Revision as of 15:44, 13 July 2006 editByrgenwulf (talk | contribs)1,234 editsm Oops← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 14:08, 23 July 2020 edit undoPaleoNeonate (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Page movers, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers29,743 edits Fix anchor to current section nameTag: Redirect target changed | ||
(220 intermediate revisions by 28 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
#REDIRECT ] {{R from merge}} | |||
{{Disputed}} | |||
{{context|July 2006}} | |||
The '''Cognitive-Theoretic Model of the Universe''' or '''CTMU''' (pronounced "cat-mew") is a ] of the relationship between ] and ]. Created in the mid-1980s by cosmologist ], the CTMU rose to media attention in 1999, buoyed by interest in Langan's extraordinarily high ]{{Fact}}. Among Langan's claims for the theory are that it constitutes ], provides the logical framework of a ], and proves the existence of ]. | |||
==History== | |||
Of limited means and largely self-taught, Langan created the CTMU in the mid-1980s while working as a nightclub bouncer on ]. His first paper on the theory, "The Resolution of Newcomb's Paradox", appeared in the December 1989–January 1990 issue of ''Noesis'', the journal of the Noetic Society (now the ]), a high-IQ society to which Langan belonged. Over the next decade Langan refined his work, continuing to publish and discuss it in ''Noesis''. | |||
For most of the 1990s, knowledge of the CTMU was limited to the Mega Society. Wider recognition began in 1999, when '']'' magazine published a profile of Langan and other members of the high-IQ community. Billing Langan as "the smartest man in America", the article's account of the weight-lifting bouncer and his Theory of Everything sparked a flurry of media interest. Articles and interviews appeared in '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', '']'', and elsewhere. Langan was featured on '']'' and '']'', and interviewed by the ]{{Fact}}. | |||
By 2002 the CTMU had drawn the attention of ], the International Society for Complexity, Information, and Design. Langan was made a fellow of the society and in September 2002 published in its online journal a 56-page paper, "The Cognitive-Theoretic Model of the Universe: A New Kind of Reality Theory". Langan's paper "Cheating the Millennium: The Mounting Explanatory Debts of Scientific Naturalism", relating the CTMU to existing theories of ], appeared in the 2004 anthology ''Uncommon Dissent''. | |||
Langan has maintained an extensive online presence, debating the CTMU in forums across the Internet and posting papers on his . He has also written an unpublished book about the CTMU called ''Design for a Universe''. | |||
==Structure== | |||
Prominent among the tools of ] are the ] (associated with ], ], and ]), and the ] (associated with ], ], and the ]). The axiomatic method derives theorems from axioms, but alternative axioms can yield contradictory theorems (as with ] and ]). The scientific method infers laws from observations, but future observations can break these laws (creating the ]). Such methodological limitations have led some theorists to conclude that all knowledge is relative: to arbitrary axioms or to restricted observations. | |||
The CTMU is an attempt to circumvent these limitations and achieve absolute knowledge. Langan writes: | |||
<blockquote>"What I mean by 'absolute' is precisely this: (1) you can't relativize your way out of it by changing the context; (2) finding it in error equates to destroying your own basis for inference. These criteria are built into the theory from the ground up using some very effective, that is to say ironclad, techniques. Logically, there is no way out."</blockquote> | |||
The CTMU is based on logical ]. In 2-valued ], a tautology is a statement that is true under every assignment of "true" and "false" to the variables within it. For example, "A or not-A" (the ]) is a tautology because it is true regardless of whether A is true or false. Langan argues that all meaningful theories conform to 2-valued logic, and that because the axioms and theorems of 2-valued logic are tautological, tautologies "define the truth concept for all of the sciences. From mathematics and physics to biology and psychology, logical tautologies reign supreme and inviolable". | |||
Langan further holds that logical tautologies constitute absolute knowledge in the sense of his criteria above. That is, where "changing the context" amounts to changing truth assignments to contextual variables, tautologies are true in every context. And where "your own basis for inference" includes 2-valued logic, logically disproving a tautology requires use of the tautology itself, destroying the inference. Accordingly Langan calls tautologies self-evident or "self-proving". | |||
Tautologies are sometimes dismissed as "empty", "vacuous", and "uninformative" on the grounds that they tell us nothing about the world. Disagreeing, Langan adjoins to logic three ] principles (described below), themselves tautological, intended to relate logic to reality. The resulting theory (the CTMU) Langan calls a "supertautology": the reality-theoretic counterpart of a tautology. A supertautology is semantically tautological with respect to its ]; that is, "(a) the theory is intrinsically tautological, and (b) its tautological structure is ] by its universe". | |||
