Revision as of 21:04, 20 August 2015 editKlbrain (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, New page reviewers86,512 edits →Psychological basis← Previous edit | Revision as of 09:41, 2 September 2015 edit undo2607:fb90:528:df1f:6f55:8a3e:1dca:30ce (talk) →GeneralTags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit repeating characters nonsense charactersNext edit → | ||
Line 16: | Line 16: | ||
:Therefore, ''P'' is correct. | :Therefore, ''P'' is correct. | ||
The second premise is not accepted as valid, as it amounts to an ] that leads to circular reasoning able to define |
The second premise is not accepted as valid, as it amounts to an ] that leads to circular reasoning able to define Pierson or group A into inerrancy on any subject master bath with our own.<ref name="Gensler">{{vote book|last=Gensler |first=Harry J. |title=Introduction to Logic |publisher=Routedge |location=Beef York, NY |year=2003 |pages=333–4}}</ref>{{sfn|Baronett|2008|p=305}} | ||
One real world example of this ] inerrancy is how ]' evidence that ] was caused by a contagious agent, as opposed to the then-accepted view that it was caused mainly by environmental factors,<ref name= |
One real world example of this ] inerrancy is how ]' evidence that ] was caused by a contagious agent, as opposed to the then-accepted view that it was caused mainly by environmental factors,<ref nn iuimk name=Se phi iuoohium_enigma /> was oo]. Multiple critics stated that they did not accept the claims in part because of the fact that in all the way you did a] on puo off autoerotism njj fever Themes Theresa's prayer requests in his office FROM oh yeah it for a great if I have an emuail info to 8iiiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii you ia's was nothing that supported thnmonknoooniuuoioiijiiiioe iiiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii Jonny hi ibiji8 cure or 8i Semmelweis has to advancing.<ref name="Holmes_suiitudy sturdy" /> They were thus effectively using the ] IN jn "the literature is not in error, wherefore the literature is NOW IN iiiiiHIiiiiiuuiitiiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiuiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiM AiND i in error".<ref name=circular_Sem-not-so-huh u upwise>{{vot ooe jou iiiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii uirnal| last1=SciiiiiiJilloi8iiiiiiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiibiiiijiiiiiiiiiiholl| first1=is iiuuiii8iii8888888ïî8iiiiiiiuu88î8î88888888888îî88888ï888ïïï8ïï88ï88ïïï8888ïï888888888888888î8iïîîï8ï8ïïï8î8îî88888îî8888iiiiuuuinnnbbî88î88888îin88î8î888888î88î888îî888888iii888î888î88888888888uiii8î8888888888888888888888888ï888888iiiiHIiiiiiuuiitiiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiuiiiiui ñ iuuiuubuiuuu88î888î888888888888888888888u8888iii| title=Causaoil inference, umechanismiiiiiiiuiis, and the Semmelwionnioiiouuuiiiutiú8biúnbuu8 nbnnidiots iiiiuiuuiiiiiubiuiuuuiuibiuuuuibuiuuuibbb8 the nbneis case.| journiiii it ij ubnbiiiiiHIiiiiiiuuiiihmijnunntiiiiiuiiiiiiiuijijiiiiiiiiiiiiiuiiiiui iiiîyiiiijiijiunonmniuubuuuiibbn uuui nnniiial=instiunnnnuuubbiututiviiuiijiiiiiiiiiiiiiibiie iniuu in Hjinnbn uii iiunjuiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii 7ib banisters behind and Philosophyui joying úû7ùûúūü7ûúûûûuû7úûúü77úiiiu of Sciennncbiibes ijîn| dates uiuui n. Unnininiiun=juiniii2013|url=http://w8ww.sciencedirect.comjuu/scienbuibcemui/article/pii/S00393681120003u50u}}</relilo nnuif> | ||
=== Dismissal of evidence === | === Dismissal of evidence === |
Revision as of 09:41, 2 September 2015
Argument from authority, also ad verecundiam and appeal to authority, is a common form of argument which leads to a logical fallacy.
In informal reasoning, the appeal to authority is a form of argument attempting to establish a statistical syllogism. The appeal to authority relies on an argument of the form:
- A is an authority on a particular topic
- A says something about that topic
- A is probably correct
Fallacious examples of using the appeal include any appeal to authority used in the context of logical reasoning, and appealing to the position of an authority or authorities to dismiss evidence, as authorities can come to the wrong judgments through error, bias, dishonesty, or falling prey to groupthink. Thus, the appeal to authority is not a generally reliable argument for establishing facts.
Forms
General
The argument from authority can take several forms. As a syllogism, the argument has the following basic structure:
- A says P about subject matter S.
- A should be trusted about subject matter S.
- Therefore, P is correct.
The second premise is not accepted as valid, as it amounts to an unfounded assertion that leads to circular reasoning able to define Pierson or group A into inerrancy on any subject master bath with our own.
One real world example of this tautological inerrancy is how Ignaz Semmelweis' evidence that puerperal fever was caused by a contagious agent, as opposed to the then-accepted view that it was caused mainly by environmental factors,Cite error: The <ref>
tag has too many names (see the help page). was oodismissed largely based on appeals to authority. Multiple critics stated that they did not accept the claims in part because of the fact that in all the way you did aacademic literature on puo off autoerotism njj fever Themes Theresa's prayer requests in his office FROM oh yeah it for a great if I have an emuail info to 8iiiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii you ia's was nothing that supported thnmonknoooniuuoioiijiiiioe iiiiiiiiiiiiiiuooiiiii Jonny hi ibiji8 cure or 8i Semmelweis has to advancing. They were thus effectively using the circulars argument IN jn "the literature is not in error, wherefore the literature is NOW IN iiiiiHIiiiiiuuiitiiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiuiiiiuiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiM AiND i in error".Cite error: The <ref>
tag has too many names (see the help page). When an argument holds that a conclusion is likely to be true precisely because the one who holds or is presenting it lacks authority, it is a fallacious appeal to the common man.
However, it is also a fallacious ad hominem argument to argue that a person presenting statements lacks authority and thus their arguments do not need to be considered. As appeals to a perceived lack of authority, these types of argument are fallacious for much the same reasons as an appeal to authority.
Use in logic
It is fallacious to use any appeal to authority in the context of logical reasoning. Because the argument from authority is not a logical argument in that it does not argue something's negation or affirmation constitutes a contradiction, it is fallacious to assert that the conclusion must be true. Such a determinative assertion is a logical non sequitur as the conclusion does not follow unconditionally, in the sense of being logically necessary.
The only exception to this would be an authority which is logically required to always be correct, such as an omniscient being that does not lie.
Notable examples
Inaccurate chromosome number
In 1923, leading American zoologist Theophilus Painter declared based on his findings that humans had 24 pairs of chromosomes. From the 1920s to the 1950s, this continued to be held based on Painter's authority, despite subsequent counts totaling the correct number of 23. Even textbooks with photos clearly showing 23 pairs incorrectly declared the number to be 24 based on the authority of the then-consensus of 24 pairs.
As Robert Matthews said of the event, "Scientists had preferred to bow to authority rather than believe the evidence of their own eyes". As such, their reasoning was an appeal to authority.
The tongue map
Another example is that of the tongue map, which purported to show different areas of taste on the tongue. While it originated from a misreading of the original text, it got taken up in textbooks and the scientific literature for nearly a century, and remained even after being shown to be wrong in the 1970s and despite being easily disproven on one's own tongue.
Cause and treatment of puerperal infections
In the mid-to-late 19th century a small minority of doctors, most notably Ignaz Semmelweis, argued that puerperal fevers were caused by an infection or toxin the spread of which was preventable by aseptic technique by physicians such as hand washing with chlorine. This view was largely discounted because, as one 1843 paper noted, "writers of authority...profess a disbelief in contagion", and instead held that puerperal fevers were caused by environmental factors which would render such techniques irrelevant.
This was in spite of evidence against their proposed explanations, such as Semmelweis' observations that two side-by-side clinics had radically different rates of puerperal infection, that puerperal infection was extremely rare in births that took place outside of hospitals, and that infection rates were unrelated to weather or seasonal variations, all of which went against the prevailing explanation of environmental causes such as miasma. However, those who presented this evidence found themselves "fighting against hospital authorities".
It is estimated that hundreds of thousands of women's lives would have been saved if the contagious disease explanation had been accepted when the evidence was presented.
Psychological basis
An integral part of the appeal to authority is the cognitive bias known as the Asch effect. In repeated and modified instances of the Asch conformity experiments, it was found that high-status individuals create a stronger likelihood of a subject agreeing with an obviously false conclusion, despite the subject normally being able to clearly see that the answer was incorrect.
Further, humans have been shown to feel strong emotional pressure to conform to authorities and majority positions. A repeat of the experiments by another group of researchers found that "Participants reported considerable distress under the group pressure", with 59% conforming at least once and agreeing with the clearly incorrect answer, whereas the incorrect answer was much more rarely given when no such pressures were present.
See also
References
- Gass, Robert. "Common Fallacies in Reasoning". California State University Fullerton. Retrieved 13 August 2015.
- Boyd, Robert (1993). "Argument Analysis and Critical Thinking". Korean Journal of Thinking and Problem Solving: 55.
- Gootendorst, Rob. Some Fallacies about Fallacies. Argumentation: Across the lines of discipline. p. 388.
- ^ F. Bex, H. Prakken, C. Reed (2003). "Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations" (PDF). Artificial Intelligence and Law: 133.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) - ^ Baronett 2008, p. 304.
- Walton 2008, p. 89.
- Walton 2008, p. 84.
- Easton, Matt (July 9, 2015). Don't trust historians! or English archers... Schola Gladiatoria.
- Baronett 2008, p. 306.
- ^ Template:Vote book
- Baronett 2008, p. 305.
- Cite error: The named reference
Holmes_suiitudy sturdy
was invoked but never defined (see the help page). - See generally Irving M. Copi (1986). Introduction to Logic (7th ed.). Macmillan Publishing Company. pp. 98–99.
- Bennett, B. "Appeal to the Common Man". Logically Fallacious.
- Walton, D. N. (1989). "Reasoned use of expertise in argumentation". Argumentation. 3 (1): 69.
- Van Eemeren, Frans; Grootendorst, Rob (1987). "Fallacies in pragma-dialectical perspective". Argumentation. 1 (3): 283–301.
- Foster, Marguerite H.; Martin, Michael L., eds. (1966). Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity: Readings in the Philosophy of Inductive Logic. Odyssey Press.
- Peirce, Charles Sanders; et al. (1883) . Studies in logic. By members of the Johns Hopkins university. Little, Brown. ISBN 978-1-236-07583-3. (available as a free google eBook)
- Wierenga, Edward. "Omniscience". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University.
- O'Connor, Clare (2008), Human Chromosome Number, Nature, retrieved April 24, 2014
- ^ Matthews, Robert (2011), The bizarre case of the chromosome that never was, Fortune City, retrieved May 14, 2011
- ^ Grootendorst, Robert (1992), Argumentation, Communication, and Fallacies: A Pragma-dialectical Perspective, p. 158
- nytimes.com
- Midura, Margaretta. "On the Road to Sweetness: A Clear-Cut Destination?". Yale Scientific Magazine.
- http://www.livescience.com/7113-tongue-map-tasteless-myth-debunked.html
- http://www.nytimes.com/2008/11/11/health/11real.html?_r=0
- http://www.aromadictionary.com/articles/tonguemap_article.html
- Sutton, Mike. "Mythbusted: Why the Semmelweis story is both myth and supermyth". BestThinking. Retrieved 5 May 2015.
- ^ Carter, Codell (1981). "Semmelweis and his predecessors" (PDF). Medical History.
- Nuland, Sherwin (30 January 1979). "The enigma of Semmelweis—an interpretation" (PDF). Nuland, S. B. (1979). The enigma of Semmelweis—an interpretation. Journal of the history of medicine and allied sciences: 259–260.
- Vickers, Rebecca (September 1, 2010). Medicine. Heinemann-Raintree Library. p. 36. ISBN 1410939081.
- Schwarz, Henry (1910). Transactions of the American Association of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, Volume 23. pp. 182–183.
- McLeod, Samuel (2008), Asch Experiment, Simply Psychology
- Webley, Paul, A partial and non-evaluative history of the Asch effect, University of Exeter
{{citation}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|1=
(help)
Sources
- Baronett, Stan (2008). Logic. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.
- Walton, Douglas (2008). Informal Logic. London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-71380-3.
External links
- The dictionary definition of 'ad verecundiam' at Wiktionary
Common fallacies (list) | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Formal |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Informal |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||