Misplaced Pages

Evolutionary psychology: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 21:48, 21 July 2015 editCAPTAIN RAJU (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Page movers, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers409,679 editsm Reverted 1 edit by 178.10.93.109 (talk) to last revision by Winner 42. (TW)← Previous edit Revision as of 21:48, 21 July 2015 edit undo178.10.90.71 (talk) Undid revision 672489524 by CAPTAIN RAJU (talk)Next edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
#REDIRECT ]
{{for|the academic journal|Evolutionary Psychology (journal)}}
{{Psychology sidebar}}
{{Evolutionary biology}}


'''Evolutionary psychology''' ('''EP''') is an approach in the ] and ]s that examines psychological structure from a ]. It seeks to identify which human psychological traits are evolved ]s – that is, the functional products of ] or ] ]. ] thinking about physiological mechanisms, such as the heart, lungs, and immune system, is common in ]. Some evolutionary ]s apply the same thinking to psychology, arguing that the ] similar to that of the body, with different modular adaptations serving different functions. Evolutionary psychologists argue that much of human behavior is the output of ]s that evolved to solve recurrent problems in human ancestral environments.<ref>Confer et al. 2010; Buss, 2005; Durrant & Ellis, 2003; Pinker, 2002; Tooby & Cosmides, 2005</ref>


Evolutionary psychologists suggest that EP is not simply a subdiscipline of psychology but that evolutionary theory can provide a foundational, ] framework that integrates the entire field of psychology, in the same way it has for biology.<ref name=Cosmides/><ref>Duntley and Buss 2008</ref><ref>Carmen, R.A., et al. (2013). Evolution Integrated Across All Islands of the Human Behavioral Archipelago: All Psychology as Evolutionary Psychology. EvoS Journal: The Journal of the Evolutionary Studies Consortium, 5, pp. 108–26. {{ISSN|1944-1932}} </ref>


Evolutionary psychologists hold that behaviors or traits that occur universally in all cultures are good candidates for evolutionary adaptations<ref name=Psychology>Schacter et al. 2007, pp. 26–27</ref> including the abilities to infer others' emotions, discern kin from non-kin, identify and prefer healthier mates, and cooperate with others. They report successful tests of theoretical predictions related to such topics as ], ], ] patterns, ], perception of ], ], and ].<ref name=social-behavior>"Despite this difficulty, there have been many careful and informative studies of human social behavior from an evolutionary perspective. Infanticide, intelligence, marriage patterns, promiscuity, perception of beauty, bride price, altruism, and the allocation of parental care have all been explored by testing predictions derived from the idea that conscious and unconscious behaviours have evolved to maximize inclusive fitness. The findings have been impressive." "social behaviour, animal." Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, 2011. Web. 23 Jan 2011. .</ref>


The theories and findings of EP have applications in many fields, including economics, environment, health, law, management, ], politics, and literature.<ref name=Oxford2007>The Oxford Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, Edited by Robin Dunbar and Louise Barret, Oxford University Press, 2007</ref><ref>The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, edited by David M. Buss, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2005</ref>


] involve questions of testability, cognitive and evolutionary assumptions (such as modular functioning of the brain, and large uncertainty about the ancestral environment), importance of non-genetic and non-adaptive explanations, as well as political and ethical issues due to interpretations of research results.<ref>{{cite book |last=Rose |first=Hilary |title=Alas, Poor Darwin : Arguments Against Evolutionary Psychology |year=2000 |publisher=Harmony; 1 Amer ed edition (10 October 2000) |isbn=0-609-60513-5 |url=http://www.amazon.com/Alas-Poor-Darwin-Evolutionary-Psychology/dp/0609605135}}</ref>


l
==Scope==
l
l
l
l
john has been here all along.
no why.


Indeed.
===Principles===
Evolutionary psychology is an approach that views ] as the product of a universal set of evolved psychological adaptations to recurring problems in the ancestral environment. Proponents of EP suggest that it seeks to integrate psychology into the other natural sciences, rooting it in the organizing theory of biology (]), and thus understanding ] as a branch of ]. Anthropologist ] and psychologist ] note:


Suitably
<blockquote>Evolutionary psychology is the long-forestalled scientific attempt to assemble out of the disjointed, fragmentary, and mutually contradictory human disciplines a single, logically integrated research framework for the psychological, social, and behavioral sciences—a framework
that not only incorporates the evolutionary sciences on a full and equal basis, but that systematically works out all of the revisions in existing belief and research practice that such a synthesis requires.<ref>Tooby & Cosmides 2005, p. 5</ref></blockquote>


Enough
Just as human ] and ] have worked to identify physical adaptations of the body that represent "human physiological nature," the purpose of evolutionary psychology is to identify evolved emotional and cognitive adaptations that represent "human psychological nature." According to ], EP is "not a single theory but a large set of hypotheses" and a term that "has also come to refer to a particular way of applying evolutionary theory to the mind, with an emphasis on adaptation, gene-level selection, and modularity." Evolutionary psychology adopts an understanding of the mind that is based on the ]. It describes mental processes as computational operations, so that, for example, a fear response is described as arising from a neurological computation that inputs the perceptional data, e.g. a visual image of a spider, and outputs the appropriate reaction, e.g. fear of possibly dangerous animals.


Bantering
While philosophers have generally considered the human mind to include broad faculties, such as reason and lust, evolutionary psychologists describe evolved psychological mechanisms as narrowly focused to deal with specific issues, such as catching cheaters or choosing mates. EP views the ] as comprising many functional mechanisms,{{Citation needed|date=June 2011}} called ''psychological adaptations'' or evolved cognitive mechanisms or '']'', designed by the process of natural selection. Examples include ], ], ], intelligence and sex-specific mating preferences, foraging mechanisms, alliance-tracking mechanisms, agent-detection mechanisms, and others. Some mechanisms, termed ''domain-specific'', deal with recurrent adaptive problems over the course of human evolutionary history.{{Citation needed|date=June 2011}} ''Domain-general'' mechanisms, on the other hand, are proposed to deal with evolutionary novelty.{{Citation needed|date=June 2011}}


Camel excrement.
EP has roots in ] and evolutionary biology but also draws on ], ], ], ], ], ], biology, and ]. EP is closely linked to ],<ref name=Psychology/> but there are key differences between them including the emphasis on ''domain-specific'' rather than ''domain-general'' mechanisms, the relevance of measures of current ], the importance of ], and psychology rather than behavior. Most of what is now labeled as sociobiological research is now confined to the field of behavioral ecology.{{Citation needed|date=February 2008}}

]'s ] can help to clarify the distinctions between several different, but complementary, types of explanations.<ref>Nesse, R.M. (2000). Tingergen's Four Questions Organized. .</ref> Evolutionary psychology focuses primarily on the "why?" questions, while traditional psychology focuses on the "how?" questions.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.1-24>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 pp. 1–24.</ref>

{| class="wikitable"
|-
| colspan="2" rowspan="2" |
! colspan="2" |''Sequential vs. Static Perspective''
|-
| '''Historical/Developmental'''<br/>''Explanation of current form in terms of a historical sequence''
| '''Current Form'''<br/>''Explanation of the current form of species''
|-
! rowspan="2" |''How vs. Why Questions''
| '''Proximate'''<br/>'''''How''''' an individual organism's structures function
| '''Ontogeny'''<br/>Developmental explanations for changes in '''''individuals''''', from DNA to their current form
| '''Mechanism'''<br/>Mechanistic explanations for how an organism's structures work
|-
| '''Evolutionary'''<br/>'''''Why''''' a species evolved the structures (adaptations) it has
| '''Phylogeny'''<br/>The history of the evolution of sequential changes in a '''''species''''' over many generations
| '''Adaptation'''<br/>A species trait that evolved to solve a reproductive or survival problem in the ancestral environment
|}

===Premises===
Evolutionary psychology is founded on several core premises.

# The brain is an information processing device, and it produces behavior in response to external and internal inputs.<ref name=Cosmides>{{cite web |last1=Cosmides |first1=L. |author1-link=Leda Cosmides |author2-link=John Tooby |last2=Tooby |first2=J. |date=13 January 1997 |url=http://www.psych.ucsb.edu/research/cep/primer.html |title=Evolutionary Psychology: A Primer |accessdate=2008-02-16 |publisher=Center for Evolutionary Psychology}}</ref><ref name=Buss-about></ref>
# The brain's adaptive mechanisms were shaped by natural and sexual selection.<ref name=Cosmides/><ref name=Buss-about/>
# Different neural mechanisms are specialized for solving problems in humanity's evolutionary past.<ref name=Cosmides/><ref name=Buss-about/>
# The brain has evolved specialized neural mechanisms that were designed for solving problems that recurred over deep evolutionary time,<ref name=Buss-about/> giving modern humans stone-age minds.<ref name=Cosmides/>
# Most contents and processes of the brain are unconscious; and most mental problems that seem easy to solve are actually extremely difficult problems that are solved unconsciously by complicated neural mechanisms.<ref name=Cosmides/>
# Human psychology consists of many specialized mechanisms, each sensitive to different classes of information or inputs. These mechanisms combine to produce manifest behavior.<ref name=Buss-about/>

==History==
] (left) and ] (right) who were, with ], acknowledged for work on animal behavior<ref name=nobel-1973>
{{cite web
|url=http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/medicine/laureates/1973/index.html
|title=The Nobel Prize in Physiology or Medicine 1973
|accessdate=2007-07-28
|publisher=Nobel Foundation
}}</ref>]]

{{Main|History of evolutionary psychology}}
Evolutionary psychology has its historical roots in ]'s theory of natural selection.<ref name=Psychology /> In ''The Origin of Species'', Darwin predicted that psychology would develop an evolutionary basis:
{{quote|In the distant future I see open fields for far more important researches. Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation.|{{cite wikisource |first=Charles |last=Darwin |title=The Origin of Species |year=1859 |page=488 |wslink=Page%3AOrigin_of_Species_1859_facsimile.djvu/500}}}}
Two of his later books were devoted to the study of animal emotions and psychology; '']'' in 1871 and '']'' in 1872. Darwin's work inspired ]'s functionalist approach to psychology.<ref name=Psychology/> Darwin's theories of evolution, adaptation, and natural selection have provided insight into why brains function the way they do.<ref name=Schacter>{{cite book |last=Schacter |title=Psychology 2nd Ed. |publisher=Worth Publishers |isbn=978-1-4292-3719-2}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Schacter |first=Daniel L. |title=Psychology |year=2011 |publisher=Worth Publishers |location=New York, NY |page=26 |edition=2 |first2=Daniel T. |last2=Gilbert |first3=Daniel M. |last3=Wegner}}</ref>

The content of EP has derived from, on one hand, the biological sciences (especially ]ary theory as it relates to ancient human environments, the study of ] and animal behavior) and, on the other, the human sciences, especially psychology.

Evolutionary biology as an ] emerged with the ] in the 1930s and 1940s.<ref>Sterelny, Kim. 2009. In Ruse, Michael & Travis, Joseph (eds) Wilson, Edward O. (Foreword) Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Ma. ISBN 978-0-674-03175-3. p. 314.</ref> In the 1930s the study of animal behavior (ethology) emerged with the work of Dutch biologist Nikolaas Tinbergen and Austrian biologists ] and ].

W.D. Hamilton's (1964) papers on ] and ]'s (1972)<ref name=Trivers1971>{{cite journal |jstor=2822435 |pages=35–57 |last1=Trivers |first1=R. L. |title=The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism |volume=46 |issue=1 |journal=] |year=1971 |doi=10.1086/406755}}</ref> theories on ] and parental investment helped to establish evolutionary thinking in psychology and the other social sciences. In 1975, ] combined evolutionary theory with studies of animal and social behavior, building on the works of Lorenz and Tinbergen, in his book '']''.

In the 1970s, two major branches developed from ethology. Firstly, the study of animal ''social'' behavior (including humans) generated sociobiology, defined by its pre-eminent proponent Edward O. Wilson in 1975 as "the systematic study of the biological basis of all social behavior"<ref>Wilson, Edward O. 1975. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Ma. ISBN 0-674-00089-7 p. 4.</ref> and in 1978 as "the extension of population biology and evolutionary theory to social organization."<ref>Wilson, Edward O. 1978. ''On Human Nature''. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Ma. p. x.</ref> Secondly, there was behavioral ecology which placed less emphasis on ''social'' behavior by focusing on the ecological and evolutionary basis of both animal and ] behavior.

In the 1970s and 1980s university departments began to include the term ''evolutionary biology'' in their titles. The modern era of evolutionary psychology was ushered in, in particular, by ]' 1979 book ''The Evolution of Human Sexuality'' and ] and ]'s 1992 book '']''.<ref name=Psychology/>

From psychology there are the primary streams of ], ] and cognitive psychology. Establishing some measure of the relative influence of genetics and environment on behavior has been at the core of ] and its variants, notably studies at the molecular level that examine the relationship between genes, neurotransmitters and behavior. ] (DIT), developed in the late 1970s and early 1980s, has a slightly different perspective by trying to explain how ] is a product of two different and interacting evolutionary processes: ] and ]. DIT is seen by some as a "middle-ground" between views that emphasize human universals versus those that emphasize cultural variation.<ref>Laland, Kevin N. and Gillian R. Brown. 2002. ''Sense & Nonsense: Evolutionary Perspectives on Human Behavior.'' Oxford University Press, Oxford. pp. 287–319.</ref>

==Theoretical foundations==
{{Main|Theoretical foundations of evolutionary psychology}}
The theories on which evolutionary psychology is based originated with Charles Darwin's work, including his speculations about the evolutionary origins of social instincts in humans. Modern evolutionary psychology, however, is possible only because of advances in evolutionary theory in the 20th century.

Evolutionary psychologists say that natural selection has provided humans with many psychological adaptations, in much the same way that it generated humans' anatomical and physiological adaptations.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.25-56>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 pp. 25–56.</ref> As with adaptations in general, psychological adaptations are said to be specialized for the environment in which an organism evolved, the environment of evolutionary adaptedness, or EEA.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.25-56/><ref name=Economics-2003>See also "Environment of evolutionary adaptation," a variation of the term used in Economics, e.g., in Rubin, Paul H., 2003, ''"Folk economics"'' Southern Economic Journal, 70:1, July 2003, 157–171.</ref> Sexual selection provides organisms with adaptations related to mating.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.25-56/> For ], which have a relatively high maximal potential reproduction rate, sexual selection leads to adaptations that help them compete for females.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.25-56/> For ], with a relatively low maximal potential reproduction rate, sexual selection leads to choosiness, which helps females select higher quality mates.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.25-56/> Charles Darwin described both natural selection and sexual selection, and he relied on group selection to explain the evolution of ] (self-sacrificing) behavior. But group selection was considered a weak explanation, because in any group the less altruistic individuals will be more likely to survive, and the group will become less self-sacrificing as a whole.

In 1964, ] proposed ] theory, emphasizing a "]" view of evolution. Hamilton noted that genes can increase the replication of copies of themselves into the next generation by influencing the organism's social traits in such a way that (statistically) results in helping the survival and reproduction of other copies of the same genes (most simply, identical copies in the organism's close relatives). According to "]", self-sacrificing behaviors (and the genes influencing them) can evolve if they typically help the organism's close relatives so much that it more than compensates for the individual animal's sacrifice. Inclusive fitness theory resolved the issue of how "altruism" can evolve. Other theories also help explain the evolution of altruistic behavior, including ], ] reciprocity, and generalized reciprocity. These theories not only help explain the development of altruistic behavior, but also account for hostility toward cheaters (individuals that take advantage of others' altruism).<ref name=moralanimal/>

Several mid-level evolutionary theories inform evolutionary psychology. The ] theory proposes that some species prosper by having many offspring, while others follow the strategy of having fewer offspring but investing much more in each one. Humans follow the second strategy. Parental investment theory explains how parents invest more or less in individual offspring based on how successful those offspring are likely to be, and thus how much they might improve the parents' inclusive fitness. According to the ], parents in good conditions tend to invest more in sons (who are best able to take advantage of good conditions), while parents in poor conditions tend to invest more in daughters (who are best able to have successful offspring even in poor conditions). According to ], animals evolve life histories to match their environments, determining details such as age at first reproduction and number of offspring. Dual inheritance theory posits that genes and human culture have interacted, with genes affecting the development of culture, and culture, in turn, affecting human evolution on a genetic level (see also the ]).

==Evolved psychological mechanisms==
{{Main|psychological adaptation|l1=Evolved psychological mechanisms}}
Evolutionary psychology is based on the hypothesis that, just like hearts, lungs, livers, kidneys, and immune systems, cognition has functional structure that has a genetic basis, and therefore has evolved by natural selection. Like other organs and tissues, this functional structure should be universally shared amongst a species, and should solve important problems of survival and ].

Evolutionary psychologists seek to understand psychological mechanisms by understanding the survival and reproductive functions they might have served over the course of evolutionary history.{{Citation needed|date=August 2011}} These might include abilities to infer others' emotions, discern kin from non-kin, identify and prefer healthier mates, cooperate with others and follow leaders. Consistent with the theory of natural selection, evolutionary psychology sees humans as often in conflict with others, including mates and relatives. For instance, a mother may wish to wean her offspring from breastfeeding earlier than does her infant, which frees up the mother to invest in additional offspring.<ref name=moralanimal/><ref>{{cite web |url=http://scilib-biology.narod.ru/MoralAnimal/index_en.html |title=The Moral Animal Whe We Are The Way We Are: The New Science of Evolutionary Psychology |accessdate=15 October 2013 |first=Robert |last=Wright}}</ref> Evolutionary psychology also recognizes the role of kin selection and reciprocity in evolving prosocial traits such as altruism.<ref name=moralanimal/> Like chimps and bonobos, humans have subtle and flexible social instincts, allowing them to form extended families, lifelong friendships, and political alliances.<ref name=moralanimal/> In studies testing theoretical predictions, evolutionary psychologists have made modest findings on topics such as infanticide, intelligence, marriage patterns, promiscuity, perception of beauty, bride price and parental investment.<ref name=social-behavior/>

===Products of evolution: adaptations, exaptations, byproducts, and random variation===
Not all traits of organisms are adaptations. As noted in the table below, traits may also be ]s, byproducts of adaptations (sometimes called "spandrels"), or random variation between individuals.<ref>Buss et al. 1998</ref>

Psychological adaptations are hypothesized to be innate or relatively easy to learn, and to manifest in cultures worldwide. For example, the ability of toddlers to learn a language with virtually no training is likely to be a psychological adaptation. On the other hand, ancestral humans did not read or write, thus today, learning to read and write require extensive training, and presumably represent byproducts of cognitive processing that use psychological adaptations designed for other functions.<ref>Pinker, Steven. (1994) The Language Instinct</ref> However, variations in manifest behavior can result from universal mechanisms interacting with different local environments. For example, Caucasians who move from a northern climate to the equator will have darker skin. The mechanisms regulating their pigmentation do not change; rather the input to the those mechanisms change, resulting in different output.

{| class="wikitable"
|-
! !! Adaptation !! Exaptation !! By-Product !! Random Variation
|-
| Definition || Organismic trait designed to solve an ancestral problem(s). Shows complexity, special "design", functionality || Adaptation that has been "re-purposed" to solve a different adaptive problem. || Byproduct of an adaptive mechanism with no current or ancestral function || Random variations in an adaptation or byproduct
|-
| Physiological Example || Bones / Umbilical cord|| Small bones of the inner ear || White color of bones / Belly button || Bumps on the skull, convex or concave belly button shape
|-
| Psychological Example || Toddlers’ ability to learn to talk with minimal instruction. || Voluntary Attention || Ability to learn to read and write. || Within-sex variations in voice pitch.
|}

One of the tasks of evolutionary psychology is to identify which psychological traits are likely to be adaptations, byproducts or random variation. ] suggested that an "adaptation is a special and onerous concept that should only be used where it is really necessary."<ref>George C Williams, ''Adaptation and Natural Selection''. p. 4.</ref> As noted by Williams and others, adaptations can be identified by their improbable complexity, species universality, and adaptive functionality.

===Obligate and facultative adaptations===
A question that may be asked about an adaptation is whether it is generally obligate (relatively robust in the face of typical environmental variation) or facultative (sensitive to typical environmental variation).<ref name=Buss-D-M-2011>Buss, D. M. (2011). Evolutionary psychology.</ref> The sweet taste of sugar and the pain of hitting one's knee against concrete are the result of fairly obligate psychological adaptations; typical environmental variability during development does not much affect their operation. By contrast, facultative adaptations are somewhat like "if-then" statements. For example, adult attachment style seems particularly sensitive to early childhood experiences. As adults, the propensity to develop close, trusting bonds with others is dependent on whether early childhood caregivers could be trusted to provide reliable assistance and attention. The adaptation for skin to tan is conditional to exposure to sunlight; this is an example of another facultative adaptation. When a psychological adaptation is facultative, evolutionary psychologists concern themselves with how developmental and environmental inputs influence the expression of the adaptation.

===Cultural universals===
{{main|Cultural universal}}
Evolutionary psychologists hold that behaviors or traits that occur universally in all cultures are good candidates for evolutionary adaptations.<ref name=Psychology/> Cultural universals include behaviors related to language, cognition, social roles, gender roles, and technology.<ref>] (1991) Human Universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.</ref> Evolved psychological adaptations (such as the ability to learn a language) interact with cultural inputs to produce specific behaviors (e.g., the specific language learned). Basic gender differences, such as greater eagerness for sex among men and greater coyness among women,<ref>Symons, D. (1979). The evolution of human sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chapter 6.</ref> are explained as sexually dimorphic psychological adaptations that reflect the different reproductive strategies of males and females.<ref name=moralanimal/><ref name=BS>Pinker 2002</ref> Evolutionary psychologists contrast their approach to what they term the "]," according to which the mind is a general-purpose cognition device shaped almost entirely by culture.<ref>Barkow et al. 1992</ref><ref name=instinct>"instinct." Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, 2011. Web. 18 Feb 2011. .</ref>

==Environment of evolutionary adaptedness==
{{Main|Human evolution}}
EP argues that to properly understand the functions of the brain, one must understand the properties of the environment in which the brain evolved. That environment is often referred to as the "environment of evolutionary adaptedness" (EEA).<ref name=Economics-2003/>

The idea of an ''environment of evolutionary adaptedness'' was first explored as a part of ] by ].<ref name=Bowlby1969>{{cite book |last=Bowlby |first=John |title=Attachment |publisher=Basic Books |location=New York |year=1969}}</ref> This is the environment to which a particular evolved mechanism is adapted. More specifically, the EEA is defined as the set of historically recurring selection pressures that formed a given adaptation, as well as those aspects of the environment that were necessary for the proper development and functioning of the adaptation.

Humans, comprising the genus '']'', appeared between 1.5 and 2.5 million years ago, a time that roughly coincides with the start of the ] 2.6 million years ago. Because the Pleistocene ended a mere 12,000 years ago, most human adaptations either newly evolved during the Pleistocene, or were maintained by ] during the Pleistocene. Evolutionary psychology therefore proposes that the majority of human psychological mechanisms are adapted to reproductive problems frequently encountered in Pleistocene environments.<ref name=Symons1992>{{cite book
|last=Symons
|first=Donald
|authorlink=Donald Symons
|chapter=On the use and misuse of Darwinism in the study of human behavior
|title=The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture
|publisher=Oxford University Press
|year=1992
|pages=137–59
|isbn=0-19-510107-3
}}</ref> In broad terms, these problems include those of growth, development, differentiation, maintenance, mating, parenting, and social relationships.

The EEA is significantly different from modern society.<ref name=EBO-social/> The ancestors of modern humans lived in smaller groups, had more cohesive cultures, and had more stable and rich contexts for identity and meaning.<ref name=EBO-social>"social behaviour, animal." Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, 2011. Web. 23 Jan 2011. .</ref> Researchers look to existing hunter-gatherer societies for clues as to how hunter-gatherers lived in the EEA.<ref name=moralanimal/> Unfortunately, the few surviving hunter-gatherer societies are different from each other, and they have been pushed out of the best land and into harsh environments, so it is not clear how closely they reflect ancestral culture.<ref name=moralanimal/>

Evolutionary psychologists sometimes look to chimpanzees, bonobos, and other great apes for insight into human ancestral behavior.<ref name=moralanimal>Wright 1995</ref> Christopher Ryan and Cacilda Jetha argue that evolutionary psychologists have overemphasized the similarity of humans and chimps, which are more violent, while underestimating the similarity of humans and bonobos, which are more peaceful.<ref>Ryan, Christopher and Cacilda Jethá. Sex at Dawn: The Prehistoric Origins of Modern Sexuality. Harper. 2010.</ref>

===Mismatches===
Since an organism's adaptations were suited to its ancestral environment, a new and different environment can create a mismatch. Because humans are mostly adapted to Pleistocene environments, psychological mechanisms sometimes exhibit "mismatches" to the modern environment. One example is the fact that although about 10,000 people are killed with guns in the US annually,<ref></ref> whereas spiders and snakes kill only a handful, people nonetheless learn to fear spiders and snakes about as easily as they do a pointed gun, and more easily than an unpointed gun, rabbits or flowers.<ref name=Ohman2001>{{cite journal
|last1=Ohman |first1=A.
|last2=Mineka |first2=S.
|year=2001
|title=Fears, phobias, and preparedness: Toward an evolved module of fear and fear learning
|journal=Psychological Review
|volume=108
|issue=3
|pages=483–522
|url=http://instruct.uwo.ca/psychology/371g/Ohman2001.pdf
|accessdate=2008-06-16
|doi=10.1037/0033-295X.108.3.483
|format=PDF
|pmid=11488376
}}</ref> A potential explanation is that spiders and snakes were a threat to human ancestors throughout the Pleistocene, whereas guns (and rabbits and flowers) were not. There is thus a mismatch between humans' evolved fear-learning psychology and the modern environment.<ref name=Pinker1999>{{Cite journal
|last=Pinker |first=Steve
|title=How the Mind Works
|pages=386–389
|year=1999
|publisher=WW Norton & Co. New York
}}</ref><ref name=Hagen2006>{{cite journal
|doi=10.1016/j.tpb.2005.09.005
|pmid=16458945
|year=2006
|last1=Hagen
|first1=EH
|last2=Hammerstein
|first2=P
|title=Game theory and human evolution: a critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games
|volume=69
|issue=3
|pages=339–48
|journal=Theoretical population biology}}</ref>

This mismatch also shows up in the phenomena of the ], a stimulus that elicits a response more strongly than the stimulus for which the response evolved. The term was coined by ] to refer to non-human animal behavior, but psychologist ] said that supernormal stimulation governs the behavior of humans as powerfully as that of other animals. She explained junk food as an exaggerated stimulus to cravings for salt, sugar, and fats,<ref>Barrett, Deirdre. Waistland: The R/Evolutionary Science Behind Our Weight and Fitness Crisis (2007). New York: W.W. Norton. pp. 31–51.</ref> and she says that television is an exaggeration of social cues of laughter, smiling faces and attention-grabbing action.<ref>Barrett, Deirdre. Supernormal Stimuli: How Primal Urges Overran Their Evolutionary Purpose. New York: W.W. Norton, 2010</ref> Magazine centerfolds and double cheeseburgers pull instincts intended for an EEA where breast development was a sign of health, youth and fertility in a prospective mate, and fat was a rare and vital nutrient.<ref name=abcde>{{Cite journal
|title=Game theory and human evolution: A critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games
|year=2006
|journal=Theoretical Population Biology
|volume=69
|pages=339–48
|last1=Hagen |first1=E. |last2=Hammerstein |first2=P.
|doi=10.1016/j.tpb.2005.09.005
|pmid=16458945
|issue=3
}}</ref>
Psychologist ] recently argued that modern organizational leadership is a mismatch.<ref>Van Vugt, Mark & Ahuja, Anjana. Naturally Selected: The Evolutionary Science of Leadership (2011). New York: Harper Business.</ref> His argument is that humans are not adapted to work in large, anonymous bureaucratic structures with formal hierarchies. The human mind still responds to personalized, charismatic leadership primarily in the context of informal, egalitarian settings. Hence the dissatisfaction and alienation that many employees experience. Salaries, bonuses and other privileges exploit instincts for relative status, which attract particularly males to senior executive positions.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Van Vugt |first1=Mark |last2=Ronay |first2=Richard |year=2014 |title=The Evolutionary Psychology of Leadership |url=|journal=Organizational Psychology Review |volume=4 |issue=|pages=74–95 |doi=10.1177/2041386613493635}}</ref>

==Research methods==
Evolutionary theory is ] in that it may generate hypotheses that might not be developed from other theoretical approaches. One of the major goals of adaptationist research is to identify which organismic traits are likely to be adaptations, and which are byproducts or random variations. As noted earlier, adaptations are expected to show evidence of complexity, functionality, and species universality, while byproducts or random variation will not. In addition, adaptations are expected to manifest as proximate mechanisms that interact with the environment in either a generally obligate or facultative fashion (see above). Evolutionary psychologists are also interested in identifying these proximate mechanisms (sometimes termed "mental mechanisms" or "psychological adaptations") and what type of information they take as input, how they process that information, and their outputs.<ref name=Buss-D-M-2011/> ], or "evo-devo," focuses on how adaptations may be activated at certain developmental times (e.g., losing baby teeth, adolescence, etc.) or how events during the development of an individual may alter life history trajectories.

Evolutionary psychologists use several strategies to develop and test hypotheses about whether a psychological trait is likely to be an evolved adaptation. Buss (2011)<ref>Buss, D.M. (2011). Evolutionary psychology. Chapter 2. Boston: Pearson/A and B.</ref> notes that these methods include:

:''Cross-cultural Consistency.'' Characteristics that have been demonstrated to be cross cultural ] such as smiling, crying, facial expressions are presumed to be evolved psychological adaptations. Several evolutionary psychologists have collected massive datasets from cultures around the world to assess cross-cultural universality.

:''Function to Form (or "problem to solution").'' The fact that males, but not females, risk potential misidentification of genetic offspring (referred to as "paternity insecurity") led evolutionary psychologists to hypothesize that, compared to females, male jealousy would be more focused on sexual, rather than emotional, infidelity.

:''Form to Function (reverse-engineering – or "solution to problem").'' ], and associated aversions to certain types of food, during pregnancy seemed to have the characteristics of an evolved adaptation (complexity and universality). ] hypothesized that the function was to avoid the ingestion of toxins during early pregnancy that could damage fetus (but which are otherwise likely to be harmless to healthy non-pregnant women).

:''Corresponding Neurological Modules.'' Evolutionary psychology and cognitive neuropsychology are mutually compatible – evolutionary psychology helps to identify psychological adaptations and their ultimate, evolutionary functions, while neuropsychology helps to identify the proximate manifestations of these adaptations.

Evolutionary psychologists also use various sources of data for testing, including experiments, ]s, data from hunter-gatherer societies, observational studies, neuroscience data, self-reports and surveys, ]s, and human products.<ref>{{cite book
|last=Buss
|first=David
|authorlink=David Buss
|title=Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind
|publisher=Pearson Education, Inc
|year=2004
|location=Boston
|isbn=978-0-205-48338-9
}}</ref>
Recently, additional methods and tools have been introduced based on fictional scenarios,<ref name=Eldakar2006>{{cite journal
|first=Omar Tonsi |last=Eldakar
|first2=David Sloan |last2=Wilson |first3=Rick |last3=O'Gorman.
|year=2006
|title=Emotions and actions associated with altruistic helping and punishment
|journal=Evolutionary Psychology
|volume=4
|pages=274–86
|url=http://www.epjournal.net/filestore/ep04274286.pdf
|accessdate=2010-08-15
|format=PDF
}}</ref> mathematical models,<ref name=Eldakar2008>{{cite journal
|doi=10.1073/pnas.0712173105
|first=Omar Tonsi |last=Eldakar
|first2=David Sloan |last2=Wilson
|year=2008
|title=Selfishness as second-order altruism
|journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA
|volume=105
|issue=19
|pages=6982–6986
|url=http://www.pnas.org/content/105/19/6982.full.pdf+html
|accessdate=2010-08-15
|format=PDF
|pmid=18448681
|pmc=2383986
}}</ref> and ].<ref name=Lima2009>{{cite journal
|first=Francisco W.S. |last=Lima
|first2=Tarik |last2=Hadzibeganovic |first3=Dietrich |last3=Stauffer.
|year=2009
|title=Evolution of ethnocentrism on undirected and directed Barabási-Albert networks
|journal=Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications
|volume=388
|pages=4999–5004
|doi=10.1016/j.physa.2009.08.029
|issue=24
}}</ref>

==Major areas of research==
Foundational areas of research in evolutionary psychology can be divided into broad categories of adaptive problems that arise from the theory of evolution itself: survival, mating, parenting, family and kinship, interactions with non-kin, and cultural evolution.

===Survival and individual level psychological adaptations===
Problems of survival are thus clear targets for the evolution of physical and psychological adaptations.{{Clarify|date=July 2011}} Major problems the ancestors of present day humans faced included food selection and acquisition; territory selection and physical shelter; and avoiding predators and other environmental threats.<ref name=Buss-D-M-2011>Buss, D.M. (2011). Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind</ref>

====Consciousness ====
{{See also|Consciousness|Animal consciousness}}

Consciousness meets ]' criteria of species universality, complexity,<ref>* {{cite journal |jstor=188711 |pages=648–70 |last1=Nichols |first1=S. |last2=Grantham |first2=T. |title=Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness |volume=67 |issue=4 |journal=Philosophy of Science |year=2000 |doi=10.1086/392859}}</ref> and functionality, and it is a ] that apparently increases fitness.<ref>Freeman and Herron. ''Evolutionary Analysis.'' 2007. Pearson Education, NJ.</ref>

In his paper "Evolution of consciousness," John Eccles argues that special anatomical and physical adaptations of the mammalian ] gave rise to consciousness.<ref>{{cite journal |jstor=2360081 |pages=7320–4 |last1=Eccles |first1=J. C. |title=Evolution of consciousness |volume=89 |issue=16 |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |year=1992 |pmid=1502142 |pmc=49701 |doi=10.1073/pnas.89.16.7320}}</ref> In contrast, others have argued that the recursive circuitry underwriting consciousness is much more primitive, having evolved initially in pre-mammalian species because it improves the capacity for interaction with both social ''and'' natural environments by providing an energy-saving "neutral" gear in an otherwise energy-expensive motor output machine.<ref>Peters, Frederic </ref> Once in place, this recursive circuitry may well have provided a basis for the subsequent development of many of the functions that consciousness facilitates in higher organisms, as outlined by Bernard J. Baars.<ref>Baars, Bernard J. ''A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness.'' 1993. Cambridge University Press.</ref> Richard Dawkins suggested that humans evolved consciousness in order to make themselves the subjects of thought.<ref name=Gaulin-5/> Daniel Povinelli suggests that large, tree-climbing apes evolved consciousness to take into account one's own mass when moving safely among tree branches.<ref name=Gaulin-5/> Consistent with this hypothesis, Gordon Gallup found that chimps and orangutans, but not little monkeys or terrestrial gorillas, demonstrated self-awareness in mirror tests.<ref name=Gaulin-5/>

The concept of consciousness can refer to voluntary action, awareness, or wakefulness. However, even voluntary behavior involves unconscious mechanisms. Many cognitive processes take place in the cognitive unconscious, unavailable to conscious awareness. Some behaviors are conscious when learned but then become unconscious, seemingly automatic. Learning, especially implicitly learning a skill, can take place outside of consciousness. For example, plenty of people know how to turn right when they ride a bike, but very few can accurately explain how they actually do so. Evolutionary psychology approaches self-deception as an adaptation that can improve one's results in social exchanges.<ref name=Gaulin-5/>

Sleep may have evolved to conserve energy when activity would be less fruitful or more dangerous, such as at night, especially in winter.<ref name=Gaulin-5>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 p. 101-121.</ref>

====Sensation and perception====
Many experts, such as ], write that the purpose of perception is knowledge, but evolutionary psychologists hold that its primary purpose is to guide action.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> For example, they say, ] seems to have evolved not to help us know the distances to other objects but rather to help us move around in space.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Evolutionary psychologists say that animals from fiddler crabs to humans use eyesight for collision avoidance, suggesting that vision is basically for directing action, not providing knowledge.<ref name=Gaulin-4>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 pp. 81–101.</ref>

Building and maintaining sense organs is metabolically expensive, so these organs evolve only when they improve an organism's fitness.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> More than half the brain is devoted to processing sensory information, and the brain itself consumes roughly one-fourth of one's metabolic resources, so the senses must provide exceptional benefits to fitness.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Perception accurately mirrors the world; animals get useful, accurate information through their senses.<ref name=Gaulin-4/>

Scientists who study perception and sensation have long understood the human senses as adaptations.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Depth perception consists of processing over half a dozen visual cues, each of which is based on a regularity of the physical world.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Vision evolved to respond to the narrow range of electromagnetic energy that is plentiful and that does not pass through objects.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Sound waves go around corners and interact with obstacles, creating a complex pattern that includes useful information about the sources of and distances to objects.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Larger animals naturally make lower-pitched sounds as a consequence of their size.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> The range over which an animal hears, on the other hand, is determined by adaptation. Homing pigeons, for example, can hear very low-pitched sound (infrasound) that carries great distances, even though most smaller animals detect higher-pitched sounds.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Taste and smell respond to chemicals in the environment that are thought to have been significant for fitness in the EEA.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> For example, salt and sugar were apparently both valuable to the human or pre-human inhabitants of the EEA, so present day humans have an intrinsic hunger for salty and sweet tastes.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> The sense of touch is actually many senses, including pressure, heat, cold, tickle, and pain.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Pain, while unpleasant, is adaptive.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> An important adaptation for senses is range shifting, by which the organism becomes temporarily more or less sensitive to sensation.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> For example, one's eyes automatically adjust to dim or bright ambient light.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> Sensory abilities of different organisms often coevolve, as is the case with the hearing of echolocating bats and that of the moths that have evolved to respond to the sounds that the bats make.<ref name=Gaulin-4/>

Evolutionary psychologists contend that perception demonstrates the principle of modularity, with specialized mechanisms handling particular perception tasks.<ref name=Gaulin-4/> For example, people with damage to a particular part of the brain suffer from the specific defect of not being able to recognize faces (prosopagnosia).<ref name=Gaulin-4/> EP suggests that this indicates a so-called face-reading module.<ref name=Gaulin-4/>

====Learning and facultative adaptations====
In evolutionary psychology, learning is said to be accomplished through evolved capacities, specifically facultative adaptations.<ref name=LearningG8>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 Chapter 8.</ref> Facultative adaptations express themselves differently depending on input from the environment.<ref name=LearningG8/> Sometimes the input comes during development and helps shape that development.<ref name=LearningG8/> For example, migrating birds learn to orient themselves by the stars during a critical period in their maturation.<ref name=LearningG8/> Evolutionary psychologists believe that humans also learn language along an evolved program, also with critical periods.<ref name=LearningG8/> The input can also come during daily tasks, helping the organism cope with changing environmental conditions.<ref name=LearningG8/> For example, animals evolved Pavlovian conditioning in order to solve problems about causal relationships.<ref name=LearningG8/> Animals accomplish learning tasks most easily when those tasks resemble problems that they faced in their evolutionary past, such as a rat learning where to find food or water.<ref name=LearningG8/> Learning capacities sometimes demonstrate differences between the sexes.<ref name=LearningG8/> In many animal species, for example, males can solve spatial problem faster and more accurately than females, due to the effects of male hormones during development.<ref name=LearningG8/> The same might be true of humans.<ref name=LearningG8/>

====Emotion and motivation====
{{Main|Evolution of emotion}}
Motivations direct and energize behavior, while emotions provide the affective component to motivation, positive or negative.<ref name=Gaulin-6>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 pp. 121–42.</ref> In the early 1970s, ] and colleagues began a line of research which suggests that many emotions are universal.<ref name=Gaulin-6/> He found evidence that humans share at least five basic emotions: fear, sadness, happiness, anger, and disgust.<ref name=Gaulin-6/> Social emotions evidently evolved to motivate social behaviors that were adaptive in the EEA.<ref name=Gaulin-6/> For example, spite seems to work against the individual but it can establish an individual's reputation as someone to be feared.<ref name=Gaulin-6/> Shame and pride can motivate behaviors that help one maintain one's standing in a community, and self-esteem is one's estimate of one's status.<ref name=moralanimal/><ref name=Gaulin-6/>
Motivation has a neurobiologial basis in the ] of the brain. Recently, it has been suggested that reward systems may evolve in such a way that there may be an ] or unavoidable ] in the motivational system for activities of short versus long duration.<ref>Belke, T. W., and ] 2007. A brief ] to run does not function as a ] for ] ] for high daily ] rates. ] 88:199-213.</ref>

====Cognition====
Cognition refers to internal representations of the world and internal information processing. From an EP perspective, cognition is not "general purpose," but uses heuristics, or strategies, that generally increase the likelihood of solving problems that the ancestors of present day humans routinely faced. For example, present day humans are far more likely to solve logic problems that involve detecting cheating (a common problem given humans' social nature) than the same logic problem put in purely abstract terms.<ref name=Gaulin-7>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 Chapter 7.</ref> Since the ancestors of present day humans did not encounter truly random events, present day humans may be cognitively predisposed to incorrectly identify patterns in random sequences. "Gamblers' Fallacy" is one example of this. Gamblers may falsely believe that they have hit a "lucky streak" even when each outcome is actually random and independent of previous trials. Most people believe that if a fair coin has been flipped 9 times and Heads appears each time, that on the tenth flip, there is a greater than 50% chance of getting Tails.<ref name=Gaulin-6/> Humans find it far easier to make diagnoses or predictions using frequency data than when the same information is presented as probabilities or percentages, presumably because the ancestors of present day humans lived in relatively small tribes (usually with fewer than 150 people) where frequency information was more readily available.<ref name=Gaulin-6/>

====Personality ====
Evolutionary psychology is primarily interested in finding commonalities between people, or basic human psychological nature. From an evolutionary perspective, the fact that people have fundamental differences in personality traits initially presents something of a puzzle.<ref name=Gaulin-9>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 Chapter 9.</ref> (Note: The field of behavioral genetics is concerned with statistically partitioning differences between people into genetic and environmental sources of variance. However, understanding the concept of ] can be tricky—heritability refers only to the differences between people, never the degree to which the traits of an individual are due to environmental or genetic factors, since traits are always a complex interweaving of both.)

Personality traits are conceptualized by evolutionary psychologists as due to normal variation around an optimum, due to frequency-dependent selection (behavioral ]s), or as facultative adaptations. Like variability in height, some personality traits may simply reflect inter-individual variability around a general optimum.<ref name=Gaulin-9/> Or, personality traits may represent different genetically predisposed "behavioral morphs" – alternate behavioral strategies that depend on the frequency of competing behavioral strategies in the population. For example, if most of the population is generally trusting and gullible, the behavioral morph of being a "cheater" (or, in the extreme case, a sociopath) may be advantageous.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1017/S0140525X00039595 |title=The sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model |year=2010 |last1=Mealey |first1=Linda |journal=] |volume=18 |issue=3 |pages=523–41}}
</ref> Finally, like many other psychological adaptations, personality traits may be facultative—sensitive to typical variations in the social environment, especially during early development. For example, later born children are more likely than first borns to be rebellious, less conscientious and more open to new experiences, which may be advantageous to them given their particular niche in family structure.<ref>{{cite book |last=Sulloway |first=F. |year=1996 |title=Born to rebel. |location=NY |publisher=Pantheon}}</ref> It is important to note that shared environmental influences do play a role in personality and are not always of less importance than genetic factors. However, shared environmental influences often decrease to near zero after adolescence but do not completely disappear.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Bouchard |first=T. J. |year=2004 |title=Genetic influence on human psychological traits. A survey. |journal=Current Directions in Psychological Science |volume=13 |number=4 |pages=148–151 |accessdate=September 14, 2014 |url=http://www.psy.miami.edu/faculty/dmessinger/c_c/rsrcs/rdgs/temperament/boucard.04.curdir.pdf| doi=10.1111/j.0963-7214.2004.002}}</ref>

====Language====
{{See also|Evolutionary linguistics|Evolutionary psychology of language}}

According to ], who builds on the work by ], the universal human ability to learn to talk between the ages of 1 – 4, basically without training, suggests that language acquisition is a distinctly human psychological adaptation (see, in particular, Pinker's '']''). Pinker and ] (1990) argue that language as a mental faculty shares many likenesses with the complex organs of the body which suggests that, like these organs, language has evolved as an adaptation, since this is the only known mechanism by which such complex organs can develop.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Pinker |first1=S. |last2=Bloom |first2=P. |year=1990 |title=Natural language and natural selection |journal=] |volume=13 |issue=4 |pages=707–27 |doi=10.1017/S0140525X00081061 |id={{citeseerx|10.1.1.116.4044}} }}</ref>

Pinker follows Chomsky in arguing that the fact that children can learn any human language with no explicit instruction suggests that language, including most of grammar, is basically innate and that it only needs to be activated by interaction. Chomsky himself does not believe language to have evolved as an adaptation, but suggests that it likely evolved as a byproduct of some other adaptation, a so-called ]. But Pinker and Bloom argue that the organic nature of language strongly suggests that it has an adaptational origin.<ref>Workman, Lance and Will Reader (2004) Evolutionary psychology: an introduction. Cambridge University Press p. 259</ref>

Evolutionary psychologists hold that the ] gene may well be associated with the evolution of human language.<ref name=10WR>Workman, Lance and Will Reader (2008). Evolutionary psychology: an introduction. 2nd Ed. Cambridge University Press. Chapter 10.</ref> In the 1980s, psycholinguist Myrna Gropnik identified a dominant gene that causes language impairment in the ] of Britain.<ref name=10WR/> This gene turned out to be a mutation of the FOXP2 gene.<ref name=10WR/> Humans have a unique allele of this gene, which has otherwise been closely conserved through most of mammalian evolutionary history.<ref name=10WR/> This unique allele seems to have first appeared between 100 and 200 thousand years ago, and it is now all but universal in humans.<ref name=10WR/> However, the once-popular idea that FOXP2 is a 'grammar gene' or that it triggered the emergence of language in ''Homo sapiens'' is now widely discredited.<ref>Diller, K. C. and R. L. Cann 2009. Evidence against a genetic-based revolution in language 50,000 years ago. In R. Botha and C. Knight (eds), ''The Cradle of Language.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 135–49.</ref>

Currently several competing theories about the evolutionary origin of language coexist, none of them having achieved a general consensus.<ref name=W&R-2008:277>Workman & Reader 2008:277 "There are a number of hypotheses suggesting that language evolved to fulfil a social function such as social grooming (to bind large groups together), the making of social contracts (to enable monogamy and male provisioning) and the use of language to impress potential mates. While each of these hypotheses has its merits, each is still highly speculative and requires more evidence from different areas of research (such as linguistics and anthropology)."</ref> Researchers of language acquisition in primates and humans such as ] and ], argue that the innatist framework has understated the role of imitation in learning and that it is not at all necessary to posit the existence of an innate grammar module to explain human language acquisition. Tomasello argues that studies of how children and primates actually acquire communicative skills suggests that humans learn complex behavior through experience, so that instead of a module specifically dedicated to language acquisition, language is acquired by the same cognitive mechanisms that are used to acquire all other kinds of socially transmitted behavior.<ref>Workman, Lance and Will Reader (2004) Evolutionary psychology: an introduction. Cambridge University Press p. 267</ref>

On the issue of whether language is best seen as having evolved as an adaptation or as a spandrel, evolutionary biologist ], following ], argues that it is unwarranted to assume that every aspect of language is an adaptation, or that language as a whole is an adaptation. He criticizes some strands of evolutionary psychology for suggesting a pan-adaptionist view of evolution, and dismisses Pinker and Bloom's question of whether "Language has evolved as an adaptation" as being misleading. He argues instead that from a biological viewpoint the evolutionary origins of language is best conceptualized as being the probable result of a convergence of many separate adaptations into a complex system.<ref>W. Tecumseh Fitch (2010) The Evolution of Language. Cambridge University Press pp. 65–66</ref> A similar argument is made by ] who in '']'' argues that the different features of language have co-evolved with the evolution of the mind and that the ability to use symbolic communication is integrated in all other cognitive processes.<ref>Deacon, Terrence W. (1997) The Symbolic Species: The Co-evolution of Language and the Brain. W.W. Norton & Co</ref>

If the theory that language could have evolved as a single adaptation is accepted, the question becomes which of its many functions has been the basis of adaptation, several evolutionary hypotheses have been posited: that it evolved for the purpose of social grooming, that it evolved to as a way to show mating potential or that it evolved to form social contracts. Evolutionary psychologists recognize that these theories are all speculative and that much more evidence is required to understand how language might have been selectively adapted.<ref>Workman, Lance and Will Reader (2004) Evolutionary psychology: an introduction. Cambridge University Press p. 277</ref>

===Mating===
{{main|Sex differences in psychology}}

Given that sexual reproduction is the means by which genes are propagated into future generations, sexual selection plays a large role in human evolution. Human ], then, is of interest to evolutionary psychologists who aim to investigate evolved mechanisms to attract and secure mates.<ref>Wilson, G.D. Love and Instinct. London: Temple Smith, 1981.</ref> Several lines of research have stemmed from this interest, such as studies of mate selection<ref>Buss 1994</ref><ref>Buss & Barnes 1986</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Li |first1=N. P. |last2=Bailey |first2=J. M. |last3=Kenrick |first3=D. T. |last4=Linsenmeier |first4=J. A. W. |year=2002 |title=The necessities and luxuries of mate preferences: Testing the tradeoffs |url=http://www.psych.northwestern.edu/psych/people/faculty/bailey/Publications/Li%20et%20al.,%202002.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |volume=6 |issue=6| pages=947–55 |pmid=12051582 |doi=10.1037/0022-3514.82.6.947}}</ref> mate poaching,<ref>Schmitt and Buss 2001</ref> mate retention,<ref>Buss 1988.</ref> ]<ref>Shackelford, Schmitt, & Buss (2005) Universal dimensions of human mate preferences; ''Personality and Individual Differences 39''</ref> and ].<ref>{{cite book |title=Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind|last=Buss|first=David M.|authorlink=|year=2008|publisher=Omegatype Typography, Inc.|location=Boston, MA|isbn=0-205-48338-0|page=iv}}</ref>

In 1972 ] published an influential paper<ref>Trivers, R. (1972). Parental investment and sexual selection. In B. Campbell (Ed.), ''Sexual Selection and the Descent of Man''. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton.</ref> on sex differences that is now referred to as ]. The size differences of ] (]) is the fundamental, defining difference between males (small gametes—sperm) and females (large gametes—ova). Trivers noted that anisogamy typically results in different levels of parental investment between the sexes, with females initially investing more. Trivers proposed that this difference in parental investment leads to the ] of different ] between the sexes and to ]. For example, he suggested that the sex that invests less in offspring will generally compete for access to the higher-investing sex to increase their ] (also see ]<ref name=doi10.1038/hdy.1948.21>{{cite doi |10.1038/hdy.1948.21}}</ref>). Trivers posited that differential parental investment led to the evolution sexual dimorphisms in ], intra- and inter- sexual reproductive competition, and ]s. In mammals, including humans, females make a much larger parental investment than males (i.e. ] followed by childbirth and ]). Parental investment theory is a branch of ].

] and ]'s (1993) ''Sexual Strategies Theory'' <ref>Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (1993). Sexual strategies theory: an evolutionary perspective on human mating. Psychological review, 100(2), 204.</ref> proposed that, due to differential parental investment, humans have evolved sexually dimorphic adaptations related to "sexual accessibility, fertility assessment, commitment seeking and avoidance, immediate and enduring resource procurement, paternity certainty, assessment of mate value, and parental investment." Their ''Strategic Interference Theory''<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |year=1989 |title=Conflict between the sexes: strategic interference and the evocation of anger and upset |url=|journal=Journal of personality and social psychology |volume=56 |issue=5| page=735 |doi=10.1037/0022-3514.56.5.735}}</ref> suggested that conflict between the sexes occurs when the preferred reproductive strategies of one sex interfere with those of the other sex, resulting in the activation of emotional responses such as anger or jealousy.

Women are generally more selective when choosing mates, especially under short-term mating conditions. However, under some circumstances, short term mating can provide benefits to women as well, such as fertility insurance, trading up to better genes, reducing risk of inbreeding, and insurance protection of her offspring.<ref>http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2000/sep/03/anthonybrowne.theobserver</ref>

Due to male paternity insecurity, sex differences have been found in such domains as ].<ref>Buss 1989</ref><ref>Buss et al. 1992</ref> Females generally react more adversely to emotional infidelity and males will react more to sexual infidelity. This particular pattern is predicted because the costs involved in mating for each sex are distinct. Women, on average, should prefer a mate who can offer resources (e.g., financial, commitment), thus, a woman risks losing such resources with a mate who commits emotional infidelity. Men, on the other hand, are never certain of the genetic paternity of their children because they do not bear the offspring themselves ("paternity insecurity"). This suggests that for men sexual infidelity would generally be more aversive than emotional infidelity because investing resources in another man's offspring does not lead to propagation of their own genes.<ref>Kalat, J. W. (2013). Biological Psychology (11th ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 9781111831004.</ref>

Another interesting line of research is that which examines women's mate preferences across the ].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Haselton |first1=M. G. |last2=Miller |first2=G. F. |year=2006 |title=Women's fertility across the cycle increases the short-term attractiveness of creative intelligence |url=http://www.sscnet.ucla.edu/comm/haselton/webdocs/haseltonmiller.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Human Nature |volume=17 |issue=1| pages=50–73 |doi=10.1007/s12110-006-1020-0 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gangestad |first1=S. W. |last2=Simpson |first2=J. A. |last3=Cousins |first3=A. J. |last4=Garver-Apgar |first4=C. E. |last5=Christensen |first5=P. N. |year=2004 |title=Women's preferences for male behavioral displays change across the menstrual cycle |url=http://faculty.oxy.edu/clint/evolution/articles/Women%E2%80%99s%20Preferences%20for%20Male%20behavioral%20display%20change%20across%20the%20menstrual%20cycle.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Psychological Science |volume=15 |issue=3| pages=203–07 |doi=10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.01503010.x |pmid=15016293 }}</ref> The theoretical underpinning of this research is that ancestral women would have evolved mechanisms to select mates with certain traits depending on their hormonal status. For example, the theory hypothesizes that, during the ovulatory phase of a woman's cycle (approximately days 10–15 of a woman's cycle),<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Wilcox |first1=A. J. |last2=Dunson |first2=D. B. |last3=Weinberg |first3=C. R. |last4=Trussell |first4=J. |last5=Baird |first5=D. D. |year=2001 |title=Likelihood of conception with a single act of intercourse: Providing benchmark rates for assessment of post-coital contraceptives |url=|journal=Contraception |volume=63 |issue=4| pages=211–15 |doi=10.1016/S0010-7824(01)00191-3 |pmid=11376648 }}</ref> a woman who mated with a male with high genetic quality would have been more likely, on average, to produce and rear a healthy offspring than a woman who mated with a male with low genetic quality. These putative preferences are predicted to be especially apparent for short-term mating domains because a potential male mate would only be offering genes to a potential offspring. This hypothesis allows researchers to examine whether women select mates who have characteristics that indicate high genetic quality during the high fertility phase of their ovulatory cycles. Indeed, studies have shown that women's preferences vary across the ovulatory cycle. In particular, Haselton and Miller (2006) showed that highly fertile women prefer creative but poor men as short-term mates. Creativity may be a proxy for good genes.<ref>Miller, G. F. (2000b) ''The mating mind: How sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature''. Anchor Books: New York.</ref> Research by Gangestad et al. (2004) indicates that highly fertile women prefer men who display social presence and intrasexual competition; these traits may act as cues that would help women predict which men may have, or would be able to acquire, resources.

===Parenting===
{{Main|Evolutionary psychology of parenting}}

Reproduction is always costly for women, and can also be for men. Individuals are limited in the degree to which they can devote time and resources to producing and raising their young, and such expenditure may also be detrimental to their future condition, survival and further reproductive output.
Parental investment is any parental expenditure (time, energy etc.) that benefits one ] at a cost to parents' ability to invest in other components of fitness (Clutton-Brock 1991: 9; Trivers 1972). Components of fitness (Beatty 1992) include the well being of existing offspring, parents' future ], and inclusive fitness through aid to kin (], 1964). Parental investment theory is a branch of life history theory.

Robert Trivers' theory of parental investment predicts that the sex making the largest investment in ], nurturing and protecting offspring will be more discriminating in mating and that the sex that invests less in offspring will compete for access to the higher investing sex (see ]).<ref name=doi10.1038/hdy.1948.21/> Sex differences in parental effort are important in determining the strength of sexual selection.

The benefits of parental investment to the offspring are large and are associated with the effects on condition, growth, survival and ultimately, on reproductive success of the offspring. However, these benefits can come at the cost of parent's ability to reproduce in the future e.g. through the increased risk of injury when defending offspring against predators, the loss of mating opportunities whilst rearing offspring and an increase in the time to the next reproduction. Overall, parents are ] to maximize the difference between the benefits and the costs, and parental care will be likely to evolve when the benefits exceed the costs.

The ] is an alleged high incidence of stepchildren being physically, emotionally or sexually abused, neglected, murdered, or otherwise mistreated at the hands of their stepparents at significantly higher rates than their genetic counterparts. It takes its name from the fairy tale character Cinderella, who in the story was cruelly mistreated by her stepmother and stepsisters.<ref>Daly, Matin, and Margo I. Wilson. (1999)</ref> Daly and Wilson (1996) noted: "Evolutionary thinking led to the discovery of the most important risk factor for child homicide – the presence of a stepparent. Parental efforts and investments are valuable resources, and selection favors those parental psyches that allocate effort effectively to promote fitness. The adaptive problems that challenge parental decision making include both the accurate identification of one's offspring and the allocation of one's resources among them with sensitivity to their needs and abilities to convert parental investment into fitness increments…. Stepchildren were seldom or never so valuable to one's expected fitness as one's own offspring would be, and those parental psyches that were easily parasitized by just any appealing youngster must always have incurred a selective disadvantage"(Daly & Wilson, 1996, pp.&nbsp;64–65). However, they note that not all stepparents will "want" to abuse their partner's children, or that genetic parenthood is any insurance against abuse. They see step parental care as primarily "mating effort" towards the genetic parent.<ref name=Daly_Wilson_98>Daly & Wilson 1998</ref>

===Family and kin===
Inclusive fitness is the sum of an organism's classical fitness (how many of its own offspring it produces and supports) and the number of equivalents of its own offspring it can add to the population by supporting others.<ref></ref> The first component is called classical fitness by Hamilton (1964).

From the gene's point of view, evolutionary success ultimately depends on leaving behind the maximum number of copies of itself in the population. Until 1964, it was generally believed that genes only achieved this by causing the individual to leave the maximum number of viable offspring. However, in 1964 W. D. Hamilton proved mathematically that, because close relatives of an organism share some identical genes, a gene can also increase its evolutionary success by promoting the reproduction and survival of these related or otherwise similar individuals. Hamilton concluded that this leads natural selection to favor organisms that would behave in ways that maximize their inclusive fitness. It is also true that natural selection favors behavior that maximizes personal fitness.

Hamilton's rule describes mathematically whether or not a gene for altruistic behavior will spread in a population:
:<math>rb > c \ </math>
where
* <math>c \ </math> is the reproductive cost to the altruist,
* <math>b \ </math> is the reproductive benefit to the recipient of the altruistic behavior, and
* <math>r \ </math> is the probability, above the population average, of the individuals sharing an altruistic gene – commonly viewed as "degree of relatedness".

The concept serves to explain how natural selection can perpetuate altruism. If there is an '"altruism gene"' (or complex of genes) that influences an organism's behavior to be helpful and protective of relatives and their offspring, this behavior also increases the proportion of the altruism gene in the population, because relatives are likely to share genes with the altruist due to ]. Altruists may also have some way to recognize altruistic behavior in unrelated individuals and be inclined to support them. As Dawkins points out in ''The Selfish Gene'' (Chapter 6) and ''The Extended Phenotype'',<ref>Dawkins, Richard, "The Extended Phenotype", Oxford University Press 1982 (Chapter 9)</ref> this must be distinguished from the ].

Although it is generally true that humans tend to be more altruistic toward their kin than toward non-kin, the relevant proximate mechanisms that mediate this cooperation have been debated (see ]), with some arguing that kin status is determined primarily via social and cultural factors (such as co-residence, maternal association of sibs, etc.),<ref name=W2010>{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2010.08.001 |title=Sixteen common misconceptions about the evolution of cooperation in humans |year=2011 |last1=West |first1=Stuart A. |last2=El Mouden |first2=Claire |last3=Gardner |first3=Andy |journal=Evolution and Human Behavior |volume=32 |issue=4 |pages=231–62 }}</ref> while others have argued that kin recognition can also mediated by biological factors such as facial resemblance and immunogenetic similarity of the major histocompatibility complex (MHC).<ref>Villinger, J., and Waldman, B. (2012). Social discrimination by quantitative assessment of immunogenetic similarity. Published online before print September 5, 2012, {{DOI|10.1098/rspb.2012.1279}} Proc. R. Soc. B</ref> For a discussion of the interaction of these social and biological kin recognition factors see Lieberman, Tooby, and Cosmides (2007)<ref>Lieberman, D., Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. The architecture of human kin detection Nature 445, 727–31 (15 February 2007) |{{DOI|10.1038/nature05510}} PMID 17301784</ref> ().

Whatever the proximate mechanisms of kin recognition there is substantial evidence that humans act generally more altruistically to close genetic kin compared to genetic non-kin.<ref name=ReferenceA>Buss, D.M. (2011). Evolutionary Psychology. Monterey: Brooks-Cole.</ref><ref name=Gaulin-2004>Gaulin & McBurney (2004), Evolutionary Psychology, 2nd Ed. NY: Prentice Hall</ref><ref>Workman & Reader (2008), Evolutionary Psychology, 2nd Ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press</ref>

===Interactions with non-kin / reciprocity===
Although interactions with non-kin are generally less altruistic compared to those with kin, cooperation can be maintained with non-kin via mutually beneficial reciprocity as was proposed by Robert Trivers.<ref name=Trivers1971/> If there are repeated encounters between the same two players in an evolutionary game in which each of them can choose either to "cooperate" or "defect," then a strategy of mutual cooperation may be favored even if it pays each player, in the short term, to defect when the other cooperates. Direct reciprocity can lead to the evolution of cooperation only if the probability, w, of another encounter between the same two individuals exceeds the cost-to-benefit ratio of the altruistic act:
: w > c/b

Reciprocity can also be indirect if information about previous interactions is shared. Reputation allows evolution of cooperation by indirect reciprocity. Natural selection favors strategies that base the decision to help on the reputation of the recipient: studies show that people who are more helpful are more likely to receive help. The calculations of indirect reciprocity are complicated and only a tiny fraction of this universe has been uncovered, but again a simple rule has emerged.<ref>{{cite journal |pmid=9634232 |year=1998 |last1=Nowak |first1=MA |last2=Sigmund |first2=K |title=Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image scoring |volume=393 |issue=6685 |pages=573–77 |doi=10.1038/31225 |journal=Nature |authorlink1=Martin Nowak |authorlink2=Karl Sigmund }}</ref> Indirect reciprocity can only promote cooperation if the probability, q, of knowing someone’s reputation exceeds the cost-to-benefit ratio of the altruistic act:
: q > c/b

One important problem with this explanation is that individuals may be able to evolve the capacity to obscure their reputation, reducing the probability, q, that it will be known.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/nature04201 |title=Human cooperation: Second-order free-riding problem solved? |last1=Fowler |first1=James H. |journal=Nature |volume=437 |issue=7058 |pages=E8; discussion E8–9 |authorlink1=James H. Fowler|date=22 September 2005 |pmid=16177738}}</ref>

Trivers argues that friendship and various social emotions evolved in order to manage reciprocity.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52>Gaulin, Steven J. C. and Donald H. McBurney. Evolutionary Psychology. Prentice Hall. 2003. ISBN 978-0-13-111529-3, Chapter 14, pp. 323–52.</ref> Liking and disliking, he says, evolved to help present day humans' ancestors form coalitions with others who reciprocated and to exclude those who did not reciprocate.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/> Moral indignation may have evolved to prevent one's altruism from being exploited by cheaters, and gratitude may have motivated present day humans' ancestors to reciprocate appropriately after benefiting from others' altruism.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/> Likewise, present day humans feel guilty when they fail to reciprocate.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/> These social motivations match what evolutionary psychologists expect to see in adaptations that evolved to maximize the benefits and minimize the drawbacks of reciprocity.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/>

Evolutionary psychologists say that humans have psychological adaptations that evolved specifically to help us identify nonreciprocators, commonly referred to as "cheaters."<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/> In 1993, Robert Frank and his associates found that participants in a prisoner's dilemma scenario were often able to predict whether their partners would "cheat," based on a half hour of unstructured social interaction.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/> In a 1996 experiment, for example, Linda Mealey and her colleagues found that people were better at remembering the faces of people when those faces were associated with stories about those individuals cheating (such as embezzling money from a church).<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.323-52/>

===Strong reciprocity (or "tribal reciprocity")===
{{Main|Strong reciprocity}}

Humans may have an evolved set of psychological adaptations that predispose them to be more cooperative than otherwise would be expected with members of their tribal ], and, more nasty to members of tribal ]. These adaptations may have be a consequent of tribal warfare.<ref>Bowles, S. (2009). 324, pp. 1293-98. (05 June 2009)</ref> Humans may also have predispositions for "]"—to punish in-group members who violate in-group rules, even when this altruistic behavior cannot be justified in terms of helping those you are related to (]), cooperating with those who you will interact with again (]), or cooperating to better your reputation with others (]).<ref name=gintis2000>{{Cite doi|10.1006/jtbi.2000.2111}}</ref><ref name=henrich2012>{{Cite doi|10.1017/S0140525X11001397}}</ref>

===Evolution and culture===
{{See also|Memetics |Cultural ecology |Dual inheritance theory}}

] is a theory of mental content based on an analogy with evolution, originating from ]' 1976 book ''].'' It purports to be an approach to ]s of cultural ]. A ], analogous to a ], is essentially a "unit of culture"—an idea, belief, pattern of behavior, etc. which is "hosted" in one or more individual minds, and which can reproduce itself from mind to mind. Thus what would otherwise be regarded as one individual influencing another to adopt a belief is seen memetically as a meme reproducing itself. As with genetics, particularly under Dawkins's interpretation, a meme's success may be due to its contribution to the effectiveness of its host. Memetics is notable for sidestepping the traditional concern with the '']'' of ideas and beliefs.

] (2002) re-stated the definition of meme as: whatever is copied from one person to another person, whether habits, skills, songs, stories, or any other kind of information. Further she said that memes, like genes, are replicators in the sense as defined by Dawkins.<ref>] (1982) King's College Sociobiology Group, eds., ''Current Problems in Sociobiology'', Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp.&nbsp;45–64. "A replicator may be defined as any entity in the universe of which copies are made."</ref> That is, they are information that is copied. Memes are copied by ], teaching and other methods. The copies are not perfect: memes are copied with variation; moreover, memes compete for humans' limited memory capacity and for the chance to be copied again. Only some of the variants can survive. The combination of these three elements (copies; variation; competition for survival) forms precisely the condition for ], and so memes (and hence human cultures) evolve. Large groups of memes that are copied and passed on together are called ] meme complexes, or ''memeplexes''. In her definition, the way that a meme replicates is through imitation.

] (DIT), also known as gene-culture coevolution, suggests that cultural information and genes co-evolve. ] and ] (1976) published perhaps the first dynamic models of gene-culture coevolution.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Feldman |first1=M. |last2=Cavalli-Sforza |first2=L. |year=1976 |title=Cultural and biological evolutionary processes, selection for a trait under complex transmission |url=|journal=Theoretical Population Biology |volume=9 |issue=2| pages=238–59 |doi=10.1016/0040-5809(76)90047-2 |pmid=1273802 }}</ref> These models were to form the basis for subsequent work on DIT, heralded by the publication of three seminal books in 1980 and 1981. Charles Lumsden and ] ''Genes, Mind and Culture'' (1981).<ref>Lumsden C., and E. Wilson. 1981. ''Genes, Mind and Culture: The Coevolutionary Process.'' Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.</ref> also outlined a series of mathematical models of how genetic evolution might favor the selection of cultural traits and how cultural traits might, in turn, affect the speed of genetic evolution. Another 1981 book relevant to this topic was Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman's ''Cultural Transmission and Evolution: A Quantitative Approach''.<ref>Cavalli-Sfornza, L. and M. Feldman. 1981. ''Cultural Transmission and Evolution: A Quantitative Approach''. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.</ref> Borrowing heavily from ] and ], this book built a mathematical theory concerning the spread of cultural traits. It describes the evolutionary implications of ], passing cultural traits from parents to offspring; oblique transmission, passing cultural traits from any member of an older generation to a younger generation; and ], passing traits between members of the same population.

] and ]'s (1985) ''Culture and the Evolutionary Process'' presents models of the evolution of social learning under different environmental conditions, the population effects of social learning, various forces of selection on cultural learning rules, different forms of biased transmission and their population-level effects, and conflicts between cultural and genetic evolution.

Along with ], ] suggested that Dual inheritance theory has potential for unifying the behavioral sciences, including economics, biology, anthropology, sociology, psychology and political science because it addresses both the genetic and cultural components of human inheritance.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gintis |first1=H. |year=2006 |title=A framework for the integration of the behavioral sciences |url=http://www.umass.edu/preferen/gintis/Unity-BBS%20Print%20Version.pdf| journal=] |volume=30 |pages=1–61 |doi=10.1017/s0140525x07000581}}</ref> Laland and Brown hold a similar view.{{Citation needed|date=March 2011}}

==In psychology sub-fields==

===Developmental psychology===
{{Main|Evolutionary developmental psychology}}

According to ], the benefits granted by evolutionary selection decrease with age. Natural selection has not eliminated many harmful conditions and nonadaptive characteristics that appear among older adults, such as ]. If it were a disease that killed 20 year-olds instead of 70 year-olds this may have been a disease that natural selection could have eliminated ages ago. Thus, unaided by evolutionary pressures against nonadaptive conditions, modern humans suffer the aches, pains, and infirmities of aging and as the benefits of evolutionary selection decrease with age, the need for culture increases.<ref>Santrock, W. John (2005). A Topical Approach to Life-Span Development (3rd ed.). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. p. 62.</ref>

===Social psychology===
As humans are a highly social species, there are many adaptive problems associated with navigating the social world (e.g., maintaining allies, managing status hierarchies, interacting with outgroup members, coordinating social activities, collective decision-making). Researchers in the emerging field of evolutionary social psychology have made many discoveries pertaining to topics traditionally studied by social psychologists, including person perception, social cognition, attitudes, altruism, emotions, ], ], motivation, prejudice, intergroup relations, and cross-cultural differences.<ref>Neuberg, S. L., Kenrick, D. T., & Schaller, M. (2010). Evolutionary social psychology. In S. T. Fiske, D. T. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (5th Edition, Vol. 2, pp. 761–796). New York: John Wiley & Sons.</ref><ref>Schaller, M., Simpson, J. A., & Kenrick, D. T. (Eds.) (2006). Evolution and social psychology. New York: Psychology Press.</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1037/1089-2699.12.1.1 |title=Evolutionary approaches to group dynamics: An introduction |year=2008 |last1=Van Vugt |first1=Mark |last2=Schaller |first2=Mark |journal=Group Dynamics: Theory, Research, and Practice |volume=12 |pages=1–6 }}</ref><ref>Van Vugt, Mark & Kameda, Tatsuya. Evolution and Groups. In J. Levine Group Processes Chapter 12 (2012). New York: Psychology Press.</ref>

When endeavouring to solve a problem humans at an early age show determination while ]s have no comparable facial expression. Researchers suspect the human determined expression evolved because when a human is determinedly working on a problem other people will frequently help.<ref></ref>

===Abnormal psychology===
Adaptationist hypotheses regarding the etiology of psychological disorders are often based on analogies between physiological and psychological dysfunctions,<ref>{{cite book |last1=] |first1=R |last2=] |first2=George C. |title=Why We Get Sick |year=1996 |publisher=Vintage |location=NY}} (adaptationist perspective to both physiological and psychological dysfunctions)</ref> as noted in the table below. Prominent theorists and ] include ] and ]. They, and others, suggest that mental disorders are due to the interactive effects of both nature and nurture, and often have multiple contributing causes.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.1-24/>

{| class="wikitable"
|-
|+ Possible Causes of Psychological 'Abnormalities' from an Adaptationist Perspective <br/>
Summary based on information in these textbooks (all titled "Evolutionary Psychology"): Buss (2011),<ref name=ReferenceA/> Gaulin & McBurney (2004),<ref name=Gaulin-2004/> Workman & Reader (2008)<ref>Workman & Reader (2008), Evolutionary Psychology, 2nd Ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,</ref> as well as Cosmides & Tooby (1999) ''Toward an evolutionary taxonomy of treatable conditions ''<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Cosmides |first1=L. |last2=Tooby |first2=J. |year=1999 |title=Toward an evolutionary taxonomy of treatable conditions |url=|journal=Journal of Abnormal Psychology |volume=108 |issue=3| pages=453–64 |doi=10.1037/0021-843X.108.3.453 |pmid=10466269 }}</ref>
|-
! Causal mechanism of failure or malfunction of adaptation !! Physiological Example !! Hypothesized Psychological Example
|-
| '''Functioning adaptation (adaptive defense)'''
| Fever / Vomiting <br><small>(functional responses to infection or ingestion of toxins)</small>
| Mild depression or anxiety <small>(functional responses to mild loss or stress</small><ref name=ncbi.nlm.nih.gov>Andrews, P. W. & Thomson, J. A. (2009). Psychol Rev. 2009 July; 116(3): 620-654. {{DOI|10.1037/a0016242}} PMID 19618990</ref><small>/ reduction of social interactions to prevent infection by contagious pathogens)</small><ref>Raison, C.L, Miller, A. N. (2012). The evolutionary significance of depression in Pathogen Host Defense (PATHOS-D) Molecular Psychiatry 1–23. .</ref>
|-
|'''By-product of an adaptation(s)'''
| Intestinal gas <br><small>(byproduct of digestion of fiber)</small>
| Sexual fetishes (?)<br><small>(possible byproduct of normal sexual arousal adaptations that have 'imprinted' on unusual objects or situations)</small>
|-
| '''Adaptations with multiple effects'''
| Gene for malaria resistance, in homozygous form, causes sickle cell anemia
| Adaptation(s) for high levels of creativity may also predispose schizophrenia or bi-polar disorder <small>(adaptations with both positive and negative effects, perhaps dependent on alternate developmental trajectories)</small>
|-
| '''Malfunctioning adaptation'''
| Allergies<br><small>(over-reactive immunological responses)</small>
| Autism <br><small>(possible malfunctioning of ] module)</small>
|-
| '''] morphs'''
| The two sexes / Different blood and immune system types
| Personality traits and personality disorders <small>(may represent alternative behavioral strategies dependent on the frequency of the strategy in the population)</small>
|-
| '''Mismatch between ancestral & current environments'''
| Modern diet-related Type 2 Diabetes
| More frequent modern interaction with strangers (compared to family and close friends) may predispose greater incidence of depression & anxiety
|-
| '''Tails of normal (bell shaped) curve'''
| Very short or tall height
| Tails of the distribution of personality traits<br><small>(e.g., extremely introverted or extroverted)</small>
|}

Evolutionary psychologists have suggested that schizophrenia and bipolar disorder may reflect a side-effect of genes with fitness benefits, such as increased creativity.<ref name=Gaulin-11>Gaulin and McBurney 2003 pp. 239-56.</ref> (Some individuals with bipolar disorder are especially creative during their manic phases and the close relatives of schizophrenics have been found to be more likely to have creative professions.<ref name=Gaulin-11/>) A 1994 report by the American Psychiatry Association found that people suffered from schizophrenia at roughly the same rate in Western and non-Western cultures, and in industrialized and pastoral societies, suggesting that schizophrenia is not a disease of civilization nor an arbitrary social invention.<ref name=Gaulin-11/> Sociopathy may represent an evolutionarily stable strategy, by which a small number of people who cheat on social contracts benefit in a society consisting mostly of non-sociopaths.<ref name=Gaulin-Steven-J-C-2003-pp.1-24/> Mild depression may be an adaptive response to withdraw from, and re-evaluate, situations that have led to disadvantageous outcomes (the "analytical rumination hypothesis") <ref name=ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/> (see ]).

Some of these speculations have yet to be developed into fully testable hypotheses, and a great deal of research is required to confirm their validity.<ref>O’Connell, H. (2004) Evolutionary theory in psychiatry and psychology. Irish Journal of Psychological Medicine, 21 (1), pp. 37–37.</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Rose |first1=S. |year=2001 |title=Revisiting evolutionary psychology and psychiatry |url=|journal=The British Journal of Psychiatry |volume=179 |pages=558–59 |doi=10.1192/bjp.179.6.558-b |issue=6 }}</ref>

===Psychology of religion===
{{Main|Evolutionary psychology of religion}}
Adaptationist perspectives on ] suggest that, like all behavior, religious behaviors are a product of the human brain. As with all other organ functions, ]'s functional structure has been argued to have a genetic foundation, and is therefore subject to the effects of natural selection and sexual selection. Like other organs and tissues, this functional structure should be universally shared amongst humans and should have solved important problems of survival and reproduction in ancestral environments. However, evolutionary psychologists remain divided on whether religious belief is more likely a consequence of evolved psychological adaptations,<ref name=Sosis>{{cite journal |year=2003 |title=Signaling, solidarity, and the sacred: the evolution of religious behavior |journal=Evolutionary Anthropology |issue=12 |pages=264–74 |last1=Sosis |first1=R. |first2=C. |last2=Alcorta |doi=10.1002/evan.10120 |volume=12}}</ref> or is a byproduct of other cognitive adaptations.<ref>{{cite journal |year=2006 |title=Whence collective rituals? A cultural selection model of ritualized behavior|journal=American Anthropologist |issue=108 |pages=824–827 |last1=Lienard |first1=P. |first2=P. |last2=Boyer |doi=10.1525/aa.2006.108.4.814 |volume=108}}</ref>

==Reception==
{{Main|Criticism of evolutionary psychology}}
Critics of evolutionary psychology accuse it of promoting genetic determinism, panadaptionism (the idea that all behaviors and anatomical features are adaptations), unfalsifiable hypotheses, distal or ultimate explanations of behavior when proximate explanations are superior, and malevolent political or moral ideas.<ref>Kurzban, Robert. . The Human Nature Review 2002 Volume 2: 99–109 (14 March ). Retrieved 14 July 2013.</ref>

===Ethical implications===
Critics have argued that evolutionary psychology might be used to justify existing social hierarchies and ] policies.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Rose |first1=Hilary |last2=Rose |first2=Steven |editor1-link=|others=|title=Alas, Poor Darwin: Arguments against Evolutionary Psychology |url=|edition=|year=2000 |publisher=Harmony Books |location=New York |isbn=978-0-609-60513-4 |pages=1–13 |chapter=Introduction |chapterurl=}}</ref><ref name=wilson2003>{{cite journal |last1=Wilson |first1=David Sloan |last2=Dietrich |first2=Eric |last3=Clark |first3=Anne B. |year=2003 |title=On the inappropriate use of the naturalistic fallacy in evolutionary psychology |journal=Biology and Philosophy |volume=18 |issue=5 |pages=669–81 |publisher=|doi=10.1023/A:1026380825208 |url=http://evolution.binghamton.edu/dswilson/wp-content/uploads/2010/01/DSW14.pdf |accessdate=March 23, 2013}}</ref> It has also been suggested by critics that evolutionary psychologists' theories and interpretations of empirical data rely heavily on ] assumptions about race and gender.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Caporael |first1=Linnda R. |last2=Brewer |first2=Marilynn B. |year=1991 |title=The Quest for Human Nature: Social and Scientific Issues in Evolutionary Psychology |journal=Journal of Social Issues |volume=47 |issue=3 |pages=1–9 |publisher=|doi=10.1111/j.1540-4560.1991.tb01819.x |url=|accessdate=}}</ref>

In response to such criticism, evolutionary psychologists often caution against committing the ] – the assumption that "what is natural" is necessarily a moral good.<ref name=wilson2003/><ref name=Pinker>Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate. NY: Penguin</ref>{{page needed|date=April 2013}}<ref name=Levy/> However, their caution against committing the naturalistic fallacy has been criticized as means to stifle legitimate ethical discussions.<ref name=wilson2003/>

===Standard social science model===
{{Main|Standard social science model}}
Evolutionary psychology has been entangled in the larger philosophical and social science controversies related to the debate on ]. Evolutionary psychologists typically contrast evolutionary psychology with what they call the standard social science model (SSSM). They characterize the SSSM as the "]", ], or "]" perspective that they say dominated the ]s throughout the 20th century and assumed that the mind was shaped almost entirely by culture.<ref name=Pinker/>

Critics have argued that evolutionary psychologists created a ] between their own view and the ] of the SSSM.<ref name=Richardson>{{cite book |last1=Richardson |first1=Robert C. |authorlink1=|authorlink2=|editor1-link=|others=|title=Evolutionary Psychology As Maladapted Psychology |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=KeqiKNFa3YgC&pg=PA176 |edition=|year=2007 |publisher=] |location=Cambridge, Mass. |isbn=978-0-262-18260-7 |page=176 |chapter=|chapterurl=}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Wallace |first=Brendan |authorlink= |title=Getting Darwin Wrong: Why Evolutionary Psychology Won't Work |url=|accessdate= |year=2010 |publisher=Imprint Academic |location=Exeter |isbn=978-1-84540-207-5 |page=136}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Solomon |first1=Sheldon |authorlink1=|authorlink2=|editor1-first=Mark |editor1-last=Schaller |editor2-first=Christian S |editor2-last=Crandall |title=The Psychological Foundations of Culture |url=|year=2004 |publisher=Lawrence Erlbaum Associates |location=Mahwah, N.J. |isbn=978-0-8058-3839-8 |page=17 |chapter=Human Awareness of Mortality and the Evolution of Culture |chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=TW4cVuyEnFAC&pg=PA17 |display-authors=etal}}</ref> Other critics regard the SSSM as a ] or a ]<ref name=Levy>{{cite journal |last1=Levy |first1=Neil |year=2004 |title=Evolutionary Psychology, Human Universals, and the Standard Social Science Model |journal=] |volume=19 |issue=3 |pages=459–72 |publisher=] |doi=10.1023/B:BIPH.0000036111.64561.63 |id={{citeseerx|10.1.1.90.9290}} }}</ref><ref name=Richardson/><ref>{{cite book |last1=Sampson |first1=Geoffrey |authorlink1=Geoffrey Sampson |authorlink2=|editor1-link=|others=|title=The "Language Instinct" Debate: Revised Edition |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=N0zJNPuXTZMC&pg=PA134 |edition=|year=2009 |publisher=Continuum |location=London |isbn=978-0-8264-7384-4 |pages=134–5 |chapter=|chapterurl=}}</ref> and suggest that the scientists whom evolutionary psychologists associate with the SSSM did not believe that the mind was a blank state devoid of any natural predispositions.<ref name=Levy/>

===Reductionism and determinism===
Some critics view evolutionary psychology as a form of genetic ] and ],<ref>{{cite book |last1=Maiers |first1=Wolfgang |authorlink1=|authorlink2=|editor1-first=Niamh |editor1-last=Stephenson |editor1-link=|others=|title=Theoretical Psychology: Critical Contributions |url=|edition=|year=2003 |publisher=Captus University Publications |location=Concord, Ont. |isbn=978-1-55322-055-8 |pages=426–35 |chapter=The Bogus Claim of Evolutionary Psychology |chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=uA5VIXQmYQUC&pg=PA426 }}</ref><ref name=Plotkin-Henry-p.150>Plotkin, Henry. 2004 Evolutionary thought in Psychology: A Brief History. Blackwell. p. 150.</ref> a common critique being that evolutionary psychology does not address the complexity of individual development and experience and fails to explain the influence of genes on behavior in individual cases.<ref name=instinct>"instinct." Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, 2011. Web. 9 Feb 2011. .</ref> Evolutionary psychologists respond that EP works within a nature-nurture interactionist framework that acknowledges that many psychological adaptations are facultative (sensitive to environmental variations during individual development). EP is generally not focused on proximate analyses of behavior but rather its focus is on the study of distal/ultimate causality (the evolution of psychological adaptations). The field of behavioral genetics is focused on the study of the proximate influence of genes on behavior.<ref name=AmPs2010/>

===Testability of hypotheses===
{{See also|Just-so story}}
A frequent critique of the discipline is that the hypotheses of evolutionary psychology are frequently arbitrary and difficult or impossible to adequately test, thus questioning its status as an actual scientific discipline, for example because many current traits probably evolved to serve different functions than they do now.<ref name=Psychology/><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Ryle |first1=Anthony |year=2005 |title=The Relevance of Evolutionary Psychology for Psychotherapy |journal=British Journal of Psychotherapy |volume=21 |issue=3 |pages=375–88 |publisher=|doi=10.1111/j.1752-0118.2005.tb00225.x |url=|accessdate=}}</ref> While evolutionary psychology hypotheses are difficult to test, evolutionary psychologists assert that it is not impossible.<ref name=Buss-Haselton-2007-pp.26-7>"Testing ideas about the evolutionary origins of psychological phenomena is indeed a challenging task, but not an impossible one" (Buss et al. 1998; Pinker, 1997b).</ref> Part of the critique of the scientific base of evolutionary psychology includes a critique of the concept of the Environments of Evolutionary Adaptation (EEA). Some critics have argued that researchers know so little about the environment in which ''Homo sapiens'' evolved that explaining specific traits as an adaption to that environment becomes highly speculative.<ref name=Plotkin-Henry-p.149>Plotkin, Henry. 2004 Evolutionary thought in Psychology: A Brief History. Blackwell. p. 149.</ref> Evolutionary psychologists respond that they do know many things about this environment, including the facts that present day humans' ancestors were hunter-gatherers, that they generally lived in small tribes, etc.<ref>The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (2005), David M. Buss, Chapter 1, pp. 5–67, Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology, John Tooby and Leda Cosmides</ref>

===Modularity of mind===
{{Main|Modularity of mind}}
Evolutionary psychologists generally presume that, like the body, the mind is made up of many evolved modular adaptations,<ref name=Kurzban-R-2011>{{cite book |last=Kurzban |first=Robert |year=2011 |title=Why Everyone (Else) Is a Hypocrite: Evolution and the Modular Mind |publisher=Princeton University Press |location=NJ |isbn=9780691146744}}</ref> although there is some disagreement within the discipline regarding the degree of general plasticity, or "generality," of some modules.<ref name=AmPs2010>{{cite doi|10.1037/a0018413}}</ref> It has been suggested that modularity evolves because, compared to non-modular networks, it would have conferred an advantage in terms of fitness<ref>{{cite book |last1=Cosmides |first1=Leda |authorlink1=|last2=Tooby |first2=John |authorlink2=|editor1-link=|others=|title=The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture |url=|year=1992 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=New York |isbn=|pages=163–228 |chapter=Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange |chapterurl=}}</ref> and because connection costs are lower.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Clune |first1=Jeff |last2=Mouret |first2=Jean-Baptiste |last3=Lipson |first3=Hod |year=2013 |title=The evolutionary origins of modularity |journal=Proceedings of the Royal Society |volume=280 |issue=1755 |pages=20122863|publisher=|doi=10.1098/rspb.2012.2863 |arxiv=1207.2743v1}}</ref>

In contrast, some academics argue that it is unnecessary to posit the existence of highly domain specific modules, and, suggest that the neural anatomy of the brain supports a model based on more domain general faculties and processes.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Panksepp |first1=Jaak |last2=Panksepp |first2=Jules B. |year=2000 |title=The Seven Sins of Evolutionary Psychology|journal=Evolution and Cognition |volume=6 |issue=2 |pages=108–131 |url=http://www.flyfishingdevon.co.uk/salmon/year3/psy364-intro-psychobiology/panksepp_seven_sins.pdf |format=PDF |accessdate=15 May 2012 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Buller |first1=David J. |authorlink1=|last2=Hardcastle |first2=Valerie Gray |authorlink2=|editor1-first=David J. |editor1-last=Buller |editor1-link=|others=|title=Adapting Minds: Evolutionary Psychology And The Persistent Quest For Human Nature |url=|year=2005 |publisher=] |location=Cambridge, Mass. |isbn=978-0-262-02579-9 |pages=127–201 |chapter=Modularity |chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=dQ5MGDvn8eIC&pg=PA127 }}</ref> Moreover, empirical support for the domain-specific theory stems almost entirely from performance on variations of the ] which is extremely limited in scope as it only tests one subtype of deductive reasoning.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Davies |first1=Paul Sheldon |last2=Fetzer |first2=James H. |last3=Foster |first3=Thomas R. |year=1995 |title=Logical reasoning and domain specificity |journal=] |volume=10 |issue=1 |pages=1–37 |publisher=|doi=10.1007/BF00851985 |url=|accessdate=}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=O'Brien |first1=David |authorlink1=|last2=Manfrinati |first2=Angela |authorlink2=|editor1-first=Mike |editor1-last=Oaksford |editor1-link=|editor2-last=Chater |editor2-first=Nick |title=Cognition and Conditionals: Probability and Logic in Human Thinking |url=|year=2010 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=New York |isbn=978-0-19-923329-8 |pages=39–54 |chapter=The Mental Logic Theory of Conditional Propositions |chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=iQSDOqAvXIoC&pg=PA47 }}</ref>

===Evolutionary psychology defense===
Evolutionary psychologists have addressed many of their critics (see, for example, books by Segerstråle (2000), ''Defenders of the Truth: The Battle for Science in the Sociobiology Debate and Beyond,''<ref>Segerstråle, Ullica Christina Olofsdotter (2000). Defenders of the truth: The battle for science in the sociobiology debate and beyond. Oxford : Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-850505-1.</ref> Barkow (2005), ''Missing the Revolution: Darwinism for Social Scientists,''<ref>Jerome H. Barkow, (2005), Missing the Revolution: Darwinism for Social Scientists
Oxford, Oxford University Press.</ref> and Alcock (2001), ''The Triumph of Sociobiology''.<ref name=Alcock-John-2001>Alcock, John (2001). The Triumph of Sociobiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-516335-3</ref>). Among their rebuttals are that some criticisms are ], are based on an incorrect nature versus nurture dichotomy, are based on misunderstandings of the discipline, etc.<ref name=AmPs2010/><ref name=Alcock-John-2001/><ref>Segerstråle, Ullica Christina Olofsdotter (2000). Defenders of the truth : the battle for science in the sociobiology debate and beyond. Oxford : Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-850505-1.</ref><ref>Barkow, Jerome (Ed.). (2006) Missing the Revolution: Darwinism for Social Scientists. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513002-7</ref><ref>Tooby, J., Cosmides, L. & Barrett, H. C. (2005). Resolving the debate on innate ideas: Learnability constraints and the evolved interpenetration of motivational and conceptual functions. In Carruthers, P., Laurence, S. & Stich, S. (Eds.), The Innate Mind: Structure and Content. NY: Oxford University Press.</ref><ref>Controversies surrounding evolutionary psychology by Edward H. Hagen, Institute for Theoretical Biology, Berlin. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 5–67). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.</ref><ref> by Gad Saad, Psychology Today blog.</ref><ref>Geher, G. (2006). Evolutionary psychology is not evil! … and here’s why … Psihologijske Teme (Psychological Topics); Special Issue on Evolutionary Psychology, 15, 181–202. </ref><ref> by John Johnson, Psychology Today blog.</ref> ] suggested that "...critics of the field, when they err, are not slightly missing the mark. Their confusion is deep and profound. It’s not like they are marksmen who can’t quite hit the center of the target; they’re holding the gun backwards."<ref>Kurzban, R. (2013). Evolutionary Psychology.</ref>

==See also==
{{Misplaced Pages books|Evolutionary psychology}}
{{Portal|Evolutionary biology}}
{{cmn|4|
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* '']''
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
}}

==Notes==
{{Reflist|2}}

==References==
* {{cite book |last=Barkow|first=Jerome H. |title=Missing the Revolution: Darwinism for Social Scientists |publisher=Oxford University Press, USA |year=2006|isbn=0-19-513002-2 |oclc=}}
* Barkow, J., Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. 1992. The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* {{cite book |last=Bowlby|first=John|title=Attachment|publisher=Basic Books|location=New York|year=1969}}
* {{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |last2=Barnes |first2=M. |year=1986 |title=Preferences in human mate selection |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/prefs_mate_selection_1986_jpsp.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |volume=50 |issue=3| pages=559–70 |doi=10.1037/0022-3514.50.3.559 }}
* {{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |year=1988 |title=From vigilance to violence: Tactics of mate retention in American undergraduates |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/Vigilance_to_Violence_1988.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Ethology and Sociobiology |volume=9 |issue=5| pages=291–317 |doi=10.1016/0162-3095(88)90010-6 }}
* {{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |year=1989 |title=Sex differences in human mate preferences: Evolutionary hypotheses tested in 37 cultures |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/SexDifferencesinHuman.PDF |journal=] |volume=12 |pages=1–49 |doi=10.1017/S0140525X00023992 }}
* {{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |last2=Larsen |first2=R. J. |last3=Westen |first3=D. |last4=Semmelroth |first4=J. |year=1992 |title=Sex differences in jealousy: Evolution, physiology, and psychology |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/SexDifferencesinJealousy.PDF |journal=Psychological Science |volume=3 |issue=4| pages=251–55 |doi=10.1111/j.1467-9280.1992.tb00038.x }}
* Buss, D. M. (1994). ''The evolution of desire: Strategies of human mating''. New York: Basic Books.
* {{cite book |last=Buss|first=David M. |title=Evolutionary psychology: the new science of the mind |publisher=Pearson/A and B |location=Boston |year=2004 |isbn=0-205-37071-3 |oclc=}}
* {{cite journal |url=http://www.sscnet.ucla.edu/comm/haselton/webdocs/spandrels.html |journal=American Psychologist |year=1998 |volume=53 |pages=533–48 |title=Adaptations, Exaptations, and Spandrels|first1=David M. |last1=Buss
|first2=Martie G. |last2=Haselton |first3=Todd K. |last3=Shackelford |first4=April L. |last4=Bleske |first5=Jerome C. |last5=Wakefield |accessdate=29 August 2011 |issue=5 |doi=10.1037/0003-066X.53.5.533 |pmid=9612136}}
* {{cite book |last=Clarke|first=Murray |title=Reconstructing reason and representation |publisher=MIT Press |location=Cambridge, Mass |year=2004 |isbn=0-262-03322-4 |oclc=}}
* Confer, Easton, Fleischman, Goetz, Lewis, Perilloux & Buss , ''American Psychologist'', 2010.
* {{cite journal |last1=Duntley |first1=J.D. |last2=Buss |first2=D.M. |year=2008 |title=Evolutionary psychology is a metatheory for psychology |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/duntleybuss2008.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Psychological Inquiry |volume=19 |pages=30–34 |doi=10.1080/10478400701774105 }}
* Durrant, R., & Ellis, B.J. (2003). Evolutionary Psychology. In M. Gallagher & R.J. Nelson (Eds.), ''Comprehensive Handbook of Psychology, Volume Three: Biological Psychology'' (pp.&nbsp;1–33). New York: Wiley & Sons.
* {{cite book |last=Evan|first=Dylan |title=Introducing Evolutionary Psychology |publisher=Totem Books USA |location=Lanham, MD |year=2000 |isbn=1-84046-043-1 |oclc=}}
* Fruehwald, Edwin Scott, Law and Human Behavior: A Study in Behavioral Biology, Neuroscience, and The Law (Vandeplas 2011). ISBN 978-1-60042-144-0
* Gaulin, Steven J. C. and Donald H. McBurney. ''Evolutionary psychology''. Prentice Hall. 2003. ISBN 978-0-13-111529-3
* {{cite book |last=Joyce|first=Richard |title=The Evolution of Morality (Life and Mind: Philosophical Issues in Biology and Psychology) |publisher=The MIT Press |location=Cambridge, Mass |year=2006|isbn=0-262-10112-2 |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last=Miller|first=Geoffrey P. |title=The mating mind: how sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature |publisher=Doubleday |location=Garden City, N.Y |year=2000 |isbn=0-385-49516-1 |oclc=}}
* Nesse, R.M. (2000). .
* {{cite book| last1=] |first1=R |last2=] |first2=George C. |title=Why We Get Sick |year=1996 |publisher=Vintage |location=NY}}
* {{cite book |last=Pinker|first=Steven |title=How the mind works |publisher=Norton |location=New York |year=1997 |isbn=0-393-04535-8 |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last=Pinker|first=Steven |title=The blank slate: the modern denial of human nature |publisher=Viking |location=New York, N.Y |year=2002 |isbn=0-670-03151-8 |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last=Richards|first=Janet C. |title=Human nature after Darwin: a philosophical introduction |publisher=Routledge |location=New York |year=2000 |isbn=0-415-21243-X |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last1=Ryan|first1=C. |last2=Jethá|first2=C.|title=Sex at Dawn: The Prehistoric Origins of Modern Sexuality |publisher=Harper |location=New York, NY |year=2010 |isbn=0-06-170780-5 |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last=Santrock|first=John W. |title=The Topical Approach to Life-Span Development(3rd ed.) |publisher=McGraw Hill |location=New York, N.Y |year=2005 |isbn=0-07-322626-2 |oclc=}}
* Schacter, Daniel L, Daniel Wegner and Daniel Gilbert. 2007. ''Psychology''. Worth Publishers. ISBN 0-7167-5215-8 ISBN 9780716752158.
* {{cite journal |last1=Schmitt |first1=D. P. |last2=Buss |first2=D. M. |year=2001 |title=Human mate poaching: Tactics and temptations for infiltrating existing relationships |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/Human_Mate_Poaching_2001.pdf |format=PDF |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |volume=80 |issue=6| pages=894–917 |doi=10.1037/0022-3514.80.6.894 |pmid=11414373 }}
* Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2005). Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), ''The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology'' (pp.&nbsp;5–67). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
* {{cite book |last=Wilson|first=Edward Osborne ("E. O.") |title=Sociobiology: the new synthesis |publisher=Belknap Press of Harvard University Press |location=Cambridge |year=1975 |isbn=0674816218 |oclc=}}
* {{cite book |last=Wright|first=Robert C. M. |title=The moral animal: evolutionary psychology and everyday life |publisher=Vintage Books |location=New York |year=1995 |isbn=0-679-76399-6 |oclc=}}

==Further reading==
<!-- Notice: moved out of External links because they're really on-line versions of books (see talk page) -->
* {{cite journal |last1=Buss |first1=D. M. |authorlink=David Buss |year=1995 |title=Evolutionary psychology: A new paradigm for psychological science |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/ANewParadigmforPsych.PDF |journal=Psychological Inquiry |volume=6 |pages=1–30 |doi=10.1207/s15327965pli0601_1 }}
* {{cite journal |last1=Confer |first1=J.C. |last2=Easton |first2=J.A. |last3=Fleischman |first3=D.S. |last4=Goetz |first4=C. D. |last5=Lewis |first5=D.M.G. |last6=Perilloux |first6=C. |last7=Buss |first7=D. M. |year=2010 |title=Evolutionary Psychology: Controversies, Questions, Prospects, and Limitations |url=http://homepage.psy.utexas.edu/homepage/Group/BussLAB/pdffiles/evolutionary_psychology_AP_2010.pdf |format=PDF |journal=American Psychologist |volume=65 |issue=2| pages=110–26 |doi=10.1037/a0018413 |pmid=20141266 }}
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Cosmides |first1=Leda |authorlink1=Leda Cosmides |last2=Tooby |first2=John|authorlink2=John Tooby |editor-first=Ronald |editor-last=Hamowy |editor-link=Ronald Hamowy |encyclopedia=The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism |title=Evolution Psychology |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=yxNgXs3TkJYC |accessdate=|edition=|year=2008 |publisher=]; ] |location=Thousand Oaks, CA |id=|isbn=978-1-4129-6580-4 |oclc=750831024| lccn=2008009151 |pages=158–61|quote=|ref=}}
* ] (2012). "", in: A. Michalos (ed.): Encyclopedia of Quality of Life Research (Springer, Berlin).
* {{cite journal|last=Kennair|first=L. E. O.|year=2002|title=Evolutionary psychology: An emerging integrative perspective within the science and practice of psychology|journal=Human Nature Review|volume=2|pages=17–61|url=http://www.human-nature.com/nibbs/02/ep.html}}
* {{cite web|url=http://homepage.uibk.ac.at/~c720126/humanethologie/ws/medicus/block1/inhalt.html|title=Evolutionary Theory of Human Sciences|last=Medicus|first=G.|year=2005|pages=9, 10, 11|accessdate=2009-09-08}}
* Oikkonen, Venla: ''Gender, Sexuality and Reproduction in Evolutionary Narratives.'' London: Routledge, 2013. ISBN 978-0-415-63599-8

==External links==
{{Library resources box
|by=no
|onlinebooks=no
|others=no
|about=yes
|label=evolutionary psychology}}
* Collaborative effort to catalog human psychological adaptations
* {{dmoz|Science/Social_Sciences/Psychology/Evolutionary_Psychology|Evolutionary Psychology}}
* .
*

===Academic societies===
* ; international society dedicated to using evolutionary theory to study human nature
* ; promotes ethological perspectives on the study of humans worldwide
* an interdisciplinary society that supports the activities of European researchers with an interest in evolutionary accounts of human cognition, behavior and society
* ; an international and interdisciplinary association of scholars, scientists, and policymakers concerned with evolutionary, genetic, and ecological knowledge and its bearing on political behavior, public policy and ethics.
* a scholarly association dedicated to fostering interdisciplinary exploration of issues at the intersection of law, biology, and evolutionary theory
* aims to foster research and education into the interdisciplinary nexus of cognitive science and evolutionary studies
* ; regional society dedicated to encouraging scholarship and dialogue on the topic of evolutionary psychology
* researchers that investigate the active role that females have had in human evolution

===Journals===
* — free access online scientific journal
* – journal of the
* An international, interdisciplinary forum for original research papers that address evolved psychology. Spans social and life sciences, anthropology, philosophy, criminology, law and the humanities.
* – an interdisciplinary peer-reviewed journal published by the
* – advances the interdisciplinary investigation of the biological, social, and environmental factors that underlie human behavior. It focuses primarily on the functional unity in which these factors are continuously and mutually interactive. These include the evolutionary, biological, and sociological processes as they interact with human social behavior.
* – devoted to theoretical advances in the fields of biology and cognition, with an emphasis on the conceptual integration afforded by evolutionary and developmental approaches.
*
* – interdisciplinary articles in psychology, neuroscience, behavioral biology, cognitive science, artificial intelligence, linguistics and philosophy. About 30% of the articles have focused on evolutionary analyses of behavior.
* — research relevant to interface of evolutionary and developmental biology
*

===Videos===
*
* by Steven Pinker about his book ]
* by evolutionary psychologist Robert Kurzban on modularity of mind, based on his book ''Why Everyone (Else) is a Hypocrite''
*
* Audio recording
*
* . Review of the nature versus nurture debate triggered by Mead's book "Coming of Age in Samoa."

{{Evolutionary psychology|state=expanded}}
{{evolution}}
{{Psychology}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=April 2012}}

{{Authority control}}

{{DEFAULTSORT:Evolutionary Psychology}}
]
]
]
]
]

Revision as of 21:48, 21 July 2015

Redirect to:

l l l l l john has been here all along. no why.

Indeed.

Suitably

Enough

Bantering

Camel excrement.