Unlike ordinary scientific theories, which rely on observation to establish their correspondence with reality, the CTMU is intended through its tautological construction to correspond with reality ], in all ]. In fact, claims Langan, "any other valid theory of reality will necessarily equate to the CTMU up to ]; whatever it adds will come by way of specificity, not generality". Verification of the CTMU is made "largely rationalistic" by its tautological nature, so that "much of the theory has to be proven like a math theorem rather than confirmed on a lab bench". | |||
In the CTMU, reality takes the form of an ] Langan calls a "Self-Configuring Self-Processing Language" or SCSPL. Much of the CTMU references, and indeed according to Langan essentially consists of, advanced mathematics, including ], ], ], ], and the logic of ]{{Dubious}}. Langan's public writings are meant to be relatively accessible, and for that reason, he says, tend to avoid heavy use of symbolic notation in favor of informal characterization. Nonetheless, he claims, the CTMU is ] and ], SCSPL is ], and he "can reduce that entire 56 page paper to variables and functional, operational and relational symbols". | |||
==Axioms== | |||
Langan defines reality as "the perceptual aggregate including (1) all scientific observations that ever were and ever will be, and (2) the entire abstract and/or ] explanatory infrastructure of ]". That is, reality is defined on relevance to perception. Associated with this definition is a tautological ] Langan calls the Reality Principle: "reality contains all and only that which is real". That is, reality is self-contained. | |||
The three metalogical principles used in the CTMU to relate logic to reality are the Metaphysical Autology Principle (associated with ]), the Mind Equals Reality Principle (associated with ]), and the Multiplex Unity Principle (associated with ]). They are tautological ] and, according to Langan, necessarily modeled by reality as a condition of its existence. Langan notes that while they are independent, "the premise of axiomatic independence is itself a rather flimsy concept. These principles are actually rather strongly related in the sense that they can to some extent be inferred from each other in a reality-theoretic context". | |||
The first principle is the Metaphysical Autology Principle or MAP, associated with closure. MAP says that reality is closed with respect to all internally relevant operations. In other words, everything essential to reality, including everything needed to describe it, is contained in reality itself. MAP is implied, Langan argues, by the definition of reality: were anything outside of reality relevant to it, it would be included by the definition and therefore inside reality. | |||
The second principle is the Mind Equals Reality Principle or M=R, associated with comprehensiveness. M=R says that reality is comprehensive enough to describe itself. That is, reality conforms to the ] of the minds describing it from within. Whereas MAP gives reality what it needs to describe itself, M=R empowers it to actually do the describing. M=R follows, argues Langan, from the definition of reality. On one hand, mind itself is included in reality by perceptual relevance. On the other hand, mind acts as a filter: that which does not conform to mental categories is irrelevant to perception, and therefore not real. Langan here breaks with ], who posited a ] reality of "things-in-themselves", independent of the ] reality we perceive. Discarding this "Kantian fallacy", Langan rejects noumena as oxymoronic "inconceivable concepts" and holds that phenomenal reality, as the only reality we can know, is the only reality there is. Accordingly, reality relates to our minds as a sort of "distributed ]". | |||
The third principle is the Multiplex Unity Principle or MU, associated with consistency. MU says that reality is consistent by virtue of the mutually inclusive relationship between itself (unity) and its contents (multiplicity). That is, reality topologically includes its contents, while its contents descriptively include it. Reality is here analogous to the ]; SCSPL extends ] with the above two senses of inclusion so that sets, now "syntactic operators", can consistently contain themselves. The consistency of reality is implied, Langan argues, by the stability of perception: a single irresolvable paradox of the form "A = not-A" would destroy the information content of reality, making it impossible to perceive. | |||
==Origins== | |||
The question of why reality exists is sometimes taken to be unanswerable or meaningless: reality "just exists", it is held, and no further explanation can be given. Alternatively, it is sometimes held that reality exists because it was created by something outside of it. Langan opposes both views, arguing that were reality to lack an explanation, it would be acausal and could not sustain itself, whereas were something outside of reality to have created it, it would be relevant to reality and therefore inside reality by definition. | |||
The CTMU treats the ] in the context of freedom and constraint. Concepts are defined by constraints specifying their structure, and structure requires explanation. Consequently, Langan argues, the only concept not in need of structural explanation is the "terminal concept" with no constraints, and no structure to explain. In the CTMU, this "ontological groundstate" is called "Unbound Telesis" or UBT. | |||
Because UBT is a medium of pure potential, everything is possible within it, and this means that what can exist, does exist. However, the requirements for existence are, asserts Langan, more stringent than is normally supposed. Because UBT is unstructured, the only possibilities which can actualize from it are those with sufficient internal structure to create and configure themselves. So in the CTMU, reality, rather than being uncaused or externally caused, is self-caused, and constrained by the structure it needs to create and configure itself, that of SCSPL. | |||
The above reasoning, holds Langan, resolves the '']'' or "something-from-nothing" paradox. The paradox arises when "nothing" is taken to exclude not just "something", but the ''potential'' for "something". Because exclusion of potential is a constraint, "nothing" in this sense requires its own explanation, and cannot serve as an ontological groundstate. But when "nothing" is viewed as unconstrained potential or UBT, asserts Langan, reality arises inevitably from it. | |||
==Teleology== | |||
Reality, Langan argues, requires as a condition of its existence not merely logical consistency, but also "] consistency". To arise from UBT, reality needs a function to distinguish ''what it is'' from ''what it is not''—to "select itself" for existence. This requirement, the "Telic Principle", generalizes the well-known ]: whereas the anthropic principle addresses the degree to which human existence constrains reality, the Telic Principle addresses the way in which reality tautologically constrains itself. | |||
Because reality is self-contained, it serves as its own selection function. That is, the function, that which it selects, and the act of selection itself are identical; "existence is everywhere the choice to exist" and "reality triples as choice, chooser and chosen". Langan explores the logic of this arrangement: " large part of the CTMU is about what happens when functions, including choice, generative and causal functions, are looped so that input coincides with output coincides with functional syntax". | |||
The requirement that reality serve as its own selection function gives it a reflexive form whose goal is to self-actualize. This "MU form" is the starting configuration of SCSPL ]. With "existence and its amplification" as its sole imperative, reality selects its "future" by maximizing a parameter Langan calls "generalized ]". The CTMU is therefore a teleological theory in which the purpose of reality is to optimally self-actualize. | |||
Because reality inherits distributive freedom from UBT, parts of reality can deviate from the teleology of reality as a whole. Unable therefore to maximize utility directly, reality instead maximizes ''potential'' utility, "setting things up" for maximum benefits should teleology be pursued. Langan takes generalized utility as the basis of a system of ], defining goodness as that which furthers teleology and extending the ] to fit the stratified structure of SCSPL. | |||
==Evolution== | |||
In the CTMU, reality evolves by "telic recursion", a metacausal generalization of ordinary ] suited to pre-informational contexts. Telic recursion occurs in two stages, one primary and global, the other secondary and local. The primary stage creates the distributed laws, including the ], which reality obeys, while the secondary stage creates nondistributed, ''ad hoc'' supplements to those laws as reality transitions from state to state. | |||
Guided by the Telic Principle, telic recursion seeks to maximize generalized utility through "telic ]" between past and future states. This potential for ] extends back to the very origin of reality, so that in effect, "the system brings itself into existence as a means of atemporal communication between its past and future whereby law and state, syntax and informational content, generate and refine each other across time to maximize total systemic self-utility." | |||
The CTMU relates ], ], and ] through a process Langan calls "conspansion"—material contraction ''qua'' spatial expansion. Because reality is self-contained, argues Langan, its external size is undefined, and it cannot expand: it has nothing to expand ''into''. Instead, it must stratify inwardly into a temporal sequence of states, each state topologically contained by, but descriptively containing, the one preceding it. In the resulting "conspansive spacetime", rather than reality expanding relative to its contents, its contents contract relative to it. The point, says Langan, is to preserve the valid relationships of conventional ] while changing their ''interpretations'' so as to resolve paradoxes of cosmology and physics. | |||
Conspansion alternates between two phases: a generative phase in which events produce new possibilities, and a selective phase in which possibilities collapse into new events. The alternation occurs at a fixed conspansion rate ''c'', understood as the rate at which reality creates itself and identified by Langan with the ] in a vacuum. Langan associates conspansive alternation with ], and the CTMU features a new ] called "Sum Over Futures" {{Dubious}}. | |||
==Mind== | |||
The fundamental entity of SCSPL reality is the "syntactic operator", or unit of self-processing ]. Because, argues Langan, ] is just the specific form of ] that occurs in a mind, information processing can be described as "generalized cognition" and self-processing information as "infocognition". So in the CTMU, reality is a ] consisting of one substance (infocognition) with two aspects (information and cognition); space is a configuration of syntactic operators, and time is the activity of these operators as they process themselves and each other. | |||
The CTMU therefore supports a kind of ]. Although every part of SCSPL has a cognitive aspect, the mental capabilities of a given subsystem depend on its structure. Langan distinguishes three "levels of self-cognition": subordinate, agentive, and global. The lowest of these levels, subordinate, encompasses low-complexity objects such as rocks. In the CTMU, rocks are cognitive in the generalized sense—their molecules interact, thereby processing information—but they do not possess ] or any intrinisic ability to optimize their environment. | |||
The next level of self-cognition, which includes humans, is that of agents or "telors": observer-participants in the ongoing creation of reality. Telors possess independent volition and constructive, creative intelligence or "sentience". In the CTMU, the distributed ] do not fully determine reality; they are supplemented by "meta-laws" created by telors as reality evolves. This ability of telors is constrained by factors including locality, interference, and the fact that it must occur within the probabilistic limits of the laws of physics. | |||
The third and highest level of self-cognition, the global level, is that of reality itself. This level possesses three formal properties of SCSPL: "syntactic self-distribution" (analogous to ]), "perfect autotransductive reflexivity" (analogous to ]), and "self-configuration up to freedom" (analogous to ]). Because these are theological attributes, Langan describes reality as "the mind of God". So, claims Langan, because the CTMU constitutes absolute truth—because it is founded on tautology and supported by logical and mathematical reasoning—it proves the existence of God. | |||
==Controversy== | |||
A theory making such bold claims as the CTMU can obviously not do so without generating some controversy and debate. For example, some people might feel that the lack of ] is an impediment to taking the theory seriously; while it has been published in ''Progress in Complexity, Information, and Design'' (PCID), the journal in question is published by the ], an ] movement, and has come under fire for lacking ] and ] <ref>"With some of the claims for peer review, notably Campbell and Meyer (2003) and the e-journal PCID, the reviewers are themselves ardent supporters of intelligent design. The purpose of peer review is to expose errors, weaknesses, and significant omissions in fact and argument. That purpose is not served if the reviewers are uncritical." Mark Isaak, TalkOrigins archive 2006 </ref>, mostly because the editorial standards are seen by some to be compromised <ref>"ID leaders know the benefits of submitting their work to independent review and have established at least two purportedly "peer-reviewed" journals for ID articles. However, one has languished for want of material and quietly ceased publication, while the other has a more overtly philosophical orientation. Both journals employ a weak standard of "peer review" that amounts to no more than vetting by the editorial board or society fellows. Matthew J. Brauer, ], and Steven G. Gey (PDF file)</ref>. However, the CTMU has yet to be fully assessed by the ] and so the final word on the validity of its claims must remain unspoken until this has happened. | |||
==Further reading== | |||
The most comprehensive paper on the CTMU is the 56-page . Less formidable, but still technical, is the . For laypeople seeking a gentler introduction, there are . | |||
==References== | |||
* Langan, Christopher M. (2002). . ''Progress in Complexity, Information, and Design'' '''1.2–1.3'''. | |||
* Langan, Christopher M. (2004). "Cheating the Millennium: The Mounting Explanatory Debts of Scientific Naturalism". In ''Uncommon Dissent: Intellectuals Who Find Darwinism Unconvincing'', edited by William Dembski. ISI Books. | |||
* McFadden, Cynthia. (], ]). . ''20/20''. | |||
* Quain, John R. (], ]). . ''Popular Science''. | |||
==Endnotes== | |||
<div class="references-small"> | |||
<!--See http://en.wikipedia.org/Wikipedia:Footnotes for an explanation of how to generate footnotes using the <ref(erences/)> tags--> | |||
<references/> | |||
</div> | |||
==External links== | |||
* official site | |||
* biography at ISCID | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 14:08, 23 July 2020
Redirect to:
- From a merge: This is a redirect from a page that was merged into another page. This redirect was kept in order to preserve the edit history of this page after its content was merged into the content of the target page. Please do not remove the tag that generates this text (unless the need to recreate content on this page has been demonstrated) or delete this page.
- For redirects with substantive page histories that did not result from page merges use {{R with history}} instead.