Revision as of 16:06, 30 August 2006 editHob Gadling (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users18,385 editsNo edit summary← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 20:01, 11 December 2024 edit undoActualOswinOswald (talk | contribs)54 editsNo edit summary | ||
(536 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{short description|Position that appears to be skeptic but is actually dogmatic}} | |||
] journal Vol 12/13 founded by ] in which he coined the term ] in the mid 1980s ]] | |||
{{Use American English|date=April 2021}} | |||
'''Pathological skepticism''' (or '''Pseudoskepticism''') refers to the excessive use of ] to the detriment of that person and/or their relationships. The term is exclusively used by: | |||
{{Use mdy dates|date=April 2021}} | |||
*organized groups of persons calling themselves "]s", "]s", or "]", or (true) ]s, who believe that ] as well as skeptics have to be ] regarding their subjects, or by | |||
*persons whose beliefs are called pseudoscience by skeptics. | |||
'''Pseudoskepticism''' (] '''pseudoscepticism''') is a philosophical or scientific position that appears to be that of ] or ] but in reality is a form of ]tism. | |||
One person even claimed that organized skepticism is automatically pathological, basing his hypothesis on the fact that one skeptic group found his ideas silly.<ref>L. David Leiter, "" (PDF), in ''Journal of Scientific Exploration'', Vol. 16, No. 1, pp. 125–128, 2002. "... it is important to clarify a basic difference, the difference between ordinary (individual) skepticism and organized skepticism. This paper does not take issue with ordinary skepticism, which is seen as a useful and important human trait ... However, organized skepticism appears to be something very different: it might be called, in the words of Ed Storms, ''pathological'' skepticism; or in the words of Marcello Truzzi, ''pseudo''skepticism."</ref> Sociologist and zetetic ] (] ] at ]) wrote in 1987 | |||
:''Since "skepticism" properly refers to doubt rather than denial -- nonbelief rather than belief -- critics who take the negative rather than an agnostic position but still call themselves "skeptics" are actually pseudo-skeptics''<ref>"Marcello Truzzi, " ''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4.</ref> | |||
==Nineteenth and early twentieth centuries== | |||
==Characteristics of Pseudoskepticism== | |||
An early use of the word was in self-denigration: on 31 August 1869, ] philosopher ] wrote in his diary: | |||
Truzzi identified the following characteristics of Pseudoskepticism: | |||
{{blockquote|My instinct is in harmony with the pessimism of Buddha and of ]. It is a doubt which never leaves me, even in my moments of religious fervor. Nature is indeed for me a ]; and I look at her, as it were, with the eyes of an artist. My intelligence remains skeptical. What, then, do I believe in? I do not know. And what is it I hope for? It would be difficult to say. Folly! I believe in goodness, and I hope that good will prevail. Deep within this ironical and disappointed being of mine there is a child hidden — a frank, sad, simple creature, who believes in the ideal, in love, in holiness, and all heavenly superstitions. A whole millennium of idyls sleeps in my heart; I am a pseudo-skeptic, a pseudo-scoffer.<ref>Charles Dudley Warner, Editor, ''Library Of The World's Best Literature Ancient And Modern, Vol. II'', 1896. Online at Project Gutenberg (e.g. )</ref>}} | |||
*The tendency to deny, rather than doubt,<ref>"Marcello Truzzi, " ''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4. "Though many in this category who dismiss and ridicule anomaly claims call themselves "skeptics," they often are really "pseudo-skeptics" because they deny rather than doubt anomaly claims"</ref> | |||
*Double standards in the application of criticism, <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. they seem less inclined to take the same critical stance towards orthodox theories. For example, they may attack alternative methods in medicine (e.g., for a lack of double-blind studies) while ignoring that similar criticisms can be levelled against much conventional medicine"</ref> | |||
*The making of judgements without full inquiry,<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "those I term scoffers often make judgements without full inquiry"</ref> | |||
*Tendency to discredit, rather than investigate,<ref>Hyman, Ray, 1980. "Pathological Science: Towards a Proper Diagnosis and Remedy," ''Zetetic Scholar'', No. 6, 31-43. Truzzi wrote: ".. they may be more interested in discrediting an anomaly claim than in dispassionately investigating it"</ref> | |||
*Use of ridicule or '']'' attacks,<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "scoffers sometimes manage to discredit anomaly claims (e.g., through ridicule or ad hominem attacks) "</ref> | |||
*Presenting insufficient evidence or proof, <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "scoffers sometimes manage to discredit anomaly claims .. without presenting any solid disproof</ref> | |||
*Pejorative labelling of proponents as "promoters", "pseudoscientists" or practitioners of "pathological science." <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "A characteristic of many scoffers is their pejorative characterization of proponents as "promoters" and sometimes even the most protoscientific anomaly claimants are labelled as "pseudoscientists" or practitioners of "pathological science." "</ref> | |||
*Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof, <ref>Marcello Truzzi, "]", ''Zetetic Scholar'', #12-13, 1987. "Critics who assert negative claims, but who mistakenly call themselves "skeptics," often act as though they have no burden of proof placed on them at all, though such a stance would be appropriate only for the agnostic or true skeptic"</ref> | |||
*Making unsubstantiated counter-claims,<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. the true skeptic does not assert a claim, ''he has no burden to prove anything''. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a ''negative hypothesis'' — saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact — he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof."</ref> | |||
*Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence,<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. many critics seem to feel it is only necessary to present a case for their counter-claims based upon plausibility rather than empirical evidence"</ref> | |||
*Suggesting that unconvincing evidence is grounds for dismissing it,<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "Showing evidence is unconvincing is not grounds for completely dismissing it."</ref> | |||
*Tendency to dismiss ''all'' evidence, <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "Some proponents of anomaly claims, like some critics, seen unwilling to consider evidence in probabilistic terms, clinging to any slim loose end as though the critic must disprove all evidence ever put forward for a particular claim."</ref> | |||
It soon acquired its usual meaning where a claimed skeptic is accused of excessive sureness in turning initial doubts into certainties. In 1908 ] wrote on ]'s criticism of philosopher ] that: | |||
==History== | |||
{{blockquote|Strauss had been a preacher but had renounced the cloth and set up shop as a critic of Christianity. He had labored with good intentions, no doubt, but the net result of all his smug agnosticism was that his disciples were as self-satisfied, bigoted, and prejudiced in the garb of agnostics as they had been before as Christians. Nietzsche's eye saw this and in the first of his little pamphlets "David Strauss, der Bekenner und der Schriftsteller" ("David Strauss, the Confessor and the Writer"), he bore down on Strauss's bourgeoise pseudo-skepticism most savagely. This was 1873.<ref>H. L. (Henry Louis) Mencken, ''The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche'' (1908) publ. T.F. Unwin. Reprinted in ''Friedrich Nietzsche'', Originally published: Boston : Luce and Co., 1913. .</ref>|sign=|source=}} | |||
Professor of Philosophy at the University of Illinois, Frederick L. Will used the term "pseudo-skepticism" in 1942. ] writes: | |||
The terms ''Pseudoskepticism'' was coined by Truzzi in 1987, in response to the ] who applied the label of "]s" to fields which Truzzi thought might be better described as ].<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "A characteristic of many scoffers is their pejorative characterization of proponents as "promoters" and sometimes even the most protoscientific anomaly claimants are labelled as "pseudoscientists" or practitioners of "pathological science." "</ref> | |||
{{blockquote| Will was no exception. He began as an analytical philosopher, distinguishing different uses of language with the aim of showing that certain traditional philosophical problems need no longer trouble us, once we have understood how to make the relevant linguistic distinctions. The enemies were two: the philosophical skeptic who poses these false problems and the philosopher who thinks that the skeptic needs to be answered. So in "Is there a Problem of Induction?" (''Journal of Philosophy'', 1942) it is two senses of "know" that are to be distinguished: "All the uneasiness, the pseudo-skepticism and the pseudo-problem of induction, would never appear if it were possible to keep clear that 'know' in the statement that we do not know statements about the future is employed in a very special sense, not at all its ordinary one.<ref>Alasdair MacIntyre "" to the book ''Pragmatism and Realism'' by Frederick L. Will (1997) quoting his earlier paper "" ''Journal of Philosophy'', Vol. 39, No. 19 (September 10, 1942), pp. 505-513</ref>}} | |||
] Professor of English, John E. Sitter used the term in 1977 in a discussion of ]: "Pope's intent, I believe, is to chasten the reader's skepticism — the pseudo-skepticism of the overly confident 'you' ... "<ref>John E. Sitter, "" ''SEL: Studies in English Literature 1500–1900'', Vol. 17, No. 3, Restoration and Eighteenth Century (Summer, 1977), pp. 435-449</ref> | |||
The term ''Pathological skepticism'' was coined by Dr Ed Storms at the Third International Conference on the Cold Fusion (ICCF3), held in Nagoya, Japan in October 1992,<ref>Scott R. Chubb, "" (PDF, 2000) ''Accountability in Research'', 2000. 8</ref>. | |||
==Truzzi== | |||
==Notes and references== | |||
In 1987, ] revived the term specifically for arguments which use scientific-sounding language to disparage or refute given beliefs, theories, or claims, but which in fact fail to follow the precepts of conventional ]. He argued that scientific skepticism is ] to new ideas, making no claims about them but waiting for them to satisfy a burden of proof before granting them validity. Pseudoskepticism, by contrast, involves "negative hypotheses"—theoretical assertions that some belief, theory, or claim is factually wrong—without satisfying the burden of proof that such negative theoretical assertions would require.<ref name="truzzi1">{{cite journal | last = Truzzi | first = Marcello | author-link= Marcello Truzzi | url = http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html | title = On Pseudo-Skepticism | year = 1987 | journal = Zetetic Scholar | issue = 12/13 | pages = 3–4| access-date = 2008-10-10}}</ref><ref>{{dead link|date=July 2024|bot=medic}}{{cbignore|bot=medic}}, '']'', February 15, 2003</ref><ref> '']'', October 10, 2007</ref><ref> '']'', January 1, 2003</ref> | |||
<div class="references-small"> | |||
<!--See http://en.wikipedia.org/Wikipedia:Footnotes for an explanation of how to generate footnotes using the <ref(erences/)> tags--> | |||
<references/> | |||
</div> | |||
In 1987, while working as a professor of ] at ], Truzzi gave the following description of pseudoskeptics in the journal ''Zetetic Scholar'' (which he founded): | |||
==See also== | |||
{{quotation|In science, the burden of proof falls upon the claimant; and the more extraordinary a claim, the heavier is the burden of proof demanded. The true skeptic takes an agnostic position, one that says the claim is not proved rather than disproved. He asserts that the claimant has not borne the burden of proof and that science must continue to build its ] of reality without incorporating the extraordinary claim as a new "fact." Since the true skeptic does not assert a claim, he has no burden to prove anything. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a negative hypothesis—saying, for instance, that a seeming ] ] was actually due to an artifact—he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof... | |||
* ] | |||
* Some ]s are criticized as pseudoskeptics, fighting any fringe claim at all costs (regardless of the propositions). | |||
* ] refers to certain epistemologies based on science. | |||
* ] is the creation of false impressions or advocacy of false ideas and concepts using rhetoric, ], or insufficient or falsified evidence. | |||
* ] is an opponent of various pseudosciences who has been accused of Pathological skepticism. | |||
* ] is a web site with a collection of cross-referenced essays over various scientific endeavors. | |||
* ] (CSICOP) is an organization which professes to encourage open minded, critical investigation of ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
Both critics and proponents need to learn to think of ] in science as more like that found in the law courts, imperfect and with varying degrees of proof and evidence. Absolute truth, like absolute justice, is seldom obtainable. We can only do our best to approximate them. | |||
===External links and resources=== | |||
|Marcello Truzzi|"On Pseudo-Skepticism", ''Zetetic Scholar'', 12/13, pp3-4, 1987<ref name="truzzi1"/>}} | |||
* Truzzi, Marcello, "''''". Oxymoron, 1998 | |||
* Drasin, Daniel, "''''". aol.com, 1997. | |||
* Milton, Richard, "''''". | |||
* Mooney, Chris, "''''". CSICOP, December, 2003. | |||
* Haack, Susan, "''''". CSICOP, December 1997. | |||
* Sofka, Michael D., "''''". ISUNY, March, 2002. | |||
* Beaty, William J., "''''". 1996. | |||
* Hyman, Ray, "''''". (csicop.org) | |||
* Martin, Brian, "''''". Society for Scientific Exploration. Journal of Scientific Exploration, Volume 12 No 4. 1998. (]) | |||
* ], "'' : Method for rating potentially revolutionary contributions to physics.''". | |||
* Kruger, Justin, and David Dunning "''''". Department of Psychology, Cornell University. | |||
* by Winston Wu | |||
* ], in which he discusses CSICOP and pseudoskeptism, what he calls "irrational rationalists" and "fundamentalist materialism" | |||
* , discussing the fallacious labeling of skeptics as "pseudo-skeptics". | |||
Truzzi attributed the following characteristics to pseudoskeptics:<ref name="truzzi1"/> | |||
] | |||
#Denying, when only doubt has been established | |||
#Double standards in the application of criticism | |||
#The tendency to discredit rather than investigate | |||
#Presenting insufficient evidence or proof | |||
#Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof | |||
#Making unsubstantiated counter-claims | |||
#Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence | |||
#Suggesting that unconvincing evidence provides grounds for completely dismissing a claim | |||
He characterized true skepticism as:<ref name="truzzi1"/> | |||
#Acceptance of doubt when neither assertion nor denial has been established | |||
#No burden of proof to take an agnostic position | |||
#Agreement that the corpus of established knowledge must be based on what is proved, but recognising its incompleteness | |||
#Even-handedness in requirement for proofs, whatever their implication | |||
#Accepting that a failure of a proof in itself proves nothing | |||
#Continuing examination of the results of experiments even when flaws are found | |||
== Subsequent usage == | |||
], who lost her initial belief in ] and in 1991 became a ] fellow, later described what she termed the "worst kind of pseudoskepticism": | |||
{{blockquote|There are some members of the skeptics’ groups who clearly believe they know the right answer prior to inquiry. They appear not to be interested in weighing alternatives, investigating strange claims, or trying out psychic experiences or altered states for themselves (heaven forbid!), but only in promoting their own particular belief structure and cohesion.<ref>JE Kennedy, "", ''The Journal of Parapsychology'', Volume 67, pp. 53–74, 2003. See Note 1 page 64 quoting Blackmore, S. J. (1994). Women skeptics. In L. Coly & R. White (Eds.), ''Women and parapsychology'' (pp. 234–236). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.</ref>}} | |||
] from the Department of Religious Studies at the ], labels the "extreme position that all significant evidence supporting paranormal phenomena is a result of deception or lies" as pseudoskepticism.<ref>Michael Stoeber, Hugo Anthony Meynell, ''Critical Reflections on the Paranormal'', SUNY Press, 1996, {{ISBN|0-7914-3063-4}}, {{ISBN|978-0-7914-3063-7}} </ref> | |||
While Truzzi's characterization was aimed at the holders of majority views whom he considered were excessively impatient of minority opinions, the term has been used to describe advocates of minority intellectual positions who engage in pseudoskeptical behavior when they characterize themselves as "skeptics" despite ] evidence that conforms to a preexisting belief. Thus according to Richard Cameron Wilson, some advocates of ] are indulging in "bogus scepticism" when they argue in this way.<ref name=Wilson_NS>, '']'', 18 September 2008</ref> Wilson argues that the characteristic feature of false skepticism is that it "centres not on an impartial search for the truth, but on the defence of a preconceived ideological position".<ref name=Wilson_fooled>Richard C. Wilson, , ''Icon'', 2008, {{ISBN|1-84831-014-5}}, 240 pages</ref> Examples include ] and ]. | |||
== See also == | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
== Notes and references == | |||
{{reflist|2}} | |||
{{skepticism}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 20:01, 11 December 2024
Position that appears to be skeptic but is actually dogmatic
Pseudoskepticism (also spelled as pseudoscepticism) is a philosophical or scientific position that appears to be that of skepticism or scientific skepticism but in reality is a form of dogmatism.
Nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
An early use of the word was in self-denigration: on 31 August 1869, Swiss philosopher Henri-Frédéric Amiel wrote in his diary:
My instinct is in harmony with the pessimism of Buddha and of Schopenhauer. It is a doubt which never leaves me, even in my moments of religious fervor. Nature is indeed for me a Maïa; and I look at her, as it were, with the eyes of an artist. My intelligence remains skeptical. What, then, do I believe in? I do not know. And what is it I hope for? It would be difficult to say. Folly! I believe in goodness, and I hope that good will prevail. Deep within this ironical and disappointed being of mine there is a child hidden — a frank, sad, simple creature, who believes in the ideal, in love, in holiness, and all heavenly superstitions. A whole millennium of idyls sleeps in my heart; I am a pseudo-skeptic, a pseudo-scoffer.
It soon acquired its usual meaning where a claimed skeptic is accused of excessive sureness in turning initial doubts into certainties. In 1908 Henry Louis Mencken wrote on Friedrich Nietzsche's criticism of philosopher David Strauss that:
Strauss had been a preacher but had renounced the cloth and set up shop as a critic of Christianity. He had labored with good intentions, no doubt, but the net result of all his smug agnosticism was that his disciples were as self-satisfied, bigoted, and prejudiced in the garb of agnostics as they had been before as Christians. Nietzsche's eye saw this and in the first of his little pamphlets "David Strauss, der Bekenner und der Schriftsteller" ("David Strauss, the Confessor and the Writer"), he bore down on Strauss's bourgeoise pseudo-skepticism most savagely. This was 1873.
Professor of Philosophy at the University of Illinois, Frederick L. Will used the term "pseudo-skepticism" in 1942. Alasdair MacIntyre writes:
Will was no exception. He began as an analytical philosopher, distinguishing different uses of language with the aim of showing that certain traditional philosophical problems need no longer trouble us, once we have understood how to make the relevant linguistic distinctions. The enemies were two: the philosophical skeptic who poses these false problems and the philosopher who thinks that the skeptic needs to be answered. So in "Is there a Problem of Induction?" (Journal of Philosophy, 1942) it is two senses of "know" that are to be distinguished: "All the uneasiness, the pseudo-skepticism and the pseudo-problem of induction, would never appear if it were possible to keep clear that 'know' in the statement that we do not know statements about the future is employed in a very special sense, not at all its ordinary one.
Notre Dame Professor of English, John E. Sitter used the term in 1977 in a discussion of Alexander Pope: "Pope's intent, I believe, is to chasten the reader's skepticism — the pseudo-skepticism of the overly confident 'you' ... "
Truzzi
In 1987, Marcello Truzzi revived the term specifically for arguments which use scientific-sounding language to disparage or refute given beliefs, theories, or claims, but which in fact fail to follow the precepts of conventional scientific skepticism. He argued that scientific skepticism is agnostic to new ideas, making no claims about them but waiting for them to satisfy a burden of proof before granting them validity. Pseudoskepticism, by contrast, involves "negative hypotheses"—theoretical assertions that some belief, theory, or claim is factually wrong—without satisfying the burden of proof that such negative theoretical assertions would require.
In 1987, while working as a professor of sociology at Eastern Michigan University, Truzzi gave the following description of pseudoskeptics in the journal Zetetic Scholar (which he founded):
In science, the burden of proof falls upon the claimant; and the more extraordinary a claim, the heavier is the burden of proof demanded. The true skeptic takes an agnostic position, one that says the claim is not proved rather than disproved. He asserts that the claimant has not borne the burden of proof and that science must continue to build its cognitive map of reality without incorporating the extraordinary claim as a new "fact." Since the true skeptic does not assert a claim, he has no burden to prove anything. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a negative hypothesis—saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact—he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof...
Both critics and proponents need to learn to think of adjudication in science as more like that found in the law courts, imperfect and with varying degrees of proof and evidence. Absolute truth, like absolute justice, is seldom obtainable. We can only do our best to approximate them.
— Marcello Truzzi, "On Pseudo-Skepticism", Zetetic Scholar, 12/13, pp3-4, 1987
Truzzi attributed the following characteristics to pseudoskeptics:
- Denying, when only doubt has been established
- Double standards in the application of criticism
- The tendency to discredit rather than investigate
- Presenting insufficient evidence or proof
- Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof
- Making unsubstantiated counter-claims
- Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence
- Suggesting that unconvincing evidence provides grounds for completely dismissing a claim
He characterized true skepticism as:
- Acceptance of doubt when neither assertion nor denial has been established
- No burden of proof to take an agnostic position
- Agreement that the corpus of established knowledge must be based on what is proved, but recognising its incompleteness
- Even-handedness in requirement for proofs, whatever their implication
- Accepting that a failure of a proof in itself proves nothing
- Continuing examination of the results of experiments even when flaws are found
Subsequent usage
Susan Blackmore, who lost her initial belief in parapsychology and in 1991 became a CSICOP fellow, later described what she termed the "worst kind of pseudoskepticism":
There are some members of the skeptics’ groups who clearly believe they know the right answer prior to inquiry. They appear not to be interested in weighing alternatives, investigating strange claims, or trying out psychic experiences or altered states for themselves (heaven forbid!), but only in promoting their own particular belief structure and cohesion.
Hugo Anthony Meynell from the Department of Religious Studies at the University of Calgary, labels the "extreme position that all significant evidence supporting paranormal phenomena is a result of deception or lies" as pseudoskepticism.
While Truzzi's characterization was aimed at the holders of majority views whom he considered were excessively impatient of minority opinions, the term has been used to describe advocates of minority intellectual positions who engage in pseudoskeptical behavior when they characterize themselves as "skeptics" despite cherry picking evidence that conforms to a preexisting belief. Thus according to Richard Cameron Wilson, some advocates of AIDS denial are indulging in "bogus scepticism" when they argue in this way. Wilson argues that the characteristic feature of false skepticism is that it "centres not on an impartial search for the truth, but on the defence of a preconceived ideological position". Examples include climate change denial and Moon landing denial.
See also
- Agnosticism
- Argument from ignorance
- Debunker
- Denialism
- Pseudoscience
- Pseudorationalism
- Scientism
- The New Inquisition
- Fundamentalist Atheism
Notes and references
- Charles Dudley Warner, Editor, Library Of The World's Best Literature Ancient And Modern, Vol. II, 1896. Online at Project Gutenberg (e.g. here)
- H. L. (Henry Louis) Mencken, The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche (1908) publ. T.F. Unwin. Reprinted in Friedrich Nietzsche, Originally published: Boston : Luce and Co., 1913. p.30.
- Alasdair MacIntyre "Foreword" to the book Pragmatism and Realism by Frederick L. Will (1997) quoting his earlier paper "Is There a Problem of Induction?" Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 39, No. 19 (September 10, 1942), pp. 505-513
- John E. Sitter, "The Argument of Pope's Epistle to Cobham" SEL: Studies in English Literature 1500–1900, Vol. 17, No. 3, Restoration and Eighteenth Century (Summer, 1977), pp. 435-449
- ^ Truzzi, Marcello (1987). "On Pseudo-Skepticism". Zetetic Scholar (12/13): 3–4. Retrieved October 10, 2008.
- |+Helped+form+the+Committee+for+the+Scientific+Investigation+of+Claims+of+the+Paranormal;+67&pqatl=google "Marcello Truzzi: Helped form the Committee for the Scientific Investigation of Claims of the Paranormal", The San Diego Union Tribune, February 15, 2003
- "Marla vs. Pollock: Who’s the Fraudiest?" LA Weekly, October 10, 2007
- "The plain truth about legal truth" Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, January 1, 2003
- JE Kennedy, "The Capricious, Actively Evasive, Unsustainable Nature of Psi: A Summary and Hypotheses", The Journal of Parapsychology, Volume 67, pp. 53–74, 2003. See Note 1 page 64 quoting Blackmore, S. J. (1994). Women skeptics. In L. Coly & R. White (Eds.), Women and parapsychology (pp. 234–236). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
- Michael Stoeber, Hugo Anthony Meynell, Critical Reflections on the Paranormal, SUNY Press, 1996, ISBN 0-7914-3063-4, ISBN 978-0-7914-3063-7 page 16
- Richard Wilson, "Against the Evidence", New Statesman, 18 September 2008
- Richard C. Wilson, "Don't get fooled again: the sceptic's guide to life", Icon, 2008, ISBN 1-84831-014-5, 240 pages
Skepticism | |
---|---|
Types of skepticism | |
Skeptical philosophies | |
Skeptical philosophers | |
Skeptical scenarios | |
Responses | |
Lists |