Revision as of 15:51, 25 February 2002 editConversion script (talk | contribs)10 editsm Automated conversion← Previous edit | Revision as of 02:28, 4 April 2002 edit undo209.4.253.25 (talk)No edit summaryNext edit → | ||
Line 66: | Line 66: | ||
workers, land rent, and machinery. The above logical | workers, land rent, and machinery. The above logical | ||
consequence of varying capital intensity has been the | consequence of varying capital intensity has been the | ||
main focus of economic analysis of Marxist economics. Indeed, Marx concluded that the |
main focus of economic analysis of Marxist economics. Indeed, Marx concluded that the distinction between value and price is central to ] economics. | ||
Marx thought that price phenomena created illusions | |||
that prevented others from noting the social relations | |||
Discussion | |||
properly analyzed in terms of value. | |||
of this |
Discussion of this distinction goes on under the rubric | ||
of the transformation problem, since it is about the | of the transformation problem, since it is about the | ||
"transformation" of labor values to prices. | "transformation" of labor values to prices. |
Revision as of 02:28, 4 April 2002
The labor theory of value is a theory in economics that the price of a commodity traded on a market tends toward the labor time required to produce that commodity. The labor theory of value is popularly associated with classical economics and Marxism. It is a theory of objective value, superseded in much of Western economics by the turn toward economic subjectivism associated with the development of neoclassical economics in the 1870s.
The labor needed to produce a commodity includes both labor directly expended on production of the commodity and labor expended on the production of capital goods used up in the production of the commodity. For example, if twenty workers are used for a year to produce capital goods used by twenty workers in the next year to produce a consumer good, the consumer good embodies the labor of forty workers.
This theory has political implications. In its original context, it was used to support the new notion of private-property. John Locke, in his Treatise on Government, asked by what right an individual can claim to own one part of the world, when according to the Bible God gave the world to all humanity. He answered that a person owns ones own labor, and that when a person labored -- even the mere lable of picking an apple off a tree -- that labor entered into the object, and so the object became property of that person. From this Locke and others further argued that commodities have value because of the labor invested in them.
As capitalism developed, this theory was used to support a very different political argument: that the role of owners in production is exploitative, since it is only the workers that add value to the product. The price of the product is said to tend towards the sum of the value of the capital goods used up in production and the value added by direct labor. But profit, interest, rent, etc. is only possible, according to the theory, if the wages of these direct workers do not fully compensate them for the value they add to the capital goods to produce the product.
The classical economists and Marx quickly realized that the price of a commoditiy does not tend to equal its value, as they conceived of it. Suppose the proportion of unpaid to paid labor time is the same for all workers. Further suppose that workers are paid when the product is sold. Technology will result in the ratio of direct labor to the value of capital goods differing among industries. If products were traded based on labor values, prices would result in different industries earning different rates of profits on the capital invested. But competition among industries should be modeled as tending to remove differences in profitability. Thus, the labor theory of value cannot be true. David Ricardo presented a numerical example of this reductio ad absurdum:
Suppose I employ twenty men at an expense of 1000 pounds for a year in the production of a commodity, and at the end of the year I employ twenty men again for another year, at a further expense of 1000 pounds in finishing or perfecting the same commodity, and that I bring it to market at the end of two years, if profits be 10 per cent., my commodity must sell for 2,310 pounds.; for I have employed 1000 pounds capital for one year, and 2,100 pounds capital for one year more. Another man employs precisely the same quantity of labour, but he employs it all in the first year; he employs forty men at an expense of 2000 pounds, and at the end of the first year he sells it with 10 per cent. profit, or for 2,200 pounds. Here then are two commodities having precisely the same quantity of labour bestowed on them, one of which sells for 2,310 pounds--the other for 2,200 pounds.
There are other difficulties with the labor theory of value associated with varying skills among heterogeneous workers, land rent, and machinery. The above logical consequence of varying capital intensity has been the main focus of economic analysis of Marxist economics. Indeed, Marx concluded that the distinction between value and price is central to capitalist economics. Marx thought that price phenomena created illusions that prevented others from noting the social relations properly analyzed in terms of value. Discussion of this distinction goes on under the rubric of the transformation problem, since it is about the "transformation" of labor values to prices.