Misplaced Pages

Argumentation ethics: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 00:13, 11 August 2015 edit162.97.179.26 (talk)No edit summary← Previous edit Revision as of 12:41, 12 August 2015 edit undo162.97.179.26 (talk) getting rid of discussion of sources that are not notableTag: section blankingNext edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Libertarianism sidebar |expanded=Concepts}} {{Libertarianism sidebar |expanded=Concepts}}
'''Argumentation ethics''' is a libertarian political theory first described in 1988 by ], a Professor Emeritus with the ] College of Business and ] Senior Fellow.<ref name="hanshoppe">{{cite journal |last=Hoppe |first=Hans-Hermann |author2=Murray N. Rothbard|author3=David Friedman|author4=Leland Yeager|author5=David Gordon|author6=Douglas Rasmussen |title=Liberty Symposium |journal=Liberty |date=November 1988 |volume=2 |url=http://www.hanshoppe.com/wp-content/uploads/publications/liberty_symposium.pdf}}</ref> Hoppe says his theory proves that arguing for any political position other than ] is logically inconsistent. He describes his argument as a strictly logical, value-free consequence of sound deductive reasoning. Responses have come mainly from Hoppe's friends and colleagues at the Mises Institute, among whom the argument's reception has been mixed.<ref name="blog.mises">{{cite web|last=Kinsella|first=Stephan|title=Revisiting Argumentation Ethics|url=http://archive.mises.org/9610/revisiting-argumentation-ethics/|work=Mises Economics Blog|publisher=]|authorlink=Stephan Kinsella|date=March 13, 2009|quote= number of thinkers weighed in, including ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ...], and others....}}</ref> '''Argumentation ethics''' is a libertarian political theory first described in 1988 by ], a Professor Emeritus with the ] College of Business and ] Senior Fellow.<ref name="hanshoppe">{{cite journal |last=Hoppe |first=Hans-Hermann |author2=Murray N. Rothbard|author3=David Friedman|author4=Leland Yeager|author5=David Gordon|author6=Douglas Rasmussen |title=Liberty Symposium |journal=Liberty |date=November 1988 |volume=2 |url=http://www.hanshoppe.com/wp-content/uploads/publications/liberty_symposium.pdf}}</ref> Hoppe says his theory proves that arguing for any political position other than ] is logically inconsistent. He describes his argument as a strictly logical, value-free consequence of sound deductive reasoning. Responses have come mainly from Hoppe's friends and colleagues at the Mises Institute, among whom the argument's reception has been mixed.<ref name="blog.mises">{{cite web|last=Kinsella|first=Stephan|title=Revisiting Argumentation Ethics|url=http://archive.mises.org/9610/revisiting-argumentation-ethics/|work=Mises Economics Blog|publisher=]|authorlink=Stephan Kinsella|date=March 13, 2009|quote= number of thinkers weighed in, including ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ... ], ...], and others....}}</ref>

==Foundation==
Hoppe states that his theory is an ], ] ] argument for ] ] ].<ref name="hanshoppe" /> Argumentation ethics asserts the ] is a ] of every argument and so cannot be logically denied during an argument. Argumentation ethics draws on ideas from ]'s and ]'s ], from ] praxeology and from the ] of ].

Hoppe first notes that when two parties are in conflict with one another, they can choose to resolve the conflict by engaging in violence, or engaging in argumentation. In the event that they choose to engage in argumentation, Hoppe asserts that the parties have implicitly rejected violence as a way to resolve their conflict. He therefore concludes that non-violence is an underlying norm (]) of argumentation that is accepted by both parties.

Hoppe states that because both parties propound propositions in the course of argumentation, and because argumentation presupposes various norms including non-violence, the act of propounding a proposition that negates the presupposed propositions of argumentation is a logical contradiction between one's actions and one's words (this is called a ]). Specifically, to ''argue'' that violence should be used to resolve conflicts (instead of argumentation) is a performative contradiction.<ref name="hanshoppe2">{{cite journal |last=Hoppe |first=Hans-Hermann |title=The Ultimate Justification of Private Property |journal=Liberty |date=September 1988 |volume=1|page=20 |url=http://www.hanshoppe.com/wp-content/uploads/publications/hoppe_ult_just_liberty.pdf}}</ref>

==Non-aggression principle==
Argumentation ethics aims to show the non-aggression principle follows from the non-violence presupposition of argumentation, and so it cannot be denied.

If violence is not a norm that can be logically justified in argumentation as a way to resolve a conflict, Hoppe asks which norms can indeed be justified in argumentation.
Hoppe first argues that only ] norms are consistent with argumentation, as arbitrary categorical distinctions have no intersubjective ]. Hoppe then argues that since argumentation requires the active use of one's body, all universal norms for resolving conflicts over the human body aside from ] are inconsistent with argumentation.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe7.html |title=Rothbardian Ethics |first=Hans-Hermann |last=Hoppe|date=20 May 2002 |publisher=] |accessdate=6 February 2012}}</ref> Hoppe then argues that since the resolution of conflicts over external resources must also be objectively justifiable, only the physical establishment of an objective link by original ] (i.e., ]) is a norm compatible with argumentation. From these Hoppe concludes that only the non-aggression principle of self-ownership and ] homesteading can be justified in an argument without contradiction.<ref>. Hans Hoppe</ref>

==Punishment and self-defense==
Bearing reference to the ] of ], ]'s "Dialogical Estoppel" theory extends argumentation ethics by considering an argument between a victim and aggressor. Kinsella argues that an aggressor cannot consistently object to being proportionally punished for his act of aggression, by the victim or by the victim's representatives, because by committing aggression he commits himself to the proposition that the use of force is legitimate, and therefore, his withholding consent based on a normative right not to be physically harmed contradicts his aggressive legitimation of force, i.e. he is "estopped" from withholding consent.<ref>. N.S. Kinsella</ref>


==Responses from colleagues== ==Responses from colleagues==

Revision as of 12:41, 12 August 2015

Part of a series on
Libertarianism
Concepts
Issues
Philosophers
Politicians
National variants
Historical background
Related topics

Argumentation ethics is a libertarian political theory first described in 1988 by Hans-Hermann Hoppe, a Professor Emeritus with the University of Nevada, Las Vegas College of Business and Ludwig von Mises Institute Senior Fellow. Hoppe says his theory proves that arguing for any political position other than libertarian anarchism is logically inconsistent. He describes his argument as a strictly logical, value-free consequence of sound deductive reasoning. Responses have come mainly from Hoppe's friends and colleagues at the Mises Institute, among whom the argument's reception has been mixed.

Responses from colleagues

Various responses to Hoppe's argument came from Hoppe's colleagues at the Ludwig von Mises Institute. Some of them accepted his argument, among them attorney Kinsella and economists Walter Block and Murray Rothbard, who called it "a dazzling breakthrough for political philosophy in general and for libertarianism in particular," adding "he has managed to transcend the famous is/ought, fact/value dichotomy that has plagued philosophy since the days of the Scholastics..."

Mises Institute economists Bob Murphy and Gene Callahan rejected Hoppe's argument. The late Austrian Economist David Osterfeld, an adjunct scholar at the Mises Institute, also rejected Hoppe's argument in an essay to which Hoppe subsequently responded.

Ludwig Von Mises Institute Senior Fellow and Auburn University philosopher Roderick Long reconstructed the argument in deductively valid form, specifying four premises on whose truth the argument's soundness depends. Long goes on to argue that each premise is either uncertain, doubtful, or clearly false. He summarizes his views by stating:

I don’t think there’s any reason to reject out of hand the kind of argument that Hoppe tries to give; on the contrary, the idea that there might be some deep connection between libertarian rights and the requirements of rational discourse is one I find attractive and eminently plausible. But I am not convinced that the specific argument Hoppe gives us is successful.

See also

References

  1. Hoppe, Hans-Hermann; Murray N. Rothbard; David Friedman; Leland Yeager; David Gordon; Douglas Rasmussen (November 1988). "Liberty Symposium" (PDF). Liberty. 2.
  2. ^ Kinsella, Stephan (March 13, 2009). "Revisiting Argumentation Ethics". Mises Economics Blog. Ludwig von Mises Institute. number of thinkers weighed in, including Rothbard, ... Conway, ... D. Friedman, ... Machan, ... Lomasky, ... Yeager, ...Rasmussen, and others....
  3. Kinsella, Stephan (19 September 2002). "Defending Argumentation Ethics: Reply to Murphy & Callahan". Anti-State.com. Retrieved 9 February 2012.
  4. ^ Rothbard, Murray N. (November 1988). "Beyond Is and Ought". Mises.org. Retrieved 14 October 2012.
  5. Murphy, Robert P.; Callahan, Gene (Spring 2006). "Hans-Hermann Hoppe's Argumentation Ethics: A Critique" (PDF). Journal of Libertarian Studies. 20 (2): 53–6. Retrieved 9 February 2012.
  6. "Comment on Hoppe / Comment on Osterfeld" (PDF). Austrian Economics Newsletter. 1988. Retrieved 14 October 2012.
  7. Long, Roderick T. "The Hopperiori Argument".

Further reading

External links

Categories: