Misplaced Pages

Superposition calculus: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 04:00, 19 January 2013 editWolfgang42 (talk | contribs)549 edits Disambiguated: theorem proverAutomated theorem prover← Previous edit Revision as of 02:38, 1 February 2013 edit undoRichardMills65 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users25,484 editsNo edit summaryNext edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
The '''superposition calculus''' is a calculus for ] in equational ]. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from ] with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) ]. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the ''unsatisfiability'' of a set of first-order ], i.e. it performs proofs by ]. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a ''fair'' derivation strategy, every ] clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable. The '''superposition calculus''' is a calculus for ] in equational ]. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from ] with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) ]. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the ''unsatisfiability'' of a set of first-order ], i.e. it performs proofs by ]. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a ''fair'' derivation strategy, every unsatisfiable (logic)|unsatisfiable clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable.


As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) ]s for ] are based on superposition (e.g. the ]), although only a few implement the pure calculus. As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) ]s for ] are based on superposition (e.g. the ]), although only a few implement the pure calculus.
Line 8: Line 8:
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * Waldmeister theorem prover|Waldmeister
* ] at * Ayane theorem prover|Ayane at


== References == == References ==

Revision as of 02:38, 1 February 2013

The superposition calculus is a calculus for reasoning in equational first-order logic. It has been developed in the early 1990s and combines concepts from first-order resolution with ordering-based equality handling as developed in the context of (unfailing) Knuth-Bendix completion. It can be seen as a generalization of either resolution (to equational logic) or unfailing completion (to full clausal logic). As most first-order calculi, superposition tries to show the unsatisfiability of a set of first-order clauses, i.e. it performs proofs by refutation. Superposition is refutation-complete — given unlimited resources and a fair derivation strategy, every unsatisfiable (logic)|unsatisfiable clause set can eventually be proved to be unsatisfiable.

As of 2007, most of the (state-of-the-art) theorem provers for first-order logic are based on superposition (e.g. the E equational theorem prover), although only a few implement the pure calculus.

Implementations

References

  • Rewrite-Based Equational Theorem Proving with Selection and Simplification, Leo Bachmair and Harald Ganzinger, Journal of Logic and Computation 3(4), 1994.
  • Paramodulation-Based Theorem Proving, Robert Nieuwenhuis and Alberto Rubio, Handbook of Automated Reasoning I(7), Elsevier Science and MIT Press, 2001.
Stub icon

This mathematical logic-related article is a stub. You can help Misplaced Pages by expanding it.

Categories: