This is an old revision of this page, as edited by That Guy, From That Show! (talk | contribs) at 10:44, 13 April 2006 (typo fixes - spelling/grammar ( you can help! )). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.
Revision as of 10:44, 13 April 2006 by That Guy, From That Show! (talk | contribs) (typo fixes - spelling/grammar ( you can help! ))(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)You must add a |reason=
parameter to this Cleanup template – replace it with {{Cleanup|January 2006|reason=<Fill reason here>}}
, or remove the Cleanup template.
The neutrality of this article is disputed. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page. Please do not remove this message until conditions to do so are met. (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
The argument from morality is one of several arguments for the existence of God. This argument comes in different forms, all aiming to prove God’s existence from the evidence of morality in the world.
The argument
The moral argument works on the idea that most people have some experience of morality, and feel there are certain rules about how they should behave.
Divine Command
- Moral law requires a moral lawgiver.
- There is a moral law.
- There must be a moral lawgiver. (from 1 and 2)
- This moral lawgiver is God.
The two premises must, of course, be defended separately. However, usually this argument is employed with those (the great majority of the human population) who already subscribe to the second premise. Thus, the first premise is the more oft-debated. That the moral lawgiver is God must also be justified, but so with most arguments for God's existence must the proven entity be shown to be God as regularly understood (e.g., that Aquinas' prime mover is the God of the Bible). This is not, however, a circular argument.
Another argument from morality can be expressed as follows:
- If God exists, then God and God alone decides what is (truly) right and wrong. Without God there could be no ultimate standards of morality.
- So, if people assumed that God does not exist, then they would be doomed to a life without fixed moral standards. They would have no reasons to think that lying, stealing, or even murder are wrong. According to this view, nonbelievers contribute to the corruption of themselves and the entire culture. (Cf the famous quote associated with Dostoevsky, "If God does not exist, everything is permitted".)
- Given the above, it is necessary that God exists if society is to have stable standards of morality.
- Everyone in society either obviously needs or already has stable standards of morality. Therefore, God exists.
That is the basis of theological ethics, or alternatively, the divine command theory. The argument is valid if and only if the following assumptions are correct:
- There is an ultimate standard of morality.
- People are able to know God's commands, and the sources of such knowledge are infallible.
- Something is right if and only if God commands it; something is wrong if and only if God forbids it; and something is morally permissible if and only if God neither commands nor forbids it.
- God's standards are stable; God's commands are as valid today as they were when the infallible sources of information were created.
- There is no alternative source of moral and ethical ideas and action, meaning that all other systems such as utilitarianism are invalid; that is to say, even if they ultimately endorse the same morals they are wrong about what it is that makes those things moral.
A third variant of the argument from morality is based on the existence of standards, and the existence of conscience in humans. In any argument, various standards are appealed to, and only unreasonable arguers would make claims like "I am right because I think I am." If no standard really exists, then no justice system can ever be objectively just, and all justice systems would be shams, which is assumed to be untrue. Therefore, it is argued that the standards of moral good exists external from ourselves, and are not arbitrary. Since such standards exist, so must God.
Pointing towards God
This form of the moral argument interprets morality as an indirect religious experience which points towards God.
- Our feelings of obligation guide us to make a moral decision.
- This obligation is due to the fact that each person has value, and this supports each decision.
- If people have an intrinsic value, there must be a source to this value.
- This source must be God.
Kant's argument
Immanuel Kant believed that in a perfect world behaving morally should lead to happiness. However, as this rarely happens in our world, he considered that there must be another answer. He argued that there are certain rational laws which we feel duty bound to follow, and these he called categorical imperatives. He concluded that if this is true, we can assume three things:
- Free will – We must have the free will to act
- Immortality – happiness will eventually reward us (in the afterlife)
- God – there is a regulating being that will reward virtue with happiness.
His argument is thus:
- If it is our unconditional duty to follow these moral laws, it must be our unconditional duty to aim for the goal of these laws, and so we seek to bring about the highest good.
- Humans do not have enough power to bring about the highest good. Even with perfect morality, we cannot ensure the perfect happiness that should follow.
- However, if we aim for the highest good, it must be possible to achieve it. If we are unable to attain this goal in our present life, there must be someone else to ensure we can attain it in a future life.
- God has this necessary power, therefore we can assume the existence of God.
Kant believes that this does not prove the existence of God, but our sense of morality implies the world is ordered in a moral way.
Criticisms
Logical flaws
The most common attack on the logic of this argument is by the conclusion (4), which is an assumption. Objections point out that there is no reason to assume that God is the moral lawgiver; or that if he exists, he should be the only moral lawmaker. Such an assumption requires knowledge of the existence of God (which is what the argument is trying to prove) and of the character of God (which is disputed).
Indeed, there is no reason to suppose (or given by the argument) why morality is objective, or that people themselves are not the moral lawgivers. Morality can easily be explained as a social contract which everybody agrees to for the purpose of maximising survival - if everybody acted as they wished, most people would invariably end up committing selfish acts (eg. to gain power and possessions) at the expense of others; eventually nobody would live. Some people might unconditionally wish not to do harm, other people might wish not to do harm to prevent harm from being done to themselves. However, the result of a social contract being formed is the same.
Formal formulation
- Humankind's core motivations are greed and a fear of the wrath of God.
- Greed is defined as wanting things that benefit oneself, possibly at the expense of others, and avoiding things that cause detriment to oneself, possibly at the expense of others.
- Greed causes people to want to experience as little suffering as possible since suffering is unpleasant.
- Morality is defined as a set of rules that one should follow to prevent suffering.
- Assume morality can only come from fear of God's wrath.
- Then a world devoid of God would have no morality. (by 5)
- Since greed is the only remaining motivation, people will engage in immoral behavior in order to satisfy their greed. (by 1, 2, 6)
- This causes a state of nature.
- Due to greed, humankind is eventually motivated to lessen the overall suffering of humanity (and thus its individuals) by preventing a state of nature. (by 1, 3)
- Governments of some sort are established to further this goal. (by 9)
- Governments create and enforce a social contract. (by 10)
- This contract is a form of morality. (by 4, 9)
- But this contradicts assumption 5 and logical consequence 6.
- Therefore assumption 5 is incorrect, thus morality doesn't only come from a fear of God's wrath.
Another criticism of the existence of standards variant, in addition to the argument for using man as the moral lawgiver, is that it equates the "ultimate standard" and God, and that this is an example of equivocation.
Contrary evidence
Many argue this argument makes the prediction that since God is the source of morality, then someone who believes that (and behaves as if) God does not exist, i. e. a nonbeliever, should generally behave less morally than a believer. Therefore, the argument goes, nonbelievers should perform immoral actions more frequently than believers.
Some of these immoral actions fall under the category of secular crime in most legislations around the world (such as homicide, rape and theft); others are punished in some but considered private actions in others (homosexual intercourse, drug consumption); other are considered immoral by certain religions (such as divorce).
The prediction has been found to fail in the following cases:
- In the United States, a 1999 poll by the Barna Research Group showed that in fact certain religious groups, such as Jews, Mainline Protestants, and Evangelical Christians, get divorced more often than atheists.
- If prison statistics in the USA are reliable, religious people are imprisoned by at least 40 times the rate of atheists.
- Believers have been responsible for countless historical atrocities, including (but not limited to) the Crusades and the September 11 attacks. While atheists have also been responsible for some atrocities, such as the Soviet gulag camps of Joseph Stalin or the genocide of the Khmer Rouge, they are not primarily motivated by their religious beliefs.
Statistics for other measures of morality provide similar results.
However, many advocates of the moral argument deny that the prediction is valid, arguing that believers who don't act morally are not correctly interpreting God's morality, and that non-believers who do act morally may still believe in morality, but only not see it as connected to God. The former defence (relating to incorrect interpretation) arguably falls victim to the "No True Scotsman" fallacy.
Responses and counter-responses
Response: Many theists, or believers, will argue that the prediction stated above does not logically stem from its premises, i.e., that (4) is a non-sequitur. Thus, from this point of view, the "contrary evidence" would in essence be evidence against a straw man.
Christians, for example, argue that The Absolute Moral Law is written in our consciences, those of both believers and non-believers (Romans 2:15). It would then follow that the morals accepted by both believers and non-believers are essentially the same. Therefore we would logically expect their behavior to be essentially the same as well. The theist making this argument would claim that that is exactly what we see throughout history and even in modern societies today.
Response: The prediction claimed above assumes that because believers believe, they will always (or usually) act on this belief. Many Christians will state that this is contrary to well-established Christian doctrine, that all are sinners (Romans 3:23, 1 John 1:8), including Christians. Simply believing in a god of some sort does not necessarily enable anyone to behave more righteously than anyone else.
Response: When assessing the above tests and "morality measures" in the prediction, some issues must be taken into account:
- How terms such as "religious", "nonreligious", "atheist", "agnostic", "believer", "nonbeliever", etc. are defined, if at all.
- Whether the tests assume that there are no factors correlated with religiosity or belief that may influence the measurement.
- Whether the statistics have taken into account the religious demographics of the U.S. namely that the 'religious' far outnumber the atheists, which could account for the above results.
- Whether society prosecutes and punishes the "correct" crimes (are laws moral? are the police, the judicial system, etc. biased towards believers or nonbelievers?).
- Whether there is such a thing as a "right" crime, or whether it's all relativistic.
The last point may be raised by some believers as an objection. It is entirely possible that those who make the laws are failing to conform with the "correct" moral standards (for example, most modern societies do not punish divorce or homosexual behaviour, which most believers consider to be morally wrong).
Response: Many theists may posit that certain societies, such as that of the United States, have been so molded by believers, that the modern individual morals of atheists are often molded by the historic values of the believers in that society. Thus, the behaviors of the two would be very similar in most circumstances.
Counter-response: While this may be so in some cases, there is nothing to suggest that this is always the case (i.e., the argument is not universal or objective). Indeed, there are counterexamples, for example in Ancient China where there was no structured concept of God, yet it had a highly advanced moral and legal system for its time.
Response: Another viewpoint to consider is that if God is not responsible for morality, then moral values are simply social constructs (or memes) created by a certain individual or group to abridge the behavior of another group to benefit themselves or others like themselves. (For example, a mother who has been abandoned by her partner may teach her sons not to cheat on their wives to spare other women from her pain, which eventually leads to the concepts of monogamy and chastity.) In this way, morality originates as a principle of self-preservation. But as it is propagated, it is ingrained into the younger generation and colours their conception of morality. The logical conclusion to this viewpoint is that the morals of a society are ultimately subjective (even though certain morals are quite ubiquitous, suggesting a common psychological prompt), so nothing is objectively wrong.
A possible reason that certain morals are so ubiquitous in otherwise divergent societies, is to be found in evolutionary theory. If consider that a society may be susceptible to natural selection, we can determine that certain moral behaviors, when practiced by a majority of a population, will give an advantage to those societies that practice them over those that do not (see Evolutionary psychology, Game theory, Evolutionarily Stable Strategy, etc). Thus, rather than having a divine source, morality simply consists of a consensus behavior that benefits the population as a whole.
External links
- Moral Arguments at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Moral Argument by C. S. Lewis
- Atheist morality
- Barna Research Poll Results