Misplaced Pages

Objectivism

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 72.199.110.160 (talk) at 01:31, 8 May 2009 (This cite and its contents should not be omitted. Rand's metaethics were her proudest/most disc. achievements. Yet, it's now GONE?! Omit ANYTHING else! Also, VITAL theory of volition gone? WARPED!). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Revision as of 01:31, 8 May 2009 by 72.199.110.160 (talk) (This cite and its contents should not be omitted. Rand's metaethics were her proudest/most disc. achievements. Yet, it's now GONE?! Omit ANYTHING else! Also, VITAL theory of volition gone? WARPED!)(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Objectivism is the philosophical system developed by the Russian-born American novelist, Ayn Rand (1905–1982). Objectivism holds that reality exists independent of consciousness; that individual persons are in contact with this reality through sensory perception; that human beings can gain objective knowledge from perception through the process of concept formation and inductive and deductive logic; that the proper moral purpose of one's life is the pursuit of one's own happiness or rational self-interest; that the only social system consistent with this morality is full respect for individual rights, embodied in pure laissez-faire capitalism; and that the role of art in human life is to transform man's widest metaphysical ideas, by selective reproduction of reality, into a physical form—a work of art—that he can comprehend and to which he can respond emotionally.

Rand originally expressed her philosophical ideas in her novels The Fountainhead, Atlas Shrugged, and other works. She further elaborated on them in The Objectivist Newsletter, The Objectivist, The Ayn Rand Letter, Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, The Virtue of Selfishness, and other non-fiction books.

The name 'Objectivism' derives from the principle that human knowledge and values are objective: they are not intrinsic to external reality, nor created by the thoughts one has, but are determined by the nature of reality, to be discovered by man's mind. Rand chose the name because her preferred term for a philosophy based on the primacy of existence, Existentialism, had already been taken.


Objectivist Principles

My philosophy, in essence, is the concept of man as a heroic being, with his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life, with productive achievement as his noblest activity, and reason as his only absolute.

— Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged 35th anniversary edition

Ayn Rand characterized Objectivism as "a philosophy for living on earth," grounded in reality, and aimed at defining man's nature and the nature of the world in which he lives.


Metaphysics: objective reality

Rand's philosophy is based on three axioms: the Axiom of Existence, the Axiom of Identity, and the Axiom of Consciousness. Rand defined an axiom as "a statement that identifies the base of knowledge and of any further statement pertaining to that knowledge, a statement necessarily contained in all others whether any particular speaker chooses to identify it or not. An axiom is a proposition that defeats its opponents by the fact that they have to accept it and use it in the process of any attempt to deny it." As Leonard Peikoff noted, being perceptually self-evident, Rand's argumentation "is not a proof that the axioms of existence, consciousness, and identity are true. It is proof that they are axioms, that they are at the base of knowledge and thus inescapable."

Objectivism states that "Existence exists" (the Axiom of Existence) and "Existence is Identity." To be is to be "an entity of a specific nature made of specific attributes." That which has no attributes does not and cannot exist. Hence, the Axiom of Identity: a thing is what it is. Whereas "existence exists" pertains to existence itself (whether something exists or not), the law of identity pertains to the nature of an object as being necessarily distinct from other objects (whether something exists as this or that). As Rand wrote, "A leaf cannot be all red and green at the same time, it cannot freeze and burn at the same time. A is A."

Rand held that when one is able to perceive something, then one's "consciousness exists" (the Axiom of Consciousness), consciousness "being the faculty of perceiving that which exists." Objectivism maintains that what exists does not exist because one thinks it exists; it simply exists, regardless of anyone's awareness, knowledge or opinion. For Rand, consciousness is an inherently relational phenomenon, as she puts it, "to be conscious is to be conscious of something," so that an objective reality independent of consciousness must exist first for consciousness to become possible, and there is no possibility of a consciousness that is conscious of nothing outside itself. Thus consciousness cannot be the only thing that exists. "It cannot be aware only of itself — there is no 'itself' until it is aware of something." Objectivism holds that the mind cannot create reality, but rather, it is a means of discovering reality.

Objectivist philosophy derives its explanations of action and causation from the Axiom of Identity, calling causation "the law of identity applied to action." According to Rand, it is entities that act, and every action is the action of an entity. The way entities act is caused by the specific nature (or "identity") of those entities; if they were different they would act differently.

Epistemology: reason

Objectivist epistemology, like most other philosophical branches of Objectivism, was first presented by Rand in Atlas Shrugged. It is more fully developed in Rand's 1967 Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. The starting point of Objectivist epistemology is the principle, presented by Rand as a direct consequence of the metaphysical axiom that "Existence is Identity," that Knowledge is Identification.

Objectivism rejects philosophical skepticism and states that only by the method of reason can man gain knowledge (identification of the facts of reality). Objectivism also rejects faith and "feeling" as means of attaining knowledge. She defined "reason" as "the faculty that identifies and integrates the material provided by man's senses." Although Rand acknowledged the importance of emotion in humans, she maintained that emotion was a consequence of the conscious or subconscious ideas one already holds, not a means of achieving awareness of reality.

Rand held that there is no "causeless knowledge," and on this basis argued against any form of mysticism, which she defined as "the acceptance of allegations without evidence or proof, either apart from or against the evidence of one's senses and reason." She continues, "Mysticism is the claim to some non-sensory, non-rational, non-definable, non-identifiable means of knowledge, such as 'instinct,' 'intuition,' 'revelation,' or any form of 'just knowing.'" According to Rand, to reach "knowledge" beyond what is given in sense-perception requires both volitional effort and adherence to a specific methodology of observation, concept-formation, and both inductive and deductive logic. A belief in "dragons" or "elves," however sincere, does not oblige reality to contain "dragons" or "elves," and a process of "proof" establishing the basis in reality of any claimed item of knowledge (if it cannot be directly observed) is a prerequisite to establising its truth. On similar grounds, Rand rejected the arguments traditionally made by epistemological skeptics who argue against the possibility of knowledge "undistorted" by the form or the means of perception.

According to Rand, like anything else, consciousness—any consciousness—possesses a specific identity and operates by a specific method. Rather than disqualifying an item of knowledge, awareness by a specific process and in a specific form is inherent in objective knowledge.

the attack on man's consciousness and particularly on his conceptual faculty has rested on the unchallenged premise that any knowledge acquired by a process of consciousness is necessarily subjective and cannot correspond to the facts of reality, since it is "processed knowledge. . . . All knowledge is processed knowledge--whether on the sensory, perceptual or conceptual level. An "unprocessed" knowledge would be a knowledge acquired without means of cognition.

Kant's arguments to the contrary, according to Rand, amount to saying: "man is limited to a consciousness of a specific nature, which perceives by specific means and no others; therefore, his consciousness is not valid; man is blind because he has eyes––deaf because he has ears––deluded because he has a mind––and the things he perceives do not exist because he perceives them." For Rand, consciousness, like anything that exists, must possess identity, and its operation requires a causal means of adhering to reality, such as logic. Unlike logic, mystical revelation, Tarot Cards, or any other equivalent of a Ouija board, simply bypass the requirement of demonstrating how it connects its results to reality, and such "methods," according to Rand are not a "short-cut" to knowledge at all, but a "short-circuit" destroying knowledge. By the same token, that consciousness has an identity, far from disqualifying its product, only grounds it in reality, and the skeptics' claim would invalidate the operation of any consciousness, whatever the means and form it utilized.

To defend and explain her position on reason, she developed a theory of sense-perception that distinguishes between the form and the object of perception, holding that the form in which an organism perceives is determined by its physiological means of perception but that in whatever form it perceives, what it perceives—the object of its perception—is reality. She rejected the Kantian dichotomy between "things as we perceive them" and "things as they are in themselves." The validity of the senses, she held, is axiomatic: sense-perception, being physiologically determined, cannot make "mistakes" or err in responding to the facts of reality. Apparent errors, such as in "optical illusions", she regarded as errors in the conceptual identification of what is seen, not in the seeing itself.

Simple sensations are not the basis of man's knowledge. Sensations are integrated as perceptions, and it is only at the level of perceptions that the foundation of epistemology lies.

Perhaps Ayn Rand's most distinctive and original contribution in epistemology is her theory of concept-formation, presented in her Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. She observed fundamental links between concepts and mathematics and held that concepts are properly formed by a process of measurement omission. Rand uses "measurement" here in the broad sense of comparing any quantitative or qualitative relationship, even such things as the intensity of love, not just physical measurements such as mass, time, or distance.

According to Objectivism, concepts 'represent classifications of observed existents according to their relationships to other observed existents.' To form a concept, one mentally isolates a group of concretes (of distinct perceptual units), on the basis of observed similarities which distinguish them from all other known concretes (similarity is 'the relationship between two or more existents which possess the same characteristic(s), but in different measure or degree'); then, by a process of omitting the particular measurements of these concretes, one integrates them into a single new mental unit: the concept, which subsumes all concretes of this kind (a potentially unlimited number). The integration is completed and retained by the selection of a perceptual symbol (a word) to designate it. 'A concept is a mental integration of two or more units possessing the same distinguishing characteristic(s), with their particular measurements omitted.'"

"...the term 'measurements omitted' does not mean, in this context, that measurements are regarded as non-existent; it means that measurements exist, but are not specified. That measurements must exist is an essential part of the process. The principle is: the relevant measurements must exist in some quantity, but may exist in any quantity."

Rand did not consider the analytic-synthetic distinction to have merit. She similarly denied the existence of a priori knowledge. Rand also considered her ideas distinct from foundationalism, naive realism, or representationalism (i.e., an indirect realist who believes in a "veil of perception") like Descartes or John Locke. An admirer of Aristotle's achievements in logic and epistemology, she titled the three parts of Atlas Shrugged ("A is A," "Non-Contradiction," and "Either/Or") in tribute to him.. The title sections appear to refer to three laws of logic: the law of identity, the law of non-contradiction and the law of excluded middle. In regard to inductive logic, she held that her theory of concepts would provide the basis for a new approach to validating inductive generalization, and Leonard Peikoff has attempted this development.

Ethics: rational self-interest

Rand's rational egoism, her advocacy of "rational selfishness," is perhaps her most well-known position. Although Rand sometimes referred to Objectivist ethics as "selfishness," as reflected in the title of her primary book on ethics, The Virtue of Selfishness, she did not use that term with the negative connotations that it usually has.

To live, man must hold three things as the supreme and ruling values of his life: Reason, Purpose, Self-esteem.

Selfishness is not to be confused with hedonism. A whim-worshipper or "hedonist," according to Rand, is not motivated by a desire to live his own human life, but by a wish to live on a sub-human level. Instead of using "that which promotes my (human) life" as his standard of value, he mistakes "that which I (mindlessly happen to) value" for a standard of value, in contradiction of the fact that, existentially, he is a human and therefore rational organism. The "I value" in whim-worship or hedonism can be replaced with "we value," "he values," "they value," or "God values," and still it would remain dissociated from reality. Rand repudiated the equation of rational selfishness with hedonistic or whim-worshipping "selfishness-without-a-self." She held that the former is good, and the latter evil, and that there is a fundamental difference between them.

In The Virtue of Selfishness she attempted to derive ethical egoism from first principles. Value is relative: something can only be valuable for a particular being, and it can only be valuable if that being has a choice. Only living things are able to choose, therefore values only exist for living things, and whatever a living thing acts to gain or keep is a value for that thing. Every living thing maintains its life for its own sake, and - according to Rand - for any living thing, only its own life is valuable for its own sake . On the assumption that every living thing should do or ought to do whatever is valuable for itself, it follows that it should do whatever promotes its own life. But people can only live if they are rational. Since reason is man's means of knowledge, it is also his greatest value, and its exercise his greatest virtue. "Man's mind is his basic tool of survival. Life is given to him, survival is not. His body is given to him, its sustenance is not. His mind is given to him, its content is not. To remain alive he must act and before he can act he must know the nature and purpose of his action. He cannot obtain his food without knowledge of food and of the way to obtain it. He cannot dig a ditch––or build a cyclotron––without a knowledge of his aim and the means to achieve it. To remain alive, he must think.". Therefore everyone ought to be rational.

Ayn Rand also claimed that in humans, who are conscious organisms, the motivation to pursue life is experienced as the pursuit of a conscious state—the pursuit of happiness. Indeed, in her one-sentence summary of Objectivism, Ayn Rand condensed her ethics into the statement that man properly lives "with his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life." According to Objectivist epistemology states of mind, such as happiness, are not primary; they are the consequence of specific facts of existence. Therefore man needs an objective, principled standard, grounded in the facts of reality, to guide him in the pursuit of this purpose. Rand regarded happiness as a biological faculty evolved from the pleasure-pain mechanism of pre-human animals. This faculty functions as an instrument providing a continuous measurement of how successful one is at meeting the challenge of life. As she wrote in The Virtue of Selfishness (23, pb 27)

Just as the pleasure-pain mechanism of man's body is an automatic indicator of his body's welfare or injury, a barometer of its basic alternative, life or death—so the emotional mechanism of man's consciousness is geared to perform the same function, as a barometer that registers the same alternative by means of two basic emotions: joy or suffering.

Rand defined a value as "that which one acts to gain and/or keep." The rational individual's choice of values to pursue is guided by his need, if he chooses to live, to act so as to maintain and promote his own life. Therefore, Rand did not hold that values proper to human life are "intrinsic" in the sense of being independent of one's choices, or that there are values that an individual must pursue by command or imperative ("reason accepts no commandments"). Neither did Rand consider proper values "subjective," to be pursued just because one has chosen, perhaps arbitrarily, to pursue them. Rather, Rand held that valid values are "objective," in the sense of being identifiable as serving to preserve and enhance one's life, writing, that "the 'good' is an aspect of reality in relation to man." Some values are specific to the nature of each individual, but there are also universal human values, including the preservation of one's own individual rights, which Rand defined as "conditions of existence required by man's nature for his proper survival."

Politics: individual rights and capitalism

Part of a series on
Individualism
Principles
Philosophers
Ideologies
Principal concerns

Objectivist politics begins with ethics: the question of if, and if so why, a rational agent needs a set of principles for living his life. The proper answer to ethics tells a rational individual how to preserve his individual rights while interacting with, benefiting from cooperation with, and trading with other individuals in society. That is, it determines the principles which constitute a moral social system.

Rand's defense of individual liberty integrates elements from her entire philosophy. Since reason is the competent but sole means of human knowledge, it is therefore humanity's most fundamental means of survival. Also, thus, the effort of thinking and the scrupulous use of reason are the most basic virtue of an ethics governed by the requirements of human life. The threat of coercion, however, neutralizes the practical effect of an individual's reason, and whether the force originates from the state or from a criminal, the coerced person must act as required, or, at least, direct his thought to escape. According to Rand, "man's mind will not function at the point of a gun." To put this conversely: freedom "works" because it liberates human reason. Just as freedom of expression is a prerequisite for a vibrant culture, and the development of science and art, so a free market generates new and ever better products and services, as the range of consumer goods and technological innovations in capitalist societies demonstrates, according to Rand. Thus, she argued for the "separation of state and economics in the same way and for the same reasons" as she argued for "the separation of state and church."

Reason being a capacity of the individual, creative innovation, by its nature, requires the individual to have the freedom to do things differently, to disagree, to buck the trend or consensus, if necessary. According to Rand, therefore, the only type of organized human behavior consistent with the operation of reason is one of voluntary cooperation. Persuasion is the method of reason, a faculty which demands reality be the ultimate arbiter of disputes among men. By its nature, the overtly irrational cannot rely on the use of persuasion, cannot permit the facts to decide differences, and must ultimately resort to force in order to prevail as means of coordinating human behavior. Thus, Rand saw reason and freedom as correlates––just as she saw mysticism and force as correlates.

Since reason is "man's basic tool of survival," Rand held that an individual has a natural moral right to act as the judgment of his or her own mind directs and to keep the product of this effort. In Rand's view, this requires that the initiation of physical force and the acquisition of property by fraud be banned. She agreed with America's Founding Fathers that the sole legitimate function of government is the protection of individual rights, including property rights. The purpose of objective criminal and civil law is to protect the individual from coercion by others, while the purpose of a constitution and Bill of Rights is to protect the individual from coercion by the State (historically the greatest violator of individual rights, in Rand's estimation). Government may use force, that is its essence, but to do so legitimately it must never act as the aggressor––it may use force only in response to initiation of force, e.g. theft, murder, foreign aggression. Rand did not believe that a free society, one in which all interaction was thus rendered voluntary, would make anyone rational, as rationality cannot be compelled and is an exclusive capacity of the individual. Nonetheless, freedom does allow those who are rational and productive to achieve at their highest capacity.

As a result, Objectivism holds that the individual possesses inalienable Rights: life, liberty, property, and the pursuit of one's own happiness. "Rights are moral principles defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context" . Government is the institution with a monopoly on the use of physical force in a given geographical area, so the issue is whether that force is to be used to protect or to violate individual rights—i.e., whether the government uses force only in retaliation or whether it initiates force against innocent citizens. Under laissez-faire Capitalism, the government is restricted to using retaliatory force, to protect individual rights—which means the only proper functions of the government are "the police, to protect men from criminals; the military forces, to protect men from foreign invaders; and the law courts, to protect men's property and contracts from breach by force or fraud, and to settle disputes among men according to objectively defined laws."

Objectivism holds that the rights of other human beings are not of direct moral import to the agent who respects them; they acquire their moral purchase through an intermediate step. An Objectivist respects the rights of other human beings out of the recognition of the value to himself or herself of living in a world in which the freedom of action of other rational (or potentially rational) human beings is respected. One's respect for the rights of others is founded on the objective value, to oneself, of other persons as actual or potential partners in cooperation and trade. According to Rand, the enormous benefits of vastly increased knowledge and wealth are possible in an organized society, but only one in which rights are protected.

Objectivism holds that the only social system which fully recognizes individual rights is Capitalism—as Rand understood it:

When I say "capitalism", I mean a full, pure, uncontrolled, unregulated laissez-faire capitalism...

Rand includes Socialism, Fascism, Communism, Nazism, and the Welfare State, as systems under which individual rights, including private property rights, are not legally protected. "To deny property rights means to turn men into property owned by the state. Whoever claims the 'right' to 'redistribute' the wealth produced by others is claiming the 'right' to treat human beings as chattel."

As Rand was an advocate of free market capitalism, she rejected many "conservative" positions on philosophical grounds. Rand strongly advocated legal abortion. She also opposed involuntary military conscription, the "draft," and she opposed any form of censorship, including legal restrictions on pornography. Rand opposed racism, and any legal application of racism, and she considered affirmative action to be an example of legal racism.

Rand also strongly opposed the nascent Environmentalist Movement of the 1960s as being hostile to technology and, therefore, to humanity itself––and thus leading America towards "a new Dark Age."

Far from regarding capitalism as a dog-eat-dog pattern of social organization, Objectivism regards it as a beneficent system in which the innovations of the most creative benefit everyone else in the society (although that is not its justification). Indeed, Objectivism values creative achievement itself and regards capitalism as the only kind of society in which it can flourish.

Aesthetics: metaphysical value-judgements

See also: Romantic realism

The Objectivist theory of art flows from its epistemology, by way of "psycho-epistemology" (Rand's term for an individual's characteristic mode of functioning in acquiring knowledge). Art, according to Objectivism, serves a human cognitive need: it allows human beings to grasp concepts as though they were percepts. Objectivism defines "art" as a "selective re-creation of reality according to an artist's metaphysical value-judgments"—that is, according to what the artist believes to be ultimately true and important about the nature of reality and humanity. In this respect Objectivism regards art as a way of presenting abstractions concretely, in perceptual form.

The human need for art, on this view, stems from the need for cognitive economy. A concept is already a sort of mental shorthand standing for a large number of concretes, allowing a human being to think indirectly or implicitly of many more such concretes than can be held explicitly in mind. But a human being cannot hold indefinitely many concepts explicitly in mind either—and yet, on the Objectivist view, needs a comprehensive conceptual framework in order to provide guidance in life. Art offers a way out of this dilemma by providing a perceptual, easily grasped means of communicating and thinking about a wide range of abstractions, including one's metaphysical value-judgments. Objectivism regards art as an effective way to communicate a moral or ethical ideal.

Objectivism does not, however, regard art as propagandistic: even though art involves moral values and ideals, its purpose is not to educate, only to show or project. Moreover, art need not be, and usually is not, the outcome of a full-blown, explicit philosophy. Usually it stems from an artist's sense of life (which is preconceptual and largely emotional).

Rand held that Romanticism was the highest school of literary art, noting that Romanticism was "based on the recognition of the principle that man possesses the faculty of volition," absent which, Rand believed, literature is robbed of dramatic power.

What the Romanticists brought to art was the primacy of values… Values are the source of emotions: a great deal of emotional intensity was projected in the work of the Romanticists and in the reactions of their audiences, as well as a great deal of color, imagination, originality, excitement, and all the other consequences of a value-oriented view of life.

The term "romanticism", however, is often affiliated with emotionalism, to which Objectivism is completely opposed. Historically, many romantic artists were philosophically subjectivist. Most Objectivists who are also artists subscribe to what they call romantic realism, which is how Ayn Rand labeled her own work.

Intellectual impact

Main article: Objectivist movement
The Fountainhead Cafe, a coffee shop in New York City inspired by Objectivism. The sign reads "Eat Objectively, Live Rich".

According to Rick Karlin, academic philosophers have generally dismissed Rand's ideas and have marginalized her philosophy. Online U.S. News and World Report columnist Sara Dabney Tisdale called Atlas Shrugged "sophomoric," "preachy," and "unoriginal." Because of Rand's criticism of contemporary intellectuals, Objectivism has been called "fiercely anti-academic." David Sidorsky, a professor of moral and political philosophy at Columbia University, says Rand's work is "outside the mainstream" and is more of an ideological movement than a well-grounded philosophy.

In the essay "On the Randian Argument" by Harvard University philosopher Robert Nozick, which appears in his collection, Socratic Puzzles (1997). Nozick is sympathetic to Rand's political conclusions, but does not think her arguments justify them. In particular, his essay criticizes her foundational argument in ethics, stating that to make her argument - that one's own life is, for each individual, the ultimate value - sound, one needs to explain why someone could not rationally prefer dying and thus having no values. Thus, he argues, her attempt to defend the morality of selfishness is essentially an instance of begging the question. Nozick also argues that Rand's solution to David Hume's famous is-ought problem is unsatisfactory (as do others). Professors Douglas Rasumussen and Douglas Den Uyl contend Nozick's article itself had misstated Rand's case.

In recent years Rand's works are more likely to be encountered in the classroom than in decades past. The Ayn Rand Society, dedicated to fostering the scholarly study of Objectivism, is affiliated with the American Philosophical Association's Eastern Division. Since 1999, several monographs were published and a refereed Journal of Ayn Rand Studies began. In 2006 the University of Pittsburgh held a conference focusing on Objectivism. In addition, two Objectivist philosophers (Tara Smith and James Lennox) hold tenured positions at two of the fifteen leading American philosophy departments. Objectivist programs and fellowships have been supported at the University of Pittsburgh University of Texas at Austin and University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill.

Rand is not found in the comprehensive academic reference texts The Oxford Companion to Philosophy or The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. A lengthy article on Rand appears in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy; she has an entry in the Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers and one forthcoming in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, as well as a brief entry in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy which features the following passage:

The influence of Rand’s ideas was strongest among college students in the USA but attracted little attention from academic philosophers. … Rand’s political theory is of little interest. Its unremitting hostility towards the state and taxation sits inconsistently with a rejection of anarchism, and her attempts to resolve the difficulty are ill-thought out and unsystematic.

Noted Aristotle scholar Allan Gotthelf (chairman of the Ayn Rand Society) responded unfavorably to this entry and came to her defense. He and other scholars have argued for more academic study of Objectivism, viewing Rand's philosophy as a unique and intellectually interesting defense of classical liberalism that is worth debating.

Criticisms

William F. Buckley, Jr. called her philosophy "stillborn." Raymond Boisvert, a philosophy professor at Siena College, has opined that Rand's theories are out of sync with the complex interrelationships and interconnected systems of modern life. Chris Matthew Sciabarra, however, in Ayn Rand; the Russian Radical, attempts to show that Rand eschewed dualistic oversimplification and embraced multi-dimensional analyses.

Psychologists Albert Ellis and Nathaniel Branden have argued that adherence to Objectivism can result in hazardous psychological effects. Following Rand's expulsion of him from her circle, Branden accused Rand and her followers of "destructive moralism," something he reports having engaged in himself when he was associated with Rand, but which he now claims "subtly encourages repression, self-alienation, and guilt." Since the publication of Rand's private journal entries regarding Branden, it has been shown that Rand herself had been warning Branden against such "moralism," "repression," "self-alienation" and "guilt," in very similar language to that now used by Branden.

Monographs and essays

Main article: Bibliography of work on Objectivism

Prominent Objectivist Leonard Peikoff, published Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand (E. P. Dutton), a comprehensive survey of Ayn Rand's philosophy. Objectivism is central to Ronald Merrill's introductory monograph The Ideas of Ayn Rand (Open Court Publishing), as it is to Chris Matthew Sciabarra's Ayn Rand: the Russian Radical (1995, Pennsylvania State University Press). Other survey works on Rand's philosophy include: Objectivism in One Lesson by Andrew Bernstein, Ph.D., (2009, Hamilton), Ayn Rand by Tibor Machan, Ph.D., (2000, Peter Lang) and On Ayn Rand by Allan Gotthelf, Ph.D., (1999, Wadsworth Philosophers Series).

Monographs on specific aspects of Objectivism include: The Evidence of the Senses (1986, Louisiana State University Press) and A Theory of Abstraction (2001, The Objectivist Center Press) by David Kelley; The Psychology of Self Esteem by Nathaniel Branden (1969, Nash); The Biological Basis of Teleological Concepts (1990, The Ayn Rand Institute Press) by Harry Binswanger; Viable Values (2000, Rowman & Littlefield), Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: the Virtuous Egoist (2006, Cambridge University Press) and Moral Rights and Political Freedom (1995, Open Court Publishing) by Tara Smith; The Capitalist Manifesto, by Andrew Bernstein (2005, University Press of America); What Art Is: the Esthetic Theory of Ayn Rand (2000, Open Court Publishing) by Louis Torres and Michelle Marder Kamhi; The Other Side of Racism (1981, Ohio State University Press) by Anne Wortham; and Ayn Rand's Atlas Shrugged: A Philosophical and Literary Companion (2007, Ashgate) by Edward Younkins.

The comprehensive Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics by George Reisman (1996), attempts to integrate Objectivist methodology and insights with both Classical and Austrian economics.

A series of essay collections on the philosophical and literary dimensions of Rand's novels, edited by Robert Mayhew, have been published: Essays on Ayn Rand's We the Living (2004), Essays on Ayn Rand's Anthem (2005), Essays on Ayn Rand's The Fountainhead (2006), Essays on Ayn Rand's Atlas Shrugged (2009) (Lexington Books).

References

  1. So identified by sources including:
    Hicks, Stephen. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2006), s.v. "Ayn Rand" Retrieved June 22, 2006.
    Smith, Tara. Review of "On Ayn Rand." The Review of Metaphysics 54, no. 3 (2001): 654–655. Retrieved from ProQuest Research Library.
    Encyclopædia Britannica (2006), s.v. "Rand, Ayn." Retrieved June 22, 2006, from Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
    One source notes: "Perhaps because she so eschewed academic philosophy, and because her works are rightly considered to be works of literature, Objectivist philosophy is regularly omitted from academic philosophy. Yet throughout literary academia, Ayn Rand is considered a philosopher. Her works merit consideration as works of philosophy in their own right." (Jenny Heyl, 1995, as cited in Mimi R Gladstein, Chris Matthew Sciabarra(eds), ed. (1999). Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand. Penn State Press. ISBN 0-271-01831-3. {{cite book}}: |editor= has generic name (help), p. 17)Rand, Ayn. Introducing Objectivism, in Peikoff, Leonard, ed. The Voice of Reason: Essays in Objectivist Thought. Meridian, New York 1990 (1962.)
  2. Rubin, Harriet (2007-09-15). "Ayn Rand's Literature of Capitalism". The New York Times. Retrieved 2007-09-18.
  3. Rand, Ayn. "What Is Capitalism?". Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. p. 23.
  4. ^ Peikoff, Leonard (1993). Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand. Meridian. ISBN 978-0452011014.
  5. ^ Rand, Ayn (1996). Atlas Shrugged (35th Anniv edition). Signet Book. ISBN 0451191145.
  6. Rubin, Harriet (2007-09-15). "Ayn Rand's Literature of Capitalism". The New York Times. Retrieved 2007-09-18.
  7. Gotthelf, Allan (2000). On Ayn Rand. Wadsworth.
  8. ^ Rand, Ayn (1990). Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. Meridian. ISBN 0-452-01030-6.
  9. Rand, Aym, "The Objectivist Ethics," The Virtue of Selfishness, New American Library, 1964.
  10. Rand, Ayn, "Faith and Force: the Destroyers of the Modern World," Philosophy Who Needs It, Bobbs-Merrill, 1982, p.75.
  11. Smith, George, Atheism: the Case Against God, Prometheus, 1989, first pub. 1979, essentially explicates the Objectivist position on religious belief.
  12. Rand, Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, Meridian, 1979, p. 81.
  13. Rand, For the New Intellectual, Random House, 1961, p. 31.
  14. Rand, For the New Intellectual, Random House, 1961, p. 223; Peikoff, Leonard, Objectivism: the Philosophy of Ayn Rand, Dutton, 1991, pp. 182-185.
  15. 'Peikoff, Leonard, “The Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy,” Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, 131
  16. Rand, Ayn (1990). Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. Meridian; for more on Rand's theory of concepts see also Kelley, David "A Theory of Abstraction" and "The Psychology of Abstraction," Cognition & Brain Theory vol. vii, no. 3 and 4 (Summer/Fall 1984), and Rasmussen, Douglas, “Quine and Aristotelian Essentialism,” The New Scholasticism 58 (Summer, 1984)
  17. Peikoff, Leonard, "The Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy," in Peikoff and Binswanger, edits., Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, expanded second edition, New American Library, 1990, pp. 88-121.
  18. Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged, "About the Author"
  19. Peter A. Angeles Dictionary of Philosophy, p. 167, Harper Collins, 1992 ISBN 0-06-461026-8
  20. Peikoff, Leonard, Objectivism: the Philosophy of Ayn Rand, pp. 73-109 and pp. 136-7, A Dutton Book, 1991 ISBN 0-525-93380-8 ; Peikoff, Leonard, Objectivism Through Induction (lecture series) Accessed April 4, 2009; as of 2008, Peikoff is writing a book called The DIM Hypothesis, where he defines what he sees as the three approaches to integration in human thought and applies the hypothesis to physics, philosophy, education, politics and other fields. He estimates that it "will be published in several years, probably in 2010." Leonard Peikoff's official website. Accessed March 2, 2008.
  21. ^ Rand, Ayn, The Virtue of Selfishness. Signet Book, 1964.
  22. 'The Virtue of Selfishness, (New York: Signet, 1961), pp 15-16
  23. ibidem p.17
  24. ibidem p. 23
  25. Rand, Atlas Shrugged, "This is John Galt Speaking."
  26. Rand, Ayn, "Philosophy: Who Needs It", Philosophy: Who Needs It.
  27. For Rand's metaethics, see Harry Binswanger, The Biological Basis of Teleological Concepts, The Ayn Rand Institute Press, 1995, and Tara Smith, Viable Values, Rowman & Littlefield, 2000.
  28. Rand, Ayn, Capitalism: the Unknown Ideal, "Let Us Alone!", p. 141.
  29. Rand, Ayn, The Virtue of Selfishness, "The Objectivist Ethics," p.37; see also, Bernstein, Andrew, Objectivisim in One Lesson, Hamilton Books, 2009.
  30. Rand, Ayn, "Faith and Force: the Destroyers of the Modern World," lecture delivered at Yale University on February 17, 1960, at Brooklyn College on April 4, 1960, and at Columbia University on May 5, 1960, reprinted in Philosophy: Who Needs It, as chapter 7, Bobbs-Merrill, 1982, pp. 58-76 .
  31. Rand, Ayn, The Virtue of Selfishness, New American Library, 1964, chapter 12, "Man's Rights", and chapter 14, "The Nature of Government"; see also, Locke, Edwin, The Prime Movers: Traits of the Great Wealth Creators, AMACOM, 2004.
  32. Rand's understanding of the nature of individual rights is defended in Tara Smith, Moral Rights and Political Freedom, Open Court 1997; see also D. Rasmussen and D. Den Uyl, Liberty and Nature, Open Court, 1991.
  33. Rand, Ayn. Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. p. 73.
  34. A good example is provided in Peikoff, Leonard, Podcast (retrieved 4-10-09), Episode 41: 10:25 - 11:37 "Q: Am I morally obligated to call for help if I see someone in a car accident or experiencing a heart attack?" "Peikoff: This is obviously from someone who does not know what the Objectivist view of selfishness is. Absolutely yes, you are morally obligated. If you have chosen to live in a society of human beings and your mode of survival depends on your trade with them then you have to value human life so far as it's not guilty or criminal to your knowledge. In that case if you know no evil about a person and no sacrifice is involved then only a psychopath would turn away from such cases. And that would mean besides all the psychological things a direct contradiction of the value of human life. You can't value your life and decide to live with others of your species and say, 'They're nothing to me, I don't care if they live or die.' That's self-contradiction."
  35. Rand, Ayn. "What Is Capitalism?". Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal.
  36. Peikoff, Leonard, The Ominous Parallels, Stein & Day, 1982.
  37. http://www.aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/socialism.html
  38. Rand, Ayn, "Of Living Death," reprinted in Peikoff, L., edit., The Voice of Reason: Essays in Objectivist Thought, New American Library, 1988, chapter 8; and see "Ayn Rand," Playboy Interview, Vol II, Golson, G. Barry, edit., Perigee, 1983, p. 17 (March 1964).
  39. Rand, Ayn, "The Wreckage of the Consensus," Capitalism: the Unknown Ideal, New American Library, 1966; and "Ayn Rand," Playboy Interview, Vol II, Golson, G. Barry, edit., Perigee, 1983, p. 23 (March 1964).
  40. Rand, Ayn, "Censorship: Local and Express," reprinted in Philosophy: Who Needs It, Bobbs-Merrill, 1982, pp. 211-231.
  41. Rand, Ayn (1999). "Racism". Return of the primitive: the anti-industrial revolution. Australia: Meridian. p. 182. ISBN 0-452-01184-1. ; see also, Wortham, Anne, The Other Side of Racism, Ohio State University Press, 1981.
  42. Rand, Ayn, "The Anti-Industrial Revolution," reprinted in The Return of the Primitive, Schwartz, P., edit., Meridian, 1999, pp. 270-290.
  43. Rand, Ayn, Capitalism: the Unknown Ideal, edit., (New American LIbrary, 1966); see also Bernstein, Andrew, The Capitalist Manifesto, University Press of America, 2005, and Reisman, George, Capitalism: a Treatise on Economics, Jameson Books, 1996.
  44. Rand, Ayn, "What is Romanticism?," The Romantic Manifesto
  45. See also, Thomas, William, edit., The Literary Art of Ayn Rand, The Objectivist Center, 2005. ISBN 1-57724-070-7, Holzer, Erika, Ayn Rand: My Fiction Writing Teacher, Madison Press, 2005, and Torres, Louis, and Kamhi, Michelle Marder, What Art Is: the Esthetic Theory of Ayn Rand, Open Court, 2000.
  46. Karlin, Rick (August 26 1994), "Ayn Rand Followers Push on Objectivists Reflect the Philosophy Found in 'The Fountainhead'", The Times Union (Albany, NY), pp. p. C1 {{citation}}: |pages= has extra text (help); Check date values in: |date= (help)CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  47. ^ Tisdale, Sara Dabney (August 13 2007), "A Celebration of Self", U.S. News & World Report, pp. p. 72 {{citation}}: |pages= has extra text (help); Check date values in: |date= (help)CS1 maint: date and year (link).
  48. For Rand's severe critique of the 20th century's "intellectual bankruptcy," and what she believed led to it, see Rand, Ayn, For the Intellectual, title essay, Random House, 1961; however, Rand did give qualified endorsement of the work of certain contemporary thinkers, e.g., Aristotle, by John Herman Randall and Reason and Analysis by Brand Blanshard.
  49. ^ McLemee, Scott (1999). "The Heirs Of Ayn Rand: Has Objectivism Gone Subjective?". Retrieved 2007-07-20. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  50. Harvey, Benjamin (2005-05-15). "Ayn Rand at 100: An 'ism' struts its stuff". Rutland Herald. Retrieved 2007-07-20.
  51. Nozick, Robert, "On the Randian Argument," in Socratic Puzzles, Harvard University Press, 1997, pp. 249-264
  52. David Friedman: Some Problems with Rand's Derivation of Ought from Is.
  53. Patrick O'Neill Rand and the Is-Ought Problem
  54. see "Nozick on the Randian Argument," The Personalist, Spring 1978, reprinted along with Nozick's article in Reading Nozick, J. Paul, ed., 1981, Rowman & Littlefield.
  55. "Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association – Eastern Division Program" (PDF). 2006. Retrieved 2007-07-25.
  56. Sharlet, Jeff (1999-04-09). "Ayn Rand has finally caught the attention of scholars: New books and research projects involve philosophy, political theory, literary criticism, and feminism". The Chronicle of Higher Education. 45 (31): 17–18.
  57. "Concepts and Objectivity: Knowledge, Science, and Values" (PDF). Retrieved 2007-07-20.
  58. Philosophy departments of the United States, ranked by the Philosophical Gourmet Report,
  59. http://www.pittmag.pitt.edu/summer2004/cornerstones.html
  60. New fellowship for study of objectivism established at The University of Texas at Austin | The University of Texas at Austin
  61. Carolina Development, UNC-Chapel Hill
  62. "Ayn Rand at the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". 2006. Retrieved 2007-07-20.
  63. Salmieri, Gregory (2005). "Ayn Rand". In John Shook (ed.). The Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers. London: Thoemmes Continuum. ISBN 1843710374. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  64. "Table of Contents". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2008-06-15.
  65. Ayn Rand Society
  66. "The Entry on Ayn Rand in the new Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2007-07-20., Error in Webarchive template: Empty url.
  67. Uyl, Douglas J. Den (1998). "On Rand as philosopher" (PDF). Reason Papers. 23: 70–71. Retrieved 2007-07-20.
  68. (Pennsylvania State Univ. Press, 1995).
  69. Ellis, Albert. Is Objectivism a Religion? Lyle Stuart, New York 1968.
  70. ^ Branden, Nathaniel. "The Benefits and Hazards of the Philosophy of Ayn Rand". Journal of Humanistic Psychology. 24 (4): 39–64. Retrieved 2008-04-08.
  71. Valliant, James S., The Passion of Ayn Rand's Critics (Durban House, 2005).

See also

External links

Ayn Rand
Bibliography
Novels
Nonfiction books
Collected essays
Screenplays
Stage plays
Other writings
Characters
Adaptations
Screen
Stage
Philosophy
Influence
Depictions
Philosophy
Branches
Branches
Aesthetics
Epistemology
Ethics
Free will
Metaphysics
Mind
Normativity
Ontology
Reality
By era
By era
Ancient
Chinese
Greco-Roman
Indian
Persian
Medieval
East Asian
European
Indian
Islamic
Jewish
Modern
People
Contemporary
Analytic
Continental
Miscellaneous
  • By region
By region
African
Eastern
Middle Eastern
Western
Miscellaneous
Categories: