Misplaced Pages

Johann Gottlieb Fichte: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 20:31, 31 May 2006 editMolobo (talk | contribs)13,968 editsm added category as shown by scholary research← Previous edit Revision as of 22:07, 31 May 2006 edit undoMatthead (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, Rollbackers21,271 edits rv to 71.137.207.222Next edit →
Line 21: Line 21:
}} }}


'''Johann Gottlieb Fichte''' (], ] – ], ]) was a ] philosopher. He is called by some the father of German nationalism and also of German ]. His significance in the ] relates to being one of the leading progenitors of ] ], forming a bridge between ] and the leading figure of ], ]. '''Johann Gottlieb Fichte''' (], ] – ], ]) was a ] philosopher, who has significance in the ] as one of the leading progenitors of ] ], forming a bridge between ] and the leading figure of ], ].


==Life and work== ==Life and work==
Line 36: Line 36:
Because of this necessity to have relations with other rational beings in order to achieve consciousness, Fichte writes that there must be a 'relation of right,' in which there is a mutual recognition of rationality by both parties. Because of this necessity to have relations with other rational beings in order to achieve consciousness, Fichte writes that there must be a 'relation of right,' in which there is a mutual recognition of rationality by both parties.


In 1806, in a ] occupied by ], Fichte gave a series of ''Addresses to the German Nation'' which became an incentive for ], and are one example of ]. Here, Fichte indirectly continues his anti-Semitic argumentation from his early works on religion and the ] and speaks of the alledged superiority of German people over others. In other earlier works he called Jews a "state within a state" that would "undermine" German nation. He openly expressed desire to ] Jews from Germany In 1806, in a ] occupied by ], Fichte gave a series of ''Addresses to the German Nation'' which became an incentive for ], and are one example of ]. Here, Fichte indirectly continues his anti-Semitic argumentation from his early works on religion and the ].
In regards to Jews getting rights he wrote that this would only be possible if one managed "to cut off all their heads in one night, and to set new ones on their shoulders, which should contain not a single Jewish idea".

Fichte also expressed severe dislike towards Poles and their culture, claiming they were "wild", "barbarian", "unclean" and "animalistic"


His son ] also made contributions to ]. His son ] also made contributions to ].
Line 82: Line 79:
] ]
] ]
]


] ]

Revision as of 22:07, 31 May 2006

Johann Gottlieb Fichte
Era18th-century philosophy
RegionWestern Philosophy
SchoolGerman Idealism
Main interestsOntology, Metaphysics, Epistemology
Notable ideasabsolute consciousness

Johann Gottlieb Fichte (May 19, 1762January 27, 1814) was a German philosopher, who has significance in the history of Western philosophy as one of the leading progenitors of German idealism, forming a bridge between Immanuel Kant and the leading figure of German Idealism, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel.

Life and work

Fichte was born in Rammenau, Saxony. In 1780, he attended the University of Jena as a student of theology. Fichte was originally a follower of Baruch Spinoza but later followed Kant's philosophy. His Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation was published anonymously in 1792 and scholars mistakenly thought the attempt was written by Kant himself. Kant cleared the confusion and openly praised the work, which greatly improved Fichte's reputation in the philosophical community.

Fichte did not endorse Kant's argument for the existence of noumena, of "things in themselves", the super-sensible reality beyond the categories of human reason. Fichte saw the rigorous and systematic separation of "things in themselves" (noumena) and things "as they appear to us" (phenomena) as an invitation to skepticism.

Rather than invite such skepticism, Fichte made the radical suggestion that we should throw out the notion of a noumenal world and instead accept the fact that consciousness does not have a grounding in a so-called "real world". In fact, Fichte achieved fame for originating the argument that consciousness is not grounded in anything outside of itself. This notion eventually became the defining characteristic of German Idealism and thus an essential underpinning to understanding the philosophies of Hegel, and of Arthur Schopenhauer, though they both reject Fichte's notion that human consciousness is itself sufficient ground for experience, and therefore postulate another "absolute" consciousness.

In his famous work Foundations of Natural Right (1796), Fichte stated that self-consciousness was a social phenomonon. Namely, he writes that self-consciousness depends upon resistance from objects in the external world. However, the mere perception of these external objects depends on self-consciousness. The solution to this paradox, Fichte thinks, is that a being gains consciousness when 'summoned' to be conscious by another rational being outside of oneself.

Fichte also used self-sufficiency idea for the state, make the goal of a “closed commercial state.” In his mind, State should control international relations, value of money and remain an autarky.

Because of this necessity to have relations with other rational beings in order to achieve consciousness, Fichte writes that there must be a 'relation of right,' in which there is a mutual recognition of rationality by both parties.

In 1806, in a Berlin occupied by Napoléon, Fichte gave a series of Addresses to the German Nation which became an incentive for German nationalism, and are one example of Romantic nationalism. Here, Fichte indirectly continues his anti-Semitic argumentation from his early works on religion and the French Revolution.

His son Immanuel Hermann Fichte also made contributions to philosophy.

Fichte died of typhus at the age of fifty-two.

Bibliography

Primary sources

  • Early Philosophical Writings
  • (1793) Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation (Versuch einer Kritik aller Offenbarung)
  • (1796) Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo)
  • (1798) The System of Ethics in accordance with the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre (Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre)
  • (1800) Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings
  • (1800) The Vocation of Man (Die Bestimmung des Menschen)
  • (1807-8) Addresses to the German Nation

Secondary Sources (English)

  • Arash Abizadeh. "Was Fichte an Ethnic Nationalist?" History of Political Thought 26.2 (2005): 334-359.
  • Daniel Breazeale. "Fichte's 'Aenesidemus' Review and the Transformation of German Idealism" The Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980/1) 545-68.
  • Daniel Breazeale and Thomas Rockmore (eds) Fichte: Historical Contexts/Contemporary Controversies. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1997.
  • Franks, Paul, All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and Skepticism in German Idealism, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2005
  • Dieter Henrich. "Fichte's Original Insight" Contemporary German Philosophy 1 (1982) 15-52.
  • T. P. Hohler. Imagination and Reflection: Intersubjectivity. Fichte's 'Grundlage' of 1794. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1982.
  • Wayne Martin. Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte's Jena Project. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997.
  • Frederick Neuhouser. Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  • Peter Suber. "A Case Study in Ad Hominem Arguments: Fichte's Science of Knowledge," Philosophy and Rhetoric, 23, 1 (1990) 12-42.
  • Robert R Williams. Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the Other. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992.
  • Gunther Zoller. Fichte's Transcendental Philosophy: The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

External links

Categories: