Misplaced Pages

Niccolò Machiavelli: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 06:13, 16 December 2019 editSurpriseandConquer (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users519 edits Undid revision 930961574 by 2409:4073:30B:C925:0:0:5F6:38B0 (talk) ?Tag: Undo← Previous edit Latest revision as of 06:58, 24 December 2024 edit undoSer Amantio di Nicolao (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Administrators6,252,162 edits Copying from Category:16th-century Italian historians to Category:Italian male non-fiction writers using Cat-a-lot 
(846 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Florentine statesman, diplomat, and political theorist (1469–1527)}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=November 2019}}
{{Redirect| Machiavelli}} {{other uses|Machiavelli (disambiguation)|Macchiavelli (surname)}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=June 2023}}
{{Infobox philosopher {{Infobox philosopher
|region = ] |region = ]
|era = ] |era = ]
|image = Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli by Santi di Tito.jpg |image = Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli.jpg
|caption = Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli by ] |caption = Portrait by ], {{circa|1550–1600}}
|name = Niccolò Machiavelli |name = Niccolò Machiavelli
|birth_date = 3 May 1469 |birth_date = {{birth date|1469|5|3|df=y}}
|birth_place = ], ] |birth_place = ], ]
|children = Primerana, Piero, Baccina, Guido, Bernardo, Lodovico
|death_date = {{death date and age|1527|6|21|1469|5|3|df=y}} |death_date = {{death date and age|1527|6|21|1469|5|3|df=y}}
|death_place = Florence, Republic of Florence |death_place = Florence, Republic of Florence
|school_tradition = {{ubl|]|]}}
|citizenship = ]
|main_interests = ] and ], ], history
|school_tradition = ], ]
|notable_works = {{ubl|'']''|'']''}}
|main_interests = ] and ], ], ]
|spouse = {{marriage|Marietta ]|1501}}
|notable_works = '']''
|notable_ideas = ] |notable_ideas = Classical realism, '']'', ], ]
|signature = Machiavelli Signature.svg |signature = Machiavelli Signature.svg
|influences = ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ]
|influenced = ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ],<ref>{{cite book |last1= Najemy |first1= John M. |title= The Cambridge Companion to Machiavelli |date= 2010 |publisher= Cambridge University Press |page= 259}}</ref> ]
}} }}


'''Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli''' ({{IPAc-en|ˌ|m|æ|k|i|ə|ˈ|v|ɛ|l|i}}, {{IPAc-en|also|US|ˌ|m|ɑː|k|-}}; {{IPA-it|nikkoˈlɔ mmakjaˈvɛlli|lang}}; 3 May 1469 – 21 June 1527) was an ] diplomat, politician, historian, philosopher, writer, playwright and poet of the ] period.<ref>{{cite web|url= https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title= Niccolo Machiavelli - Italian statesman and writer}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url= http://www.biography.com/people/niccol%C3%B2-machiavelli-9392446|title= Niccolò Machiavelli}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|url= https://www.iep.utm.edu/machiave/|title= Niccolò Machiavelli |date= |website= Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|archive-url= |archive-date=|access-date=1 November 2018}}</ref> He has often been called the father of modern ]<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=1w5sCPpcDPMC&pg=PA65&dq=Machiavelli+father+of+modern+political+philosophy#v=onepage&q=Machiavelli%20father%20of%20modern%20political%20philosophy&f=false|title=Between Eternities: On the Tradition of Political Philosophy, Past, Present, and Future|last=Smith|first=Gregory B.|date=2008|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=9780739120774|location=|pages=65|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=2d4qgsSLZQgC&pg=PA29&dq=Machiavelli+founder+of+modern+political+philosophy#v=onepage&q=Machiavelli%20founder%20of%20modern%20political%20philosophy&f=false|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|date=2004|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=9780739106310|location=|pages=29|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=W5m6lCFR53YC&printsec=frontcover&dq=leo+strauss+what+is+political+philosophy#v=onepage&q=Machiavelli&f=false|title=What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies|last=Strauss is most notable for this description.|date=15 October 1988|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226777139|location=|pages=41|language=en}}</ref> and ]. For many years he served as a senior official in the ] with responsibilities in diplomatic and military affairs. He wrote comedies, carnival songs, and poetry. His personal correspondence is of high importance to historians and scholars.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R1mYDwAAQBAJ&lpg=PP1&dq=machiavelli%20letters&pg=PP1#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513-1515|last=Najemy|first=John M.|date=15 January 2019|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=9780691656649|language=en}}</ref> He worked as secretary to the Second ] of the Republic of Florence from 1498 to 1512, when the ] were out of power. He wrote his best-known work '']'' (''Il Principe'') in 1513, having been exiled from city affairs. '''Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli'''{{efn|{{IPAc-en|ˈ|n|ɪ|k|ə|l|əʊ|_|ˌ|m|æ|k|i|ə|ˈ|v|ɛ|l|i}} {{respell|NIK|ə|loh|_|MAK|ee|ə|VEL|ee}}, {{IPAc-en|USalso|-|_|ˌ|m|ɑː|k|-}} {{respell|-_|MAHK|-}};<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.ldoceonline.com/dictionary/niccolo-machiavelli|title=Machiavelli, Niccolò|work=]|publisher=]|accessdate=5 August 2023}}</ref><ref>{{Cite dictionary |url=http://www.lexico.com/en/definition/Machievelli,+Niccol%C3%B2 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220210021945/https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavelli,_niccolo?s=t |url-status=dead |archive-date=10 February 2022 |title=Machievelli, Niccolò |dictionary=] US English Dictionary |publisher=]}}</ref><ref>{{cite American Heritage Dictionary|Machiavelli|access-date=9 February 2022}}</ref> {{IPA|it|nikkoˈlɔ mmakjaˈvɛlli|lang}}; also ] in English as '''Nicholas&nbsp;Machiavel''' ({{IPAc-en|ˈ|m|æ|k|i|ə|v|ɛ|l}} {{respell|MAK|ee|ə|vel}}, {{IPAc-en|USalso|ˈ|m|ɑː|k|-}} {{respell|MAHK|-}}).}} (3 May 1469 – 21 June 1527) was a ]<ref>Dietz, Mary G.. Machiavelli, Niccolò (1469–1527), 1998, https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-S080-1. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis</ref><ref>Berridge, G.R., Lloyd, L. (2012). M. In: Barder, B., Pope, L.E., Rana, K.S. (eds) The Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Diplomacy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137017611_13</ref> diplomat, author, philosopher, and historian who lived during the ]. He is best known for his political treatise '']'' ({{lang|it|Il Principe}}), written around 1513 but not published until 1532, five years after his death.<ref>For example: {{cite web|url= https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title= Niccolo Machiavelli Italian statesman and writer|date= 17 June 2023}} and {{Cite web|url= https://www.iep.utm.edu/machiave/|title= Niccolò Machiavelli |website= Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=1 November 2018}}</ref> He has often been called the father of modern ] and ].<ref>For example: {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1w5sCPpcDPMC&pg=PA65|title=Between Eternities: On the Tradition of Political Philosophy, Past, Present, and Future|last=Smith|first=Gregory B.|date=2008|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0739120774|page=65}}, {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2d4qgsSLZQgC&pg=PA29|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|date=2004|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0739106310|page=29}}, {{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=W5m6lCFR53YC|title=What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies|last=Strauss|year=1988|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226777139|page=41}}</ref>


For many years he served as a senior official in the ] with responsibilities in diplomatic and military affairs. He wrote comedies, carnival songs, and poetry. His personal correspondence is also important to historians and scholars of Italian correspondence.<ref>{{harvnb|Najemy|1993|p=missing}}</ref> He worked as ] to the second ] of the Republic of Florence from 1498 to 1512, when the ] were out of power.
The word ''Machiavellian'' is widely used as a pejorative to characterize unscrupulous politicians of the sort Machiavelli advised most famously in ''The Prince.''<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli {{!}} Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=8 August 2019}}</ref> Machiavelli proposed that immoral behavior, such as dishonesty and the killing of innocents, was normal and effective in politics.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=0QNxMcwNu7cC&printsec=frontcover&dq=ernst+cassirer+the+myth+of+the+state#v=onepage&q=ernst%20cassirer%20the%20myth%20of%20the%20state&f=false|title=The Myth of the State|last=Cassirer|first=Ernst|date=1946|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=9780300000368|location=|pages=141–145|language=en}}</ref> He also notably encouraged politicians to engage in evil when it would be necessary for political expediency.<ref>For example, The Prince chap. 15, and The Discourses Book I, chapter 9</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E7mScxst9UoC&lpg=PP1&dq=history%20of%20political%20philosophy&pg=PT315#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=History of Political Philosophy|last=Strauss|first=Leo|last2=Cropsey|first2=Joseph|date=15 June 2012|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226924717|location=|pages=297|language=en|url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&lpg=PP1&dq=machiavelli's%20virtue&pg=PA178#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|date=25 February 1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226503721|location=|pages=178|language=en}}</ref> The book gained notoriety due to claims that it teaches "evil recommendations to tyrants to help them maintain their power".<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Giorgini |first1= Giovanni |title= Five Hundred Years of Italian Scholarship on Machiavelli's Prince |journal= Review of Politics |date= 2013 |volume= 75 |issue= 4 |pages= 625–40|doi= 10.1017/S0034670513000624}}</ref>


After his death Machiavelli's name came ] of the sort he advised most famously in his work, ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|access-date=8 August 2019}}</ref> He claimed that his experience and reading of history showed him that politics has always involved deception, treachery, and crime.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/mythofstate0000cass|url-access=registration|quote=ernst cassirer the myth of the state.|title=The Myth of the State|last=Cassirer|first=Ernst|date=1946|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=978-0300000368|pages=–145}}</ref> He advised rulers to engage in evil when political necessity requires it, and argued specifically that successful reformers of states should not be blamed for killing other leaders who could block change.<ref>For example, ''The Prince'' chap. 15, and ''The Discourses'' Book I, chapter 9</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E7mScxst9UoC&q=history%20of%20political%20philosophy&pg=PT315|title=History of Political Philosophy|last1=Strauss|first1=Leo|last2=Cropsey|first2=Joseph|year= 2012|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226924717|page=297}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=machiavelli's%20virtue&pg=PA178|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year= 1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503721|page=178}}</ref> Machiavelli's ''Prince'' has been surrounded by controversy since it was published. Some consider it to be a straightforward description of political reality. Others view ''The Prince'' as a manual, teaching would-be tyrants how they should seize and maintain power.<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Giorgini |first1= Giovanni |title= Five Hundred Years of Italian Scholarship on Machiavelli's Prince |journal= Review of Politics |date= 2013 |volume= 75 |issue= 4 |pages= 625–640|doi= 10.1017/S0034670513000624|s2cid= 146970196 | issn=0034-6705}}</ref> Even into recent times, some scholars, such as ], have restated the traditional opinion that Machiavelli was a "teacher of evil".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Strauss|first=Leo|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oi2GDwAAQBAJ&q=thoughts+on+Machiavelli|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|year=2014|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226230979|language=en|page=9}}</ref>
The term ''Machiavellian'' often connotes political deceit, deviousness, and ]. Even though Machiavelli has become most famous for his work on principalities, scholars also give attention to the exhortations in his other works of political philosophy. His much less popular treatise, the '']'', is often said to have paved the way of modern republicanism.<ref>Harvey Mansfield and Nathan Tarcov, "Introduction to the Discourses". In their translation of the Discourses on Livy</ref>

Even though Machiavelli has become most famous for his work on principalities, scholars also give attention to the exhortations in his other works of political philosophy. While less well known than ''The Prince'', the '']'' (composed {{circa|1517}}) has been said to have paved the way for modern ].<ref>Harvey Mansfield and Nathan Tarcov, "Introduction to the Discourses". In their translation of the ''Discourses on Livy''</ref> His works were a major influence on ] authors who revived interest in ], such as ] and ].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Theodosiadis|first=Michail|date=June–August 2021|title=From Hobbes and Locke to Machiavelli's virtù in the political context of meliorism: popular eucosmia and the value of moral memory|journal=Polis Revista|volume=11|pages=25–60}}</ref> Machiavelli's political realism has continued to influence generations of academics and politicians, including ], and his approach has been compared to the '']'' of figures such as ].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Pflanze |first=Otto |date=1958 |title=Bismarck's "Realpolitik" |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1404857 |journal=The Review of Politics |volume=20 |issue=4 |pages=492–514 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500034185 |jstor=1404857 |s2cid=144663704 |issn=0034-6705}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Arendt |first=Hannah |title=The Human Condition |publisher=Chicago University Press |year=1988 |location=Chicago |page=77}}</ref>


== Life == == Life ==
{{See also|Timeline of Niccolò Machiavelli}} {{For timeline|Timeline of Niccolò Machiavelli}}
]
Machiavelli was born in ], Italy, the third child and first son of attorney ] and his wife, Bartolomea di Stefano Nelli.<ref>{{Harvtxt|de Grazia|1989}}</ref> The Machiavelli family is believed to be descended from the old ] and to have produced thirteen Florentine ],<ref>{{CathEncy|wstitle=Niccolò Machiavelli}}</ref> one of the offices of a group of nine citizens selected by drawing lots every two months and who formed the government, or ]; but he was never a full citizen of Florence because of the nature of Florentine citizenship in that time even under the republican regime. Machiavelli married Marietta Corsini in 1502.<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Guarini|1999|p=21}}</ref>


]]]
Machiavelli was born in a tumultuous era in which popes waged acquisitive wars against Italian ]s, and people and cities often fell from power as France, Spain, and the ] battled for regional influence and control. Political-military alliances continually changed, featuring ] (mercenary leaders), who changed sides without warning, and the rise and fall of many short-lived governments.<ref>Maurizio Viroli, ''Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli'' (2000), ch 1</ref>
Machiavelli was born in ], Italy, the third child and first son of attorney ] and his wife, Bartolomea di Stefano Nelli, on 3 May 1469.<ref>{{Harvtxt|de Grazia|1989}}</ref> The Machiavelli family is believed to be descended from the old ] and to have produced thirteen Florentine ],<ref>{{CathEncy|wstitle=Niccolò Machiavelli}}</ref> one of the offices of a group of nine citizens selected by drawing lots every two months and who formed the government, or ]; he was never, though, a full citizen of Florence because of the nature of Florentine citizenship in that time even under the republican regime. Machiavelli married Marietta ] in 1501. They had seven children, five sons and two daughters: Primerana, Bernardo, Lodovico, Guido, {{interlanguage link|lt=Piero|Piero Machiavelli|it}}, Baccina and Totto.<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Guarini|1999|p=21}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |title=Machiavèlli, Niccolò nell'Enciclopedia Treccani |url=https://www.treccani.it/enciclopedia/niccolo-machiavelli |access-date=2023-07-11 |website=www.treccani.it |language=it-IT}}</ref>


Machiavelli was born in a tumultuous era. The Italian ]s, and the families and individuals who ran them could rise and fall suddenly, as popes and the kings of France, Spain, and the ] waged acquisitive wars for regional influence and control. Political-military alliances continually changed, featuring ] (mercenary leaders), who changed sides without warning, and the rise and fall of many short-lived governments.<ref>Maurizio Viroli, ''Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli'' (2000), ch 1</ref>
Machiavelli was taught grammar, rhetoric, and Latin. It is thought that he did not learn Greek even though Florence was at the time one of the centers of Greek scholarship in Europe. In 1494 Florence restored the ], expelling the ] family that had ruled Florence for some sixty years. Shortly after the execution of ], Machiavelli was appointed to an office of the second chancery, a medieval writing office that put Machiavelli in charge of the production of official Florentine government documents.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QMasak4LLcQC&lpg=PP1&dq=inauthor:%22Roberto%20Ridolfi%22&pg=PT28#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli|last=Ridolfi|first=Roberto|date=17 June 2013|publisher=Routledge|isbn=9781135026615|location=|pages=28|language=en}}</ref> Shortly thereafter, he was also made the secretary of the ''Dieci di Libertà e Pace.''


Machiavelli was taught grammar, rhetoric, and Latin by his teacher, Paolo da Ronciglione.<ref>{{Citation|url=https://totallyhistory.com/niccolo-machiavelli/|title=Niccolo Machiavelli Biography – Life of Florentine Republic Official|date=13 December 2013}}</ref> It is unknown whether Machiavelli knew Greek; Florence was at the time one of the centres of Greek scholarship in Europe.<ref>{{cite web |title=Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) |url=https://iep.utm.edu/machiave/ |website=IEP |publisher=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> In 1494 Florence restored ], expelling the ] family that had ruled Florence for some sixty years. Shortly after the execution of ], Machiavelli was appointed to an office of the second chancery, a medieval writing office that put Machiavelli in charge of the production of official Florentine government documents.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QMasak4LLcQC&pg=PT28|title=The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli|last=Ridolfi|first=Roberto|year=2013|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1135026615|page=28|language=en}}</ref> Shortly thereafter, he was also made the secretary of the ''Dieci di Libertà e Pace''.
]]]


In the first decade of the sixteenth century, he carried out several diplomatic missions: most notably to the Papacy in Rome. Moreover, from 1502 to 1503, he witnessed the brutal reality of the state-building methods of ] (1475–1507) and his father, ], who were then engaged in the process of trying to bring a large part of Central Italy under their possession.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli {{!}} Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=28 July 2019}}</ref> The pretext of defending Church interests was used as a partial justification by the Borgias. Other excursions to the court of ] and the Spanish court influenced his writings such as ''The Prince''. In the first decade of the sixteenth century, he carried out several diplomatic missions, most notably to the papacy in Rome. Florence sent him to ] to pacify the leaders of two opposing factions which had broken into riots in 1501 and 1502; when this failed, the leaders were banished from the city, a strategy which Machiavelli had favoured from the outset.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=136|loc=notes}} From 1502 to 1503, he witnessed the brutal reality of the state-building methods of ] (1475–1507) and his father, ], who were then engaged in the process of trying to bring a large part of central Italy under their possession.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Niccolo-Machiavelli|title=Niccolo Machiavelli {{!}} Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts|website=Encyclopædia Britannica|language=en|access-date=28 July 2019}}</ref> The pretext of defending Church interests was used as a partial justification by the Borgias. Other excursions to the court of ] and the Spanish court influenced his writings such as '']''.


Between 1503 and 1506, Machiavelli was responsible for the Florentine militia. He distrusted mercenaries (a distrust that he explained in his official reports and then later in his theoretical works for their unpatriotic and uninvested nature in the war that makes their allegiance fickle and often too unreliable when most needed<ref>This point is made especially in The Prince, Chap XII</ref>) and instead staffed his army with citizens, a policy that was to be repeatedly successful. Under his command, Florentine citizen-soldiers defeated Pisa in 1509.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9hIPlryeSTQC&lpg=PP1&dq=inauthor:%22Maurizio%20Viroli%22&pg=PA105#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|date=9 January 2002|publisher=Macmillan|isbn=9780374528003|location=|pages=105|language=en}}</ref> At the start of the 16th century, Machiavelli conceived of a militia for Florence, and he then began recruiting and creating it.<ref name="Viroli 81–86">{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9hIPlryeSTQC&pg=PA105|title=Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|year= 2002|publisher=Macmillan|isbn=978-0374528003|pages= 81–86}}</ref> He distrusted mercenaries (a distrust that he explained in his official reports and then later in his theoretical works for their unpatriotic and uninvested nature in the war that makes their allegiance fickle and often unreliable when most needed),<ref>This point is made especially in ''The Prince'', Chap XII</ref> and instead staffed his army with citizens, a policy that yielded some positive results. By February 1506 he was able to have four hundred farmers marching on parade, suited (including iron breastplates), and armed with lances and small firearms.<ref name="Viroli 81–86"/> Under his command, Florentine citizen-soldiers conquered ] in 1509.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9hIPlryeSTQC&pg=PA105|title=Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|year= 2002|publisher=Macmillan|isbn=978-0374528003|page=105}}</ref>


] in Florence]]
However, Machiavelli's success did not last. In August 1512 the Medici, backed by ], used Spanish troops to defeat the Florentines at ], but many historians have argued that it was due to ]'s unwillingness to compromise with the Medici, who were holding Prato under siege. In the wake of the siege, Soderini resigned as Florentine head of state and left in exile. The experience would, like Machiavelli's time in foreign courts and with the Borgia, heavily influence his political writings.


Machiavelli's success was short-lived. In August 1512, the Medici, backed by ], used Spanish troops to defeat the Florentines at ].<ref>Many historians have argued that this was due to ]'s unwillingness to compromise with the Medici, who were holding Prato under siege.</ref> In the wake of the siege, ] resigned as Florentine head of state and fled into exile. The experience would, like Machiavelli's time in foreign courts and with the Borgia, heavily influence his political writings. The Florentine city-state and the republic were dissolved, with Machiavelli then being removed from office and banished from the city for a year.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} In 1513, the Medici accused him of conspiracy against them and had him imprisoned.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Skinner |first=Quentin |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kiYz6d278IC&q=quentin%20skinner%20machiavelli&pg=PT36 |title=Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2000 |isbn=978-0191540349 |publication-place=Oxford, England |page=36 |language=en}}</ref> Despite being subjected to torture{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} ("]", in which the prisoner is hanged from his bound wrists from the back, forcing the arms to bear the body's weight and dislocating the shoulders), he denied involvement and was released after three weeks.
] in the ] in Florence]]


Machiavelli then retired to his farm estate at ], near ], where he devoted himself to studying and writing political treatises. During this period, he represented the Florentine Republic on diplomatic visits to France, Germany, and elsewhere in Italy.{{sfn|Machiavelli|1981|p=3|loc=intro}} Despairing of the opportunity to remain directly involved in political matters, after a time he began to participate in intellectual groups in Florence and wrote several plays that (unlike his works on political theory) were both popular and widely known in his lifetime. Politics remained his main passion, and to satisfy this interest, he maintained a well-known correspondence with more politically connected friends, attempting to become involved once again in political life.<ref>Niccolò Machiavelli (1996), ''Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence'', Northern Illinois University Press, translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.</ref> In a letter to ], he described his experience:
After the Medici victory, the Florentine city-state and the republic were dissolved, and Machiavelli was deprived of office in 1512. In 1513 the Medici accused him of conspiracy against them and had him imprisoned.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kiYz6d278IC&lpg=PP1&dq=quentin%20skinner%20machiavelli&pg=PT36#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|date=12 October 2000|publisher=OUP Oxford|isbn=9780191540349|location=|pages=36|language=en}}</ref> Despite having been subjected to torture ("]" in which the prisoner is hanged from his bound wrists, from the back, forcing the arms to bear the body's weight and dislocating the shoulders), he denied involvement and was released after three weeks.


<blockquote>When evening comes, I go back home, and go to my study. On the threshold, I take off my work clothes, covered in mud and filth, and I put on the clothes an ambassador would wear. Decently dressed, I enter the ancient courts of rulers who have long since died. There, I am warmly welcomed, and I feed on the only food I find nourishing and was born to savour. I am not ashamed to talk to them and ask them to explain their actions and they, out of kindness, answer me. Four hours go by without my feeling any anxiety. I forget every worry. I am no longer afraid of poverty or frightened of death. I live entirely through them.<ref>Joshua Kaplan, "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance," ''The Modern Scholar'' (14 lectures in the series; lecture #7 / disc 4), 2005.</ref></blockquote>
Machiavelli then retired to his estate at ], near ], and devoted himself to studying and writing of the political treatises that earned his place in the intellectual development of political philosophy and political conduct.<ref>Donno, Daniel, in the introduction to the Bantam Classic edition of ''The Prince'' (1966)</ref>


Machiavelli died on 21 June 1527 from a stomach ailment<ref>{{Cite web |title=Washingtonpost.com: Horizon Section |url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-srv/national/horizon/jan99/morality.htm |access-date=2023-11-03 |website=www.washingtonpost.com}}</ref> at the age of 58 after receiving his ].<ref>"Even such men as Malatesta and Machiavelli, after spending their lives in estrangement from the Church, sought on their deathbeds her assistance and consolations. Both made good confessions and received the Holy Viaticum." – Ludwig von Pastor, , Vol. 5, p. 137.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Black |first1=Robert |title=Machiavelli |year= 2013 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1317699583 |page=283 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=C54lAgAAQBAJ |language=en}}</ref> He was buried at the ] in Florence. In 1789 ], and ], initiated the construction of a monument on Machiavelli's tomb. It was sculpted by ], with an epitaph by Doctor Ferroni inscribed on it.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Sil |first1=Narasingha Prosad |title=Kauṭilya's Arthaśāstra: A Comparative Study |date=1985 |publisher=Academic Publishers Calcutta|page=217 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=A2_9tHqptIMC|language=en}}</ref>{{efn|The Latin legend reads: <small>TANTO NOMINI NULLUM PAR ELOGIUM</small> ("So great a name (has) no adequate praise" or "No ] (would be) a match for such a great name" or "There is no praise equal to so great a name.")}}
Despairing of the opportunity to remain directly involved in political matters, after a time, he began to participate in intellectual groups in Florence and wrote several plays that (unlike his works on political theory) were both popular and widely known in his lifetime. Still, politics remained his main passion and, to satisfy this interest, he maintained a well-known correspondence with more politically connected friends, attempting to become involved once again in political life.<ref>Machiavelli, Niccolò (1996), Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence, Northern Illinois University Press. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.</ref>


==Major works==
In a letter to ], he described his exile:
===''The Prince''===
{{Main|The Prince}}
], to whom the final version of ''The Prince'' was dedicated]]


Machiavelli's best-known book ''Il Principe'' contains several maxims concerning politics. Instead of the more traditional target audience of a hereditary prince, it concentrates on the possibility of a "new prince". To retain power, the hereditary prince must carefully balance the interests of a variety of institutions to which the people are accustomed.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Zuckert |first=Catherine H. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yZUtDwAAQBAJ&q=catherine+zuckert+machiavelli |title=Machiavelli's Politics |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=2017 |isbn=978-0226434803}}</ref> By contrast, a new prince has the more difficult task in ruling: He must first stabilise his newfound power in order to build an enduring political structure. Machiavelli suggests that the political benefits of stability and security can be achieved in the face of moral corruption. Machiavelli believed that public and private morality had to be understood as two different things in order to rule well.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolo |title=The Prince |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1984 |isbn=0-19-281602-0 |location=Oxford, New York |pages=59–60}}</ref> As a result, a ruler must be concerned not only with reputation, but also must be positively willing to act unscrupulously at the right times. Machiavelli believed that, for a ruler, it was better to be widely feared than to be greatly loved; a loved ruler retains authority by obligation, while a feared leader rules by fear of punishment.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |year=1532 |location=Italy |pages=120–121}}</ref> As a political theorist, Machiavelli emphasized the "necessity" for the methodical exercise of brute force or deceit, including extermination of entire noble families, to head off any chance of a challenge to the prince's authority.<ref>Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', Chapter III</ref>
<blockquote>When evening comes, I go back home, and go to my study. On the threshold, I take off my work clothes, covered in mud and filth, and I put on the clothes an ambassador would wear. Decently dressed, I enter the ancient courts of rulers who have long since died. There, I am warmly welcomed, and I feed on the only food I find nourishing and was born to savour. I am not ashamed to talk to them and ask them to explain their actions and they, out of kindness, answer me. Four hours go by without my feeling any anxiety. I forget every worry. I am no longer afraid of poverty or frightened of death. I live entirely through them.<ref>Joshua Kaplan, "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance," ''The Modern Scholar'' (14 lectures in the series; lecture #7 / disc 4), 2005</ref></blockquote>

Scholars often note that Machiavelli glorifies instrumentality in state building, an approach embodied by the saying, often attributed to interpretations of ''The Prince'', "]".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=harvey+mansfield+machiavelli |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1998 |isbn=978-0226503721}}</ref> Fraud and deceit are held by Machiavelli as necessary for a prince to use.<ref>''The Prince'', Chapter XVIII, "In What Mode Should Faith Be Kept By Princes"</ref> Violence may be necessary for the successful stabilization of power and introduction of new political institutions. Force may be used to eliminate political rivals, destroy resistant populations, and purge the community of other men strong enough of a character to rule, who will inevitably attempt to replace the ruler.<ref>''The Prince''. especially Chapters 3, 5 and 8</ref> In one passage, Machiavelli subverts the advice given by ] to avoid duplicity and violence, by saying that the prince should "be the fox to avoid the snares, and a lion to overwhelm the wolves". It would become one of Machiavelli's most famous maxims.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2kiYz6d278IC&q=machiavelli+skinner|title=Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|date=2000-10-12|publisher=OUP Oxford|isbn=9780191540349|language=en}}</ref> Machiavelli's view that acquiring a state and maintaining it requires ] means has been noted as the chief theme of the treatise.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=12}}</ref> Machiavelli has become infamous for such political advice, ensuring that he would be remembered in history through the adjective "Machiavellian".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Kanzler |first=Peter |title=The Prince (1532), The Leviathan (1651), The Two Treatises of Government (1689), The Constitution of Pennsylvania (1776) |publisher=Peter Kanzler |year=2020 |isbn=978-1716844508 |page=22}}</ref>

Due to the treatise's controversial analysis on politics, in 1559, the ] banned ''The Prince'', putting it on the ''{{lang|la|]}}''.<ref>{{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_yPeCwAAQBAJ&dq=index+librorum+prohibitorum+1559+machiavelli&pg=PA16 | title=The Routledge Guidebook to Machiavelli's the Prince | isbn=978-1-317-53673-4 | last1=Scott | first1=John T. | date=31 March 2016 | publisher=Routledge }}</ref><ref>Landon, W. J. (2005). Politics, Patriotism and Language: Niccolò Machiavelli's" secular Patria" and the Creation of an Italian National Identity (Vol. 57). Peter Lang.</ref> ], including ] ({{circa|1466}}{{snd}}1536), also viewed the book negatively. As a treatise, its primary intellectual contribution to the history of political thought is the fundamental break between political ] and political ], due to it being a manual on acquiring and keeping political power. In contrast with ] and ], Machiavelli insisted that an imaginary ideal society is not a model by which a prince should orient himself.

Concerning the differences and similarities in Machiavelli's advice to ruthless and tyrannical princes in ''The Prince'' and his more republican exhortations in ''Discourses on Livy'', a few commentators assert that ''The Prince'', although written as advice for a monarchical prince, contains arguments for the superiority of republican regimes, similar to those found in the ''Discourses''. In the 18th century, the work was even called a ], for example by ] (1712–1778).<ref>''Discourse on Political Economy'': opening pages.</ref><ref>{{Cite web |last=Berlin |first=Isaiah |title=The Originality of Machiavelli |url=http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/published_works/ac/machiavelli.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20121202125009/http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/published_works/ac/machiavelli.pdf |archive-date=2 December 2012 |access-date=18 October 2012}}</ref>

Scholars such as ] (1899–1973) and ] ({{b.|1932}}) have stated that sections of ''The Prince'' and his other works have deliberately esoteric statements throughout them.<ref>This point made most notably by {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}.</ref> However, Mansfield states that this is the result of Machiavelli's seeing grave and serious things as humorous because they are "manipulable by men", and sees them as grave because they "answer human necessities".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=machiavelli%27s+virtue |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1998 |isbn=978-0226503721 |pages=228–229}}</ref>

The Marxist theorist ] (1891–1937) argued that Machiavelli's audience was the common people, as opposed to the ruling class, who were already made aware of the methods described through their education.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Thomas |first=Peter D. |year=2017 |title=The Modern Prince |journal=History of Political Thought |volume=38 |issue=3 |pages=523–544 |jstor=26210463}}</ref>

===''Discourses on Livy''===
{{Main|Discourses on Livy}}


The ''Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius'', written around 1517, and published in 1531, often referred to simply as the ''Discourses'' or ''Discorsi'', is nominally a discussion regarding the classical history of early ], although it strays far from this subject matter and also uses contemporary political examples to illustrate points. Machiavelli presents it as a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured. It is a larger work than ''The Prince'', and while it more openly explains the advantages of republics, it also contains many similar themes from his other works.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ia_oOgHlR58C|title=Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year=2001|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503707}}</ref> For example, Machiavelli has noted that to save a republic from corruption, it is necessary to return it to a "kingly state" using violent means.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.constitution.org/mac/disclivy1.htm|title=Discourses on Livy: Book 1, Chapter 18|website=www.constitution.org|access-date=9 May 2019}}</ref> He excuses Romulus for murdering his brother ] and co-ruler ] to gain absolute power for himself in that he established a "civil way of life".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+machiavelli|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 9|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref> Commentators disagree about how much the two works agree with each other, as Machiavelli frequently refers to leaders of republics as "princes".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=the+discourses+machiavelli+mansfield|title=Discourses on Livy|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref> Machiavelli even sometimes acts as an advisor to ].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+machiavelli|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 16|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&q=Thus,+the+charge+that+Machiavelli's+republic+is+a+tyranny+turns+out+to+be+true+after+&pg=PR60|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|year=2005|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1139448338|page=3}}</ref> Other scholars have pointed out the aggrandizing and imperialistic features of Machiavelli's republic.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yCsxDwAAQBAJ&q=hulliung+citizen+machiavelli|title=Citizen Machiavelli|last=Hulliung|first=Mark|year=2017|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1351528481}}</ref> Nevertheless, it became one of the central texts of modern ], and has often been argued to be a more comprehensive work than ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975|pp=183–219}}</ref>
Machiavelli died in 1527 at 58 after receiving his ].<ref>"Even such men as Malatesta and Machiavelli, after spending their lives in estrangement from the Church, sought on their death-beds her assistance and consolations. Both made good confessions and received the Holy Viaticum." - Ludwig von Pastor, ''History of the Popes'', Vol. 5, p. 137, </ref> He was buried at the ] in Florence. An epitaph honouring him is inscribed on his monument. The Latin legend reads: <small>TANTO NOMINI NULLUM PAR ELOGIUM</small> ("So great a name (has) no adequate praise" or "No ] (would be) a match for such a great name").


== Originality == == Originality ==
] ]


Commentators have taken very different approaches to Machiavelli and not always agreed. Major discussion has tended to be about two issues: first, how unified and philosophical his work is, and second, concerning how innovative or traditional it is.<ref name=Fischer>{{Harvcoltxt|Fischer|2000}}</ref> Major commentary on Machiavelli's work has focused on two issues: how unified and philosophical his work is and how innovative or traditional it is.<ref name=Fischer>{{Harvcoltxt|Fischer|2000}}</ref>


=== Coherence === === Coherence ===
There is some disagreement concerning how best to describe the unifying themes, if there are any, that can be found in Machiavelli's works, especially in the two major political works, ''The Prince'' and ''Discourses''. Some commentators have described him as inconsistent, and perhaps as not even putting a high priority in consistency.<ref name=Fischer/> Others such as ] have argued that his ideas must have changed dramatically over time. Some have argued that his conclusions are best understood as a product of his times, experiences and education. Others, such as ] and ], have argued strongly that there is a very strong and deliberate consistency and distinctness, even arguing that this extends to all of Machiavelli's works including his comedies and letters.<ref name=Fischer/><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&printsec=frontcover&dq=mansfield+machiavelli+virtue|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|date=25 February 1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226503721|language=en}}</ref> There is some disagreement concerning how best to describe the unifying themes, if there are any, that can be found in Machiavelli's works, especially in the two major political works, ''The Prince'' and ''Discourses''. Some commentators have described him as inconsistent, and perhaps as not even putting a high priority on consistency.<ref name=Fischer/><ref>Interpreting Modern Political Philosophy: From Machiavelli to Marx, pg. 40</ref> Others such as ] have argued that his ideas must have changed dramatically over time. Some have argued that his conclusions are best understood as a product of his times, experiences and education. Others, such as ] and ], have argued strongly that there is a strong and deliberate consistency and distinctness, even arguing that this extends to all of Machiavelli's works including his comedies and letters.<ref name=Fischer/><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&q=mansfield+machiavelli+virtue|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|year=1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226503721|language=en}}</ref>


=== Influences === === Influences ===
Commentators such as Leo Strauss have gone so far as to name Machiavelli as the deliberate originator of ] itself. Others have argued that Machiavelli is only a particularly interesting example of trends which were happening around him. In any case Machiavelli presented himself at various times as someone reminding Italians of the old virtues of the Romans and Greeks, and other times as someone promoting a completely new approach to politics.<ref name=Fischer/> Commentators such as Leo Strauss have gone so far as to name Machiavelli as the deliberate originator of ] itself. Others have argued that Machiavelli is only a particularly interesting example of trends which were happening around him. In any case, Machiavelli presented himself at various times as someone reminding Italians of the old virtues of the Romans and Greeks, and other times as someone promoting a completely new approach to politics.<ref name=Fischer/>


That Machiavelli had a wide range of influences is in itself not controversial. Their relative importance is however a subject of on-going discussion. It is possible to summarize some of the main influences emphasized by different commentators. That Machiavelli had a wide range of influences is in itself not controversial. Their relative importance is however a subject of ongoing discussion. It is possible to summarize some of the main influences emphasized by different commentators.


'''The Mirror of Princes genre'''
'''1. The Mirror of Princes genre.''' {{Harvcoltxt|Gilbert|1938}} summarized the similarities between ''The Prince'' and the genre it obviously imitates, the so-called "]" style. This was a classically influenced genre, with models at least as far back as ] and ]. While Gilbert emphasized the similarities, however, he agreed with all other commentators that Machiavelli was particularly novel in the way he used this genre, even when compared to his contemporaries such as ] and ]. One of the major innovations Gilbert noted was that Machiavelli focused upon the "deliberate purpose of dealing with a new ruler who will need to establish himself in defiance of custom". Normally, these types of works were addressed only to hereditary princes. (Xenophon is also an exception in this regard.)


{{Harvcoltxt|Gilbert|1938}} summarized the similarities between ''The Prince'' and the genre it obviously imitates, the so-called "]" style. This was a classically influenced genre, with models at least as far back as ] and ]. While Gilbert emphasized the similarities, however, he agreed with all other commentators that Machiavelli was particularly novel in the way he used this genre, even when compared to his contemporaries such as ] and ]. One of the major innovations Gilbert noted was that Machiavelli focused on the "deliberate purpose of dealing with a new ruler who will need to establish himself in defiance of custom". Normally, these types of works were addressed only to hereditary princes. (Xenophon is also an exception in this regard.)
'''2. Classical republicanism.''' Commentators such as ] and ], in the so-called "Cambridge School" of interpretation, have asserted that some of the republican themes in Machiavelli's political works, particularly the '']'', can be found in medieval Italian literature which was influenced by classical authors such as ].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=GF6X2ow__MgC&printsec=frontcover&dq=quentin+skinner+machiavelli#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=The Foundations of Modern Political Thought: Volume 1, The Renaissance|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|date=30 November 1978|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=9780521293372|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=1oj8CwAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=pocock+machiavelli#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|last=Pocock|first=J. G. A.|date=20 September 2016|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=9781400883516|language=en}}</ref>


'''Classical republicanism'''
], author of the '']'']]


Commentators such as ] and ], in the so-called "Cambridge School" of interpretation, have asserted that some of the republican themes in Machiavelli's political works, particularly the '']'', can be found in medieval Italian literature which was influenced by classical authors such as ].<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GF6X2ow__MgC&q=quentin+skinner+machiavelli|title=The Foundations of Modern Political Thought: Volume 1, The Renaissance|last=Skinner|first=Quentin|year= 1978|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521293372|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1oj8CwAAQBAJ&q=pocock+machiavelli|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|last=Pocock|first=J. G. A.|year=2016|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=978-1400883516|language=en}}</ref>
'''3. Classical political philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle.''' The Socratic school of classical political philosophy, especially ], had become a major influence upon European political thinking in the late ]. It existed both in the Catholicised form presented by ], and in the more controversial "]" form of authors like ]. Machiavelli was critical of Catholic political thinking and may have been influenced by Averroism. But he rarely cites Plato and Aristotle, and most likely did not approve of them. ] argued that the strong influence of ], a student of Socrates more known as an historian, rhetorician and soldier, was a major source of Socratic ideas for Machiavelli, sometimes not in line with Aristotle. While interest in ] was increasing in Florence during Machiavelli's lifetime, Machiavelli does not show particular interest in him, but was indirectly influenced by his readings of authors such as ], ] and ].


'''Classical political philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle'''
The major difference between Machiavelli and the Socratics, according to Strauss, is Machiavelli's materialism, and therefore his rejection of both a teleological view of nature and of the view that philosophy is higher than politics. With their ] understanding of things, Socratics ] that desirable things tend to happen by nature, as if nature desired them, but Machiavelli claimed that such things happen by blind chance or human action.<ref name=Strauss>{{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}}</ref>


], author of the '']'']]
'''4. Classical materialism.''' Strauss argued that Machiavelli may have seen himself as influenced by some ideas from classical materialists such as ], ] and ]. Strauss however sees this also as a sign of major innovation in Machiavelli, because classical materialists did not share the Socratic regard for political life, while Machiavelli clearly did.<ref name=Strauss/>
The Socratic school of classical political philosophy, especially ], had become a major influence upon European political thinking in the late ]. It existed both in the Catholicised form presented by ], and in the more controversial "]" form of authors like ]. Machiavelli was critical of Catholic political thinking and may have been influenced by Averroism. But he rarely cites Plato and Aristotle, and most likely did not approve of them. ] argued that the strong influence of ], a student of Socrates more known as a historian, rhetorician and soldier, was a major source of Socratic ideas for Machiavelli, sometimes not in line with Aristotle. While interest in ] was increasing in Florence during Machiavelli's lifetime, Machiavelli does not show particular interest in him, but was indirectly influenced by his readings of authors such as ], ] and ].


The major difference between Machiavelli and the Socratics, according to Strauss, is Machiavelli's materialism, and therefore his rejection of both a teleological view of nature and of the view that philosophy is higher than politics. With their ] understanding of things, Socratics argued that by nature, everything that acts, acts towards some end, as if nature desired them, but Machiavelli claimed that such things happen by blind chance or human action.<ref name=Strauss>{{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}}</ref>
'''5. Thucydides.'''

Some scholars note the similarity between Machiavelli and the Greek historian ], since both emphasized ].<ref>Paul Anthony Rahe, ''Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English Republic'' (2008) p. 282</ref><ref>Jack Donnelly, ''Realism and International Relations'' (2000) p. 68</ref> Strauss argued that Machiavelli may indeed have been influenced by ], but he felt it was a new combination:-
'''Classical materialism'''
<blockquote>...contemporary readers are reminded by Machiavelli's teaching of Thucydides; they find in both authors the same "realism," i.e., the same denial of the power of the gods or of justice and the same sensitivity to harsh necessity and elusive chance. Yet Thucydides never calls in question the intrinsic superiority of nobility to baseness, a superiority that shines forth particularly when the noble is destroyed by the base. Therefore Thucydides' History arouses in the reader a sadness which is never aroused by Machiavelli's books. In Machiavelli we find comedies, parodies, and satires but nothing reminding of tragedy. One half of humanity remains outside of his thought. There is no tragedy in Machiavelli because he has no sense of the sacredness of "the common." — {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=292}}</blockquote>

Strauss argued that Machiavelli may have seen himself as influenced by some ideas from classical materialists such as ], ] and ]. Strauss however sees this also as a sign of major innovation in Machiavelli, because classical materialists did not share the Socratic regard for political life, while Machiavelli clearly did.<ref name=Strauss/>

'''Thucydides'''

Some scholars note the similarity between Machiavelli and the Greek historian ], since both emphasized ].<ref>Paul Anthony Rahe, ''Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English Republic'' (2008), p. 282.</ref><ref>Jack Donnelly, ''Realism and International Relations'' (2000), p. 68.</ref> Strauss argued that Machiavelli may indeed have been influenced by ], but he felt it was a new combination:
<blockquote>...contemporary readers are reminded by Machiavelli's teaching of Thucydides; they find in both authors the same "realism", i.e., the same denial of the power of the gods or of justice and the same sensitivity to harsh necessity and elusive chance. Yet Thucydides never calls in question the intrinsic superiority of nobility to baseness, a superiority that shines forth particularly when the noble is destroyed by the base. Therefore Thucydides' History arouses in the reader a sadness which is never aroused by Machiavelli's books. In Machiavelli we find comedies, parodies, and satires but nothing reminding of tragedy. One half of humanity remains outside of his thought. There is no tragedy in Machiavelli because he has no sense of the sacredness of "the common". – {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=292}}</blockquote>


== Beliefs == == Beliefs ==
Line 94: Line 117:
Machiavelli is sometimes seen as the prototype of a modern empirical scientist, building generalizations from experience and historical facts, and emphasizing the uselessness of theorizing with the imagination.<ref name=Fischer/> Machiavelli is sometimes seen as the prototype of a modern empirical scientist, building generalizations from experience and historical facts, and emphasizing the uselessness of theorizing with the imagination.<ref name=Fischer/>


{{quote|He emancipated politics from theology and moral philosophy. He undertook to describe simply what rulers actually did and thus anticipated what was later called the scientific spirit in which questions of good and bad are ignored, and the observer attempts to discover only what really happens.|Joshua Kaplan, 2005<ref name=twsC11r44fzf>{{cite news|author=Joshua Kaplan|title=Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance|publisher=The Modern Scholar|quote=14 lectures in the series; (lectures #7) – see disc 4|year=2005}}</ref>}} {{blockquote|He emancipated politics from theology and moral philosophy. He undertook to describe simply what rulers actually did and thus anticipated what was later called the scientific spirit in which questions of good and bad are ignored, and the observer attempts to discover only what really happens.|Joshua Kaplan, 2005<ref name=twsC11r44fzf>{{cite news|author=Joshua Kaplan|title=Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance|publisher=The Modern Scholar|quote=14 lectures in the series; (lectures #7) – see disc 4|year=2005}}</ref>}}


Machiavelli felt that his early schooling along the lines of a traditional classical education was essentially useless for the purpose of understanding politics. Nevertheless, he advocated intensive study of the past, particularly regarding the founding of a city, which he felt was a key to understanding its later development.<ref name=twsC11r44fzf/> Moreover, he studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. Machiavelli denies the classical opinion that living virtuously always leads to happiness. For example, Machiavelli viewed misery as "one of the vices that enables a prince to rule."<ref>Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, ''History of Political Philosophy'' (1987) p. 300</ref> Machiavelli stated that "it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved."<ref>Niccolò Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', Chap 17</ref> In much of Machiavelli's work, he often states that the ruler must adopt unsavory policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime. Machiavelli felt that his early schooling along the lines of traditional classical education was essentially useless for the purpose of understanding politics. Nevertheless, he advocated intensive study of the past, particularly regarding the founding of a city, which he felt was a key to understanding its later development.<ref name=twsC11r44fzf/> Moreover, he studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. Machiavelli denies the classical opinion that living virtuously always leads to happiness. For example, Machiavelli viewed misery as "one of the vices that enables a prince to rule."<ref>Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, ''History of Political Philosophy'' (1987), p. 300.</ref> Machiavelli stated that "it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved."<ref>Niccolò Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', Chap 17.</ref> In much of Machiavelli's work, he often states that the ruler must adopt unsavoury policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime. Because cruelty and fraud play such important roles in his politics, it is not unusual for certain issues (such as murder and betrayal) to be commonplace within his works.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/machiave/|title=Niccolò Machiavelli, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|last=|first=|date=|website=|archive-url=|archive-date=|access-date=}}</ref>


A related and more controversial proposal often made is that he described how to do things in politics in a way which seemed neutral concerning who used the advice—tyrants or good rulers.<ref name=Fischer/> That Machiavelli strove for realism is not doubted, but for four centuries scholars have debated how best to describe his morality. ''The Prince'' made the word ''Machiavellian'' a byword for deceit, despotism, and political manipulation. ] declared himself inclined toward the traditional view that Machiavelli was self-consciously a "teacher of evil," since he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=oi2GDwAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=leo+strauss#v=onepage&q=leo%20strauss&f=false|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|last=Strauss|first=Leo|date=4 July 2014|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226230979|language=en}}</ref> Strauss takes up this opinion because he asserted that failure to accept the traditional opinion misses the "intrepidity of his thought" and "the graceful subtlety of his speech."<ref>{{Cite book|url=http://archive.org/details/LeoStraussThoughtsOnMachiavelli_201411|title=Leo Strauss "Thoughts On Machiavelli"|last=Leo Strauss|publisher=|year=|isbn=|location=|pages=9}}</ref> Italian ] philosopher ] (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values in reality do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make.<ref>{{Cite book|url=http://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.123166|title=Benedetto Croce My Philosophy|last=Carritt|first=e f|date=1949}}</ref> German philosopher ] (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist—a ] of politics—in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment.<ref>Ernst Cassirer, </ref> On the other hand, ] has argued that ''The Prince''{{'}}s advice presupposes the importance of ideas like ] in making changes to the political system.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131029210725/http://blogs.the-american-interest.com/stratblog/2011/05/03/when-isms-go-to-war/|title=When Isms go to War {{!}} StratBlog|date=29 October 2013|website=web.archive.org|access-date=29 October 2019}}</ref> A related and more controversial proposal often made is that he described how to do things in politics in a way which seemed neutral concerning who used the advice{{snd}}tyrants or good rulers.<ref name=Fischer/> That Machiavelli strove for realism is not doubted, but for four centuries scholars have debated how best to describe his morality. ''The Prince'' made the word ''Machiavellian'' a byword for deceit, despotism, and political manipulation. ] declared himself inclined toward the traditional view that Machiavelli was self-consciously a "teacher of evil", since he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oi2GDwAAQBAJ&q=leo+strauss|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|last=Strauss|first=Leo|year= 2014|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226230979|language=en}}</ref> Strauss takes up this opinion because he asserted that failure to accept the traditional opinion misses the "intrepidity of his thought" and "the graceful subtlety of his speech".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Strauss |first=Leo |url=http://archive.org/details/LeoStraussThoughtsOnMachiavelli_201411 |title=Leo Strauss "Thoughts On Machiavelli" |page=9}}</ref> Italian ] philosopher ] (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values, in reality, do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Carritt |first=E. F. |url=http://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.123166 |title=Benedetto Croce My Philosophy |date=1949}}</ref> German philosopher ] (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist{{snd}}a ] of politics{{snd}}in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Cassirer |first=Ernst |title=The Myth of the State |date=1961-09-10 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0-300-00036-8 |location=New Haven, Connecticut; London, England |pages=136 |language=English}}</ref> On the other hand, ] has argued that ''The Prince''{{'}}s advice presupposes the importance of ideas like ] in making changes to the political system.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://blogs.the-american-interest.com/stratblog/2011/05/03/when-isms-go-to-war/|title=When Isms go to War {{!}} StratBlog|date=29 October 2013|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131029210725/http://blogs.the-american-interest.com/stratblog/2011/05/03/when-isms-go-to-war/|access-date=29 October 2019|archive-date=29 October 2013}}</ref>


=== Fortune === === Fortune ===
Machiavelli is generally seen as being critical of Christianity as it existed in his time, specifically its effect upon politics, and also everyday life.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Km5itjMehYUC&printsec=frontcover&dq=machiavelli#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Discourses on Livy|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=27 February 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500331|location=|pages=131|language=en}}</ref> In his opinion, Christianity, along with the ] ] that the church had come to accept, allowed practical decisions to be guided too much by imaginary ] and encouraged people to lazily leave events up to ] or, as he would put it, chance, luck or fortune. While Christianity sees modesty as a virtue and pride as sinful, Machiavelli took a more classical position, seeing ambition, spiritedness, and the pursuit of glory as good and natural things, and part of the virtue and prudence that good princes should have. Therefore, while it was traditional to say that leaders should have virtues, especially prudence, Machiavelli's use of the words ''virtù'' and ''prudenza'' was unusual for his time, implying a spirited and immodest ambition. Mansfield describes his usage of ''virtu'' as a "comprimise with evil".<ref>Mansfield, Harvey (1998) , page 233</ref> Famously, Machiavelli argued that virtue and prudence can help a man control more of his future, in the place of allowing fortune to do so. Machiavelli is generally seen as being critical of ] as it existed in his time, specifically its effect upon politics, and also everyday life.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=machiavelli |title=Discourses on Livy |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=2009 |isbn=978-0226500331 |page=131 |language=en-us}}</ref> In his opinion, Christianity, along with the ] ] that the Church had come to accept, allowed practical decisions to be guided too much by imaginary ] and encouraged people to lazily leave events up to ] or, as he would put it, chance, luck or fortune. While Christianity sees modesty as a virtue and pride as sinful, Machiavelli took a more classical position, seeing ambition, spiritedness, and the pursuit of glory as good and natural things, and part of the virtue and prudence that good princes should have. Therefore, while it was traditional to say that leaders should have virtues, especially prudence, Machiavelli's use of the words ''virtù'' and ''prudenza'' was unusual for his time, implying a spirited and immodest ambition. Mansfield describes his usage of ''virtù'' as a "compromise with evil".<ref>{{Cite book |last=Mansfield |first=Harvey C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&dq=machiavelli's%20virtue&pg=PA233 |title=Machiavelli's Virtue |date=1998-02-25 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-50372-1 |pages=233 |language=en-us}}</ref> Famously, Machiavelli argued that virtue and prudence can help a man control more of his future, in the place of allowing fortune to do so.


{{Harvcoltxt|Najemy|1993}} has argued that this same approach can be found in Machiavelli's approach to love and desire, as seen in his comedies and correspondence. Najemy shows how Machiavelli's friend Vettori argued against Machiavelli and cited a more traditional understanding of fortune. Najemy has argued that this same approach can be found in Machiavelli's approach to love and desire, as seen in his comedies and correspondence. Najemy shows how Machiavelli's friend Vettori argued against Machiavelli and cited a more traditional understanding of fortune.{{sfn|Najemy|1993|p=missing}}


On the other hand, ] in Machiavelli's time meant that classical pre-Christian ideas about virtue and prudence, including the possibility of trying to control one's future, were not unique to him. But humanists did not go so far as to promote the extra glory of deliberately aiming to establish a new state, in defiance of traditions and laws. On the other hand, ] in Machiavelli's time meant that classical pre-Christian ideas about virtue and prudence, including the possibility of trying to control one's future, were not unique to him. But humanists did not go so far as to promote the extra glory of deliberately aiming to establish a new state, in defiance of traditions and laws.
Line 109: Line 132:
While Machiavelli's approach had classical precedents, it has been argued that it did more than just bring back old ideas and that Machiavelli was not a typical humanist. {{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}} argues that the way Machiavelli combines classical ideas is new. While Xenophon and Plato also described realistic politics and were closer to Machiavelli than Aristotle was, they, like Aristotle, also saw philosophy as something higher than politics. Machiavelli was apparently a ] who objected to explanations involving ], or ]. While Machiavelli's approach had classical precedents, it has been argued that it did more than just bring back old ideas and that Machiavelli was not a typical humanist. {{Harvcoltxt|Strauss|1958}} argues that the way Machiavelli combines classical ideas is new. While Xenophon and Plato also described realistic politics and were closer to Machiavelli than Aristotle was, they, like Aristotle, also saw philosophy as something higher than politics. Machiavelli was apparently a ] who objected to explanations involving ], or ].


Machiavelli's promotion of ambition among leaders while denying any higher standard meant that he encouraged risk-taking, and innovation, most famously the founding of new modes and orders. His advice to princes was therefore certainly not limited to discussing how to maintain a state. It has been argued that Machiavelli's promotion of innovation led directly to the argument for ] as an aim of ] and ]. But while a belief that humanity can control its own future, control nature, and "progress" has been long-lasting, Machiavelli's followers, starting with his own friend ], have tended to prefer peaceful progress through economic development, and not warlike progress. As Harvey {{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1995|p=74}} wrote: "In attempting other, more regular and scientific modes of overcoming fortune, Machiavelli's successors formalized and emasculated his notion of virtue." Machiavelli's promotion of ambition among leaders while denying any higher standard meant that he encouraged risk-taking, and innovation, most famously the founding of new modes and orders. His advice to princes was therefore certainly not limited to discussing how to maintain a state. It has been argued that Machiavelli's promotion of innovation led directly to the argument for ] as an aim of ] and ]. But while a belief that humanity can control its own future, control nature, and "progress" has been long-lasting, Machiavelli's followers, starting with his own friend ], have tended to prefer peaceful progress through economic development, and not warlike progress. As Harvey {{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1995|p=74}} wrote: "In attempting other, more regular and scientific modes of overcoming fortune, Machiavelli's successors formalized and emasculated his notion of virtue."


Machiavelli however, along with some of his classical predecessors, saw ambition and spiritedness, and therefore war, as inevitable and part of ]. Machiavelli however, along with some of his classical predecessors, saw ambition and spiritedness, and therefore war, as inevitable and part of ].


Strauss concludes his 1958 book '']'' by proposing that this promotion of progress leads directly to the modern ]. Strauss argued that the unavoidable nature of such arms races, which have existed before modern times and led to the collapse of peaceful civilizations, provides us with both an explanation of what is most truly dangerous in Machiavelli's innovations, but also the way in which the aims of his immoral innovation can be understood. Strauss concludes his 1958 book '']'' by proposing that this promotion of progress leads directly to the advent of new technologies being invented in both good and bad governments. Strauss argued that the unavoidable nature of such arms races, which existed before modern times and led to the collapse of peaceful civilizations, show that classical-minded men "had to admit in other words that in an important respect the good city has to take its bearings by the practice of bad cities or that the bad impose their law on the good".{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=298–299}}


===Religion=== ===Religion===
Machiavelli shows repeatedly that he saw religion as man-made, and that the value of religion lies in its contribution to social order and the rules of morality must be dispensed with if security requires it.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Km5itjMehYUC&printsec=frontcover&dq=discourses+on+livy#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Discourses on Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11-15|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=27 February 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500331|location=|pages=|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=ehzOd8DVlNkC&printsec=frontcover&dq=the+prince+mansfield|title=The Prince: Second Edition|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=15 May 2010|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500508|location=|pages=69–71|language=en}}</ref> In ''The Prince,'' the ''Discourses,'' and in the ''],'' he describes "prophets", as he calls them, like ], ], ], and ] (he treated pagan and Christian patriarchs in the same way) as the greatest of new princes, the glorious and brutal founders of the most novel innovations in politics, and men whom Machiavelli assures us have always used a large amount of armed force and murder against their own people.<ref>Especially in the Discourses III.30, but also The Prince Chap.VI</ref> He estimated that these sects last from 1,666 to 3,000 years each time, which, as pointed out by Leo Strauss, would mean that Christianity became due to start finishing about 150 years after Machiavelli.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=314}}</ref> Machiavelli's concern with Christianity as a sect was that it makes men weak and inactive, delivering politics into the hands of cruel and wicked men without a fight.<ref>See for example {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=206}}.</ref> Machiavelli shows repeatedly that he saw religion as man-made, and that the value of religion lies in its contribution to social order and the rules of morality must be dispensed with if security requires it.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km5itjMehYUC&q=discourses+on+livy|title=Discourses on Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11–15|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year= 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500331|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ehzOd8DVlNkC&q=the+prince+mansfield|title=The Prince: Second Edition|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year= 2010|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=978-0226500508|pages=69–71|language=en}}</ref> In ''The Prince'', the ''Discourses'' and in the '']'' he describes "prophets", as he calls them, like ], ], ] and ] (he treated pagan and Christian patriarchs in the same way) as the greatest of new princes, the glorious and brutal founders of the most novel innovations in politics, and men whom Machiavelli assures us have always used a large amount of armed force and murder against their own people.<ref>Especially in the ''Discourses'' III.30, but also ''The Prince'' Chap.VI</ref> He estimated that these sects last from 1,666 to 3,000 years each time, which, as pointed out by Leo Strauss, would mean that Christianity became due to start finishing about 150 years after Machiavelli.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=314}}</ref> Machiavelli's concern with Christianity as a sect was that it makes men weak and inactive, delivering politics into the hands of cruel and wicked men without a fight.<ref>See for example {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=206}}.</ref> While Machiavelli's own religious allegiance has been debated, it is assumed that he had a low regard of contemporary Christianity.<ref>Parsons, W. B. (2016). Machiavelli's gospel: The critique of Christianity in the prince. Boydell & Brewer.</ref>


While fear of ] can be replaced by fear of the prince, if there is a strong enough prince, Machiavelli felt that having a religion is in any case especially essential to keeping a republic in order. For Machiavelli, a truly great prince can never be conventionally religious himself, but he should make his people religious if he can. According to {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=226–27}} he was not the first person to ever explain religion in this way, but his description of religion was novel because of the way he integrated this into his general account of princes. While fear of ] can be replaced by fear of the prince, if there is a strong enough prince, Machiavelli felt that having a religion is in any case especially essential to keeping a republic in order.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Vavouras |first1=Elias |last2=Theodosiadis |first2=Michail |date=October 2024 |title=The Concept of Religion in Machiavelli: Political Methodology, Propaganda and Ideological Enlightenment |journal=Religions |language=en |volume=15 |issue=10 |pages=1203 |doi=10.3390/rel15101203 |doi-access=free |issn=2077-1444}}</ref> For Machiavelli, a truly great prince can never be conventionally religious himself, but he should make his people religious if he can. According to {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|pp=226–227}} he was not the first person to explain religion in this way, but his description of religion was novel because of the way he integrated this into his general account of princes.


Machiavelli's judgment that democracies need religion for practical political reasons was widespread among modern proponents of republics until approximately the time of the ]. This therefore represents a point of disagreement between himself and late modernity.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=231}}</ref> Machiavelli's judgment that governments need religion for practical political reasons was widespread among modern proponents of republics until approximately the time of the ]. This, therefore, represents a point of disagreement between Machiavelli and late modernity.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958|p=231}}</ref>


===Positive side to factional and individual vice=== ===Positive side to factional and individual vice===
Despite the classical precedents, which Machiavelli was not the only one to promote in his time, Machiavelli's realism and willingness to argue that good ends justify bad things, is seen as a critical stimulus towards some of the most important theories of modern politics. Despite the classical precedents, which Machiavelli was not the only one to promote in his time, Machiavelli's realism and willingness to argue that good ends justify bad things, is seen as a critical stimulus towards some of the most important theories of modern politics.


Firstly, particularly in the ''Discourses on Livy,'' Machiavelli is unusual in the positive side he sometimes seems to describe in factionalism in republics. For example, quite early in the ''Discourses,'' (in Book I, chapter 4), a chapter title announces that ''the disunion'' of the ] and ] in Rome ''"kept Rome free".'' That a community has different components whose interests must be balanced in any good regime is an idea with classical precedents, but Machiavelli's particularly extreme presentation is seen as a critical step towards the later political ideas of both a ] or ], ideas which lay behind the ], as well as many other modern state constitutions. Firstly, particularly in the ''Discourses on Livy'', Machiavelli is unusual in the positive side to factionalism in republics which he sometimes seems to describe. For example, quite early in the ''Discourses'', (in Book I, chapter 4), a chapter title announces that ''the disunion'' of the ] and ] in Rome ''"kept Rome free"''. That a community has different components whose interests must be balanced in any good regime is an idea with classical precedents, but Machiavelli's particularly extreme presentation is seen as a critical step towards the later political ideas of both a ] or ], ideas which lay behind the ], as well as many other modern state constitutions.


Similarly, the modern economic argument for ], and most modern forms of economics, was often stated in the form of "]." Also in this case, even though there are classical precedents, Machiavelli's insistence on being both realistic and ambitious, not only admitting that vice exists but being willing to risk encouraging it, is a critical step on the path to this insight. Similarly, the modern economic argument for ], and most modern forms of economics, was often stated in the form of "]". Also in this case, even though there are classical precedents, Machiavelli's insistence on being both realistic and ambitious, not only admitting that vice exists but being willing to risk encouraging it, is a critical step on the path to this insight.


Mansfield however argues that Machiavelli's own aims have not been shared by those he influenced. Machiavelli argued against seeing mere peace and economic growth as worthy aims on their own, if they would lead to what Mansfield calls the "taming of the prince."<ref>{{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1993}}</ref> Mansfield however argues that Machiavelli's own aims have not been shared by those he influenced. Machiavelli argued against seeing mere peace and economic growth as worthy aims on their own if they would lead to what Mansfield calls the "taming of the prince".<ref>{{Harvtxt|Mansfield|1993}}</ref>

===''Machiavellian''===

]'' (]), used as an example of a successful ruler in ''The Prince'']]

Machiavelli is most famous for a short political treatise, '']'', written in 1513 but not published until 1532, five years after his death. Although he privately circulated ''The Prince'' among friends, the only theoretical work to be printed in his lifetime was '']'', which was about military science. Since the 16th century, generations of politicians remain attracted and repelled by its neutral acceptance, and also positive encouragement, of the immorality of powerful men, described especially in ''The Prince'' but also in his other works.

His works are sometimes even said to have contributed to the modern negative connotations of the words ''politics'' and ''politician'',<ref>{{Harvtxt|Bireley|1990|p=241}}</ref> and it is sometimes thought that it is because of him that ''Old Nick'' became an English term for the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Fischer|2000|p=94}}</ref> More obviously, the adjective ''Machiavellian'' became a term describing a form of politics that is "marked by cunning, duplicity, or bad faith".<ref>{{Cite dictionary |url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Machiavellian |title=Definition of MACHIAVELLIAN |dictionary=] |access-date=17 October 2018}}</ref> ''Machiavellianism'' also remains a popular term used casually in political discussions, often as a byword for bare-knuckled political realism.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&lpg=PP1&dq=paul%20a%20rahe&pg=PR36#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|date=2005-11-14|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-139-44833-8|location=|pages=xxxvi|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{cite dictionary |url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Machiavellianism |title=Definition of Machiavellianism |dictionary=] |access-date=19 June 2019}}</ref>

While Machiavellianism is notable in the works of Machiavelli, scholars generally agree that his works are complex and have equally influential themes within them. For example, J.G.A. {{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975}} saw him as a major source of the republicanism that spread throughout England and North America in the 17th and 18th centuries and Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}, whose view of Machiavelli is quite different in many ways, had similar remarks about Machiavelli's influence on republicanism and argued that even though Machiavelli was a teacher of evil he had a "grandeur of vision" that led him to advocate immoral actions. Whatever his intentions, which are still debated today, he has become associated with any proposal where "]". For example, Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=297}} wrote:{{quote|Machiavelli is the only political thinker whose name has come into common use for designating a kind of politics, which exists and will continue to exist independently of his influence, a politics guided exclusively by considerations of expediency, which uses all means, fair or foul, iron or poison, for achieving its ends—its end being the aggrandizement of one's country or fatherland—but also using the fatherland in the service of the self-aggrandizement of the politician or statesman or one's party.}}


==Influence== ==Influence==
]]] ]]]
To quote Robert Bireley:<ref>Bireley, Robert (1990), ''The Counter Reformation Prince'', p. 14</ref> To quote Robert Bireley:<ref>Bireley, Robert (1990), ''The Counter Reformation Prince'', p. 14.</ref>


{{quote|...there were in circulation approximately fifteen editions of the ''Prince'' and nineteen of the ''Discourses'' and French translations of each before they were placed on ] of ] in 1559, a measure which nearly stopped publication in Catholic areas except in France. Three principal writers took the field against Machiavelli between the publication of his works and their condemnation in 1559 and again by the Tridentine Index in 1564. These were the English cardinal ] and the Portuguese bishop ], both of whom lived for many years in Italy, and the Italian humanist and later bishop, Ambrogio Caterino Politi.}} {{blockquote|...there were in circulation approximately fifteen editions of the ''Prince'' and nineteen of the ''Discourses'' and French translations of each before they were placed on ] of ] in 1559, a measure which nearly stopped publication in Catholic areas except in France. Three principal writers took the field against Machiavelli between the publication of his works and their condemnation in 1559 and again by the Tridentine Index in 1564. These were the English cardinal ] and the Portuguese bishop ], both of whom lived for many years in Italy, and the Italian humanist and later bishop, ].}}


Machiavelli's ideas had a profound impact on political leaders throughout the modern west, helped by the new technology of the printing press. During the first generations after Machiavelli, his main influence was in non-republican governments. Pole reported that ''The Prince'' was spoken of highly by ] in England and had influenced ] in his turn towards Protestantism, and in his tactics, for example during the ].<ref name=BireleyP15>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=15}}</ref> A copy was also possessed by the Catholic king and emperor ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999|p=248}}</ref> In France, after an initially mixed reaction, Machiavelli came to be associated with ] and the ]. As {{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}} reports, in the 16th century, Catholic writers "associated Machiavelli with the Protestants, whereas Protestant authors saw him as Italian and Catholic". In fact, he was apparently influencing both Catholic and Protestant kings.<ref>While Bireley focuses on writers in the Catholic countries, {{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999}} makes the same observation, writing with more of a focus upon the Protestant ].</ref> Machiavelli's ideas had a profound impact on political leaders throughout the modern west, helped by the new technology of the printing press. During the first generations after Machiavelli, his main influence was in non-republican governments. Pole reported that ''The Prince'' was spoken of highly by ] in England and had influenced ] in his turn towards Protestantism, and in his tactics, for example during the ].<ref name="BireleyP15">{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=15}}</ref> A copy was also possessed by the Catholic king and emperor ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999|p=248}}</ref> In France, after an initially mixed reaction, Machiavelli came to be associated with ] and the ]. As {{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}} reports, in the 16th century, Catholic writers "associated Machiavelli with the Protestants, whereas Protestant authors saw him as Italian and Catholic". In fact, he was apparently influencing both Catholic and Protestant kings.<ref>While Bireley focuses on writers in the Catholic countries, {{Harvcoltxt|Haitsma Mulier|1999}} makes the same observation, writing with more of a focus upon the Protestant ].</ref>


One of the most important early works dedicated to criticism of Machiavelli, especially ''The Prince'', was that of the ], ], whose work commonly referred to as ''Discourse against Machiavelli'' or ''Anti Machiavel'' was published in ] in 1576.<ref>The first English edition was ''A Discourse upon the meanes of wel governing and maintaining in good peace, a Kingdome, or other principalitie'', translated by Simon Patericke.</ref> He accused Machiavelli of being an atheist and accused politicians of his time by saying that his works were the "Koran of the courtiers", that "he is of no reputation in the court of France which hath not Machiavel's writings at the fingers ends".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}</ref> Another theme of Gentillet was more in the spirit of Machiavelli himself: he questioned the effectiveness of immoral strategies (just as Machiavelli had himself done, despite also explaining how they could sometimes work). This became the theme of much future political discourse in Europe during the 17th century. This includes the Catholic ] writers summarised by Bireley: ], ], Carlo Scribani, ], ], and ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=18}}</ref> These authors criticized Machiavelli, but also followed him in many ways. They accepted the need for a prince to be concerned with reputation, and even a need for cunning and deceit, but compared to Machiavelli, and like later modernist writers, they emphasized ] much more than the riskier ventures of war. These authors tended to cite ] as their source for realist political advice, rather than Machiavelli, and this pretense came to be known as "]".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|pp=223–30}}</ref> "Black tacitism" was in support of princely rule, but "red tacitism" arguing the case for republics, more in the original spirit of Machiavelli himself, became increasingly important. One of the most important early works dedicated to criticism of Machiavelli, especially ''The Prince'', was that of the ], ], whose work commonly referred to as ''Discourse against Machiavelli'' or ''Anti Machiavel'' was published in ] in 1576.<ref>The first English edition was ''A Discourse upon the meanes of wel governing and maintaining in good peace, a Kingdome, or other principalitie'', translated by Simon Patericke.</ref> He accused Machiavelli of being an atheist and accused politicians of his time by saying that his works were the "Koran of the courtiers", that "he is of no reputation in the court of France which hath not Machiavel's writings at the fingers ends".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}</ref> Another theme of Gentillet was more in the spirit of Machiavelli himself: he questioned the effectiveness of immoral strategies (just as Machiavelli had himself done, despite also explaining how they could sometimes work). This became the theme of much future political discourse in Europe during the 17th century. This includes the Catholic ] writers summarised by Bireley: ], ], Carlo Scribani, ], ], and ].<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=18}}</ref> These authors criticized Machiavelli, but also followed him in many ways. They accepted the need for a prince to be concerned with reputation, and even a need for cunning and deceit, but compared to Machiavelli, and like later modernist writers, they emphasized ] much more than the riskier ventures of war. These authors tended to cite ] as their source for realist political advice, rather than Machiavelli, and this pretence came to be known as "]".<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|pp=223–230}}</ref> "Black tacitism" was in support of princely rule, but "red tacitism" arguing the case for republics, more in the original spirit of Machiavelli himself, became increasingly important. Cardinal ] read The Prince while he was in Italy, and on which he gave his comments.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ip1oAgAAQBAJ&dq=found+this+type+of+book+to+be+written+by+an+enemy+of+the+human+race.+It+explains+every+means+whereby+religion,+justice+and+any+inclination+toward+virtue+could+be+destroyed%22&pg=PR20|title=Machiavelli's Prince: A New Reading|last=Benner|first=Erica|date=2013-11-28|publisher=OUP Oxford|isbn=9780191003929|language=en}}</ref> ], king of ] and patron of ], wrote ], with the aim of rebutting ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/Anti-Machiavel|title=Anti-Machiavel {{!}} treatise by Frederick the Great|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=2019-04-16}}</ref>


] argued the case for what would become ] which would be based more upon real experience and experimentation, free from assumptions about metaphysics, and aimed at increasing control of nature. He named Machiavelli as a predecessor.]] ] argued the case for what would become ] which would be based more upon real experience and experimentation, free from assumptions about metaphysics, and aimed at increasing control of nature. He named Machiavelli as a predecessor.]]
Modern ] philosophy developed in the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, starting in the generations after Machiavelli. This philosophy tended to be republican, but as with the Catholic authors, Machiavelli's realism and encouragement of using innovation to try to control one's own fortune were more accepted than his emphasis upon war and factional violence. Not only was innovative economics and politics a result, but also ], leading some commentators to say that the 18th century ] involved a "humanitarian" moderating of Machiavellianism.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> Modern ] philosophy developed in the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, starting in the generations after Machiavelli. Modern political philosophy tended to be republican, but as with the Catholic authors, Machiavelli's realism and encouragement of innovation to try to control one's own fortune were more accepted than his emphasis upon war and factional violence. Not only was innovative economics and politics a result, but also ], leading some commentators to say that the 18th century ] involved a "humanitarian" moderating of Machiavellianism.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref>


The importance of Machiavelli's influence is notable in many important figures in this endeavor, for example ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}: "Jean Bodin's first comments, found in his ''Method for the Easy Comprehension of History'', published in 1566, were positive."</ref> ],<ref>Bacon wrote: "We are much beholden to Machiavelli and other writers of that class who openly and unfeignedly declare or describe what men do, and not what they ought to do." {{Citation|title=Of the Advancement of Learning|chapter=II.21.9}}. See {{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}} Chapter 4.</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}} chapter 6.</ref> ], ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Worden|1999}}</ref> ],<ref>{{cite web|title=Spinoza's Political Philosophy|url= http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spinoza-political/#IntBac|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|accessdate=19 March 2011|publisher= Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|year= 2013}}</ref> ], ],<ref>Danford "Getting Our Bearings: Machiavelli and Hume" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> ], and ]. Although he was not always mentioned by name as an inspiration, due to his controversy, he is also thought to have been an influence for other major philosophers, such as ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Schaefer|1990}}</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, chapter 11.</ref> ], ]<ref>Barnes Smith "The Philosophy of Liberty: Locke's Machiavellian Teaching" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> and ].<ref>Carrese "The Machiavellian Spirit of Montesquieu's Liberal Republic" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}. Shklar "Montesquieu and the new republicanism" in {{Harvtxt|Bock|1999}}.</ref> The importance of Machiavelli's influence is notable in many important figures in this endeavour, for example ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Bireley|1990|p=17}}: "Jean Bodin's first comments, found in his ''Method for the Easy Comprehension of History'', published in 1566, were positive."</ref> ],<ref>Bacon wrote: "We are much beholden to Machiavelli and other writers of that class who openly and unfeignedly declare or describe what men do, and not what they ought to do." {{Citation|title=Of the Advancement of Learning|chapter=II.21.9}}. See {{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}} Chapter 4.</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}} chapter 6.</ref> ], ],<ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Worden|1999}}</ref> ],<ref>{{cite encyclopedia|title=Spinoza's Political Philosophy|url= http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spinoza-political/#IntBac|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=19 March 2011|publisher= Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|year= 2013}}</ref> ], ],<ref>Danford "Getting Our Bearings: Machiavelli and Hume" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> ], and ]. Although he was not always mentioned by name as an inspiration, due to his controversy, he is also thought to have been an influence for other major philosophers, such as ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Schaefer|1990}}</ref> ],<ref>{{Harvtxt|Kennington|2004}}, chapter 11.</ref> ], ]<ref>Barnes Smith "The Philosophy of Liberty: Locke's Machiavellian Teaching" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref> and ].<ref>Carrese "The Machiavellian Spirit of Montesquieu's Liberal Republic" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref><ref>{{Harvcoltxt|Shklar|1999}}</ref> Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who is associated with very different political ideas, viewed Machiavelli's work as a satirical piece in which Machiavelli exposes the faults of a one-man rule rather than exalting amorality.


<blockquote>In the seventeenth century it was in England that Machiavelli's ideas were most substantially developed and adapted, and that republicanism came once more to life; and out of seventeenth-century English republicanism there were to emerge in the next century not only a theme of English political and historical reflection{{snd}}of the writings of the ] circle and of ] and of early parliamentary radicals{{snd}}but a stimulus to the ] in Scotland, on the Continent, and in America.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Worden|1999}}</ref></blockquote>
Although Jean-Jacques Rousseau is associated with very different political ideas he was also influenced by him, although he viewed Machiavelli's work as a satirical piece in which Machiavelli exposes the faults of a one-man rule rather than exalting amorality.


].]]
<blockquote>In the seventeenth century it was in England that Machiavelli's ideas were most substantially developed and adapted, and that republicanism came once more to life; and out of seventeenth-century English republicanism there were to emerge in the next century not only a theme of English political and historical reflection—of the writings of the ] circle and of ] and of early parliamentary radicals—but a stimulus to the ] in Scotland, on the Continent, and in America.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Worden|1999}}</ref></blockquote>
Scholars have argued that Machiavelli was a major indirect and direct influence upon the political thinking of the ] due to his overwhelming favouritism of ] and the republican type of government. According to John McCormick, it is still very much debatable whether or not Machiavelli was "an advisor of tyranny or partisan of liberty."<ref>John P. McCormick, ''Machiavellian democracy'' (Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 23.</ref> ], ] and ] followed Machiavelli's republicanism when they opposed what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared ] was creating with the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> Hamilton learned from Machiavelli about the importance of foreign policy for domestic policy, but may have broken from him regarding how rapacious a republic needed to be in order to survive.<ref>Walling "Was Alexander Hamilton a Machiavellian Statesman?" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref><ref>{{Harvtxt|Harper|2004}}</ref> ] was less influenced by Machiavelli.<ref>Spalding "The American Prince? George Washington's Anti-Machiavellian moment" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref>
].]]
Scholars have argued that Machiavelli was a major indirect and direct influence upon the political thinking of the ] due to his overwhelming favoritism of ] and the republican type of government. According to John McCormick, it is still very much debatable whether or not Machiavelli was "an advisor of tyranny or partisan of liberty."<ref>John P. McCormick, ''Machiavellian democracy'' (Cambridge University Press, 2011) p. 23</ref> ], ] and ] followed Machiavelli's republicanism when they opposed what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared ] was creating with the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref> Hamilton learned from Machiavelli about the importance of foreign policy for domestic policy, but may have broken from him regarding how rapacious a republic needed to be in order to survive.<ref>Walling "Was Alexander Hamilton a Machiavellian Statesman?" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.</ref><ref>{{Harvtxt|Harper|2004}}</ref> ] was less influenced by Machiavelli.<ref>Spalding "The American Prince? George Washington's Anti-Machiavellian moment" in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}</ref>


The Founding Father who perhaps most studied and valued Machiavelli as a political philosopher was ], who profusely commented on the Italian's thought in his work, ''A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America''.<ref name=thompson>{{Harvtxt|Thompson|1995}}</ref> In this work, John Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and ], as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.<ref name=thompson/> The Founding Father who perhaps most studied and valued Machiavelli as a political philosopher was ], who profusely commented on the Italian's thought in his work, ''A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America''.<ref name="thompson">{{Harvtxt|Thompson|1995}}</ref> In this work, John Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and ], as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.<ref name="thompson" />


===20th century=== ===20th century===
The 20th-century Italian Communist ] drew great inspiration from Machiavelli's writings on ethics, morals, and how they relate to the State and revolution in his writings on ], and how a society can be manipulated by controlling popular notions of morality.<ref>Marcia Landy, "Culture and Politics in the work of Antonio Gramsci," 167–88, in ''Antonio Gramsci: Intellectuals, Culture, and the Party'', ed. James Martin (New York: Routledge, 2002).</ref> The 20th-century Italian Communist ] drew great inspiration from Machiavelli's writings on ethics, morals, and how they relate to the State and revolution in his writings on ], and how a society can be manipulated by controlling popular notions of morality.<ref>Marcia Landy, "Culture and Politics in the work of Antonio Gramsci," 167–188, in ''Antonio Gramsci: Intellectuals, Culture, and the Party'', ed. James Martin (New York: Routledge, 2002).</ref>


] read ''The Prince'' and annotated his own copy.<ref>Stalin: A Biography ] read ''The Prince'' and annotated his own copy.<ref>Service, Robert. ''Stalin: A Biography'', p.10.</ref>
By Robert Service, p.10</ref>


In the 20th century there was also renewed interest in Machiavelli's play '']'' (1518), which received numerous stagings, including several in New York, at the ] in 1976 and the ] in 1979, as a musical comedy by ] in Munich's Anti Theatre in 1971, and at London's ] in 1984.<ref name="Jann Racquoi 1979">Review by Jann Racquoi, ''Heights/Inwood Press of North Manhattan'', 14 March 1979.</ref>
===Revival of interest in the comedies===
In the 20th century there was also renewed interest in Machiavelli's '']'' (1518), which received numerous stagings, including several in New York, at the ] in 1976 and the ] in 1979, as a musical comedy by ] in Munich's antiteater in 1971, and at London's ] in 1984.<ref name="Jann Racquoi 1979">Review by Jann Racquoi, ''Heights/Inwood Press of North Manhattan'', 14 March 1979.</ref>


{{Anchor|Machiavellian}}
==Works==
{{Republicanism sidebar}}
{{See also|Category:Works by Niccolò Machiavelli}}


===''The Prince''=== === "Machiavellian" ===
]'' (]), used as an example of a successful ruler in ''The Prince'']]
{{Main|The Prince}}
Machiavelli's works are sometimes even said to have contributed to the modern negative connotations of the words ''politics'' and ''politician'',<ref>{{Harvtxt|Bireley|1990|p=241}}</ref> and it is sometimes thought that it is because of him that ''Old Nick'' became an English term for the ].<ref>{{Harvtxt|Fischer|2000|p=94}}</ref> More obviously, the adjective ''Machiavellian'' became a term describing a form of politics that is "marked by cunning, duplicity, or bad faith".<ref>{{Cite dictionary|title=Definition of MACHIAVELLIAN|dictionary=]|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/Machiavellian|access-date=17 October 2018}}</ref> ''Machiavellianism'' also remains a popular term used casually in political discussions, often as a byword for bare-knuckled political realism.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&q=paul%20a%20rahe&pg=PR36|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|year=2005|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1139448338|page=xxxvi|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Meinecke |first=Friedrich |date=1957 |title=Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d'État and Its Place in Modern History |page=36 |url=https://archive.org/details/machiavellismdoc00mein |publisher=Yale University Press}}</ref>


While Machiavellianism is notable in the works of Machiavelli, scholars generally agree that his works are complex and have equally influential themes within them. For example, J. G. A. {{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975}} saw him as a major source of the ] that spread throughout England and North America in the 17th and 18th centuries and Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}, whose view of Machiavelli is quite different in many ways, had similar remarks about Machiavelli's influence on republicanism and argued that even though Machiavelli was a teacher of evil he had a "grandeur of vision" that led him to advocate immoral actions. Whatever his intentions, which are still debated today, he has become associated with any proposal where "]". For example, Leo {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1987|p=297}} wrote:
Machiavelli's best-known book ''Il Principe'' contains several maxims concerning politics. Instead of the more traditional target audience of a hereditary prince, it concentrates on the possibility of a "new prince". To retain power, the hereditary prince must carefully balance the interests of a variety of institutions to which the people are accustomed. By contrast, a new prince has the more difficult task in ruling: He must first stabilise his newfound power in order to build an enduring political structure. Machiavelli suggests that the social benefits of stability and security can be achieved in the face of moral corruption. Machiavelli believed that public and private morality had to be understood as two different things in order to rule well. As a result, a ruler must be concerned not only with reputation, but also must be positively willing to act unscrupulously at the right times. Machiavelli believed as a ruler, it was better to be widely feared than to be greatly loved; A loved ruler retains authority by obligation while a feared leader rules by fear of punishment.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Prince|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=1532|isbn=|location=Italy|pages=120–21|quote=|via=}}</ref> As a political theorist, Machiavelli emphasized the "necessity" for the methodical exercise of brute force or deceit including extermination of entire noble families to head off any chance of a challenge to the prince's authority.<ref>Machiavelli ''The Prince'', Chapter III</ref>
{{blockquote|Machiavelli is the only political thinker whose name has come into common use for designating a kind of politics, which exists and will continue to exist independently of his influence, a politics guided exclusively by considerations of expediency, which uses all means, fair or foul, iron or poison, for achieving its ends{{snd}}its end being the aggrandizement of one's country or fatherland{{snd}}but also using the fatherland in the service of the self-aggrandizement of the politician or statesman or one's party.}}


{{anchor|Machiavel}}
Scholars often note that Machiavelli glorifies instrumentality in state building, an approach embodied by the saying, often attributed to interpretations of The Prince, "]".<ref></ref> Fraud and deceit are held by Machiavelli as necessary for a prince to use.<ref>The Prince, Chapter XVIII, "In What Mode Should Faith Be Kept By Princes"</ref> Violence may be necessary for the successful stabilisation of power and introduction of new political institutions. Force may be used to eliminate political rivals, to destroy resistant populations, and to purge the community of other men strong enough of a character to rule, who will inevitably attempt to replace the ruler.<ref>The Prince. especially Chapters 3, 5 and 8</ref> Machiavelli has become infamous for such political advice, ensuring that he would be remembered in history through the adjective, "Machiavellian".


===In popular culture===
] to whom the final version of ''The Prince'' was dedicated]]
{{main|Machiavelli in popular culture}}


Due to Machiavelli's popularity, he has been featured in various ways in cultural depictions. In ] (Elizabethan and Jacobian), the term "]" (from 'Nicholas Machiavel', an "anglicization" of Machiavelli's name based on French) was used for a stock antagonist that resorted to ruthless means to preserve the power of the state, and is now considered a synonym of "Machiavellian".<ref>Kahn, V. (1994). Machiavellian rhetoric: From the counter-reformation to Milton. Princeton University Press.</ref><ref>{{cite web|access-date=31 December 2021|title=Machiavel|url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803100122752|website=Oxford Reference}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|access-date=31 December 2021|title=MACHIAVEL English Definition and Meaning {{!}} Lexico.com|url=https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavel|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210516180221/https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/machiavel|url-status=dead|archive-date=16 May 2021|website=Lexico Dictionaries }}</ref>
Due to the treatise's controversial analysis on politics, the ] banned ''The Prince'', putting it on the '']''. ] also viewed the book negatively, including ] of ]. As a treatise, its primary intellectual contribution to the history of political thought is the fundamental break between political ] and political ], due to it being a manual on acquiring and keeping political power. In contrast with ] and ], Machiavelli insisted that an imaginary ideal society is not a model by which a prince should orient himself.


]'s play '']'' (ca. 1589) contains a prologue by a character called Machiavel, a ] ghost based on Machiavelli.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://player.fm/series/jew-of-malta-the-by-marlowe-christopher |title=Jew of Malta, The by MARLOWE, Christopher |work=Player FM |year=2016 |access-date=12 May 2018}}</ref> Machiavel expresses the cynical view that power is amoral, saying:
Concerning the differences and similarities in Machiavelli's advice to ruthless and tyrannical princes in ''The Prince'' and his more republican exhortations in ''Discourses on Livy'', few assert that ''The Prince'', although written as advice for a monarchical prince, contains arguments for the superiority of republican regimes, similar to those found in the ''Discourses''. In the 18th century, the work was even called a ], for example by ].<ref>''Discourse on Political Economy'': opening pages.</ref><ref>{{cite web|last=Berlin|first=Isaiah|title=The Originality of Machiavelli|url=http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/published_works/ac/machiavelli.pdf|accessdate=18 October 2012}}</ref> More recently, scholars such as ] and ] have stated that sections of ''The Prince'' and his other works have deliberately esoteric statements throughout them.<ref>This point made most notably by {{Harvtxt|Strauss|1958}}.</ref> However, this is not to say that they thought it was a joke, rather that Machiavelli sees grave and serious things as humorous because they are manipulable by men, and sees them as grave because they "answer human necessities".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Q4EULB2IM50C&printsec=frontcover&dq=machiavelli's+virtue#v=onepage&q=machiavelli's%20virtue&f=false|title=Machiavelli's Virtue|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|date=25 February 1998|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226503721|location=|pages=228–229|language=en}}</ref>
{{blockquote|<poem>
"I count religion but a childish toy,
And hold there is no sin but ignorance."
</poem>}}


Shakespeares titular character, '']'', refers to Machiavelli in '']'', as the "murderous Machiavel".<ref>{{cite web | url=https://www.folger.edu/explore/shakespeares-works/henry-vi-part-3/read/ | title=Henry VI, Part 3 - Entire Play &#124; Folger Shakespeare Library }}</ref>
Other interpretations include for example that of ], who argued that Machiavelli's audience for this work was not even the ruling class but the common people because the rulers already knew these methods through their education.


==Works==
===''Discourses on Livy''===
{{See also|Category:Works by Niccolò Machiavelli}}
{{Main|Discourses on Livy}}

The ''Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius'', written around 1517, published in 1531, often referred to simply as the "Discourses" or ''Discorsi'', is nominally a discussion regarding the classical history of early ] although it strays very far from this subject matter and also uses contemporary political examples to illustrate points. Machiavelli presents it as a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured. It is a much larger work than ''The Prince'', and while it more openly explains the advantages of republics, it also contains many similar themes from his other works.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ia_oOgHlR58C&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey C.|date=15 April 2001|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226503707|language=en}}</ref> For example, Machiavelli has noted that to save a republic from corruption, it is necessary to return it to a "kingly state" using violent means.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.constitution.org/mac/disclivy1.htm|title=Discourses on Livy: Book 1, Chapter 18|last=|first=|date=|website=www.constitution.org|language=en|archive-url=|archive-date=|access-date=9 May 2019}}</ref> He also excused Romulus for murdering his brother ] and co-ruler ] to gain absolute power for himself in that he established a "civil way of life".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Km5itjMehYUC&printsec=frontcover&dq=discourses+machiavelli#v=onepage&q=discourses%20machiavelli&f=false|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 9|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=27 February 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500331|location=|pages=|language=en}}</ref> Commentators disagree about how much the two works agree with each other, as Machiavelli frequently refers to leaders of republics as "princes".<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Km5itjMehYUC&printsec=frontcover&dq=the+discourses+machiavelli+mansfield#v=onepage&q&f=false|title=Discourses on Livy|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=27 February 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500331|language=en}}</ref> Machiavelli even sometimes acts as an advisor to tyrants.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Km5itjMehYUC&printsec=frontcover&dq=discourses+machiavelli#v=onepage&q=discourses%20machiavelli&f=false|title=Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 16|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|date=27 February 2009|publisher=University of Chicago Press|isbn=9780226500331|location=|pages=|language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZqroV-TkIhgC&pg=PR60&lpg=PR60&dq=Thus,+the+charge+that+Machiavelli's+republic+is+a+tyranny+turns+out+to+be+true+after+|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|date=14 November 2005|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=9781139448338|location=|pages=3|language=en}}</ref> Other scholars have pointed out the aggrandizing and imperialistic features of Machiavelli's republic.<ref>{{Cite book|url=https://books.google.com/?id=yCsxDwAAQBAJ&dq=hulliung+citizen+machiavelli|title=Citizen Machiavelli|last=Hulliung|first=Mark|date=5 July 2017|publisher=Routledge|isbn=9781351528481|language=en}}</ref> Nevertheless, it includes early versions of the concept of ] and asserts the superiority of a republic over a principality. It became one of the central texts of modern ], and has often been argued to be a more comprehensive work to ''The Prince''.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Pocock|1975|pp=183–219}}</ref>

From ''The Discourses'':
* "In fact, when there is combined under the same constitution a prince, a ], and the power of the people, then these three powers will watch and keep each other reciprocally in check." Book I, Chapter II
* "Doubtless these means are cruel and destructive of all civilised life, and neither Christian, nor even human, and should be avoided by everyone. In fact, the life of a private citizen would be preferable to that of a king at the expense of the ruin of so many human beings." Book I, Chapter XXVI
* "Now, in a well-ordered republic, it should never be necessary to resort to extra-constitutional measures. ..." Book I, Chapter XXXIV
* "... the governments of the people are better than those of princes." Book I, Chapter LVIII
* "... if we compare the faults of a people with those of princes, as well as their respective good qualities, we shall find the people vastly superior in all that is good and glorious". Book I, Chapter LVIII
* "For government consists mainly in so keeping your subjects that they shall be neither able nor disposed to injure you. ..." Book II, Chapter XXIII
* "... no prince is ever benefited by making himself hated." Book III, Chapter XIX
* "Let not princes complain of the faults committed by the people subjected to their authority, for they result entirely from their own negligence or bad example." Book III, Chapter XXIX<ref>The Modern Library, New York, 1950, translated by Christian E. Detmold.</ref>


===Other political and historical works=== ===Political and historical works===
] ]
* '']'' (1499) * '']'' (1499)
Line 214: Line 217:
* '']'' (1502) – A discourse about the provision of money. * '']'' (1502) – A discourse about the provision of money.
* ''Ritratti delle cose di Francia'' (1510) – Portrait of the affairs of France. * ''Ritratti delle cose di Francia'' (1510) – Portrait of the affairs of France.
* ''Ritracto delle cose della Magna'' (1508–1512) – Portrait of the affairs of Germany. * '']'' (1508–1512) – Portrait of the affairs of Germany.
* '']'' (1513)
* '']'' (1517)
* ''Dell'Arte della Guerra'' (1519–1520) – '']'', high military science. * ''Dell'Arte della Guerra'' (1519–1520) – '']'', high military science.
* '']'' (1520) – A discourse about the reforming of Florence. * '']'' (1520) – A discourse about the reforming of Florence.
* ''Sommario delle cose della citta di Lucca'' (1520) – A summary of the affairs of the city of Lucca. * ''Sommario delle cose della citta di Lucca'' (1520) – A summary of the affairs of the city of Lucca.
* ''The ] of Lucca'' (1520) – ''Vita di ] da Lucca'', a short biography. * ''The ] of Lucca'' (1520) – ''Vita di ] da Lucca'', a short biography.
* ''Istorie Florentine'' (1520–1525) – '']'', an eight-volume history of the city-state Florence, commissioned by Giulio de' Medici, later ]. * ''Istorie Fiorentine'' (1520–1525) – '']'', an eight-volume history of the city-state Florence, commissioned by Giulio de' Medici, later ].


===Fictional works=== ===Fictional works===
{{See also|Machiavelli as a dramatist}} {{See also|Machiavelli as a dramatist}}
{{Republicanism sidebar}}

Besides being a statesman and political scientist, Machiavelli also translated classical works, and was a playwright (''Clizia'', ''Mandragola''), a poet (''Sonetti'', ''Canzoni'', ''Ottave'', ''Canti carnascialeschi''), and a novelist (''Belfagor arcidiavolo''). Besides being a statesman and political scientist, Machiavelli also translated classical works, and was a playwright (''Clizia'', ''Mandragola''), a poet (''Sonetti'', ''Canzoni'', ''Ottave'', ''Canti carnascialeschi''), and a novelist (''Belfagor arcidiavolo'').


Some of his other work: Some of his other work:
* '']'' (1506) – a poem in ]. * '']'' (1506) – a poem in ].
* '']'' (1509) – a poem. * '']'' (1509) – a poem.
* ] or ''The Girl From Andros'' (1517) – a semi-autobiographical comedy, adapted from ].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://yaledailynews.com/blog/2012/04/18/first-time-machiavelli-translation-debuts-at-yale/|title=First-time Machiavelli translation debuts at Yale|publisher=yaledailynews.com}}</ref> * ] or ''The Girl from Andros'' (1517) – a semi-autobiographical comedy, adapted from ].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://yaledailynews.com/blog/2012/04/18/first-time-machiavelli-translation-debuts-at-yale/|title=First-time Machiavelli translation debuts at Yale|date=18 April 2012|publisher=yaledailynews.com}}</ref>
* ''Mandragola'' (1518) – '']'' – a five-act prose comedy, with a verse prologue. * '']'' (1518) – '']'' – a five-act prose comedy, with a verse prologue.
* '']'' (1525) – a prose comedy. * '']'' (1525) – a prose comedy.
* '']'' (1515) – a novella. * '']'' (1515) – a novella.
* ''Asino d'oro'' (1517) – '']'' is a ] poem, a new version of the ] by ]. * '']'' (1517) – '']'' is a ] poem, a new version of the ] by ].
* ''Frammenti storici'' (1525) – fragments of stories. * ''Frammenti storici'' (1525) – fragments of stories.


===Other works=== ===Other works===
''Della Lingua'' (Italian for "Of the Language") (1514), a dialogue about Italy's language is normally attributed to Machiavelli. ''Della Lingua'' (Italian for "On the Language") (1514), a dialogue about Italy's language is normally attributed to Machiavelli.


Machiavelli's literary executor, Giuliano de' Ricci, also reported having seen that Machiavelli, his grandfather, made a comedy in the style of ] which included living Florentines as characters, and to be titled ''Le Maschere''. It has been suggested that due to such things as this and his style of writing to his superiors generally, there was very likely some animosity to Machiavelli even before the return of the Medici.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Godman|1998|p=240}}. Also see {{Harvtxt|Black|1999|pp=97–98}}</ref> Machiavelli's literary executor, Giuliano de' Ricci, also reported having seen that Machiavelli, his grandfather, made a comedy in the style of ] which included living Florentines as characters, and to be titled ''Le Maschere''. It has been suggested that due to such things as this and his style of writing to his superiors generally, there was very likely some animosity to Machiavelli even before the return of the Medici.<ref>{{Harvtxt|Godman|1998|p=240}}. Also see {{Harvtxt|Black|1999|pp=97–98}}</ref>

==In popular culture==
]'s play '']'' (ca. 1589) contains a prologue by a character called Machiavel, a ] ghost based on Machiavelli.<ref>{{cite book |author=Students' Academy |title=Literature Help: The Jew of Malta |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0lBVCAAAQBAJ&pg=PT5 |publisher=] |date=12 November 2014 |page=5 |isbn=9781312671249}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://player.fm/series/jew-of-malta-the-by-marlowe-christopher |title=Jew of Malta, The by MARLOWE, Christopher |work=Player FM |year=2016 |access-date=12 May 2018}}</ref> Machiavel expresses the cynical view that power is amoral, saying "I count religion but a childish toy,/And hold there is no sin but ignorance."

Somerset Maugham's last book "Then and Now" fictionalizes Machiavelli's interactions with Cesare Borgia which formed the foundation of "The Prince."

Niccolò Machiavelli plays a vital role in the young adult book series '']''.<ref>{{cite book |last=Yelegaonkar |first=Dr. Shirkant |title=Western Thinker's in Political Science |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nQTECQAAQBAJ&pg=PT130 |publisher=] |year=2009 |page=130 |isbn=9781329082779}}</ref> He is an immortal working in national security for the French government.<ref>{{cite book |last=Knickerbocker |first=Joan L. |title=Literature for Young Adults: Books (and More) for Contemporary Readers |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YTorDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT355 |publisher=] |date=15 March 2017 |page=355 |isbn=9781351813020}}</ref>

Niccolò Machiavelli aids ] and protagonist Nicholas Dawson in their dangerous intrigues in ]'s 1979 ] '']''.<ref name="Maclaine">{{cite web |url=http://www.historicalnovels.info/City-of-God.html |title=''City of God'' by Cecelia Holland |first=David |last=Maclaine |website=Historicalnovels.info |accessdate=5 September 2014}}</ref> David Maclaine writes that in the novel, Machiavelli "is an off-stage presence whose spirit permeates this work of intrigue and betrayal ... It is a brilliant introduction to the people and events that gave us the word 'Machiavellian.'"<ref name="Maclaine" /> Machiavelli appears as an Immortal adversary of ] in ]'s 1997 '']'' novel ''The Measure of a Man'', and is a character in ]'s novel series '']'' (2007–2012). Machiavelli is also one of the main characters in '']'' (2008) by ], mostly referred to as "Niccolò 'il Macchia", and the central protagonist in the 2012 novel ''The Malice of Fortune'' by Michael Ennis.

Television dramas centering on the early ] have also made use of Machiavelli to underscore his influence in early modern political philosophy. Machiavelli has been featured as a supporting character in '']'' (2007–2010),<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.theanneboleynfiles.com/resources/the-tudors-episode-guide/the-tudors-season-1/the-tudors-season-1-episode-2-simply-henry/ |title=The Tudors Season 1 Episode 2 – Simply Henry |access-date=8 February 2018 |work=The Anne Boleyn Files}}</ref><ref>{{cite news |last=Smith |first=Lucinda |title=An epic for our times: How Game of Thrones reached highbrow status |url=https://www.prospectmagazine.co.uk/arts-and-books/an-epic-for-our-times-how-game-of-thrones-reached-highbrow-status |date=25 July 2017 |access-date=8 February 2018 |journal=]}}</ref> ] (2011–2014) and '']'' (2011–2013).<ref name=Ashurst>{{cite journal |last=Ashurst |first=Sam |title=The 7 most wildly inaccurate historical dramas on TV |url=http://www.digitalspy.com/tv/feature/a833561/inaccurate-historical-drama/ |date=20 July 2017 |access-date=8 February 2018 |journal=]}}</ref> and the 1981 BBC mini series ].

Machiavelli appears in the popular historical ]s '']'' (2009) and '']'' (2010), in which he is portrayed as a member of the secret society of Assassins.<ref>{{cite book |last=Yelegaonkar |first=Dr. Shrikant |title=Western Thinker's in Political Science |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nQTECQAAQBAJ&pg=PT131 |publisher=] |page=131 |year=2009 |isbn=9781329082779}}</ref>

A highly fictionalised version of Machiavelli appears in the ] children's TV series '']'' (2011–2012),<ref> BBC</ref> in which he is "Mac", a black streetwise hustler who is best friends with fellow teenagers ], ], and ]. In the 2013 episode "Ewings Unite!" of the television series '']'', legendary oil baron ] wills his copy of '']'' to his adopted nephew ], telling him to "use it, because being smart and sneaky is an unbeatable combination." In '']'' (2013–2015)—an American ] drama series that presents a fictional account of Leonardo da Vinci's early life<ref>{{Cite newspaper|url=https://www.theguardian.com/artanddesign/jonathanjonesblog/2013/apr/16/da-vincis-demons-reinvents-leonardo|title=''Da Vinci's Demons'': the new TV show that totally reinvents Leonardo's life|work=]|author=Jonathan Jones|accessdate=10 March 2014|date=16 April 2013}}</ref>—] plays a young Niccolò "Nico" Machiavelli, although the character's full name is not revealed until the finale of the second season.

The 1967 '']'' episode "The Death Merchant" stars famed character actor ] as Niccolò Machiavelli, who has been time-displaced to the ]. The character's personality and behaviour seem to portray Cesare Borgia rather than Machiavelli himself, suggesting that the writers may have confused the two.

Machiavelli is played by ] in the 2013 BBC radio play ''The Prince'' written by ]. Together with his defence attorney ] (]), he presents examples from history to the devil to support his political theories and appeal his sentence in Hell.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/b01slm1l|title=BBC Radio 4 – Saturday Drama, The Prince|publisher=BBC}}</ref>

The historical novel ''The City of Man'' (2009) by author Michael Harrington fully portrays the complex personalities of the two main characters—] and a formative Niccolò Machiavelli—in opposition during the turbulent last decade of 15th century Florence. The portrayal of Machiavelli draws from his later writings and observations of the chaotic events of his youth before rising from obscurity to be appointed as Second Chancellor of the Florentine Republic at the age of twenty-nine, only one month after Savonarola's execution. Major characters include ], his son Piero, ], ], ], ], ] (Rodrigo Borgia), ] (model for The Prince), Piero and Tommaso Soderini, Il Cronaca and the diarist, Luca Landucci.

The American rapper ] read Machiavelli while in prison and became greatly influenced by his work. Upon his release from prison, Tupac honored Machiavelli in 1996 by changing his own rap name from 2Pac to Makaveli.<ref>{{cite web|last1=Briceño|first1=Norberto|title=28 Things You Didn't Know About Tupac Shakur|url=https://www.buzzfeed.com/norbertobriceno/aint-nothin-but-a-gangsta-party#.nfa1lOgAA|website=Buzzfeed|accessdate=4 October 2015}}</ref>

In the 1993 crime drama '']'', local mob boss Sonny tells his young protege Calogero that while he was doing a 10-year sentence in jail, he passed the time and stayed out of trouble by reading Machiavelli, whom he describes as "a famous writer from 500 years ago"—and then tells him how Machiavelli's philosophy, including his famous advice about how it is preferable for a leader to be feared rather than loved if he cannot be both—have made him a successful mob boss.


==See also== ==See also==
{{Portal|Italy|Biography}} {{Portal|Italy|Biography}}
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ]


==References== ==References==
'''Footnotes'''
{{notelist}}

'''Citations'''
{{Reflist|30em}} {{Reflist|30em}}

===Sources===
* {{cite book |last1=Machiavelli |first1=Niccolò |translator=Daniel Donno |title=The Prince and Selected Discourses |year=1981 |publisher=Bantam Classic Books |location=New York |isbn=0553212273 |edition=}}
* {{Cite book|last=Haitsma Mulier|first=Eco|chapter=A controversial republican|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{cite book |last=Harper |first=John Lamberton |title=American Machiavelli: Alexander Hamilton and the Origins of US Foreign Policy |location=New York |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2004 |isbn=978-0521834858 }}
* {{Cite book|last=Shklar|first=J.|chapter=Montesquieu and the new republicanism|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{Cite book|last=Worden|first=Blair|chapter=Milton's republicanism and the tyranny of heaven|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}


==Further reading== ==Further reading==
===Biographies=== ===Biographies===
{{refbegin}} {{refbegin|30em}}
* {{cite journal |last1=Baron |first1=Hans |title=Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of 'the Prince' |journal=The English Historical Review |date=April 1961 |volume=76 |issue=299 |pages=217–253 |jstor=557541}} * {{cite journal |last1=Baron |first1=Hans |title=Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of 'the Prince' |journal=The English Historical Review |date=April 1961 |volume=76 |issue=299 |pages=217–253 |doi=10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217 |jstor=557541}}
* Black, Robert. ''Machiavelli: From Radical to Reactionary''. London: Reaktion Books (2022)
* Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in ''Cambridge Modern History'' (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp.&nbsp;190–218
* Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in ''Cambridge Modern History'' (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp.&nbsp;190–218
* Capponi, Niccolò. ''An Unlikely Prince: The Life and Times of Machiavelli'' (Da Capo Press; 2010) 334 pages * Capponi, Niccolò. ''An Unlikely Prince: The Life and Times of Machiavelli'' (Da Capo Press; 2010) 334 pages
* Celenza, Christopher S. ''Machiavelli: A Portrait'' (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2015) 240 pages. {{ISBN|9780674416123}} * Celenza, Christopher S. ''Machiavelli: A Portrait'' (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2015) 240 pages. {{ISBN|978-0674416123}}
* {{Citation|last=Godman|first=Peter|title=From Poliziano to Machiavelli: Florentine Humanism in the High Renaissance|year=1998|publisher=Princeton University Press}} * {{Citation|last=Godman|first=Peter|title=From Poliziano to Machiavelli: Florentine Humanism in the High Renaissance|year=1998|publisher=Princeton University Press}}
* {{Citation|last=de Grazia|first=Sebastian|title=Machiavelli in Hell|year=1989|isbn=978-0679743422}}, an intellectual biography that won the Pulitzer Prize; * {{Citation|last=de Grazia|first=Sebastian|title=Machiavelli in Hell|year=1989|publisher=Knopf Doubleday Publishing |isbn=978-0679743422}}, an intellectual biography that won the Pulitzer Prize; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210309023042/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0679743421 |date=9 March 2021 }}
* Hale, J. R. ''Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy'' (1961) * Hale, J. R. ''Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy'' (1961) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090619174443/http://www.questia.com/read/10359207?title=Machiavelli%20and%20Renaissance%20Italy |date=19 June 2009 }}
* Hulliung, Mark. ''Citizen Machiavelli'' (1983) * Hulliung, Mark. ''Citizen Machiavelli'' (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 1983)
* Oppenheimer, Paul. ''Machiavelli : a life beyond ideology'' (2011) London ; New York : Continuum. {{ISBN|9781847252210}} * Lee, Alexander. ''Machiavelli: His Life and Times'' (London: Picador, 2020)
* Oppenheimer, Paul. ''Machiavelli: A Life Beyond Ideology'' (London; New York: Continuum, 2011) {{ISBN|978-1847252210}}
* Ridolfi, Roberto. ''The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (1963), a biography
* Ridolfi, Roberto. ''The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (1963)
* Schevill, Ferdinand. ''Six Historians'' (1956), pp.&nbsp;61–91 * Schevill, Ferdinand. ''Six Historians'' (1956), pp.&nbsp;61–91
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli'', in series, ''Past Masters''. Oxford, Eng.: Oxford University Press, 1981. pp. vii, 102. {{ISBN|0-19-287516-7}} pbk. * Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli'', in ''Past Masters'' series. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1981. pp. vii, 102. {{ISBN|0192875167}} pbk.
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction'' (2000) * Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction'' (2d ed., 2019) {{ISBN|978-0198837572}} pbk.
* Unger, Miles J. 'Machiavelli: A Biography' (Simon & Schuster 2011) an account of Machiavelli's life and work. * Unger, Miles J. ''Machiavelli: A Biography'' (Simon & Schuster, 2011)
* Villari, Pasquale. ''The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2 vol 1892) ( ; ) * Villari, Pasquale. ''The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2 vols. 1892) (; )
* {{Citation|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|title=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|publisher=Farrar, Straus & Giroux|year=2000|title-link=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli}} * {{Citation|last=Viroli|first=Maurizio|title=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli|publisher=Farrar, Straus & Giroux|year=2000|title-link=Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210324211333/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0374221871 |date=24 March 2021 }}
* Viroli, Maurizio. ''Machiavelli'' (1998) * Viroli, Maurizio. ''Machiavelli'' (1998) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171020021045/https://www.questia.com/read/23271960?title=Machiavelli |date=20 October 2017 }}
* Vivanti, Corrado. ''Niccolò Machiavelli: An Intellectual Biography'' (Princeton University Press; 2013) 261 pages * Vivanti, Corrado. ''Niccolò Machiavelli: An Intellectual Biography'' (Princeton University Press; 2013) 261 pages
{{refend}} {{refend}}


===Political thought=== ===Political thought===
{{refbegin}} {{refbegin|30em}}
* Baron, Hans. ''The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny'' (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. ; ; also * Baron, Hans. ''The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny'' (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. ; ; also
* Baron, Hans. ''In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism'' (2 vols. 1988). * Baron, Hans. ''In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism'' (2 vols. 1988).
* {{Citation|last= Baron|first=Hans|title=Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of ''The Prince''|journal=English Historical Review|issue=76|year=1961|pages=217–53|doi=10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217|volume=lxxvi|postscript= .|jstor=557541}} * {{Citation|last= Baron|first=Hans|title=Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of ''The Prince''|journal=English Historical Review|issue=76|year=1961|pages=217–253|doi=10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217|volume=lxxvi|postscript= .|jstor=557541}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.jstor.org/stable/557541 |date=18 November 2022 }}
* ]. "The Originality of Machiavelli", in Berlin, Isaiah (1980). ''Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas''. New York: The Viking Press.
* {{Citation|title=The Counter Reformation Prince|last=Bireley|first=Robert|year=1990}} * {{Citation|title=The Counter Reformation Prince|last=Bireley|first=Robert|year=1990}}
* {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli, servant of the Florentine republic|last=Black|first=Robert|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} * {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli, servant of the Florentine republic|last=Black|first=Robert|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{Cite book |editor1-last=Bock |editor1-first=Gisela |editor2-last=Skinner |editor2-first=Quentin |editor3-last=Viroli |editor3-first=Maurizio |title=Machiavelli and Republicanism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9MNULqj7T4YC |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1993 |isbn=978-0-521-43589-5}} * {{Cite book |editor1-last=Bock |editor1-first=Gisela |editor2-last=Skinner |editor2-first=Quentin |editor3-last=Viroli |editor3-first=Maurizio |title=Machiavelli and Republicanism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9MNULqj7T4YC |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1993 |isbn=978-0521435895}}
* Chabod, Federico (1958). ''Machiavelli & the Renaissance'' ; * Chabod, Federico (1958). ''Machiavelli & the Renaissance'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090619162346/http://www.questia.com/read/56380461?title=Machiavelli%20%26%20the%20Renaissance |date=19 June 2009 }}; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080820112213/http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01383 |date=20 August 2008 }}
* Connell, William J. (2001), "Machiavelli on Growth as an End," in Anthony Grafton and J.H.M. Salmon, eds., ''Historians and Ideologues: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Kelley'', Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 259-277. * Connell, William J. (2001), "Machiavelli on Growth as an End," in Anthony Grafton and J.H.M. Salmon, eds., ''Historians and Ideologues: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Kelley'', Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 259–277.
* Donskis, Leonidas, ed. (2011). Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi, {{ISBN|978-90-420-3277-4}}, E-{{ISBN|978-90-420-3278-1}} * Donskis, Leonidas, ed. (2011). Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi, {{ISBN|978-9042032774}}, E-{{ISBN|978-9042032781}}
* ] "Niccolò Machiavelli: The Florentine Commune" in ''The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000. * ] "Niccolò Machiavelli: The Florentine Commune" in ''The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
* {{cite journal |last1=Fischer |first1=Markus |title=Machiavelli's Political Psychology |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Autumn 1997 |volume=59 |issue=4 |pages=789–829 |jstor=1408308 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500028333}} * {{cite journal |last1=Fischer |first1=Markus |title=Machiavelli's Political Psychology |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Autumn 1997 |volume=59 |issue=4 |pages=789–829 |jstor=1408308 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500028333|s2cid=146570913 }}
* {{Citation|title=Well-ordered License: On the Unity of Machiavelli's Thought|last=Fischer|first=Markus|publisher=Lexington Book|year=2000}} * {{Citation|title=Well-ordered License: On the Unity of Machiavelli's Thought|last=Fischer|first=Markus|publisher=Lexington Book|year=2000}}
* {{cite book |last= Frederick II of Prussia|title=Anti-Machiavel: The Refutation of Machiavelli s Prince |date=1980 |orig-date=1740|translator-last=Sonnino|translator-first=Paul|publisher=Ohio University Press |location=Athens, OH |isbn=9780821405598}}
* {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli and the crisis of the Italian republics|last=Guarini|first=Elena|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}} * {{Citation|chapter=Machiavelli and the crisis of the Italian republics|last=Guarini|first=Elena|title=Machiavelli and Republicanism|year=1999|editor1-last=Bock|editor1-first=Gisela|editor2-last=Skinner|editor2-first=Quentin|editor3-last=Viroli|editor3-first=Maurizio|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{Citation|title=Machiavelli's ''Prince'' and Its Forerunners|year=1938|publisher=Duke University Press|last=Gilbert|first=Allan}} * {{Citation|title=Machiavelli's ''Prince'' and Its Forerunners|year=1938|publisher=Duke University Press|last=Gilbert|first=Allan}}
* Gilbert, Felix. ''Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy'' (2nd ed. 1984) * Gilbert, Felix. ''Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy'' (2nd ed. 1984) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055742/https://www.fulcrum.org/concern/monographs/rb68xf36w |date=18 November 2022 }}
* Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. ''The Makers of Modern Strategy'' (1944) * Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. ''The Makers of Modern Strategy'' (1944)
* Jensen, De Lamar, ed. ''Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist?'' (1960) essays by scholars * Jensen, De Lamar, ed. ''Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist?'' (1960) essays by scholars {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100425072059/http://www.questia.com/read/34624137?title=Machiavelli%3A%20Cynic%2C%20Patriot%2C%20or%20Political%20Scientist%3F |date=25 April 2010 }}
* {{Cite book |last= Jurdjevic |first= Mark |year= 2014 |title= A Great and Wretched City: Promise and Failure in Machiavelli's Florentine Political Thought |location= Cambridge, Massachusetts |publisher= ] |isbn= 978-0-674-72546-1}} * {{Cite book |last= Jurdjevic |first= Mark |year= 2014 |title= A Great and Wretched City: Promise and Failure in Machiavelli's Florentine Political Thought |location= Cambridge, Massachusetts |publisher= ] |isbn= 978-0674725461}}
* {{Citation|last=Kennington|first=Richard|year=2004|title=On Modern Origins|publisher=Lexington Books}} * {{Citation|last=Kennington|first=Richard|year=2004|title=On Modern Origins|publisher=Lexington Books}}
* Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun. 1981), pp.&nbsp;293–305 * Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun. 1981), pp.&nbsp;293–305 {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160808041013/http://www.jstor.org/stable/1961365 |date=8 August 2016 }}
* {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|year=1993|title=Taming the Prince|publisher=The Johns Hopkins University Press}} * {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|year=1993|title=Taming the Prince|publisher=The Johns Hopkins University Press}}
* {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|chapter=Machiavelli and the Idea of Progress|year=1995|editor1-last=Melzer|editor2-last=Weinberger|editor3-last=Zinman|title=History and the Idea of Progress|publisher=Cornell University Press}} * {{Citation|last=Mansfield|first=Harvey|chapter=Machiavelli and the Idea of Progress|year=1995|editor1-last=Melzer|editor2-last=Weinberger|editor3-last=Zinman|title=History and the Idea of Progress|publisher=Cornell University Press}}
* Mansfield, Harvey C. '' Machiavelli's Virtue'' (1996), 371 pp * Mansfield, Harvey C. '' Machiavelli's Virtue'' (1996), 371 pp.
* Mansfield, Harvey C. ''Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy'' (2001) * Mansfield, Harvey C. ''Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy'' (2001) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210311142259/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0226503704 |date=11 March 2021 }}
* {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Machiavelli, Leonardo and the Science of Power | publisher = University of Notre Dame Press | year = 1996 | isbn = 978-0-268-01433-9 |authorlink=Roger Masters}} See also . * {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Machiavelli, Leonardo and the Science of Power | publisher = University of Notre Dame Press | year = 1996 | isbn = 978-0268014339 |author-link=Roger Masters}} See also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.nytimes.com/1996/12/08/us/scholar-sees-leonardo-s-influence-on-machiavelli.html?sec=&spon=&pagewanted=print |date=18 November 2022 }}.
* {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Fortune is a River: Leonardo Da Vinci and Niccolò Machiavelli's Magnificent Dream to Change the Course of Florentine History | publisher = Simon & Schuster | year = 1998 | isbn = 978-0-452-28090-8 |authorlink=Roger Masters}} Also available in Chinese ({{ISBN|9789572026113}}), Japanese ({{ISBN|9784022597588}}), German ({{ISBN|9783471794029}}), Portuguese ({{ISBN|9788571104969}}), and Korean ({{ISBN|9788984070059}}). See also . * {{Citation| author = Roger Masters | title = Fortune is a River: Leonardo Da Vinci and Niccolò Machiavelli's Magnificent Dream to Change the Course of Florentine History | publisher = Simon & Schuster | year = 1998 | isbn = 978-0-452-28090-8 |author-link=Roger Masters}} Also available in Chinese ({{ISBN|9789572026113}}), Japanese ({{ISBN|978-4022597588}}), German ({{ISBN|978-3471794029}}), Portuguese ({{ISBN|978-8571104969}}), and Korean ({{ISBN|978-8984070059}}). See also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055738/https://www.nytimes.com/1998/07/17/books/books-of-the-times-a-river-ran-through-their-dreams.html?sec=&spon=&pagewanted=print |date=18 November 2022 }}.
* {{Citation|last= Mattingly|first=Garrett|title=Machiavelli's Prince: Political Science or Political Satire?|journal=The American Scholar|issue=27|year=Autumn 1958|pages=482–91|postscript=.}} * {{Citation|last= Mattingly|first=Garrett|title=Machiavelli's Prince: Political Science or Political Satire?|journal=The American Scholar|issue=27|date=Autumn 1958|pages=482–491|postscript=.}}
* {{Citation|title=Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513–1515|last=Najemy|first=John|year=1993|publisher=Princeton University Press}} * {{Citation|title=Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513–1515|last=Najemy|first=John|year=1993|publisher=Princeton University Press}}
* {{Citation|last= Najemy|first=John M.|title=Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism|journal=American Historical Review|issue=1|year=1996|pages= 119–29|doi=10.2307/2169227|volume=101|jstor= 2169227|postscript=.}} * {{Citation|last= Najemy|first=John M.|title=Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism|journal=American Historical Review|issue=1|year=1996|pages= 119–129|doi=10.2307/2169227|volume=101|jstor= 2169227|postscript=.}}
* {{cite journal |last1=Parel |first1=A. J. |title=The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Spring 1991 |volume=53 |issue=2 |pages=320–339 |jstor=1407757 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500014649}} * {{cite journal |last1=Parel |first1=A. J. |title=The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity |journal=The Review of Politics |date=Spring 1991 |volume=53 |issue=2 |pages=320–339 |jstor=1407757 |doi=10.1017/S0034670500014649|s2cid=170629105 }}
* {{Citation|last=Parel|first=Anthony|chapter=Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters|title=The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy|location=Toronto|year=1972|pages=3–28}} * {{Citation|last=Parel|first=Anthony|chapter=Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters|title=The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy|location=Toronto|year=1972|pages=3–28}}
* {{Citation|last=Parsons|first=William B.|title=Machiavelli's Gospel|year=2016|publisher=University of Rochester Press|isbn=9781580464918}} * {{Citation|last=Parsons|first=William B.|title=Machiavelli's Gospel|year=2016|publisher=University of Rochester Press|isbn=978-1580464918}}
* {{Citation|last=Pocock|first=J.G.A.|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|publisher=Princeton|year=1975}} new ed. 2003, a highly influential study of ''Discourses'' and its vast influence; ; also * {{Citation|last=Pocock|first=J.G.A.|title=The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition|publisher=Princeton|year=1975}} new ed. 2003, a highly influential study of ''Discourses'' and its vast influence; {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210318183144/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0691114722 |date=18 March 2021 }}; also {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20101007145157/http://www.questia.com/read/100774068?title=The%20Machiavellian%20Moment%3A%20Florentine%20Political%20Thought%20and%20the%20Atlantic%20Republican%20Tradition |date=7 October 2010 }}
* Pocock, J. G. A. "The Machiavellian Moment Revisited: a Study in History and Ideology.: ''Journal of Modern History'' 1981 53(1): 49–72. . * Pocock, J. G. A. "The Machiavellian Moment Revisited: a Study in History and Ideology.: ''Journal of Modern History'' 1981 53(1): 49–72. {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180911191259/https://www.jstor.org/stable/1877064 |date=11 September 2018 }}.
* {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul|title=Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution|year=1992}} * {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul|title=Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution|year=1992}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090923182527/http://www.questia.com/library/book/republics-ancient-and-modern-classical-republicanism-and-the-american-revolution-vol-2-by-paul-a-rahe.jsp |date=23 September 2009 }}
* {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|year=2006|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521851879}} Excerpt, reviews and Text search shows Machiavelli's ''Discourses'' had a major impact on shaping conservative thought. * {{Citation|last=Rahe|first=Paul A.|title=Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy|year=2006|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521851879}} Excerpt, reviews and Text search shows Machiavelli's ''Discourses'' had a major impact on shaping conservative thought.
* Ruggiero, Guido. (2007) * Ruggiero, Guido. (2007)
* {{Citation|first=David|last=Schaefer|year=1990|publisher=Cornell University Press|title=The Political Philosophy of Montaigne}}. * {{Citation|first=David|last=Schaefer|year=1990|publisher=Cornell University Press|title=The Political Philosophy of Montaigne}}.
* {{cite journal |last1=Scott |first1=John T. |last2=Sullivan |first2=Vickie B. |title=Patricide and the Plot of the Prince: Cesare Borgia and Machiavelli's Italy |journal=The American Political Science Review |date=1994 |volume=88 |issue=4 |pages=887–900 |doi=10.2307/2082714 |issn=0003-0554|jstor=2082714}} * {{cite journal |last1=Scott |first1=John T. |last2=Sullivan |first2=Vickie B. |title=Patricide and the Plot of the Prince: Cesare Borgia and Machiavelli's Italy |journal=The American Political Science Review |date=1994 |volume=88 |issue=4 |pages=887–900 |doi=10.2307/2082714 |issn=0003-0554|jstor=2082714|s2cid=144798597 }}
* Skinner, Quentin. ''The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, v. I, The Renaissance,'' (1978) * Skinner, Quentin. ''The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, v. I, The Renaissance,'' (1978)
* {{Citation|last= Soll|first=Jacob|title=Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism|publisher=University of Michigan Press|year=2005}} * {{Citation|last= Soll|first=Jacob|title=Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism|publisher=University of Michigan Press|year=2005}}
* Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ''Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2005) * Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ''Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2005)
* {{Citation|chapter=Niccolò Machiavelli|title=History of Political Philosophy|edition=3rd|editor1-last=Strauss|editor1-first=Leo|editor2-last=Cropsey|editor2-first=Joseph|last=Strauss|first=Leo|year=1987|publisher=University of Chicago Press}} * {{Citation|chapter=Niccolò Machiavelli|title=History of Political Philosophy|edition=3rd|editor1-last=Strauss|editor1-first=Leo|editor2-last=Cropsey|editor2-first=Joseph|last=Strauss|first=Leo|year=1987|publisher=University of Chicago Press}}
* {{Citation|last=Strauss|first=Leo|authorlink = Leo Strauss|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|publisher=University of Chicago Press|location=Chicago|year=1958|isbn=978-0-226-77702-3}} * {{Citation|last=Strauss|first=Leo|author-link = Leo Strauss|title=Thoughts on Machiavelli|publisher=University of Chicago Press|location=Chicago|year=1958|isbn=978-0226777023}}
* {{Citation|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B., ed.|title=The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works|publisher=Yale U. Press|year=2000}} * {{Citation|editor-last= Sullivan|editor-first=Vickie B.|title=The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works|publisher=Yale U. Press|year=2000}}
* {{Citation|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B.|title=Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed|publisher=Northern Illinois University Press|year=1996}} * {{Citation|last= Sullivan|first=Vickie B.|title=Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed|publisher=Northern Illinois University Press|year=1996}}
* von Vacano, Diego, "The Art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham MD: Lexington: 2007. * von Vacano, Diego, "The Art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham MD: Lexington: 2007.
* {{Citation|first=C. Bradley |last=Thompson|title=John Adams's Machiavellian Moment| journal=The Review of Politics|volume=57|issue=3|year=1995|pages=389–417|doi=10.1017/S0034670500019689}}. Also in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}. * {{Citation|first=C. Bradley |last=Thompson|title=John Adams's Machiavellian Moment| journal=The Review of Politics|volume=57|issue=3|year=1995|pages=389–417|doi=10.1017/S0034670500019689|s2cid=154074090 }}. Also in {{Harvtxt|Rahe|2006}}.
* {{Citation|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|location=Lexington|year=2004}} * {{Citation|last=Whelan|first=Frederick G.|title=Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought|location=Lexington|year=2004}}
* {{cite book |last1=Wight |first1=Martin |authorlink1=Martin Wight |editor1-last=Wight |editor1-first=Gabriele |editor2-last= Porter |editor2-first=Brian |title=Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=9780199273676 |url=http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780199273676.do |ref=harv |language=en}} * {{cite book |last1=Wight |first1=Martin |author-link1=Martin Wight |editor1-last=Wight |editor1-first=Gabriele |editor2-last= Porter |editor2-first=Brian |title=Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=978-0199273676 |url=http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780199273676.do |language=en}}
* Zuckert, Catherine, (2017) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.google.com/books/edition/Machiavelli_s_Politics/yZUtDwAAQBAJ?hl=en&gbpv=1&dq=catherine+zuckert&printsec=frontcover |date=18 November 2022 }}
{{refend}} {{refend}}


===Italian studies=== ===Italian studies===
{{refbegin}} {{refbegin|30em}}
* Barbuto, Marcelo (2005), "Questa oblivione delle cose. Reflexiones sobre la cosmología de Maquiavelo (1469-1527)," ''Revista Daimon'', 34, Universidad de Murcia, pp.&nbsp;34–52. * Barbuto, Marcelo (2005), "Questa oblivione delle cose. Reflexiones sobre la cosmología de Maquiavelo (1469–1527)," ''Revista Daimon'', 34, Universidad de Murcia, pp.&nbsp;34–52.
* Barbuto, Marcelo (2008), "Discorsi, I, XII, 12–14. La Chiesa romana di fronte alla republica cristiana", ''Filosofia Politica'', 1, Il Mulino, Bologna, pp.&nbsp;99–116. * Barbuto, Marcelo (2008), "Discorsi, I, XII, 12–14. La Chiesa romana di fronte alla republica cristiana", ''Filosofia Politica'', 1, Il Mulino, Bologna, pp.&nbsp;99–116.
* Celli, Carlo ( 2009), ''Il carnevale di Machiavelli'', Firenze, L.S. Olschki.
* ] (2015), ''Machiavelli nel Rinascimento italiano'', Milano, Franco Angeli. * ] (2015), ''Machiavelli nel Rinascimento italiano'', Milano, Franco Angeli.
* Giuseppe Leone, "Silone e Machiavelli. Una scuola...che non crea prìncipi", pref. di Vittoriano Esposito, Centro Studi Ignazio Silone, Pescina, 2003. * Giuseppe Leone, "Silone e Machiavelli. Una scuola...che non crea prìncipi", pref. di Vittoriano Esposito, Centro Studi Ignazio Silone, Pescina, 2003.
* Martelli, Mario (2004), "La Mandragola e il suo prologo", ''Interpres'', XXIII, pp.&nbsp;106–42. * Martelli, Mario (2004), "La Mandragola e il suo prologo", ''Interpres'', XXIII, pp.&nbsp;106–142.
* Martelli, Mario (2003), "Per la definizione della nozione di principe civile", ''Interpres'', XXII. * Martelli, Mario (2003), "Per la definizione della nozione di principe civile", ''Interpres'', XXII.
* Martelli, Mario (2001), "I dettagli della filologia", ''Interpres'' XX, pp.&nbsp;212–71. * Martelli, Mario (2001), "I dettagli della filologia", ''Interpres'' XX, pp.&nbsp;212–271.
* Martelli, Mario (1999a), "Note su Machiavelli", ''Interpres'' XVIII, pp.&nbsp;91–145. * Martelli, Mario (1999a), "Note su Machiavelli", ''Interpres'' XVIII, pp.&nbsp;91–145.
* Martelli, Mario (1999b), ''Saggio sul Principe'', Salerno Editrice, Roma. * Martelli, Mario (1999b), ''Saggio sul Principe'', Salerno Editrice, Roma.
* Martelli, Mario (1999c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola: valutazione politica e valutazione religiosa", Girolamo Savonarola. L´uomo e il frate". Atti del xxxv Convegno storico internazionale (Todi, II-14 ottobre 1998), CISAM, Spoleto, pp.&nbsp;139–53. * Martelli, Mario (1999c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola: valutazione politica e valutazione religiosa", Girolamo Savonarola. L´uomo e il frate". Atti del xxxv Convegno storico internazionale (Todi, II-14 ottobre 1998), CISAM, Spoleto, pp.&nbsp;139–153.
* Martelli, Mario (1998a), ''Machiavelli e gli storici antichi, osservazioni su alcuni luoghi dei discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'', Quaderni di Filologia e critica, 13, Salerno Editrice, Roma. * Martelli, Mario (1998a), ''Machiavelli e gli storici antichi, osservazioni su alcuni luoghi dei discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'', Quaderni di Filologia e critica, 13, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
* Martelli, Mario (1998b), "Machiavelli politico amante poeta", ''Interpres'' XVII, pp.&nbsp;211–56. * Martelli, Mario (1998b), "Machiavelli politico amante poeta", ''Interpres'' XVII, pp.&nbsp;211–256.
* Martelli, Mario (1998c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola", ''Savonarola. Democrazia, tirannide, profezia'', a cura di G.C. Garfagnini, Florencia, Sismel-Edizioni del Galluzo, pp.&nbsp;67–89. * Martelli, Mario (1998c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola", ''Savonarola. Democrazia, tirannide, profezia'', a cura di G.C. Garfagnini, Florencia, Sismel-Edizioni del Galluzo, pp.&nbsp;67–89.
* Martelli, Mario and Bausi, Francesco (1997), "Politica, storia e letteratura: Machiavelli e Guicciardini", ''Storia della letteratura italiana'', E. Malato (ed.), vol. IV. Il primo Cinquecento, Salerno Editrice, Roma, pp.&nbsp;251–320. * Martelli, Mario and Bausi, Francesco (1997), "Politica, storia e letteratura: Machiavelli e Guicciardini", ''Storia della letteratura italiana'', E. Malato (ed.), vol. IV. Il primo Cinquecento, Salerno Editrice, Roma, pp.&nbsp;251–320.
Line 383: Line 379:
* Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. ''The Portable Machiavelli'' (1979) * Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. ''The Portable Machiavelli'' (1979)
* Penman, Bruce. ''The Prince and Other Political Writings,'' (1981) * Penman, Bruce. ''The Prince and Other Political Writings,'' (1981)
* {{Citation|last= Wootton|first=David, ed.|title=Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli|location=Indianapolis|publisher=Hackett Pubs.|year=1994}} * {{Citation |editor-last=Wootton |editor-first=David |title=Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli |location=Indianapolis |publisher=Hackett Pubs. |year=1994}} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210316084453/https://www.amazon.com/dp/087220247X |date=16 March 2021 }}


'''The Prince''' '''The Prince'''
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|title=The Prince with Related Documents|year=2016|publisher=Bedford/St. Martin's|location=Boston|isbn=978-1-319-04892-1|edition=Second|url=http://www.macmillanlearning.com/Catalog/product/prince-secondedition-connell}}. Translated by ] * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince with Related Documents |year=2016 |publisher=Bedford/St. Martin's |location=Boston |isbn=978-1319048921 |edition=2nd |url=http://www.macmillanlearning.com/Catalog/product/prince-secondedition-connell}}. Translated by ]
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò |title= The Prince |publisher=Adagio Press|location=US|year=2015|isbn=978-0996767705}}. Edited by W. Garner. Translated by Luigi Ricci. * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Adagio Press |location=US |year=2015 |isbn=978-0996767705}}. Edited by W. Garner. Translated by Luigi Ricci. {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221118055737/https://www.amazon.com/Prince-Niccolo-Machiavelli/dp/0996767703 |date=18 November 2022 }}
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò |title= The Prince |publisher=Penguin|location=London|year=1961|isbn=978-0-14-044915-0}}. Translated by George Bull * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Penguin |location=London |year=1961 |isbn=978-0140449150}}. Translated by ]
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=2006|title=El Principe/The Prince: Comentado Por Napoleon Bonaparte / Commentaries by Napoleon Buonaparte''|publisher= Mestas Ediciones}}. Translated into Spanish by Marina Massa-Carrara * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=Penguin |location=London |year=2009 |isbn=978-1846140440}}. Translated by ]
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò |title=The Prince|publisher=University of Chicago Press|year=1985}}. Translated by Harvey Mansfield * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=W.W. Norton & Company |location=New York |year=1992 |isbn=0393962202}}. Translated by ] (Norton Critical Edition, 2nd ed., with "Backgrounds, Interpretations, Marginalia").
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò |title= The Prince|year=1995|publisher=Everyman}}. Translated and Edited by Stephen J. Milner. Introduction, Notes and other critical apparatus by J.M. Dent. * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |year=2006 |title=El Principe/The Prince: Comentado Por Napoleon Bonaparte / Commentaries by Napoleon Buonaparte |publisher=Mestas Ediciones}}. Translated into Spanish by Marina Massa-Carrara
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1985}}. Translated by Harvey Mansfield
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Peter Bondanella (1998) 101 pp
* {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=The Prince |year=1995 |publisher=Everyman}}. Translated and Edited by Stephen J. Milner. Introduction, Notes and other critical apparatus by J.M. Dent.
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Rufus Goodwin and Benjamin Martinez (2003)
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Peter Bondanella (1998) 101 pp {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100425072104/http://www.questia.com/read/97573377?title=The%20Prince |date=25 April 2010 }}
* ''The Prince'' (2007)
* ''The Prince'' ed. by Rufus Goodwin and Benjamin Martinez (2003) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210317074201/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0937832383 |date=17 March 2021 }}
* Machiavelli, Niccolò. ''The Prince,'' (1908 edition tr by W. K. Marriott)
* ''The Prince'' (2007) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210310164023/https://www.amazon.com/dp/0979415403 |date=10 March 2021 }}
* {{Citation|last= Marriott|first=W. K.|title=The Prince|publisher=Red and Black Publishers|year=2008}} {{ISBN|978-1-934941-00-3}}
* Machiavelli, Niccolò. ''The Prince,'' (1908 edition tr by W. K. Marriott) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090924041033/http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/1232 |date=24 September 2009 }}
* {{Citation |last=Marriott |first=W. K. |title=The Prince |publisher=Red and Black Publishers |year=2008}} {{ISBN|978-1934941003}}
* ''Il principe'' (2006) ed. by Mario Martelli and Nicoletta Marcelli, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, Salerno Editrice, Roma. * ''Il principe'' (2006) ed. by Mario Martelli and Nicoletta Marcelli, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, Salerno Editrice, Roma.


'''The Discourses on Livy''' '''The Discourses on Livy'''
* ''Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'' (2001), ed. by Francesco Bausi, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, II vol. Salerno Editrice, Roma. * ''Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio'' (2001), ed. by Francesco Bausi, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, II vol. Salerno Editrice, Roma.
* ''The Discourses,'' * ''The Discourses,'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120815054146/http://constitution.org/mac/disclivy_.htm |date=15 August 2012 }}
* ''The Discourses,'' tr. with introduction and notes by L. J. Walker (2 vol 1950). * ''The Discourses,'' tr. with introduction and notes by L. J. Walker (2 vol 1950).
* Machiavelli, Niccolò (1531). '']''. Translated by Leslie J. Walker, S.J, revisions by Brian Richardson (2003). London: Penguin Books. {{ISBN|0-14-044428-9}} * Machiavelli, Niccolò (1531). '']''. Translated by Leslie J. Walker, S.J, revisions by Brian Richardson (2003). London: Penguin Books. {{ISBN|0-14-044428-9}}
Line 407: Line 405:


'''The Art of War''' '''The Art of War'''
* ''The Seven Books on the Art of War'' * ''The Seven Books on the Art of War'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120716191533/http://www.constitution.org/mac/artofwar_.htm |date=16 July 2012 }}
* ''The Art of War'', University of Chicago Press, edited with new translation and commentary by ] (2003) * ''The Art of War'', University of Chicago Press, edited with new translation and commentary by ] (2003)
* ''The Art of War'' * ''The Art of War''
* ''The Art of War'', Niccolò Machiavelli. Da Capo press edition, 2001, with introduction by Neal Wood. * ''The Art of War'', Niccolò Machiavelli. Da Capo press edition, 2001, with introduction by Neal Wood.


'''Florentine Histories''' '''Florentine Histories'''
* ''History of Florence'' * ''History of Florence'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080920223244/http://www.gutenberg.org/files/2464/2464-h/2464-h.htm |date=20 September 2008 }}
* ''Reform of Florence'' * ''Reform of Florence'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120815053458/http://constitution.org/mac/florence.htm |date=15 August 2012 }}
* {{Citation|title=Florentine Histories|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|year=1988|publisher=Princeton University Press}}. Translation by Laura F Banfield and Harvey Mansfield. * {{Citation |title=Florentine Histories |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |year=1988 |publisher=Princeton University Press}}. Translation by Laura F. Banfield and Harvey Mansfield, Jr.


'''Correspondence''' '''Correspondence'''
* ''Epistolario privado. Las cartas que nos desvelan el pensamiento y la personalidad de uno de los intelectuales más importantes del Renacimiento'', Juan Manuel Forte (edición y traducción), Madrid, La Esfera de los Libros, 2007, 435 págs, {{ISBN|978-84-9734-661-0}} * ''Epistolario privado. Las cartas que nos desvelan el pensamiento y la personalidad de uno de los intelectuales más importantes del Renacimiento'', Juan Manuel Forte (edición y traducción), Madrid, La Esfera de los Libros, 2007, 435 págs, {{ISBN|978-8497346610}}
* ''The Private Correspondence of Niccolò Machiavelli,'' ed. by Orestes Ferrara; (1929) * ''The Private Correspondence of Niccolò Machiavelli,'' ed. by Orestes Ferrara; (1929) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090623124540/http://www.questia.com/read/77267435?title=The%20Private%20Correspondence%20of%20Nicolo%20Machiavelli |date=23 June 2009 }}
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|title=Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence|year=1996|publisher=Northern Illinois University Press}}. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices. * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence |year=1996 |publisher=Northern Illinois University Press}}. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.
* Also see {{Harvtxt|Najemy|1993}}. * Also see {{Harvtxt|Najemy|1993}}.


'''Poetry and comedy''' '''Poetry and comedy'''
* {{Citation|last=Machiavelli|first=Niccolò|title=Comedies of Machiavelli|year=1985|publisher=University Press of New England}} Bilingual edition of ''The Woman from Andros'', '']'', and '']'', edited by David Sices and James B. Atkinson. * {{Citation |last=Machiavelli |first=Niccolò |title=Comedies of Machiavelli |year=1985 |publisher=University Press of New England}} Bilingual edition of ''The Woman from Andros'', '']'', and '']'', edited by David Sices and James B. Atkinson.
* Hoeges, Dirk. ''Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano'', Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, {{ISBN|3-631-54669-6}}. * Hoeges, Dirk. ''Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano'', Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, {{ISBN|3631546696}}.
{{refend}} {{refend}}


==External links== ==External links==
{{Sister project links |wikt=no |commons=Niccolò Machiavelli |b=no |n=no |q=Niccolò Machiavelli |s=Author:Niccolò Machiavelli |v=no |species=no}} {{Sister project links |wikt=no |commons=Niccolò Machiavelli |b=no |n=no |q=Niccolò Machiavelli |s=Author:Niccolò Machiavelli |v=no |species=no}}
* {{StandardEbooks|Standard Ebooks URL=https://standardebooks.org/ebooks/niccolo-machiavelli}}
* {{Gutenberg author |id=563}}
* {{Internet Archive author |sname=Niccolò Machiavelli}}
* {{Librivox author |id=885}}
* {{cite EB1911|wstitle=Machiavelli, Niccolò |volume=17 |pages=233–237 |short=x}} * {{cite EB1911|wstitle=Machiavelli, Niccolò |volume=17 |pages=233–237 |short=x}}
* *
* - ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.'' * ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.''
* {{cite Collier's New Encyclopedia|wstitle=Macchiavelli |volume=6 |page=53 |short=x}} * {{cite Collier's New Encyclopedia|wstitle=Macchiavelli |volume=6 |page=53 |short=x}}
* *
* Mises Institute
* ] article "" with extensive discussion of Machiavelli * ] article "" with extensive discussion of Machiavelli
*
*
* {{Gutenberg author |id=563}}
* {{Internet Archive author |sname=Niccolò Machiavelli}}
* {{Librivox author |id=885}}
* at the ], including some of his works
* : text, concordances and frequency list * : text, concordances and frequency list
* : Italian and English text
*
*
*
* : Italian and English text
*
*
* ; with Quentin Skinner, Regius Professor of History at the University of Cambridge; Evelyn Welch, Professor of Renaissance Studies at Queen Mary, University of London; Lisa Jardine, Director of the Centre for Editing Lives and Letters at Queen Mary, University of London
*
{{Niccolò Machiavelli}} {{Niccolò Machiavelli}}
{{Social and political philosophy}} {{Political philosophy}}


{{Authority control}} {{Authority control}}
Line 464: Line 454:
] ]
] ]
]
] ]
] ]
]
]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]
] ]

Latest revision as of 06:58, 24 December 2024

Florentine statesman, diplomat, and political theorist (1469–1527) For other uses, see Machiavelli (disambiguation) and Macchiavelli (surname).

Niccolò Machiavelli
Portrait by Santi di Tito, c. 1550–1600
Born(1469-05-03)3 May 1469
Florence, Republic of Florence
Died21 June 1527(1527-06-21) (aged 58)
Florence, Republic of Florence
Notable work
Spouse Marietta Corsini ​(m. 1501)
EraRenaissance philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Main interestsPolitics and political philosophy, military theory, history
Notable ideasClassical realism, virtù, modern republicanism, national interest
Signature

Niccolò di Bernardo dei Machiavelli (3 May 1469 – 21 June 1527) was a Florentine diplomat, author, philosopher, and historian who lived during the Italian Renaissance. He is best known for his political treatise The Prince (Il Principe), written around 1513 but not published until 1532, five years after his death. He has often been called the father of modern political philosophy and political science.

For many years he served as a senior official in the Florentine Republic with responsibilities in diplomatic and military affairs. He wrote comedies, carnival songs, and poetry. His personal correspondence is also important to historians and scholars of Italian correspondence. He worked as secretary to the second chancery of the Republic of Florence from 1498 to 1512, when the Medici were out of power.

After his death Machiavelli's name came to evoke unscrupulous acts of the sort he advised most famously in his work, The Prince. He claimed that his experience and reading of history showed him that politics has always involved deception, treachery, and crime. He advised rulers to engage in evil when political necessity requires it, and argued specifically that successful reformers of states should not be blamed for killing other leaders who could block change. Machiavelli's Prince has been surrounded by controversy since it was published. Some consider it to be a straightforward description of political reality. Others view The Prince as a manual, teaching would-be tyrants how they should seize and maintain power. Even into recent times, some scholars, such as Leo Strauss, have restated the traditional opinion that Machiavelli was a "teacher of evil".

Even though Machiavelli has become most famous for his work on principalities, scholars also give attention to the exhortations in his other works of political philosophy. While less well known than The Prince, the Discourses on Livy (composed c. 1517) has been said to have paved the way for modern republicanism. His works were a major influence on Enlightenment authors who revived interest in classical republicanism, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau and James Harrington. Machiavelli's political realism has continued to influence generations of academics and politicians, including Hannah Arendt, and his approach has been compared to the Realpolitik of figures such as Otto von Bismarck.

Life

For a chronological guide, see Timeline of Niccolò Machiavelli.
Oil painting of Machiavelli by Cristofano dell'Altissimo

Machiavelli was born in Florence, Italy, the third child and first son of attorney Bernardo di Niccolò Machiavelli and his wife, Bartolomea di Stefano Nelli, on 3 May 1469. The Machiavelli family is believed to be descended from the old marquesses of Tuscany and to have produced thirteen Florentine Gonfalonieres of Justice, one of the offices of a group of nine citizens selected by drawing lots every two months and who formed the government, or Signoria; he was never, though, a full citizen of Florence because of the nature of Florentine citizenship in that time even under the republican regime. Machiavelli married Marietta Corsini in 1501. They had seven children, five sons and two daughters: Primerana, Bernardo, Lodovico, Guido, Piero [it], Baccina and Totto.

Machiavelli was born in a tumultuous era. The Italian city-states, and the families and individuals who ran them could rise and fall suddenly, as popes and the kings of France, Spain, and the Holy Roman Empire waged acquisitive wars for regional influence and control. Political-military alliances continually changed, featuring condottieri (mercenary leaders), who changed sides without warning, and the rise and fall of many short-lived governments.

Machiavelli was taught grammar, rhetoric, and Latin by his teacher, Paolo da Ronciglione. It is unknown whether Machiavelli knew Greek; Florence was at the time one of the centres of Greek scholarship in Europe. In 1494 Florence restored the republic, expelling the Medici family that had ruled Florence for some sixty years. Shortly after the execution of Savonarola, Machiavelli was appointed to an office of the second chancery, a medieval writing office that put Machiavelli in charge of the production of official Florentine government documents. Shortly thereafter, he was also made the secretary of the Dieci di Libertà e Pace.

In the first decade of the sixteenth century, he carried out several diplomatic missions, most notably to the papacy in Rome. Florence sent him to Pistoia to pacify the leaders of two opposing factions which had broken into riots in 1501 and 1502; when this failed, the leaders were banished from the city, a strategy which Machiavelli had favoured from the outset. From 1502 to 1503, he witnessed the brutal reality of the state-building methods of Cesare Borgia (1475–1507) and his father, Pope Alexander VI, who were then engaged in the process of trying to bring a large part of central Italy under their possession. The pretext of defending Church interests was used as a partial justification by the Borgias. Other excursions to the court of Louis XII and the Spanish court influenced his writings such as The Prince.

At the start of the 16th century, Machiavelli conceived of a militia for Florence, and he then began recruiting and creating it. He distrusted mercenaries (a distrust that he explained in his official reports and then later in his theoretical works for their unpatriotic and uninvested nature in the war that makes their allegiance fickle and often unreliable when most needed), and instead staffed his army with citizens, a policy that yielded some positive results. By February 1506 he was able to have four hundred farmers marching on parade, suited (including iron breastplates), and armed with lances and small firearms. Under his command, Florentine citizen-soldiers conquered Pisa in 1509.

Machiavelli's tomb in the Santa Croce Church in Florence

Machiavelli's success was short-lived. In August 1512, the Medici, backed by Pope Julius II, used Spanish troops to defeat the Florentines at Prato. In the wake of the siege, Piero Soderini resigned as Florentine head of state and fled into exile. The experience would, like Machiavelli's time in foreign courts and with the Borgia, heavily influence his political writings. The Florentine city-state and the republic were dissolved, with Machiavelli then being removed from office and banished from the city for a year. In 1513, the Medici accused him of conspiracy against them and had him imprisoned. Despite being subjected to torture ("with the rope", in which the prisoner is hanged from his bound wrists from the back, forcing the arms to bear the body's weight and dislocating the shoulders), he denied involvement and was released after three weeks.

Machiavelli then retired to his farm estate at Sant'Andrea in Percussina, near San Casciano in Val di Pesa, where he devoted himself to studying and writing political treatises. During this period, he represented the Florentine Republic on diplomatic visits to France, Germany, and elsewhere in Italy. Despairing of the opportunity to remain directly involved in political matters, after a time he began to participate in intellectual groups in Florence and wrote several plays that (unlike his works on political theory) were both popular and widely known in his lifetime. Politics remained his main passion, and to satisfy this interest, he maintained a well-known correspondence with more politically connected friends, attempting to become involved once again in political life. In a letter to Francesco Vettori, he described his experience:

When evening comes, I go back home, and go to my study. On the threshold, I take off my work clothes, covered in mud and filth, and I put on the clothes an ambassador would wear. Decently dressed, I enter the ancient courts of rulers who have long since died. There, I am warmly welcomed, and I feed on the only food I find nourishing and was born to savour. I am not ashamed to talk to them and ask them to explain their actions and they, out of kindness, answer me. Four hours go by without my feeling any anxiety. I forget every worry. I am no longer afraid of poverty or frightened of death. I live entirely through them.

Machiavelli died on 21 June 1527 from a stomach ailment at the age of 58 after receiving his last rites. He was buried at the Church of Santa Croce in Florence. In 1789 George Nassau Clavering, and Pietro Leopoldo, Grand Duke of Tuscany, initiated the construction of a monument on Machiavelli's tomb. It was sculpted by Innocenzo Spinazzi, with an epitaph by Doctor Ferroni inscribed on it.

Major works

The Prince

Main article: The Prince
Lorenzo di Piero de' Medici, to whom the final version of The Prince was dedicated

Machiavelli's best-known book Il Principe contains several maxims concerning politics. Instead of the more traditional target audience of a hereditary prince, it concentrates on the possibility of a "new prince". To retain power, the hereditary prince must carefully balance the interests of a variety of institutions to which the people are accustomed. By contrast, a new prince has the more difficult task in ruling: He must first stabilise his newfound power in order to build an enduring political structure. Machiavelli suggests that the political benefits of stability and security can be achieved in the face of moral corruption. Machiavelli believed that public and private morality had to be understood as two different things in order to rule well. As a result, a ruler must be concerned not only with reputation, but also must be positively willing to act unscrupulously at the right times. Machiavelli believed that, for a ruler, it was better to be widely feared than to be greatly loved; a loved ruler retains authority by obligation, while a feared leader rules by fear of punishment. As a political theorist, Machiavelli emphasized the "necessity" for the methodical exercise of brute force or deceit, including extermination of entire noble families, to head off any chance of a challenge to the prince's authority.

Scholars often note that Machiavelli glorifies instrumentality in state building, an approach embodied by the saying, often attributed to interpretations of The Prince, "The ends justify the means". Fraud and deceit are held by Machiavelli as necessary for a prince to use. Violence may be necessary for the successful stabilization of power and introduction of new political institutions. Force may be used to eliminate political rivals, destroy resistant populations, and purge the community of other men strong enough of a character to rule, who will inevitably attempt to replace the ruler. In one passage, Machiavelli subverts the advice given by Cicero to avoid duplicity and violence, by saying that the prince should "be the fox to avoid the snares, and a lion to overwhelm the wolves". It would become one of Machiavelli's most famous maxims. Machiavelli's view that acquiring a state and maintaining it requires evil means has been noted as the chief theme of the treatise. Machiavelli has become infamous for such political advice, ensuring that he would be remembered in history through the adjective "Machiavellian".

Due to the treatise's controversial analysis on politics, in 1559, the Catholic Church banned The Prince, putting it on the Index Librorum Prohibitorum. Humanists, including Erasmus (c. 1466 – 1536), also viewed the book negatively. As a treatise, its primary intellectual contribution to the history of political thought is the fundamental break between political realism and political idealism, due to it being a manual on acquiring and keeping political power. In contrast with Plato and Aristotle, Machiavelli insisted that an imaginary ideal society is not a model by which a prince should orient himself.

Concerning the differences and similarities in Machiavelli's advice to ruthless and tyrannical princes in The Prince and his more republican exhortations in Discourses on Livy, a few commentators assert that The Prince, although written as advice for a monarchical prince, contains arguments for the superiority of republican regimes, similar to those found in the Discourses. In the 18th century, the work was even called a satire, for example by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).

Scholars such as Leo Strauss (1899–1973) and Harvey Mansfield (b. 1932) have stated that sections of The Prince and his other works have deliberately esoteric statements throughout them. However, Mansfield states that this is the result of Machiavelli's seeing grave and serious things as humorous because they are "manipulable by men", and sees them as grave because they "answer human necessities".

The Marxist theorist Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937) argued that Machiavelli's audience was the common people, as opposed to the ruling class, who were already made aware of the methods described through their education.

Discourses on Livy

Main article: Discourses on Livy

The Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius, written around 1517, and published in 1531, often referred to simply as the Discourses or Discorsi, is nominally a discussion regarding the classical history of early Ancient Rome, although it strays far from this subject matter and also uses contemporary political examples to illustrate points. Machiavelli presents it as a series of lessons on how a republic should be started and structured. It is a larger work than The Prince, and while it more openly explains the advantages of republics, it also contains many similar themes from his other works. For example, Machiavelli has noted that to save a republic from corruption, it is necessary to return it to a "kingly state" using violent means. He excuses Romulus for murdering his brother Remus and co-ruler Titus Tatius to gain absolute power for himself in that he established a "civil way of life". Commentators disagree about how much the two works agree with each other, as Machiavelli frequently refers to leaders of republics as "princes". Machiavelli even sometimes acts as an advisor to tyrants. Other scholars have pointed out the aggrandizing and imperialistic features of Machiavelli's republic. Nevertheless, it became one of the central texts of modern republicanism, and has often been argued to be a more comprehensive work than The Prince.

Originality

Engraved portrait of Machiavelli, from the Peace Palace Library's Il Principe, published in 1769

Major commentary on Machiavelli's work has focused on two issues: how unified and philosophical his work is and how innovative or traditional it is.

Coherence

There is some disagreement concerning how best to describe the unifying themes, if there are any, that can be found in Machiavelli's works, especially in the two major political works, The Prince and Discourses. Some commentators have described him as inconsistent, and perhaps as not even putting a high priority on consistency. Others such as Hans Baron have argued that his ideas must have changed dramatically over time. Some have argued that his conclusions are best understood as a product of his times, experiences and education. Others, such as Leo Strauss and Harvey Mansfield, have argued strongly that there is a strong and deliberate consistency and distinctness, even arguing that this extends to all of Machiavelli's works including his comedies and letters.

Influences

Commentators such as Leo Strauss have gone so far as to name Machiavelli as the deliberate originator of modernity itself. Others have argued that Machiavelli is only a particularly interesting example of trends which were happening around him. In any case, Machiavelli presented himself at various times as someone reminding Italians of the old virtues of the Romans and Greeks, and other times as someone promoting a completely new approach to politics.

That Machiavelli had a wide range of influences is in itself not controversial. Their relative importance is however a subject of ongoing discussion. It is possible to summarize some of the main influences emphasized by different commentators.

The Mirror of Princes genre

Gilbert (1938) summarized the similarities between The Prince and the genre it obviously imitates, the so-called "Mirror of Princes" style. This was a classically influenced genre, with models at least as far back as Xenophon and Isocrates. While Gilbert emphasized the similarities, however, he agreed with all other commentators that Machiavelli was particularly novel in the way he used this genre, even when compared to his contemporaries such as Baldassare Castiglione and Erasmus. One of the major innovations Gilbert noted was that Machiavelli focused on the "deliberate purpose of dealing with a new ruler who will need to establish himself in defiance of custom". Normally, these types of works were addressed only to hereditary princes. (Xenophon is also an exception in this regard.)

Classical republicanism

Commentators such as Quentin Skinner and J.G.A. Pocock, in the so-called "Cambridge School" of interpretation, have asserted that some of the republican themes in Machiavelli's political works, particularly the Discourses on Livy, can be found in medieval Italian literature which was influenced by classical authors such as Sallust.

Classical political philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle

Xenophon, author of the Cyropedia

The Socratic school of classical political philosophy, especially Aristotle, had become a major influence upon European political thinking in the late Middle Ages. It existed both in the Catholicised form presented by Thomas Aquinas, and in the more controversial "Averroist" form of authors like Marsilius of Padua. Machiavelli was critical of Catholic political thinking and may have been influenced by Averroism. But he rarely cites Plato and Aristotle, and most likely did not approve of them. Leo Strauss argued that the strong influence of Xenophon, a student of Socrates more known as a historian, rhetorician and soldier, was a major source of Socratic ideas for Machiavelli, sometimes not in line with Aristotle. While interest in Plato was increasing in Florence during Machiavelli's lifetime, Machiavelli does not show particular interest in him, but was indirectly influenced by his readings of authors such as Polybius, Plutarch and Cicero.

The major difference between Machiavelli and the Socratics, according to Strauss, is Machiavelli's materialism, and therefore his rejection of both a teleological view of nature and of the view that philosophy is higher than politics. With their teleological understanding of things, Socratics argued that by nature, everything that acts, acts towards some end, as if nature desired them, but Machiavelli claimed that such things happen by blind chance or human action.

Classical materialism

Strauss argued that Machiavelli may have seen himself as influenced by some ideas from classical materialists such as Democritus, Epicurus and Lucretius. Strauss however sees this also as a sign of major innovation in Machiavelli, because classical materialists did not share the Socratic regard for political life, while Machiavelli clearly did.

Thucydides

Some scholars note the similarity between Machiavelli and the Greek historian Thucydides, since both emphasized power politics. Strauss argued that Machiavelli may indeed have been influenced by pre-Socratic philosophers, but he felt it was a new combination:

...contemporary readers are reminded by Machiavelli's teaching of Thucydides; they find in both authors the same "realism", i.e., the same denial of the power of the gods or of justice and the same sensitivity to harsh necessity and elusive chance. Yet Thucydides never calls in question the intrinsic superiority of nobility to baseness, a superiority that shines forth particularly when the noble is destroyed by the base. Therefore Thucydides' History arouses in the reader a sadness which is never aroused by Machiavelli's books. In Machiavelli we find comedies, parodies, and satires but nothing reminding of tragedy. One half of humanity remains outside of his thought. There is no tragedy in Machiavelli because he has no sense of the sacredness of "the common". – Strauss (1958, p. 292)

Beliefs

Amongst commentators, there are a few consistently made proposals concerning what was most new in Machiavelli's work.

Empiricism and realism versus idealism

Machiavelli is sometimes seen as the prototype of a modern empirical scientist, building generalizations from experience and historical facts, and emphasizing the uselessness of theorizing with the imagination.

He emancipated politics from theology and moral philosophy. He undertook to describe simply what rulers actually did and thus anticipated what was later called the scientific spirit in which questions of good and bad are ignored, and the observer attempts to discover only what really happens.

— Joshua Kaplan, 2005

Machiavelli felt that his early schooling along the lines of traditional classical education was essentially useless for the purpose of understanding politics. Nevertheless, he advocated intensive study of the past, particularly regarding the founding of a city, which he felt was a key to understanding its later development. Moreover, he studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. Machiavelli denies the classical opinion that living virtuously always leads to happiness. For example, Machiavelli viewed misery as "one of the vices that enables a prince to rule." Machiavelli stated that "it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved." In much of Machiavelli's work, he often states that the ruler must adopt unsavoury policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime. Because cruelty and fraud play such important roles in his politics, it is not unusual for certain issues (such as murder and betrayal) to be commonplace within his works.

A related and more controversial proposal often made is that he described how to do things in politics in a way which seemed neutral concerning who used the advice – tyrants or good rulers. That Machiavelli strove for realism is not doubted, but for four centuries scholars have debated how best to describe his morality. The Prince made the word Machiavellian a byword for deceit, despotism, and political manipulation. Leo Strauss declared himself inclined toward the traditional view that Machiavelli was self-consciously a "teacher of evil", since he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception. Strauss takes up this opinion because he asserted that failure to accept the traditional opinion misses the "intrepidity of his thought" and "the graceful subtlety of his speech". Italian anti-fascist philosopher Benedetto Croce (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values, in reality, do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make. German philosopher Ernst Cassirer (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist – a Galileo of politics – in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment. On the other hand, Walter Russell Mead has argued that The Prince's advice presupposes the importance of ideas like legitimacy in making changes to the political system.

Fortune

Machiavelli is generally seen as being critical of Christianity as it existed in his time, specifically its effect upon politics, and also everyday life. In his opinion, Christianity, along with the teleological Aristotelianism that the Church had come to accept, allowed practical decisions to be guided too much by imaginary ideals and encouraged people to lazily leave events up to providence or, as he would put it, chance, luck or fortune. While Christianity sees modesty as a virtue and pride as sinful, Machiavelli took a more classical position, seeing ambition, spiritedness, and the pursuit of glory as good and natural things, and part of the virtue and prudence that good princes should have. Therefore, while it was traditional to say that leaders should have virtues, especially prudence, Machiavelli's use of the words virtù and prudenza was unusual for his time, implying a spirited and immodest ambition. Mansfield describes his usage of virtù as a "compromise with evil". Famously, Machiavelli argued that virtue and prudence can help a man control more of his future, in the place of allowing fortune to do so.

Najemy has argued that this same approach can be found in Machiavelli's approach to love and desire, as seen in his comedies and correspondence. Najemy shows how Machiavelli's friend Vettori argued against Machiavelli and cited a more traditional understanding of fortune.

On the other hand, humanism in Machiavelli's time meant that classical pre-Christian ideas about virtue and prudence, including the possibility of trying to control one's future, were not unique to him. But humanists did not go so far as to promote the extra glory of deliberately aiming to establish a new state, in defiance of traditions and laws.

While Machiavelli's approach had classical precedents, it has been argued that it did more than just bring back old ideas and that Machiavelli was not a typical humanist. Strauss (1958) argues that the way Machiavelli combines classical ideas is new. While Xenophon and Plato also described realistic politics and were closer to Machiavelli than Aristotle was, they, like Aristotle, also saw philosophy as something higher than politics. Machiavelli was apparently a materialist who objected to explanations involving formal and final causation, or teleology.

Machiavelli's promotion of ambition among leaders while denying any higher standard meant that he encouraged risk-taking, and innovation, most famously the founding of new modes and orders. His advice to princes was therefore certainly not limited to discussing how to maintain a state. It has been argued that Machiavelli's promotion of innovation led directly to the argument for progress as an aim of politics and civilization. But while a belief that humanity can control its own future, control nature, and "progress" has been long-lasting, Machiavelli's followers, starting with his own friend Guicciardini, have tended to prefer peaceful progress through economic development, and not warlike progress. As Harvey Mansfield (1995, p. 74) wrote: "In attempting other, more regular and scientific modes of overcoming fortune, Machiavelli's successors formalized and emasculated his notion of virtue."

Machiavelli however, along with some of his classical predecessors, saw ambition and spiritedness, and therefore war, as inevitable and part of human nature.

Strauss concludes his 1958 book Thoughts on Machiavelli by proposing that this promotion of progress leads directly to the advent of new technologies being invented in both good and bad governments. Strauss argued that the unavoidable nature of such arms races, which existed before modern times and led to the collapse of peaceful civilizations, show that classical-minded men "had to admit in other words that in an important respect the good city has to take its bearings by the practice of bad cities or that the bad impose their law on the good".Strauss (1958, pp. 298–299)

Religion

Machiavelli shows repeatedly that he saw religion as man-made, and that the value of religion lies in its contribution to social order and the rules of morality must be dispensed with if security requires it. In The Prince, the Discourses and in the Life of Castruccio Castracani he describes "prophets", as he calls them, like Moses, Romulus, Cyrus the Great and Theseus (he treated pagan and Christian patriarchs in the same way) as the greatest of new princes, the glorious and brutal founders of the most novel innovations in politics, and men whom Machiavelli assures us have always used a large amount of armed force and murder against their own people. He estimated that these sects last from 1,666 to 3,000 years each time, which, as pointed out by Leo Strauss, would mean that Christianity became due to start finishing about 150 years after Machiavelli. Machiavelli's concern with Christianity as a sect was that it makes men weak and inactive, delivering politics into the hands of cruel and wicked men without a fight. While Machiavelli's own religious allegiance has been debated, it is assumed that he had a low regard of contemporary Christianity.

While fear of God can be replaced by fear of the prince, if there is a strong enough prince, Machiavelli felt that having a religion is in any case especially essential to keeping a republic in order. For Machiavelli, a truly great prince can never be conventionally religious himself, but he should make his people religious if he can. According to Strauss (1958, pp. 226–227) he was not the first person to explain religion in this way, but his description of religion was novel because of the way he integrated this into his general account of princes.

Machiavelli's judgment that governments need religion for practical political reasons was widespread among modern proponents of republics until approximately the time of the French Revolution. This, therefore, represents a point of disagreement between Machiavelli and late modernity.

Positive side to factional and individual vice

Despite the classical precedents, which Machiavelli was not the only one to promote in his time, Machiavelli's realism and willingness to argue that good ends justify bad things, is seen as a critical stimulus towards some of the most important theories of modern politics.

Firstly, particularly in the Discourses on Livy, Machiavelli is unusual in the positive side to factionalism in republics which he sometimes seems to describe. For example, quite early in the Discourses, (in Book I, chapter 4), a chapter title announces that the disunion of the plebs and senate in Rome "kept Rome free". That a community has different components whose interests must be balanced in any good regime is an idea with classical precedents, but Machiavelli's particularly extreme presentation is seen as a critical step towards the later political ideas of both a division of powers or checks and balances, ideas which lay behind the US constitution, as well as many other modern state constitutions.

Similarly, the modern economic argument for capitalism, and most modern forms of economics, was often stated in the form of "public virtue from private vices". Also in this case, even though there are classical precedents, Machiavelli's insistence on being both realistic and ambitious, not only admitting that vice exists but being willing to risk encouraging it, is a critical step on the path to this insight.

Mansfield however argues that Machiavelli's own aims have not been shared by those he influenced. Machiavelli argued against seeing mere peace and economic growth as worthy aims on their own if they would lead to what Mansfield calls the "taming of the prince".

Influence

Statue at the Uffizi

To quote Robert Bireley:

...there were in circulation approximately fifteen editions of the Prince and nineteen of the Discourses and French translations of each before they were placed on the Index of Paul IV in 1559, a measure which nearly stopped publication in Catholic areas except in France. Three principal writers took the field against Machiavelli between the publication of his works and their condemnation in 1559 and again by the Tridentine Index in 1564. These were the English cardinal Reginald Pole and the Portuguese bishop Jeronymo Osorio, both of whom lived for many years in Italy, and the Italian humanist and later bishop, Ambrogio Caterino Politi.

Machiavelli's ideas had a profound impact on political leaders throughout the modern west, helped by the new technology of the printing press. During the first generations after Machiavelli, his main influence was in non-republican governments. Pole reported that The Prince was spoken of highly by Thomas Cromwell in England and had influenced Henry VIII in his turn towards Protestantism, and in his tactics, for example during the Pilgrimage of Grace. A copy was also possessed by the Catholic king and emperor Charles V. In France, after an initially mixed reaction, Machiavelli came to be associated with Catherine de' Medici and the St. Bartholomew's Day massacre. As Bireley (1990:17) reports, in the 16th century, Catholic writers "associated Machiavelli with the Protestants, whereas Protestant authors saw him as Italian and Catholic". In fact, he was apparently influencing both Catholic and Protestant kings.

One of the most important early works dedicated to criticism of Machiavelli, especially The Prince, was that of the Huguenot, Innocent Gentillet, whose work commonly referred to as Discourse against Machiavelli or Anti Machiavel was published in Geneva in 1576. He accused Machiavelli of being an atheist and accused politicians of his time by saying that his works were the "Koran of the courtiers", that "he is of no reputation in the court of France which hath not Machiavel's writings at the fingers ends". Another theme of Gentillet was more in the spirit of Machiavelli himself: he questioned the effectiveness of immoral strategies (just as Machiavelli had himself done, despite also explaining how they could sometimes work). This became the theme of much future political discourse in Europe during the 17th century. This includes the Catholic Counter Reformation writers summarised by Bireley: Giovanni Botero, Justus Lipsius, Carlo Scribani, Adam Contzen, Pedro de Ribadeneira, and Diego de Saavedra Fajardo. These authors criticized Machiavelli, but also followed him in many ways. They accepted the need for a prince to be concerned with reputation, and even a need for cunning and deceit, but compared to Machiavelli, and like later modernist writers, they emphasized economic progress much more than the riskier ventures of war. These authors tended to cite Tacitus as their source for realist political advice, rather than Machiavelli, and this pretence came to be known as "Tacitism". "Black tacitism" was in support of princely rule, but "red tacitism" arguing the case for republics, more in the original spirit of Machiavelli himself, became increasingly important. Cardinal Reginald Pole read The Prince while he was in Italy, and on which he gave his comments. Frederick the Great, king of Prussia and patron of Voltaire, wrote Anti-Machiavel, with the aim of rebutting The Prince.

Francis Bacon argued the case for what would become modern science which would be based more upon real experience and experimentation, free from assumptions about metaphysics, and aimed at increasing control of nature. He named Machiavelli as a predecessor.

Modern materialist philosophy developed in the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, starting in the generations after Machiavelli. Modern political philosophy tended to be republican, but as with the Catholic authors, Machiavelli's realism and encouragement of innovation to try to control one's own fortune were more accepted than his emphasis upon war and factional violence. Not only was innovative economics and politics a result, but also modern science, leading some commentators to say that the 18th century Enlightenment involved a "humanitarian" moderating of Machiavellianism.

The importance of Machiavelli's influence is notable in many important figures in this endeavour, for example Bodin, Francis Bacon, Algernon Sidney, Harrington, John Milton, Spinoza, Rousseau, Hume, Edward Gibbon, and Adam Smith. Although he was not always mentioned by name as an inspiration, due to his controversy, he is also thought to have been an influence for other major philosophers, such as Montaigne, Descartes, Hobbes, Locke and Montesquieu. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who is associated with very different political ideas, viewed Machiavelli's work as a satirical piece in which Machiavelli exposes the faults of a one-man rule rather than exalting amorality.

In the seventeenth century it was in England that Machiavelli's ideas were most substantially developed and adapted, and that republicanism came once more to life; and out of seventeenth-century English republicanism there were to emerge in the next century not only a theme of English political and historical reflection – of the writings of the Bolingbroke circle and of Gibbon and of early parliamentary radicals – but a stimulus to the Enlightenment in Scotland, on the Continent, and in America.

John Adams admired Machiavelli's rational description of the realities of statecraft. Adams used Machiavelli's works to argue for mixed government.

Scholars have argued that Machiavelli was a major indirect and direct influence upon the political thinking of the Founding Fathers of the United States due to his overwhelming favouritism of republicanism and the republican type of government. According to John McCormick, it is still very much debatable whether or not Machiavelli was "an advisor of tyranny or partisan of liberty." Benjamin Franklin, James Madison and Thomas Jefferson followed Machiavelli's republicanism when they opposed what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared Alexander Hamilton was creating with the Federalist Party. Hamilton learned from Machiavelli about the importance of foreign policy for domestic policy, but may have broken from him regarding how rapacious a republic needed to be in order to survive. George Washington was less influenced by Machiavelli.

The Founding Father who perhaps most studied and valued Machiavelli as a political philosopher was John Adams, who profusely commented on the Italian's thought in his work, A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America. In this work, John Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and Montesquieu, as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.

20th century

The 20th-century Italian Communist Antonio Gramsci drew great inspiration from Machiavelli's writings on ethics, morals, and how they relate to the State and revolution in his writings on Passive Revolution, and how a society can be manipulated by controlling popular notions of morality.

Joseph Stalin read The Prince and annotated his own copy.

In the 20th century there was also renewed interest in Machiavelli's play La Mandragola (1518), which received numerous stagings, including several in New York, at the New York Shakespeare Festival in 1976 and the Riverside Shakespeare Company in 1979, as a musical comedy by Peer Raben in Munich's Anti Theatre in 1971, and at London's National Theatre in 1984.

"Machiavellian"

Portrait of a Gentleman (Cesare Borgia), used as an example of a successful ruler in The Prince

Machiavelli's works are sometimes even said to have contributed to the modern negative connotations of the words politics and politician, and it is sometimes thought that it is because of him that Old Nick became an English term for the Devil. More obviously, the adjective Machiavellian became a term describing a form of politics that is "marked by cunning, duplicity, or bad faith". Machiavellianism also remains a popular term used casually in political discussions, often as a byword for bare-knuckled political realism.

While Machiavellianism is notable in the works of Machiavelli, scholars generally agree that his works are complex and have equally influential themes within them. For example, J. G. A. Pocock (1975) saw him as a major source of the republicanism that spread throughout England and North America in the 17th and 18th centuries and Leo Strauss (1958), whose view of Machiavelli is quite different in many ways, had similar remarks about Machiavelli's influence on republicanism and argued that even though Machiavelli was a teacher of evil he had a "grandeur of vision" that led him to advocate immoral actions. Whatever his intentions, which are still debated today, he has become associated with any proposal where "the end justifies the means". For example, Leo Strauss (1987, p. 297) wrote:

Machiavelli is the only political thinker whose name has come into common use for designating a kind of politics, which exists and will continue to exist independently of his influence, a politics guided exclusively by considerations of expediency, which uses all means, fair or foul, iron or poison, for achieving its ends – its end being the aggrandizement of one's country or fatherland – but also using the fatherland in the service of the self-aggrandizement of the politician or statesman or one's party.

In popular culture

Main article: Machiavelli in popular culture

Due to Machiavelli's popularity, he has been featured in various ways in cultural depictions. In English Renaissance theatre (Elizabethan and Jacobian), the term "Machiavel" (from 'Nicholas Machiavel', an "anglicization" of Machiavelli's name based on French) was used for a stock antagonist that resorted to ruthless means to preserve the power of the state, and is now considered a synonym of "Machiavellian".

Christopher Marlowe's play The Jew of Malta (ca. 1589) contains a prologue by a character called Machiavel, a Senecan ghost based on Machiavelli. Machiavel expresses the cynical view that power is amoral, saying:

 
   "I count religion but a childish toy,
   And hold there is no sin but ignorance."

Shakespeares titular character, Richard III, refers to Machiavelli in Henry VI, Part III, as the "murderous Machiavel".

Works

See also: Category:Works by Niccolò Machiavelli

Political and historical works

Peter Withorne's 1573 translation of The Art of War

Fictional works

See also: Machiavelli as a dramatist
Part of the Politics series
Republicanism
Concepts
Schools
Types
Philosophers
Politicians
Theoretical works
History
National variants
Related topics
icon Politics portal

Besides being a statesman and political scientist, Machiavelli also translated classical works, and was a playwright (Clizia, Mandragola), a poet (Sonetti, Canzoni, Ottave, Canti carnascialeschi), and a novelist (Belfagor arcidiavolo).

Some of his other work:

Other works

Della Lingua (Italian for "On the Language") (1514), a dialogue about Italy's language is normally attributed to Machiavelli.

Machiavelli's literary executor, Giuliano de' Ricci, also reported having seen that Machiavelli, his grandfather, made a comedy in the style of Aristophanes which included living Florentines as characters, and to be titled Le Maschere. It has been suggested that due to such things as this and his style of writing to his superiors generally, there was very likely some animosity to Machiavelli even before the return of the Medici.

See also

References

Footnotes

  1. /ˈnɪkəloʊ ˌmækiəˈvɛli/ NIK-ə-loh MAK-ee-ə-VEL-ee, US also /- ˌmɑːk-/ -⁠ MAHK-; Italian: [nikkoˈlɔ mmakjaˈvɛlli]; also occasionally rendered in English as Nicholas Machiavel (/ˈmækiəvɛl/ MAK-ee-ə-vel, US also /ˈmɑːk-/ MAHK-).
  2. The Latin legend reads: TANTO NOMINI NULLUM PAR ELOGIUM ("So great a name (has) no adequate praise" or "No eulogy (would be) a match for such a great name" or "There is no praise equal to so great a name.")

Citations

  1. "Machiavelli, Niccolò". Longman Dictionary of Contemporary English. Longman. Retrieved 5 August 2023.
  2. "Machievelli, Niccolò". Lexico US English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 10 February 2022.
  3. "Machiavelli". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (5th ed.). HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 February 2022.
  4. Dietz, Mary G.. Machiavelli, Niccolò (1469–1527), 1998, https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-S080-1. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis
  5. Berridge, G.R., Lloyd, L. (2012). M. In: Barder, B., Pope, L.E., Rana, K.S. (eds) The Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Diplomacy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137017611_13
  6. For example: "Niccolo Machiavelli – Italian statesman and writer". 17 June 2023. and "Niccolò Machiavelli". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 November 2018.
  7. For example: Smith, Gregory B. (2008). Between Eternities: On the Tradition of Political Philosophy, Past, Present, and Future. Lexington Books. p. 65. ISBN 978-0739120774., Whelan, Frederick G. (2004). Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought. Lexington Books. p. 29. ISBN 978-0739106310., Strauss (1988). What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies. University of Chicago Press. p. 41. ISBN 978-0226777139.
  8. Najemy 1993, p. missing
  9. "Niccolo Machiavelli". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 8 August 2019.
  10. Cassirer, Ernst (1946). The Myth of the State. Yale University Press. pp. 141–145. ISBN 978-0300000368. ernst cassirer the myth of the state.
  11. For example, The Prince chap. 15, and The Discourses Book I, chapter 9
  12. Strauss, Leo; Cropsey, Joseph (2012). History of Political Philosophy. University of Chicago Press. p. 297. ISBN 978-0226924717.
  13. Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. p. 178. ISBN 978-0226503721.
  14. Giorgini, Giovanni (2013). "Five Hundred Years of Italian Scholarship on Machiavelli's Prince". Review of Politics. 75 (4): 625–640. doi:10.1017/S0034670513000624. ISSN 0034-6705. S2CID 146970196.
  15. Strauss, Leo (2014). Thoughts on Machiavelli. University of Chicago Press. p. 9. ISBN 978-0226230979.
  16. Harvey Mansfield and Nathan Tarcov, "Introduction to the Discourses". In their translation of the Discourses on Livy
  17. Theodosiadis, Michail (June–August 2021). "From Hobbes and Locke to Machiavelli's virtù in the political context of meliorism: popular eucosmia and the value of moral memory". Polis Revista. 11: 25–60.
  18. Pflanze, Otto (1958). "Bismarck's "Realpolitik"". The Review of Politics. 20 (4): 492–514. doi:10.1017/S0034670500034185. ISSN 0034-6705. JSTOR 1404857. S2CID 144663704.
  19. Arendt, Hannah (1988). The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press. p. 77.
  20. de Grazia (1989)
  21. Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1913). "Niccolò Machiavelli" . Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
  22. Guarini (1999:21)
  23. "Machiavèlli, Niccolò nell'Enciclopedia Treccani". www.treccani.it (in Italian). Retrieved 11 July 2023.
  24. Maurizio Viroli, Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli (2000), ch 1
  25. Niccolo Machiavelli Biography – Life of Florentine Republic Official, 13 December 2013
  26. "Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527)". IEP. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  27. Ridolfi, Roberto (2013). The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli. Routledge. p. 28. ISBN 978-1135026615.
  28. Machiavelli 1981, p. 136, notes.
  29. "Niccolo Machiavelli | Biography, Books, Philosophy, & Facts". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 July 2019.
  30. ^ Viroli, Maurizio (2002). Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli. Macmillan. pp. 81–86. ISBN 978-0374528003.
  31. This point is made especially in The Prince, Chap XII
  32. Viroli, Maurizio (2002). Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli. Macmillan. p. 105. ISBN 978-0374528003.
  33. Many historians have argued that this was due to Piero Soderini's unwillingness to compromise with the Medici, who were holding Prato under siege.
  34. ^ Machiavelli 1981, p. 3, intro.
  35. Skinner, Quentin (2000). Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. p. 36. ISBN 978-0191540349.
  36. Niccolò Machiavelli (1996), Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence, Northern Illinois University Press, translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.
  37. Joshua Kaplan, "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance," The Modern Scholar (14 lectures in the series; lecture #7 / disc 4), 2005.
  38. "Washingtonpost.com: Horizon Section". www.washingtonpost.com. Retrieved 3 November 2023.
  39. "Even such men as Malatesta and Machiavelli, after spending their lives in estrangement from the Church, sought on their deathbeds her assistance and consolations. Both made good confessions and received the Holy Viaticum." – Ludwig von Pastor, History of the Popes, Vol. 5, p. 137.
  40. Black, Robert (2013). Machiavelli. Routledge. p. 283. ISBN 978-1317699583.
  41. Sil, Narasingha Prosad (1985). Kauṭilya's Arthaśāstra: A Comparative Study. Academic Publishers Calcutta. p. 217.
  42. Zuckert, Catherine H. (2017). Machiavelli's Politics. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226434803.
  43. Machiavelli, Niccolo (1984). The Prince. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 59–60. ISBN 0-19-281602-0.
  44. Machiavelli, Niccolò (1532). The Prince. Italy. pp. 120–121.
  45. Machiavelli, The Prince, Chapter III
  46. Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503721.
  47. The Prince, Chapter XVIII, "In What Mode Should Faith Be Kept By Princes"
  48. The Prince. especially Chapters 3, 5 and 8
  49. Skinner, Quentin (12 October 2000). Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780191540349.
  50. Strauss (1958, pp. 12)
  51. Kanzler, Peter (2020). The Prince (1532), The Leviathan (1651), The Two Treatises of Government (1689), The Constitution of Pennsylvania (1776). Peter Kanzler. p. 22. ISBN 978-1716844508.
  52. Scott, John T. (31 March 2016). The Routledge Guidebook to Machiavelli's the Prince. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-53673-4.
  53. Landon, W. J. (2005). Politics, Patriotism and Language: Niccolò Machiavelli's" secular Patria" and the Creation of an Italian National Identity (Vol. 57). Peter Lang.
  54. Discourse on Political Economy: opening pages.
  55. Berlin, Isaiah. "The Originality of Machiavelli" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2 December 2012. Retrieved 18 October 2012.
  56. This point made most notably by Strauss (1958).
  57. Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. pp. 228–229. ISBN 978-0226503721.
  58. Thomas, Peter D. (2017). "The Modern Prince". History of Political Thought. 38 (3): 523–544. JSTOR 26210463.
  59. Mansfield, Harvey C. (2001). Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503707.
  60. "Discourses on Livy: Book 1, Chapter 18". www.constitution.org. Retrieved 9 May 2019.
  61. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 9. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
  62. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
  63. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy: Book One, Chapter 16. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
  64. Rahe, Paul A. (2005). Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy. Cambridge University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-1139448338.
  65. Hulliung, Mark (2017). Citizen Machiavelli. Routledge. ISBN 978-1351528481.
  66. Pocock (1975, pp. 183–219)
  67. ^ Fischer (2000)
  68. Interpreting Modern Political Philosophy: From Machiavelli to Marx, pg. 40
  69. Mansfield, Harvey C. (1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226503721.
  70. Skinner, Quentin (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought: Volume 1, The Renaissance. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521293372.
  71. Pocock, J. G. A. (2016). The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1400883516.
  72. ^ Strauss (1958)
  73. Paul Anthony Rahe, Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English Republic (2008), p. 282.
  74. Jack Donnelly, Realism and International Relations (2000), p. 68.
  75. ^ Joshua Kaplan (2005). "Political Theory: The Classic Texts and their Continuing Relevance". The Modern Scholar. 14 lectures in the series; (lectures #7) – see disc 4
  76. Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, History of Political Philosophy (1987), p. 300.
  77. Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince, Chap 17.
  78. "Niccolò Machiavelli, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  79. Strauss, Leo (2014). Thoughts on Machiavelli. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226230979.
  80. Strauss, Leo. Leo Strauss "Thoughts On Machiavelli". p. 9.
  81. Carritt, E. F. (1949). Benedetto Croce My Philosophy.
  82. Cassirer, Ernst (10 September 1961). The Myth of the State. New Haven, Connecticut; London, England: Yale University Press. p. 136. ISBN 978-0-300-00036-8.
  83. "When Isms go to War | StratBlog". 29 October 2013. Archived from the original on 29 October 2013. Retrieved 29 October 2019.
  84. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy. University of Chicago Press. p. 131. ISBN 978-0226500331.
  85. Mansfield, Harvey C. (25 February 1998). Machiavelli's Virtue. University of Chicago Press. p. 233. ISBN 978-0-226-50372-1.
  86. Najemy 1993, p. missing.
  87. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2009). Discourses on Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11–15. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226500331.
  88. Machiavelli, Niccolò (2010). The Prince: Second Edition. University of Chicago Press. pp. 69–71. ISBN 978-0226500508.
  89. Especially in the Discourses III.30, but also The Prince Chap.VI
  90. Strauss (1987, p. 314)
  91. See for example Strauss (1958, p. 206).
  92. Parsons, W. B. (2016). Machiavelli's gospel: The critique of Christianity in the prince. Boydell & Brewer.
  93. Vavouras, Elias; Theodosiadis, Michail (October 2024). "The Concept of Religion in Machiavelli: Political Methodology, Propaganda and Ideological Enlightenment". Religions. 15 (10): 1203. doi:10.3390/rel15101203. ISSN 2077-1444.
  94. Strauss (1958, p. 231)
  95. Mansfield (1993)
  96. Bireley, Robert (1990), The Counter Reformation Prince, p. 14.
  97. Bireley (1990:15)
  98. Haitsma Mulier (1999:248)
  99. While Bireley focuses on writers in the Catholic countries, Haitsma Mulier (1999) makes the same observation, writing with more of a focus upon the Protestant Netherlands.
  100. The first English edition was A Discourse upon the meanes of wel governing and maintaining in good peace, a Kingdome, or other principalitie, translated by Simon Patericke.
  101. Bireley (1990:17)
  102. Bireley (1990:18)
  103. Bireley (1990:223–230)
  104. Benner, Erica (28 November 2013). Machiavelli's Prince: A New Reading. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780191003929.
  105. "Anti-Machiavel | treatise by Frederick the Great". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 April 2019.
  106. Kennington (2004), Rahe (2006)
  107. Bireley (1990:17): "Jean Bodin's first comments, found in his Method for the Easy Comprehension of History, published in 1566, were positive."
  108. Bacon wrote: "We are much beholden to Machiavelli and other writers of that class who openly and unfeignedly declare or describe what men do, and not what they ought to do." "II.21.9", Of the Advancement of Learning. See Kennington (2004) Chapter 4.
  109. Rahe (2006) chapter 6.
  110. Worden (1999)
  111. "Spinoza's Political Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2013. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
  112. Danford "Getting Our Bearings: Machiavelli and Hume" in Rahe (2006).
  113. Schaefer (1990)
  114. Kennington (2004), chapter 11.
  115. Barnes Smith "The Philosophy of Liberty: Locke's Machiavellian Teaching" in Rahe (2006).
  116. Carrese "The Machiavellian Spirit of Montesquieu's Liberal Republic" in Rahe (2006)
  117. Shklar (1999)
  118. Worden (1999)
  119. John P. McCormick, Machiavellian democracy (Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 23.
  120. Rahe (2006)
  121. Walling "Was Alexander Hamilton a Machiavellian Statesman?" in Rahe (2006).
  122. Harper (2004)
  123. Spalding "The American Prince? George Washington's Anti-Machiavellian moment" in Rahe (2006)
  124. ^ Thompson (1995)
  125. Marcia Landy, "Culture and Politics in the work of Antonio Gramsci," 167–188, in Antonio Gramsci: Intellectuals, Culture, and the Party, ed. James Martin (New York: Routledge, 2002).
  126. Service, Robert. Stalin: A Biography, p.10.
  127. Review by Jann Racquoi, Heights/Inwood Press of North Manhattan, 14 March 1979.
  128. Bireley (1990, p. 241)
  129. Fischer (2000, p. 94)
  130. "Definition of MACHIAVELLIAN". merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 17 October 2018.
  131. Rahe, Paul A. (2005). Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy. Cambridge University Press. p. xxxvi. ISBN 978-1139448338.
  132. Meinecke, Friedrich (1957). Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d'État and Its Place in Modern History. Yale University Press. p. 36.
  133. Kahn, V. (1994). Machiavellian rhetoric: From the counter-reformation to Milton. Princeton University Press.
  134. "Machiavel". Oxford Reference. Retrieved 31 December 2021.
  135. "MACHIAVEL English Definition and Meaning | Lexico.com". Lexico Dictionaries. Archived from the original on 16 May 2021. Retrieved 31 December 2021.
  136. "Jew of Malta, The by MARLOWE, Christopher". Player FM. 2016. Retrieved 12 May 2018.
  137. "Henry VI, Part 3 - Entire Play | Folger Shakespeare Library".
  138. "First-time Machiavelli translation debuts at Yale". yaledailynews.com. 18 April 2012.
  139. Godman (1998, p. 240). Also see Black (1999, pp. 97–98)

Sources

  • Machiavelli, Niccolò (1981). The Prince and Selected Discourses. Translated by Daniel Donno. New York: Bantam Classic Books. ISBN 0553212273.
  • Haitsma Mulier, Eco (1999). "A controversial republican". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.
  • Harper, John Lamberton (2004). American Machiavelli: Alexander Hamilton and the Origins of US Foreign Policy. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521834858.
  • Shklar, J. (1999). "Montesquieu and the new republicanism". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.
  • Worden, Blair (1999). "Milton's republicanism and the tyranny of heaven". In Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press.

Further reading

Biographies

  • Baron, Hans (April 1961). "Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of 'the Prince'". The English Historical Review. 76 (299): 217–253. doi:10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217. JSTOR 557541.
  • Black, Robert. Machiavelli: From Radical to Reactionary. London: Reaktion Books (2022)
  • Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in Cambridge Modern History (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp. 190–218 online Google edition
  • Capponi, Niccolò. An Unlikely Prince: The Life and Times of Machiavelli (Da Capo Press; 2010) 334 pages
  • Celenza, Christopher S. Machiavelli: A Portrait (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2015) 240 pages. ISBN 978-0674416123
  • Godman, Peter (1998), From Poliziano to Machiavelli: Florentine Humanism in the High Renaissance, Princeton University Press
  • de Grazia, Sebastian (1989), Machiavelli in Hell, Knopf Doubleday Publishing, ISBN 978-0679743422, an intellectual biography that won the Pulitzer Prize; excerpt and text search Archived 9 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
  • Hale, J. R. Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy (1961) online edition Archived 19 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine
  • Hulliung, Mark. Citizen Machiavelli (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 1983)
  • Lee, Alexander. Machiavelli: His Life and Times (London: Picador, 2020)
  • Oppenheimer, Paul. Machiavelli: A Life Beyond Ideology (London; New York: Continuum, 2011) ISBN 978-1847252210
  • Ridolfi, Roberto. The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli (1963)
  • Schevill, Ferdinand. Six Historians (1956), pp. 61–91
  • Skinner, Quentin. Machiavelli, in Past Masters series. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1981. pp. vii, 102. ISBN 0192875167 pbk.
  • Skinner, Quentin. Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction (2d ed., 2019) ISBN 978-0198837572 pbk.
  • Unger, Miles J. Machiavelli: A Biography (Simon & Schuster, 2011)
  • Villari, Pasquale. The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli (2 vols. 1892) (Vol 1; Vol 2)
  • Viroli, Maurizio (2000), Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli, Farrar, Straus & Giroux excerpt and text search Archived 24 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
  • Viroli, Maurizio. Machiavelli (1998) online edition Archived 20 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine
  • Vivanti, Corrado. Niccolò Machiavelli: An Intellectual Biography (Princeton University Press; 2013) 261 pages

Political thought

  • Baron, Hans. The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. excerpts and text search; ACLS E-books; also vol 2 in ACLS E-books
  • Baron, Hans. In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism (2 vols. 1988).
  • Baron, Hans (1961), "Machiavelli: the Republican Citizen and Author of The Prince", English Historical Review, lxxvi (76): 217–253, doi:10.1093/ehr/LXXVI.CCXCIX.217, JSTOR 557541. in JSTOR Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
  • Berlin, Isaiah. "The Originality of Machiavelli", in Berlin, Isaiah (1980). Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas. New York: The Viking Press.
  • Bireley, Robert (1990), The Counter Reformation Prince
  • Black, Robert (1999), "Machiavelli, servant of the Florentine republic", in Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.), Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cambridge University Press
  • Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio, eds. (1993). Machiavelli and Republicanism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521435895.
  • Chabod, Federico (1958). Machiavelli & the Renaissance online edition Archived 19 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine; online from ACLS E-Books Archived 20 August 2008 at the Wayback Machine
  • Connell, William J. (2001), "Machiavelli on Growth as an End," in Anthony Grafton and J.H.M. Salmon, eds., Historians and Ideologues: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Kelley, Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 259–277.
  • Donskis, Leonidas, ed. (2011). Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi, ISBN 978-9042032774, E-ISBN 978-9042032781
  • Everdell, William R. "Niccolò Machiavelli: The Florentine Commune" in The End of Kings: A History of Republics and Republicans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
  • Fischer, Markus (Autumn 1997). "Machiavelli's Political Psychology". The Review of Politics. 59 (4): 789–829. doi:10.1017/S0034670500028333. JSTOR 1408308. S2CID 146570913.
  • Fischer, Markus (2000), Well-ordered License: On the Unity of Machiavelli's Thought, Lexington Book
  • Frederick II of Prussia (1980) . Anti-Machiavel: The Refutation of Machiavelli s Prince. Translated by Sonnino, Paul. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press. ISBN 9780821405598.
  • Guarini, Elena (1999), "Machiavelli and the crisis of the Italian republics", in Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; Viroli, Maurizio (eds.), Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cambridge University Press
  • Gilbert, Allan (1938), Machiavelli's Prince and Its Forerunners, Duke University Press
  • Gilbert, Felix. Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy (2nd ed. 1984) online from ACLS-E-books Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine
  • Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. The Makers of Modern Strategy (1944)
  • Jensen, De Lamar, ed. Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist? (1960) essays by scholars online edition Archived 25 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine
  • Jurdjevic, Mark (2014). A Great and Wretched City: Promise and Failure in Machiavelli's Florentine Political Thought. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674725461.
  • Kennington, Richard (2004), On Modern Origins, Lexington Books
  • Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," The American Political Science Review, Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun. 1981), pp. 293–305 in JSTOR Archived 8 August 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  • Mansfield, Harvey (1993), Taming the Prince, The Johns Hopkins University Press
  • Mansfield, Harvey (1995), "Machiavelli and the Idea of Progress", in Melzer; Weinberger; Zinman (eds.), History and the Idea of Progress, Cornell University Press
  • Mansfield, Harvey C. Machiavelli's Virtue (1996), 371 pp.
  • Mansfield, Harvey C. Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy (2001) excerpt and text search Archived 11 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine
  • Roger Masters (1996), Machiavelli, Leonardo and the Science of Power, University of Notre Dame Press, ISBN 978-0268014339 See also NYT book review Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Roger Masters (1998), Fortune is a River: Leonardo Da Vinci and Niccolò Machiavelli's Magnificent Dream to Change the Course of Florentine History, Simon & Schuster, ISBN 978-0-452-28090-8 Also available in Chinese (ISBN 9789572026113), Japanese (ISBN 978-4022597588), German (ISBN 978-3471794029), Portuguese (ISBN 978-8571104969), and Korean (ISBN 978-8984070059). See also NYT book review Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Mattingly, Garrett (Autumn 1958), "Machiavelli's Prince: Political Science or Political Satire?", The American Scholar (27): 482–491.
  • Najemy, John (1993), Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli-Vettori Letters of 1513–1515, Princeton University Press
  • Najemy, John M. (1996), "Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism", American Historical Review, 101 (1): 119–129, doi:10.2307/2169227, JSTOR 2169227.
  • Parel, A. J. (Spring 1991). "The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity". The Review of Politics. 53 (2): 320–339. doi:10.1017/S0034670500014649. JSTOR 1407757. S2CID 170629105.
  • Parel, Anthony (1972), "Introduction: Machiavelli's Method and His Interpreters", The Political Calculus: Essays on Machiavelli's Philosophy, Toronto, pp. 3–28{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • Parsons, William B. (2016), Machiavelli's Gospel, University of Rochester Press, ISBN 978-1580464918
  • Pocock, J.G.A. (1975), The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition, Princeton new ed. 2003, a highly influential study of Discourses and its vast influence; excerpt and text search Archived 18 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine; also online 1975 edition Archived 7 October 2010 at the Wayback Machine
  • Pocock, J. G. A. "The Machiavellian Moment Revisited: a Study in History and Ideology.: Journal of Modern History 1981 53(1): 49–72. Fulltext: in Jstor Archived 11 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Rahe, Paul (1992), Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution online edition Archived 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine
  • Rahe, Paul A. (2006), Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0521851879 Excerpt, reviews and Text search shows Machiavelli's Discourses had a major impact on shaping conservative thought.
  • Ruggiero, Guido. Machiavelli in Love: Sex, Self and Society in Renaissance Italy (2007)
  • Schaefer, David (1990), The Political Philosophy of Montaigne, Cornell University Press.
  • Scott, John T.; Sullivan, Vickie B. (1994). "Patricide and the Plot of the Prince: Cesare Borgia and Machiavelli's Italy". The American Political Science Review. 88 (4): 887–900. doi:10.2307/2082714. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 2082714. S2CID 144798597.
  • Skinner, Quentin. The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, v. I, The Renaissance, (1978)
  • Soll, Jacob (2005), Publishing The Prince: History, Reading and the Birth of Political Criticism, University of Michigan Press
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Niccolò Machiavelli (2005)
  • Strauss, Leo (1987), "Niccolò Machiavelli", in Strauss, Leo; Cropsey, Joseph (eds.), History of Political Philosophy (3rd ed.), University of Chicago Press
  • Strauss, Leo (1958), Thoughts on Machiavelli, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0226777023
  • Sullivan, Vickie B., ed. (2000), The Comedy and Tragedy of Machiavelli: Essays on the Literary Works, Yale U. Press
  • Sullivan, Vickie B. (1996), Machiavelli's Three Romes: Religion, Human Liberty, and Politics Reformed, Northern Illinois University Press
  • von Vacano, Diego, "The Art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham MD: Lexington: 2007.
  • Thompson, C. Bradley (1995), "John Adams's Machiavellian Moment", The Review of Politics, 57 (3): 389–417, doi:10.1017/S0034670500019689, S2CID 154074090. Also in Rahe (2006).
  • Whelan, Frederick G. (2004), Hume and Machiavelli: Political Realism and Liberal Thought, Lexington{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • Wight, Martin (2005). Wight, Gabriele; Porter, Brian (eds.). Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199273676.
  • Zuckert, Catherine, (2017) "Machiavelli's Politics" Archived 18 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine

Italian studies

  • Barbuto, Marcelo (2005), "Questa oblivione delle cose. Reflexiones sobre la cosmología de Maquiavelo (1469–1527)," Revista Daimon, 34, Universidad de Murcia, pp. 34–52.
  • Barbuto, Marcelo (2008), "Discorsi, I, XII, 12–14. La Chiesa romana di fronte alla republica cristiana", Filosofia Politica, 1, Il Mulino, Bologna, pp. 99–116.
  • Celli, Carlo ( 2009), Il carnevale di Machiavelli, Firenze, L.S. Olschki.
  • Connell, William J. (2015), Machiavelli nel Rinascimento italiano, Milano, Franco Angeli.
  • Giuseppe Leone, "Silone e Machiavelli. Una scuola...che non crea prìncipi", pref. di Vittoriano Esposito, Centro Studi Ignazio Silone, Pescina, 2003.
  • Martelli, Mario (2004), "La Mandragola e il suo prologo", Interpres, XXIII, pp. 106–142.
  • Martelli, Mario (2003), "Per la definizione della nozione di principe civile", Interpres, XXII.
  • Martelli, Mario (2001), "I dettagli della filologia", Interpres XX, pp. 212–271.
  • Martelli, Mario (1999a), "Note su Machiavelli", Interpres XVIII, pp. 91–145.
  • Martelli, Mario (1999b), Saggio sul Principe, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
  • Martelli, Mario (1999c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola: valutazione politica e valutazione religiosa", Girolamo Savonarola. L´uomo e il frate". Atti del xxxv Convegno storico internazionale (Todi, II-14 ottobre 1998), CISAM, Spoleto, pp. 139–153.
  • Martelli, Mario (1998a), Machiavelli e gli storici antichi, osservazioni su alcuni luoghi dei discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio, Quaderni di Filologia e critica, 13, Salerno Editrice, Roma.
  • Martelli, Mario (1998b), "Machiavelli politico amante poeta", Interpres XVII, pp. 211–256.
  • Martelli, Mario (1998c), "Machiavelli e Savonarola", Savonarola. Democrazia, tirannide, profezia, a cura di G.C. Garfagnini, Florencia, Sismel-Edizioni del Galluzo, pp. 67–89.
  • Martelli, Mario and Bausi, Francesco (1997), "Politica, storia e letteratura: Machiavelli e Guicciardini", Storia della letteratura italiana, E. Malato (ed.), vol. IV. Il primo Cinquecento, Salerno Editrice, Roma, pp. 251–320.
  • Martelli, Mario (1985–1986), "Schede sulla cultura di Machiavelli", Interpres VI, pp. 283–330.
  • Martelli, Mario (1982) "La logica provvidenzialistica e il capitolo XXVI del Principe", Interpres IV, pp. 262–384.
  • Martelli, Mario (1974), "L´altro Niccolò di Bernardo Machiavelli", Rinascimento, XIV, pp. 39–100.
  • Sasso, Gennaro (1993), Machiavelli: storia del suo pensiero politico, II vol., Bologna, Il Mulino,
  • Sasso, Gennaro (1987–1997) Machiavelli e gli antichi e altri saggi, 4 vols., Milano, R. Ricciardi

Editions

Collections

  • Gilbert, Allan H. ed. Machiavelli: The Chief Works and Others, (3 vol. 1965), the standard scholarly edition
  • Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. The Portable Machiavelli (1979)
  • Penman, Bruce. The Prince and Other Political Writings, (1981)
  • Wootton, David, ed. (1994), Selected political writings of Niccolò Machiavelli, Indianapolis: Hackett Pubs. excerpt and text search Archived 16 March 2021 at the Wayback Machine

The Prince

The Discourses on Livy

  • Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio (2001), ed. by Francesco Bausi, Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Niccolò Machiavelli, II vol. Salerno Editrice, Roma.
  • The Discourses, online 1772 edition Archived 15 August 2012 at the Wayback Machine
  • The Discourses, tr. with introduction and notes by L. J. Walker (2 vol 1950).
  • Machiavelli, Niccolò (1531). The Discourses. Translated by Leslie J. Walker, S.J, revisions by Brian Richardson (2003). London: Penguin Books. ISBN 0-14-044428-9
  • The Discourses, edited with an introduction by Bernard Crick (1970).

The Art of War

Florentine Histories

Correspondence

  • Epistolario privado. Las cartas que nos desvelan el pensamiento y la personalidad de uno de los intelectuales más importantes del Renacimiento, Juan Manuel Forte (edición y traducción), Madrid, La Esfera de los Libros, 2007, 435 págs, ISBN 978-8497346610
  • The Private Correspondence of Niccolò Machiavelli, ed. by Orestes Ferrara; (1929) online edition Archived 23 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine
  • Machiavelli, Niccolò (1996), Machiavelli and his friends: Their personal correspondence, Northern Illinois University Press. Translated and edited by James B. Atkinson and David Sices.
  • Also see Najemy (1993).

Poetry and comedy

  • Machiavelli, Niccolò (1985), Comedies of Machiavelli, University Press of New England Bilingual edition of The Woman from Andros, The Mandrake, and Clizia, edited by David Sices and James B. Atkinson.
  • Hoeges, Dirk. Niccolò Machiavelli. Dichter-Poeta. Mit sämtlichen Gedichten, deutsch/italienisch. Con tutte le poesie, tedesco/italiano, Reihe: Dialoghi/Dialogues: Literatur und Kultur Italiens und Frankreichs, Band 10, Peter Lang Verlag, Frankfurt/M. u.a. 2006, ISBN 3631546696.

External links

Niccolò Machiavelli
Historical and
political works
Imaginative works
Concepts
Category:Works by Niccolò Machiavelli
Political philosophy
Terms
Government
Ideologies
Concepts
Philosophers
Antiquity
Middle Ages
Early modern
period
18th and 19th
centuries
20th and 21st
centuries
Works
Related
Categories: