Revision as of 12:36, 3 May 2012 editTkuvho (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers9,424 editsNo edit summary← Previous edit | Revision as of 04:30, 15 March 2013 edit undoAddbot (talk | contribs)Bots2,838,809 editsm Bot: Migrating 1 interwiki links, now provided by Wikidata on d:q4139289Next edit → | ||
Line 30: | Line 30: | ||
] | ] | ||
] | ] | ||
] |
Revision as of 04:30, 15 March 2013
Smooth infinitesimal analysis is a modern reformulation of the calculus in terms of infinitesimals. Based on the ideas of F. W. Lawvere and employing the methods of category theory, it views all functions as being continuous and incapable of being expressed in terms of discrete entities. As a theory, it is a subset of synthetic differential geometry.
The nilsquare or nilpotent infinitesimals are numbers ε where ε² = 0 is true, but ε = 0 need not be true at the same time.
This approach departs from the classical logic used in conventional mathematics by denying the law of the excluded middle, i.e., NOT (a ≠ b) does not imply a = b. In particular, for all infinitesimals ε, neither ε = 0 nor NOT (ε = 0) is provable. One can see that the law of excluded middle cannot hold from the following basic theorem:
- In smooth infinitesimal analysis, every function whose domain is R, the real numbers extended by infinitesimals, is continuous and infinitely differentiable.
Despite this fact, one could attempt to define a discontinuous function f(x) by specifying that f(x) = 1 for x = 0, and f(x) = 0 for x ≠ 0. If the law of the excluded middle held, then this would be a fully defined, discontinuous function. However, there are plenty of x, namely the infinitesimals, such that neither x = 0 nor x ≠ 0 holds, so the function is not defined on the extended real numbers.
In typical models of smooth infinitesimal analysis, the infinitesimals are not invertible, and therefore the theory does not contain infinite numbers. However, there are also models that include invertible infinitesimals.
Other mathematical systems exist which include infinitesimals, including non-standard analysis and the surreal numbers. Smooth infinitesimal analysis is like non-standard analysis in that (1) it is meant to serve as a foundation for analysis, and (2) the infinitesimal quantities do not have concrete sizes (as opposed to the surreals, in which a typical infinitesimal is 1/ω, where ω is the von Neumann ordinal). However, smooth infinitesimal analysis differs from non-standard analysis in its use of nonclassical logic, and in lacking the transfer principle. Some theorems of standard and non-standard analysis are false in smooth infinitesimal analysis, including the intermediate value theorem and the Banach–Tarski paradox. Statements in non-standard analysis can be translated into statements about limits, but the same is not always true in smooth infinitesimal analysis.
Intuitively, smooth infinitesimal analysis can be interpreted as describing a world in which lines are made out of infinitesimally small segments, not out of points. These segments can be thought of as being long enough to have a definite direction, but not long enough to be curved. The construction of discontinuous functions fails because a function is identified with a curve, and the curve cannot be constructed pointwise. We can imagine the intermediate value theorem's failure as resulting from the ability of an infinitesimal segment to straddle a line. Similarly, the Banach–Tarski paradox fails because a volume cannot be taken apart into points.
See also
Further reading
- John Lane Bell, Invitation to Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis (PDF file)
- Bell, John L., A Primer of Infinitesimal Analysis, Cambridge University Press, 1998. Second edition, 2008.
- Ieke Moerdijk and Reyes, G.E., Models for Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis, Springer-Verlag, 1991.
External links
- Michael O'Connor, An Introduction to Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis