Revision as of 02:38, 1 February 2013 editRichardMills65 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users25,484 editsNo edit summary← Previous edit | Revision as of 17:25, 3 February 2013 edit undoBenea (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers32,665 editsm Reverted edits by RichardMills65 (talk) to last version by Wolfgang42Next edit → | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
The '''superposition calculus''' is a calculus for ] in equational ]. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from ] with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) ]. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the ''unsatisfiability'' of a set of first-order ], i.e. it performs proofs by ]. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a ''fair'' derivation strategy, every unsatisfiable (logic)|unsatisfiable clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable. | The '''superposition calculus''' is a calculus for ] in equational ]. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from ] with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) ]. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the ''unsatisfiability'' of a set of first-order ], i.e. it performs proofs by ]. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a ''fair'' derivation strategy, every ] clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable. | ||
As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) ]s for ] are based on superposition (e.g. the ]), although only a few implement the pure calculus. | As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) ]s for ] are based on superposition (e.g. the ]), although only a few implement the pure calculus. | ||
Line 8: | Line 8: | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* Waldmeister theorem prover|Waldmeister | * ] | ||
* Ayane theorem prover|Ayane at | * ] at | ||
== References == | == References == |
Revision as of 17:25, 3 February 2013
The superposition calculus is a calculus for reasoning in equational first-order logic. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from first-order resolution with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) Knuth-Bendix completion. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the unsatisfiability of a set of first-order clauses, i.e. it performs proofs by refutation. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a fair derivation strategy, every unsatisfiable clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable.
As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) theorem provers for first-order logic are based on superposition (e.g. the E equational theorem prover), although only a few implement the pure calculus.
Implementations
References
- Rewrite-Based Equational Theorem Proving with Selection and Simplification, Leo Bachmair and Harald Ganzinger, Journal of Logic and Computation 3(4), 1994.
- Paramodulation-Based Theorem Proving, Robert Nieuwenhuis and Alberto Rubio, Handbook of Automated Reasoning I(7), Elsevier Science and MIT Press, 2001.
This mathematical logic-related article is a stub. You can help Misplaced Pages by expanding it. |