))))</math> | |||
*]: <math>n! = n (n - 1)! = n (n - 1)\cdots 1</math> | |||
*]: <math>f (n) = f (n - 1) + f (n - 2)</math> | |||
*]s: <math>C_0=1</math>, <math>C_{n+1} = (4n+2)C_n/(n+2)</math> | |||
*Computing compound ] | |||
*The ] | |||
*] | |||
{{col-end}} | |||
==Bibliography== | |||
* {{cite journal|first=Edsger W.|last=Dijkstra|authorlink=Edsger W. Dijkstra|title=Recursive Programming|journal=Numerische Mathematik|volume=2|issue=1|year=1960|pages=312–318|doi=10.1007/BF01386232}} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Johnsonbaugh, Richard | title=Discrete Mathematics | publisher=Prentice Hall | year=2004 | isbn=0-13-117686-2 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Hofstadter, Douglas | title=Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid | publisher=Basic Books | year=1999 | isbn=0-465-02656-7 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Shoenfield, Joseph R. | title=Recursion Theory | publisher=A K Peters Ltd | year=2000 | isbn=1-56881-149-7 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Causey, Robert L. | title=Logic, Sets, and Recursion | publisher=Jones & Bartlett | year=2001 | isbn=0-7637-1695-2 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Cori, Rene; Lascar, Daniel; Pelletier, Donald H. | title=Recursion Theory, Gödel's Theorems, Set Theory, Model Theory | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=2001 | isbn=0-19-850050-5 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Barwise, Jon; Moss, Lawrence S. | title=Vicious Circles | publisher=Stanford Univ Center for the Study of Language and Information | year=1996 | isbn=0-19-850050-5 }} - offers a treatment of ]. | |||
*{{cite book | author=Rosen, Kenneth H. | title=Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications | publisher=McGraw-Hill College | year=2002 | isbn=0-07-293033-0 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Cormen, Thomas H., Charles E. Leiserson, Ronald L. Rivest, Clifford Stein | title=Introduction to Algorithms | publisher=Mit Pr | year=2001 | isbn=0-262-03293-7 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author = Kernighan, B.; Ritchie, D. | title=The C programming Language | publisher=Prentice Hall | year = 1988 | isbn = 0-13-110362-8 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Stokey, Nancy,; Robert Lucas; Edward Prescott | title=Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics | publisher=Harvard University Press | year=1989 | isbn=0-674-75096-9}} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Hungerford |title=Algebra | publisher=Springer|year=1980|isbn=978-0-387-90518-1}}, first chapter on set theory. | |||
==See also== | ==See also== | ||
* {{Annotated link|Corecursion}} | |||
<div style="-moz-column-count:3; column-count:3;"> | |||
* {{Annotated link|Course-of-values recursion}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Digital infinity}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|A Dream Within a Dream (poem)}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Droste effect}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|False awakening}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Fixed point combinator}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Infinite compositions of analytic functions}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Infinite loop}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Infinite regress}} | |||
<!-- | |||
* {{Annotated link|Infinitism}} | |||
Including ] in this list will not display correctly, and | |||
* {{Annotated link|Infinity mirror}} | |||
is considered to break ]. See discussion on the talk page. | |||
* {{Annotated link|Iterated function}} | |||
--> | |||
* {{Annotated link|Mathematical induction}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Mise en abyme}} | |||
* ] | |||
<!-- {{Annotated link|Recursion}} and ] will not display correctly in this list, and including it | |||
* ] | |||
is considered to break ]. See discussion on the talk page.--> | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Reentrant (subroutine)}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Self-reference}} | |||
* ] | |||
* {{Annotated link|Spiegel im Spiegel}} | |||
</div> | |||
* {{Annotated link|Strange loop}} | |||
* {{Annotated link|Tail recursion}} | |||
* {{Annotated link|Tupper's self-referential formula}} | |||
* {{Annotated link|Turtles all the way down}} | |||
==References== | ==References== | ||
{{Reflist}} | |||
<references/> | |||
==Bibliography== | |||
{{refbegin}} | |||
* {{cite journal|first=Edsger W.|last=Dijkstra|author-link=Edsger W. Dijkstra|title=Recursive Programming|journal=Numerische Mathematik|volume=2|issue=1|year=1960|pages=312–318|doi=10.1007/BF01386232|s2cid=127891023}} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Johnsonbaugh, Richard|author-link=Richard Johnsonbaugh | title=Discrete Mathematics | publisher=Prentice Hall | year=2004 | isbn=978-0-13-117686-7 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Hofstadter, Douglas | author-link=Douglas Hofstadter | title=Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid | publisher=Basic Books | year=1999 | isbn=978-0-465-02656-2 | url=https://archive.org/details/gdelescherbachet00hofs }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Shoenfield, Joseph R. |author-link=Joseph R. Shoenfield| title=Recursion Theory | url=https://archive.org/details/recursiontheory0000shoe | url-access=registration | publisher=A K Peters Ltd | year=2000 | isbn=978-1-56881-149-9 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author=] | title=Logic, Sets, and Recursion | url=https://archive.org/details/logicsetsrecursi0000caus | url-access=registration | publisher=Jones & Bartlett | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-7637-1695-0 }} | |||
*{{cite book |author1=Cori, Rene |author2=Lascar, Daniel |author3=Pelletier, Donald H. | title=Recursion Theory, Gödel's Theorems, Set Theory, Model Theory | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-19-850050-6 }} | |||
*{{cite book | author1=Barwise, Jon| author2=Moss, Lawrence S. |author1-link=Jon Barwise| title=Vicious Circles | publisher=Stanford Univ Center for the Study of Language and Information | year=1996 | isbn=978-0-19-850050-6 }} - offers a treatment of ]. | |||
*{{cite book | author=Rosen, Kenneth H. | title=Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications | publisher=McGraw-Hill College | year=2002 | isbn=978-0-07-293033-7 }} | |||
*{{cite book | last1=Cormen |first1=Thomas H. |first2=Charles E. |last2=Leiserson |first3=Ronald L. |last3=Rivest |first4=Clifford |last4=Stein | title=Introduction to Algorithms | publisher=Mit Pr | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-262-03293-3 }} | |||
*{{cite book |author1=Kernighan, B. |author2=Ritchie, D. |title=The C programming Language |publisher=Prentice Hall |year=1988 |isbn=978-0-13-110362-7 |url=https://archive.org/details/cprogramminglang00bria }} | |||
*{{cite book |author1=Stokey, Nancy |author2=Robert Lucas |author3=Edward Prescott | title=Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics | publisher=Harvard University Press | year=1989 | isbn=978-0-674-75096-8}} | |||
*{{cite book | author=Hungerford |title=Algebra | publisher=Springer|year=1980|isbn=978-0-387-90518-1}}, first chapter on set theory. | |||
{{refend}} | |||
==External links== | ==External links== | ||
{{Commons category}} | |||
{{Wiktionary|recursion|recursivity}} | {{Wiktionary|recursion|recursivity}} | ||
* - tutorial by Alan Gauld | * - tutorial by Alan Gauld | ||
* - contains pointers to recursion in Formal Languages, Linguistics, Math and Computer Science | |||
* | * | ||
* | * | ||
{{Fractals}} | {{Fractals}} | ||
{{logic}} | {{Mathematical logic}} | ||
{{Authority control}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 09:29, 14 December 2024
Process of repeating items in a self-similar way For other uses, see Recursion (disambiguation).
Recursion occurs when the definition of a concept or process depends on a simpler or previous version of itself. Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from linguistics to logic. The most common application of recursion is in mathematics and computer science, where a function being defined is applied within its own definition. While this apparently defines an infinite number of instances (function values), it is often done in such a way that no infinite loop or infinite chain of references can occur.
A process that exhibits recursion is recursive. Video feedback displays recursive images, as does an infinity mirror.
Formal definitions
In mathematics and computer science, a class of objects or methods exhibits recursive behavior when it can be defined by two properties:
- A simple base case (or cases) — a terminating scenario that does not use recursion to produce an answer
- A recursive step — a set of rules that reduces all successive cases toward the base case.
For example, the following is a recursive definition of a person's ancestor. One's ancestor is either:
- One's parent (base case), or
- One's parent's ancestor (recursive step).
The Fibonacci sequence is another classic example of recursion:
- Fib(0) = 0 as base case 1,
- Fib(1) = 1 as base case 2,
- For all integers n > 1, Fib(n) = Fib(n − 1) + Fib(n − 2).
Many mathematical axioms are based upon recursive rules. For example, the formal definition of the natural numbers by the Peano axioms can be described as: "Zero is a natural number, and each natural number has a successor, which is also a natural number." By this base case and recursive rule, one can generate the set of all natural numbers.
Other recursively defined mathematical objects include factorials, functions (e.g., recurrence relations), sets (e.g., Cantor ternary set), and fractals.
There are various more tongue-in-cheek definitions of recursion; see recursive humor.
Informal definition
Recursion is the process a procedure goes through when one of the steps of the procedure involves invoking the procedure itself. A procedure that goes through recursion is said to be 'recursive'.
To understand recursion, one must recognize the distinction between a procedure and the running of a procedure. A procedure is a set of steps based on a set of rules, while the running of a procedure involves actually following the rules and performing the steps.
Recursion is related to, but not the same as, a reference within the specification of a procedure to the execution of some other procedure.
When a procedure is thus defined, this immediately creates the possibility of an endless loop; recursion can only be properly used in a definition if the step in question is skipped in certain cases so that the procedure can complete.
Even if it is properly defined, a recursive procedure is not easy for humans to perform, as it requires distinguishing the new from the old, partially executed invocation of the procedure; this requires some administration as to how far various simultaneous instances of the procedures have progressed. For this reason, recursive definitions are very rare in everyday situations.
In language
Linguist Noam Chomsky, among many others, has argued that the lack of an upper bound on the number of grammatical sentences in a language, and the lack of an upper bound on grammatical sentence length (beyond practical constraints such as the time available to utter one), can be explained as the consequence of recursion in natural language.
This can be understood in terms of a recursive definition of a syntactic category, such as a sentence. A sentence can have a structure in which what follows the verb is another sentence: Dorothy thinks witches are dangerous, in which the sentence witches are dangerous occurs in the larger one. So a sentence can be defined recursively (very roughly) as something with a structure that includes a noun phrase, a verb, and optionally another sentence. This is really just a special case of the mathematical definition of recursion.
This provides a way of understanding the creativity of language—the unbounded number of grammatical sentences—because it immediately predicts that sentences can be of arbitrary length: Dorothy thinks that Toto suspects that Tin Man said that.... There are many structures apart from sentences that can be defined recursively, and therefore many ways in which a sentence can embed instances of one category inside another. Over the years, languages in general have proved amenable to this kind of analysis.
The generally accepted idea that recursion is an essential property of human language has been challenged by Daniel Everett on the basis of his claims about the Pirahã language. Andrew Nevins, David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues are among many who have argued against this. Literary self-reference can in any case be argued to be different in kind from mathematical or logical recursion.
Recursion plays a crucial role not only in syntax, but also in natural language semantics. The word and, for example, can be construed as a function that can apply to sentence meanings to create new sentences, and likewise for noun phrase meanings, verb phrase meanings, and others. It can also apply to intransitive verbs, transitive verbs, or ditransitive verbs. In order to provide a single denotation for it that is suitably flexible, and is typically defined so that it can take any of these different types of meanings as arguments. This can be done by defining it for a simple case in which it combines sentences, and then defining the other cases recursively in terms of the simple one.
A recursive grammar is a formal grammar that contains recursive production rules.
Recursive humor
Recursion is sometimes used humorously in computer science, programming, philosophy, or mathematics textbooks, generally by giving a circular definition or self-reference, in which the putative recursive step does not get closer to a base case, but instead leads to an infinite regress. It is not unusual for such books to include a joke entry in their glossary along the lines of:
- Recursion, see Recursion.
A variation is found on page 269 in the index of some editions of Brian Kernighan and Dennis Ritchie's book The C Programming Language; the index entry recursively references itself ("recursion 86, 139, 141, 182, 202, 269"). Early versions of this joke can be found in Let's talk Lisp by Laurent Siklóssy (published by Prentice Hall PTR on December 1, 1975, with a copyright date of 1976) and in Software Tools by Kernighan and Plauger (published by Addison-Wesley Professional on January 11, 1976). The joke also appears in The UNIX Programming Environment by Kernighan and Pike. It did not appear in the first edition of The C Programming Language. The joke is part of the functional programming folklore and was already widespread in the functional programming community before the publication of the aforementioned books.
Another joke is that "To understand recursion, you must understand recursion." In the English-language version of the Google web search engine, when a search for "recursion" is made, the site suggests "Did you mean: recursion." An alternative form is the following, from Andrew Plotkin: "If you already know what recursion is, just remember the answer. Otherwise, find someone who is standing closer to Douglas Hofstadter than you are; then ask him or her what recursion is."
Recursive acronyms are other examples of recursive humor. PHP, for example, stands for "PHP Hypertext Preprocessor", WINE stands for "WINE Is Not an Emulator", GNU stands for "GNU's not Unix", and SPARQL denotes the "SPARQL Protocol and RDF Query Language".
In mathematics
Recursively defined sets
Main article: Recursive definitionExample: the natural numbers
See also: Closure (mathematics)The canonical example of a recursively defined set is given by the natural numbers:
- 0 is in
- if n is in , then n + 1 is in
- The set of natural numbers is the smallest set satisfying the previous two properties.
In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (or Peano postulates or Dedekind–Peano axioms), are axioms for the natural numbers presented in the 19th century by the German mathematician Richard Dedekind and by the Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. The Peano Axioms define the natural numbers referring to a recursive successor function and addition and multiplication as recursive functions.
Example: Proof procedure
Another interesting example is the set of all "provable" propositions in an axiomatic system that are defined in terms of a proof procedure which is inductively (or recursively) defined as follows:
- If a proposition is an axiom, it is a provable proposition.
- If a proposition can be derived from true reachable propositions by means of inference rules, it is a provable proposition.
- The set of provable propositions is the smallest set of propositions satisfying these conditions.
Finite subdivision rules
Main article: Finite subdivision ruleFinite subdivision rules are a geometric form of recursion, which can be used to create fractal-like images. A subdivision rule starts with a collection of polygons labelled by finitely many labels, and then each polygon is subdivided into smaller labelled polygons in a way that depends only on the labels of the original polygon. This process can be iterated. The standard `middle thirds' technique for creating the Cantor set is a subdivision rule, as is barycentric subdivision.
Functional recursion
A function may be recursively defined in terms of itself. A familiar example is the Fibonacci number sequence: F(n) = F(n − 1) + F(n − 2). For such a definition to be useful, it must be reducible to non-recursively defined values: in this case F(0) = 0 and F(1) = 1.
Proofs involving recursive definitions
Applying the standard technique of proof by cases to recursively defined sets or functions, as in the preceding sections, yields structural induction — a powerful generalization of mathematical induction widely used to derive proofs in mathematical logic and computer science.
Recursive optimization
Dynamic programming is an approach to optimization that restates a multiperiod or multistep optimization problem in recursive form. The key result in dynamic programming is the Bellman equation, which writes the value of the optimization problem at an earlier time (or earlier step) in terms of its value at a later time (or later step).
The recursion theorem
In set theory, this is a theorem guaranteeing that recursively defined functions exist. Given a set X, an element a of X and a function f: X → X, the theorem states that there is a unique function (where denotes the set of natural numbers including zero) such that
for any natural number n.
Dedekind was the first to pose the problem of unique definition of set-theoretical functions on by recursion, and gave a sketch of an argument in the 1888 essay "Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?"
Proof of uniqueness
Take two functions and such that:
where a is an element of X.
It can be proved by mathematical induction that F(n) = G(n) for all natural numbers n:
- Base Case: F(0) = a = G(0) so the equality holds for n = 0.
- Inductive Step: Suppose F(k) = G(k) for some . Then F(k + 1) = f(F(k)) = f(G(k)) = G(k + 1).
- Hence F(k) = G(k) implies F(k + 1) = G(k + 1).
By induction, F(n) = G(n) for all .
In computer science
Main article: Recursion (computer science)A common method of simplification is to divide a problem into subproblems of the same type. As a computer programming technique, this is called divide and conquer and is key to the design of many important algorithms. Divide and conquer serves as a top-down approach to problem solving, where problems are solved by solving smaller and smaller instances. A contrary approach is dynamic programming. This approach serves as a bottom-up approach, where problems are solved by solving larger and larger instances, until the desired size is reached.
A classic example of recursion is the definition of the factorial function, given here in Python code:
def factorial(n): if n > 0: return n * factorial(n - 1) else: return 1
The function calls itself recursively on a smaller version of the input (n - 1)
and multiplies the result of the recursive call by n
, until reaching the base case, analogously to the mathematical definition of factorial.
Recursion in computer programming is exemplified when a function is defined in terms of simpler, often smaller versions of itself. The solution to the problem is then devised by combining the solutions obtained from the simpler versions of the problem. One example application of recursion is in parsers for programming languages. The great advantage of recursion is that an infinite set of possible sentences, designs or other data can be defined, parsed or produced by a finite computer program.
Recurrence relations are equations which define one or more sequences recursively. Some specific kinds of recurrence relation can be "solved" to obtain a non-recursive definition (e.g., a closed-form expression).
Use of recursion in an algorithm has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is usually the simplicity of instructions. The main disadvantage is that the memory usage of recursive algorithms may grow very quickly, rendering them impractical for larger instances.
In biology
Shapes that seem to have been created by recursive processes sometimes appear in plants and animals, such as in branching structures in which one large part branches out into two or more similar smaller parts. One example is Romanesco broccoli.
In the social sciences
Authors use the concept of recursivity to foreground the situation in which specifically social scientists find themselves when producing knowledge about the world they are always already part of. According to Audrey Alejandro, “as social scientists, the recursivity of our condition deals with the fact that we are both subjects (as discourses are the medium through which we analyse) and objects of the academic discourses we produce (as we are social agents belonging to the world we analyse).” From this basis, she identifies in recursivity a fundamental challenge in the production of emancipatory knowledge which calls for the exercise of reflexive efforts:
we are socialised into discourses and dispositions produced by the socio-political order we aim to challenge, a socio-political order that we may, therefore, reproduce unconsciously while aiming to do the contrary. The recursivity of our situation as scholars – and, more precisely, the fact that the dispositional tools we use to produce knowledge about the world are themselves produced by this world – both evinces the vital necessity of implementing reflexivity in practice and poses the main challenge in doing so.
— Audrey Alejandro, Alejandro (2021)
In business
Further information: Management cyberneticsRecursion is sometimes referred to in management science as the process of iterating through levels of abstraction in large business entities. A common example is the recursive nature of management hierarchies, ranging from line management to senior management via middle management. It also encompasses the larger issue of capital structure in corporate governance.
In art
See also: Mathematics and art and Infinity mirrorThe Matryoshka doll is a physical artistic example of the recursive concept.
Recursion has been used in paintings since Giotto's Stefaneschi Triptych, made in 1320. Its central panel contains the kneeling figure of Cardinal Stefaneschi, holding up the triptych itself as an offering. This practice is more generally known as the Droste effect, an example of the Mise en abyme technique.
M. C. Escher's Print Gallery (1956) is a print which depicts a distorted city containing a gallery which recursively contains the picture, and so ad infinitum.
In culture
The film Inception has colloquialized the appending of the suffix -ception to a noun to jokingly indicate the recursion of something.
See also
- Corecursion – Type of algorithm in computer science
- Course-of-values recursion – Technique for defining number-theoretic functions by recursion
- Digital infinity – Term in theoretical linguistics
- A Dream Within a Dream (poem) – Poem by Edgar Allan PoePages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Droste effect – Recursive visual effect
- False awakening – Vivid and convincing dream about awakening from sleep
- Fixed point combinator – Higher-order function Y for which Y f = f (Y f)Pages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Infinite compositions of analytic functions – Mathematical theory about infinitely iterated function composition
- Infinite loop – Programming idiom
- Infinite regress – Philosophical problem
- Infinitism – Philosophical view that knowledge may be justified by an infinite chain of reasons
- Infinity mirror – Parallel or angled mirrors, creating smaller reflections that appear to recede to infinity
- Iterated function – Result of repeatedly applying a mathematical function
- Mathematical induction – Form of mathematical proof
- Mise en abyme – Technique of placing a copy of an image within itself, or a story within a story
- Reentrant (subroutine) – Concept in computer programmingPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Self-reference – Sentence, idea or formula that refers to itself
- Spiegel im Spiegel – 1978 musical composition by Arvo Pärt
- Strange loop – Cyclic structure that goes through several levels in a hierarchical system
- Tail recursion – Subroutine call performed as final action of a procedurePages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Tupper's self-referential formula – Formula that visually represents itself when graphed
- Turtles all the way down – Statement of infinite regress
References
- Causey, Robert L. (2006). Logic, sets, and recursion (2nd ed.). Sudbury, Mass.: Jones and Bartlett Publishers. ISBN 0-7637-3784-4. OCLC 62093042.
- "Peano axioms | mathematics". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
- "Definition of RECURSIVE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
- Pinker, Steven (1994). The Language Instinct. William Morrow.
- Pinker, Steven; Jackendoff, Ray (2005). "The faculty of language: What's so special about it?". Cognition. 95 (2): 201–236. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.116.7784. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2004.08.004. PMID 15694646. S2CID 1599505.
- Nordquist, Richard. "What Is Recursion in English Grammar?". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
- Nevins, Andrew; Pesetsky, David; Rodrigues, Cilene (2009). "Evidence and argumentation: A reply to Everett (2009)" (PDF). Language. 85 (3): 671–681. doi:10.1353/lan.0.0140. S2CID 16915455. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-01-06.
- Drucker, Thomas (4 January 2008). Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 110. ISBN 978-0-8176-4768-1.
- Barbara Partee and Mats Rooth. 1983. In Rainer Bäuerle et al., Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language. Reprinted in Paul Portner and Barbara Partee, eds. 2002. Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings. Blackwell.
- Nederhof, Mark-Jan; Satta, Giorgio (2002), "Parsing Non-recursive Context-free Grammars", Proceedings of the 40th Annual Meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics (ACL '02), Stroudsburg, PA, USA: Association for Computational Linguistics, pp. 112–119, doi:10.3115/1073083.1073104.
- ^ Hunter, David (2011). Essentials of Discrete Mathematics. Jones and Bartlett. p. 494. ISBN 9781449604424.
- Shaffer, Eric. "CS 173:Discrete Structures" (PDF). University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Retrieved 7 July 2023.
- "Introduction to Computer Science and Programming in C; Session 8: September 25, 2008" (PDF). Columbia University. Retrieved 7 July 2023.
- "recursion - Google Search". www.google.com. Retrieved 2019-10-24.
- A. Kanamori, "In Praise of Replacement", pp.50--52. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, vol. 18, no. 1 (2012). Accessed 21 August 2023.
- "Picture of the Day: Fractal Cauliflower". 28 December 2012. Retrieved 19 April 2020.
- Bourdieu, Pierre (1992). "Double Bind et Conversion". Pour Une Anthropologie Réflexive. Paris: Le Seuil.
- Giddens, Anthony (1987). Social Theory and Modern Sociology. Polity Press.
- Alejandro, Audrey (2021). "Reflexive discourse analysis: A methodology for the practice of reflexivity". European Journal of International Relations. 27 (1): 171. doi:10.1177/1354066120969789. ISSN 1354-0661. S2CID 229461433.
- Riding, Allan; Haines, George H.; Thomas, Roland (1994). "The Canadian Small Business–Bank Interface: A Recursive Model". Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice. 18 (4). SAGE Journals: 5–24. doi:10.1177/104225879401800401.
- Beer, Stafford (1972). Brain Of The Firm. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0471948391.
- Tang, Daisy. "Recursion". Retrieved 24 September 2015.
More examples of recursion: Russian Matryoshka dolls. Each doll is made of solid wood or is hollow and contains another Matryoshka doll inside it.
- "Giotto di Bondone and assistants: Stefaneschi triptych". The Vatican. Retrieved 16 September 2015.
- Svozil, Karl (2018). Physical (A)Causality: Determinism, Randomness and Uncaused Events. Springer. p. 12. ISBN 9783319708157.
- Cooper, Jonathan (5 September 2007). "Art and Mathematics". Retrieved 5 July 2020.
- "-ception – The Rice University Neologisms Database". Rice University. Archived from the original on July 5, 2017. Retrieved December 23, 2016.
Bibliography
- Dijkstra, Edsger W. (1960). "Recursive Programming". Numerische Mathematik. 2 (1): 312–318. doi:10.1007/BF01386232. S2CID 127891023.
- Johnsonbaugh, Richard (2004). Discrete Mathematics. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-117686-7.
- Hofstadter, Douglas (1999). Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-02656-2.
- Shoenfield, Joseph R. (2000). Recursion Theory. A K Peters Ltd. ISBN 978-1-56881-149-9.
- Causey, Robert L. (2001). Logic, Sets, and Recursion. Jones & Bartlett. ISBN 978-0-7637-1695-0.
- Cori, Rene; Lascar, Daniel; Pelletier, Donald H. (2001). Recursion Theory, Gödel's Theorems, Set Theory, Model Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-850050-6.
- Barwise, Jon; Moss, Lawrence S. (1996). Vicious Circles. Stanford Univ Center for the Study of Language and Information. ISBN 978-0-19-850050-6. - offers a treatment of corecursion.
- Rosen, Kenneth H. (2002). Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications. McGraw-Hill College. ISBN 978-0-07-293033-7.
- Cormen, Thomas H.; Leiserson, Charles E.; Rivest, Ronald L.; Stein, Clifford (2001). Introduction to Algorithms. Mit Pr. ISBN 978-0-262-03293-3.
- Kernighan, B.; Ritchie, D. (1988). The C programming Language. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-110362-7.
- Stokey, Nancy; Robert Lucas; Edward Prescott (1989). Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-75096-8.
- Hungerford (1980). Algebra. Springer. ISBN 978-0-387-90518-1., first chapter on set theory.
External links
- Recursion - tutorial by Alan Gauld
- Zip Files All The Way Down
- Nevins, Andrew and David Pesetsky and Cilene Rodrigues. Evidence and Argumentation: A Reply to Everett (2009). Language 85.3: 671--681 (2009)
Fractals | |
---|---|
Characteristics | |
Iterated function system | |
Strange attractor | |
L-system | |
Escape-time fractals | |
Rendering techniques | |
Random fractals | |
People | |
Other |
|
Mathematical logic | |||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
General | |||||||||
Theorems (list) and paradoxes | |||||||||
Logics |
| ||||||||
Set theory |
| ||||||||
Formal systems (list), language and syntax |
| ||||||||
Proof theory | |||||||||
Model theory | |||||||||
Computability theory | |||||||||
Related | |||||||||
Mathematics portal |