In Greek mythology, Ate (Ancient Greek: Ἄτη, romanized: Átē, lit. 'Delusion, Recklessness, Folly, Ruin') is the personification of moral blindness and error. She could blind the mind of both gods and men leading them astray. Ate was banished from Olympus by Zeus for blinding him to Hera's trickery denying Heracles his birthright. Homer calls Ate the daughter of Zeus, while Hesiod has Ate as the daughter of Eris (Strife).
Personification
Like all the children of Eris (Strife), Ate is a personified abstraction, allegorizing the meaning of her name, and represents one of the many harms which might be thought to result from discord and strife. The meaning of her name, the Greek word atē (ἄτη), is difficult to define. Atē is a verbal noun of the verb aáō (ἀάω). According to The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, aáō means to "lead astray", "befuddle", "blind", or "delude", while ἄτη can mean: (1) the state of "delusion, infatuation (inflicted on a person's mind by a god, esp Zeus)", (2) "reckless behavior ... recklessness, folly", and (3) "ruin, calamity, harm". As informed by the meanings and usage of the unpersonified atē, personified Ate can apparently represent any part (or all?) of the causal sequence: (1) a blinding or clouding of the mind—causing (2) ill-considered and reckless actions—causing (3) the ruin such actions entail. She is thought of as being the instigator of delusion and its resulting destruction.
Mythology
Beyond being a mere personification, Ate has little actual identity. In the Iliad, Agamemnon, the leader of Greek expedition against Troy, tells the story of Ate's deception of Zeus, and her subsequent banishment from Olympus, an etiological myth supposedly explaining how Ate entered the world of men. As told by Agamemnon, Hera tricked Zeus into swearing an oath that resulted in Zeus' son Heracles losing the birthright Zeus had intended for him. Zeus blamed Ate for clouding his mind causing him not to see Hera's deception. In great anger Zeus grabbed Ate by the hair and flung her from Mount Olympus, and thereby Ate came to inhabit the "fields of men". According to the mythographer Apollodorus, when Ate was thrown down by Zeus, Ate landed in Phrygia at a place called "the hill of the Phrygian Ate", where the city of Troy was founded. The Hellenistic poet Lycophron, in his Alexandra, also mentions the place calling it "the high Hill of Doom ".
Family
Homer's Iliad calls Ate the eldest daughter of Zeus, with no mother mentioned. However, Hesiod's Theogony has Ate as one of the several children of Eris (Strife), with no father mentioned. Her syblings include (among several others) her brothers Horkos (Oath), and the Machai (Wars), and sisters Limos (Famine), and Dysnomia (Lawlessness). Aeschylus, in his tragedy Agamemnon, has the Chorus call Peitho "the unendurable child of scheming Ruin ".
Zeus
Ate is closely associated with Zeus. In the Iliad, Ate is called the "eldest" daughter of Zeus, an apparent indication of her power and her importance to Zeus. Ate (or the impersonal atē) is often referred to as the agent (or instrument) of Zeus' divine retribution. In the Iliad, Zeus is begged to send Ate so that the denier of "Prayers ... may fall and pay full recompense." Although Agamemnon blames Ate for blinding him (which led to his dishonoring Achilles), he also says that it was Zeus (via Ate?) who robbed him of his senses. According to Hesiod, Zeus never sends war, nor famine, nor "calamity " to those who honor Justice, while Solon says that "Zeus sends to punish" men.
Ate also appears as an agent of Zeus' justice in Aeschylus's tragic trilogy the Oresteia. In Agamemnon, the first play of the trilogy, Ate is linked with Helen of Troy, and Agamemnon's wife Clytemnestra, both of whom act as agents of Zeus' retribution. Helen, who plays an instrumental role in Zeus' punishment of Troy, is likened to a "priest" of Ate, while Clytemnestra, who, by killing Agamemnon, is the direct instrument of Zeus' punishment, says that she did so with the aid of "Ruin ". In the Libation Bearers, the second play of the Oresteia, Aeschylus describes Zeus as one who sends Ate to avenge "reckless human violence!"
Ancient Greek sources
Personified Ate occurs several times in Greek literature, from the Archaic through the Classical periods.
Homer
In Homer, atē is something inflicted by the gods; it causes delusion, then folly, then disaster. Ate, as the personification of atē, receives its fullest development in Homer's Iliad, his epic poem about the Trojan War. However, to what extent Homer may have considered Ate to be an actual divinity as opposed to a mere allegory is unclear. The references to the goddess in the Iliad revolve around Agamemnon's folly in having robbed Achilles, the Greeks greatest warrior, of his war prize, the slave Briseis, and Achilles' subsequent refusal to fight, which brought the Greeks to the brink of defeat. While the concept of atē is a central theme in the Iliad, occurring many times, Ate, as the personification of atē, is explicitly found in just two speeches, one in Book 9, and the other in Book 19.
Allegory of the Prayers
During the embassy to Achilles in Book 9, Achilles' old tutor Phoenix, trying to persuade Achilles to accept Agamemnon's offer of reparations, and return to battle, tells the following parable in which the "fleet of foot" Ate ("Blindness") outruns "halting" Prayers:
For Prayers there are as well, the daughters of great Zeus, halting and wrinkled and of eyes askance, and they are ever mindful to follow in the steps of Blindness. But Blindness is strong and fleet of foot, so she far outruns them all, and goes before them over all the earth making men to fall, and Prayers follow after, seeking to heal the hurt. Now him who will respect the daughters of Zeus, when they draw near, him they greatly benefit, and hear him when he prays; but if a man denies them and stubbornly refuses, then they go and beg Zeus, son of Cronos, that Blindness may follow that man so that he may fall and pay full recompense.
— Homer, Iliad 9.502–512; translation by A.T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt
In this allegory, Ate appears twice. First Ate causes damage to human beings. Then Prayers follow after Ate to repair her damage. But if the repair offered by Prayers is rejected (in this case if Achilles rejects Agamemnon's appeal) then Ate appears again as the punishment for such rejections. Ate both runs in front of Prayers, and when Prayers are refused, Ate also follows close behind. These two appearances can also be seen as examples of the Homeric Ate's dual role, as both cause and effect. Here Ate is both the cause of the original offense (Agamemnon's insult to Achilles), and the disastrous consequences which would (and will) follow from Achilles' refusal of Agamemnon's attempt to make amends.
Agamemnon's apology
In Book 19, Agamemnon attempts to excuse himself for having taken Briseis from Achilles, by blaming the "accursed" Ate (among others) for blinding his mind:
It is not I who am at fault, but Zeus and Fate and Erinys, that walks in darkness, since in the place of assembly they cast on my mind fierce blindness on that day when on my own authority I took from Achilles his prize. But what could I do? It is a god that brings all things to their end. Eldest daughter of Zeus is Ate who blinds all— accursed one; delicate are her feet, for it is not the ground that she touches, but she walks over the heads of men, bringing men to harm, and this one or that she ensnares.
— Homer, Iliad 19.86–94; translation by A.T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt
Phoenix's speech in Book 9 and Agamemnon's in Book 19 reveal different aspects of Ate's nature. The first emphasizes Ate's strength and speed, and her use by Zeus to punish (in this case, those who disregard Prayers). The second describes Ate's soft feet, walking not on the ground, but above the "heads of men", where, apparently unnoticed, she brings "men to harm".
To further excuse his conduct, Agamemnon tells the story—as an illustration of Ate's great power—of how:
once even blinded Zeus, though men say that he is the greatest among men and gods;
— Homer, Iliad 19.95–96; translation by A.T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt
According to Agamemnon, when Alcmene was about to give birth to Zeus's son Heracles, Zeus, in his great pride, boasted that on that day would be born a man, of Zeus's blood, who would be king of the Argives. But Hera tricked Zeus into swearing an unbreakable oath such that whatever man, of Zeus's blood, born that day would be king. Then Hera delayed the birth of Heracles, and caused Eurystheus, the great grandson of Zeus, to be born prematurely, and thus Heracles lost the birthright Zeus had intended for him. Zeus (like Agamemnon) blamed Ate for blinding him to Hera's trickery. As punishment, an enraged Zeus:
seized Ate by her bright-tressed head, angered in his mind, and swore a mighty oath that never again to Olympus and the starry heaven should Ate come, who blinds all. So said he, and whirling her in his hand flung her from the starry heaven, and quickly she came to the tilled fields of men. At thought of her would he ever groan when he saw his dear son in disgraceful toil at Eurystheus’ tasks.
— Homer, Iliad 19.126–133; translation by A.T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt
Hesiod
Hesiod presented Ate as one of the several offspring of Eris, all of whom were personifications representing some of the many harms which can arise out of discord and strife. Hesiod particular associates Ate with her sister Dysnomia (Lawlessness). While listing the children of Eris, he lists both on the same line (230) of his Theogony and says they are "much like one another".
In a passage in his Works and Days (213–285), Hesiod describes various relationships between several personifications, including Ate. The passage, which discusses the superiority of Dike (Justice) over Hybris, also mentions Eirene (Peace), who attends those who "heed" Dike (228), and Ate's brother Horkos (Oath), who "runs along side crooked judgements" (219). In particular Hesiod associates Ate with "war", which might refer to Ate's brothers, the Machai (Wars), and her sister Limos (Famine) as all being punishments for those who "foster" Hybris:
give heed to Justice and do not foster Outrageousness ... far-seeing Zeus never marks out painful war; nor does famine attend straight-judging men, nor calamity , but they share out in festivities the fruits of the labors they care for.
— Hesiod, Works and Days 213–231; translation by Glenn W. Most
Aeschylus
Among the tragic poets, the use of atē and (thus) Ate is somewhat different than it is in the Iliad. In both Homer and tragedy, atē can be used to mean the original delusion as well as the resulting destruction. However, while Homer was more focused on the former, tragedy became more focused on the latter. In tragedy, atē came to be less associated with internal damage: a damaged mind, and more with external damage: ruin, disaster, destruction. Here, Ate can be seen as an avenger of evil actions and a just punisher of evil actors, similar to Nemesis and the Erinyes (Furies).
Ate was particularly prominent in the plays of Aeschylus, and less so in the later tragedians such as Euripides, where the idea of Dike (Justice) becomes more fully developed. Personified Ate appears several times in Aeschylus' tragedy Agamemnon, where she is called "scheming", and made the mother of an "unendurable child", the "miserable" Peitho (Temptation). Aeschylus also associates Ate with divine retribution: Zeus' punishment inflicted on Troy for Paris's abduction of Helen. In a long speech about Helen, the Chorus likens her to a lion cub raised as a loved and loving pet which ends up savagely killing those who raised it, the cub (and by extension Helen) being reared, by divine intent, as a "priest" of Ate. The Chorus goes on to describe Ate as:
the deity with whom none can war or fight,
— Aeschylus, Agamemnon 769–771; translation by Alan H. Sommerstein
the unholy arrogance
of Ruin , black for the house
In the final scene of the play, Clytemnestra, with bloody sword and clothes, emerges from the palace to reveal that she has killed her husband Agamemnon, in retribution for his having killed their daughter Iphigenia. She describes her act as the "Justice" due for the killing of Iphigenia, and that she was aided by "Ruin" and "Fury" .
In Aeschylus's Libation Bearers, Ate is explicitly said to be the agent of Zeus' justice:
Zeus, Zeus, who sends up from below
— Aeschylus, Libation Bearers, 382–385; translation by Alan H. Sommerstein
avenging ruin soon or late,
against audacious, reckless
human violence!
Ate also occurs twice in Aeschylus' Persians. At the beginning of the play, the Chorus of Persian elders voice their foreboding on their war with Greece:
But what mortal man can escape
— Aeschylus, Persians 93–101; translation by Alan H. Sommerstein
the guileful deception of a god?
...
For Ruin begins by fawning on a man in a friendly way
and leads him astray into her net,
from which it is impossible for a mortal to escape and flee.
Ate here represents both cause and effect. She begins by deceiving and misleading mortals, and ends by the mortals being caught in her inescapable net. While, at the end of the play, Aeschylus returns to his typical focus of Ate as disastrous consequence, having the Chorus lament their devastating defeat: "What an evil eye Ruin has cast upon us!"
At the end of the battle in Aeschylus's Seven Against Thebes, Ate's "trophy" stands at the gate of Thebes where both of Orestes' sons have died killing each other in battle, representing the final victory of the "powers of destruction" over the cursed House of Laius.
Other
There are several other references to Ate in ancient Greek sources. A fragment attributed to one of the two lyric poets of early sixth-century Lesbos: Sappho or Alcaeus, refers to Ate as "insatiable". A fragment of the fifth-century BC philosopher Empedocles refers to the "meadow of Ate", which probably signifies the mortal world. The fifth-century BC Greek epic poet Panyassis associated Ate (along with Hybris, the personification of insolence) with excessive drinking. According to Panyassis, the first round of wine, is for the Graces (the goddesses of beauty), Horae (the goddesses of good order), and Dionysus (the god of wine), while the second round, is for Aphrodite (goddess of love), and Dionysus again. But the third round is when "Hybris and Ate take their unlovely turn", bringing "good hospitality to a bad end".
In his third-century BC epic poem the Argonautica, about the adventures of Jason and the Argonauts, Apollonius of Rhodes has Hera say that "even the gods are sometimes visited by Ate". In Nonnus's fifth-century AD epic poem Dionysiaca, in order to gratify Hera, Ate persuades the boy Ampelus whom Dionysus passionately loves, to impress Dionysus by riding on a bull from which Ampelus subsequently falls and breaks his neck. In Quintus Smyrnaeus's in his third-century AD Posthomerica, associates Ate with the punishment of insolence:
Lesser men should beware of insulting their kings either face-to-face or behind their backs: the result is terrible wrath. Justice does exist: Ruin , who brings mortals misery upon misery, punishes an insolent tongue.
— Quintus Smyrnaeus, Posthomerica 1.751–754; translation by Neil Hopkinson
Shakespeare
In the play Julius Caesar, Shakespeare introduces the goddess Ate as an invocation of vengeance and menace. Mark Antony, lamenting Caesar's murder, envisions:
And Caesar's spirit, raging for revenge,
With Ate by his side come hot from hell,
Shall in these confines with a monarch's voice
Cry "Havoc!" and let slip the dogs of war,
Shakespeare also mentions her in the play Much Ado About Nothing, when Benedick says, referring to Beatrice,
Come, talk not of her. You shall find her the
infernal Ate in good apparel.
So too, in King John, Shakespeare refers to Queen Eleanor as "An Ate stirring him [John] to blood and strife", and, in Love's Labour's Lost, Birone jeers "Pompey is moved. More Ates, more Ates! stir them on, stir them on!"
See also
- Folly (allegory)
- 111 Ate, a main-belt asteroid
Notes
- The personification of atē is variously translated. Common translations include: 'Delusion' (Hard, p. 31; Lattimore, p. 394 ln. 91; compare The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη 1.), 'Recklessness' (Most, p. 21; compare The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη 2.), 'Folly' (Gantz, p. 10; compare The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη 2.), or 'Ruin' (Caldwell, p. 42 on 212–232; Lattimore, p. 211 ln. 505; compare The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη 3.); compare LSJ, s.v. ἄτη. Other translations include 'Blindness' (Iliad 9.505 Wyatt), 'Error' (Grimal, s.v. Ate).
- Rose and Dietrich, s.v. Ate; Dräger, s.v. Ate; Grimal, s.v. Ate; Tripp, s.v. Ate; Parada, s.v. Ate; Smith, s.v. Ate; LSJ, s.v. ἄτη.
- Hard, p. 31; Gantz, p. 10.
- Sommerstein 2013, p. 1: "The overwhelming impression one gets after exposure to the recent literature on atē is that, firstly, it is an extremely hard concept for the modern mind to understand and, secondly, no two scholars agree on what it meant.".
- Dräger, Brill's New Pauly s.v. Ate.
- The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἀάω; compare LSJ, s.v. ἀάω.
- The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη; compare with LSJ, s.v. ἄτη.
- Yamagata, p. 21; Hard, p. 31; Rose and Dietrich, s.v. Ate; Dräger, s.v. Ate. Padel, in discussing Homer's use of atē (p. 174), calls this sequence the "atē-sequence" and "Homer's damage-chain": "In most but not all Homeric contexts, atē and aaō seem to mark inner, prior 'damage' done to the mind, which then causes a terrible outward act. Call it the X-act. it is a mistake, a crime, with consequences: further outward 'damage.' Damage in the world. Atē belongs in a causal chain. Damage, X-act, damage. This chain is the word's main point"; and when discussing Ate as personified by Homer, Padel notes (p. 181) that Ate can represent either the first place or last place in this sequence (or both at once, as she does in the Iliad's "allegory of the Prayers", see below). Sommerstein 2013, p. 3 has a somewhat more expanded view, seeing this atē-sequence as a "process ... starting with a divine initiative and finishing with a human catastrophe, whose beginning, middle and end can all be called atē", and that this "whole process" can be thought of "as a single instance of atē".
- The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, s.v. ἄτη -Ἄτη.
- Gantz, p. 10.
- Coray, pp. 50–51 on 86b–138, 57 on 94, 72 on 128–130; Padel, p. 182; Davies, p. 2.
- Hard, p. 31; Homer, Iliad 19.95–133. It is unknown to what extent this story was part of the existing mythology of Heracles, or was an ad hoc Homeric invention, see Coray, p. 59 on 95–133.
- Grimal, s.v. Ate; Apollodorus, 3.12.3. Compare Tzetzes on Lycophron 29; Stephanus of Byzantium, s.v. Ἲλιον.
- Lycophron, Alexandra 29.
- Gantz, p. 10; Homer, Iliad 19.91.
- Gantz, p. 10; Hesiod, Theogony 226–232.
- Aeschylus, Agamemnon 385–386.
- Coray, p. 56 on 91 πρέσβα; Padel, p. 182; Homer, Iliad 19.90. Murray and Padel translate Homer's πρέσβα here as 'eldest'. According to Coray, the word πρέσβα "means 'venerable', perhaps in rank and dignity in the case of goddesses", while noting that "the meaning 'eldest' ... may be heard here as well".
- Lloyd-Jones, p. 192.
- Homer, Iliad 19.510–512.
- Coray, p. 75 on 136, 137; Homer, Iliad 19.136–137.
- Hesiod, Works and Days 225–231
- Solon fr 13 Gerber 75–76.
- Aeschylus, Libation Bearers 382–385.
- Whether to capitalize atē or its translation, to indicate personification or not, is an editorial choice made "according to the degree of prsonification suggested by the phrase." (West 1978, p. 210 on 213 Δικης). So "occurs" here means the capitalization of the word by the editor/translator being cited, while at the same time understanding that, according to Padel, p. 181: "orthography makes no difference to how she operates". For discussions of the use of both Ate, and the much more frequently occurring atē (particularly as used in Homer and Greek tragedy), see: Dodds, pp. 2–8, 37–41; Doyle 1984; Padel, pp. 167–196 (Chapters 16, 17, 18), pp. 249–259 (Appendix); Sommerstein 2013.
- Sommerstein, p. 3; Padel, p. 9;
- Cairns, p. 24; Padel p. 182.
- Dodds, p. 5, describes the instances of the personification of atē in the Iliad as "transparent pieces of allegory". Cairns, pp. 24–25, calls Ate an ad hoc Homeric invention, and says that it is only for the purposes of the argument Homer is presenting that "Atē is actually a goddess". Coray, p. 59 on 95–133, says that it is an open question "whether Ate is a Homeric creation". Padel, p. 169, notes that such modern distinctions between, for example "concrete and metaphorical", may have little meaning for Homer, and, p. 181, that "Homer personifies atē twice. Here, according to conventions of scholarship and poetry which imitates Greek, we start calling her Ate. But orthography makes no difference to how she operates".
- Cairns, p. 45.
- For discussions of Ate (and atē) in Homer see: Padel, pp. 167–187 (Chapters 16, 17); Cairns 2012.
- Padel, p. 181; Rose and Dietrich, s.v. Ate; Dräger, s.v. Ate. For a discussion of the so-called "Parable of the Prayers", see: Held 1987, Yamagata 2005.
- Padel, pp. 174, 181, which sees Ate here as part what Padel calls "Homers damage-chain": mental damage, causing a bad act, causing damage in the world, with Ate occupying both the front and back of this causal chain.
- Cairns, pp. 14–15; 25–27; 46–56.
- Hard, p. 31; Dodds, pp. 2–3. For a detailed commentary on Book 19 see Coray 2016.
- Coray, p. 55 on 91–94.
- Coray, pp. 50–51 on 86b–138.
- Held, p. 253.
- Hard, p. 31; Gantz, p. 10; Homer, Iliad 19.95–124. For a description of the parallel structure between the preceding section of the Iliad and this section, showing the links Agamemnon is trying to make between himself and Zeus, see Coray, p. 51 on 86b–138.
- According to Coray, p. 72 on 126–127 'shining hair', such language implying "carefully coiffed hair, gleaming with the oil used to care for it, is a mark of a refined appearance ... and is part of Ate’s alluring look".
- Hard, p. 31.
- West 1966, p. 232 on 230 Δυσνομίην τ’ Ἄτην τε; Hesiod, Theogony 230. The phrase "much like one another" might apply to all the previously listed children of Eris, however according to Doyle, p. 25, the usual interpretation is that the phrase applies just to Dysnomia and Ate.
- West 1978, p. 209 on 213–85 The superiority of Dike over Hybris; Hesiod, Works and Days 213–231.
- Rose and Dietrich, s.v. Ate; compare Solon, fr. 4 Gerber , 30–35 , where "Lawfulness , weakens insolence , and dries up the blooming flowers of ruin ".
- Although Most's Greek text chooses not to capitalize limos or atē here, West 1978, p. 106 ls. 230–231, does.
- For discussion of tragic usage see Doyle 1984; Padel, pp. 188–196 (Chapter 18), 249–259 (Appendix); Sommerstein 2013.
- Sommerstein 2013, p. 4, which notes that, although Homer is more focused on the beginning of the atē-process, "the end is always kept in mind: a mental aberration which does not have catastrophic consequences is not called atē".
- Sommerstein 2013, pp. 5, 9; Doyle, p. 1.
- Smith, s.v. Ate.
- Sommerstein, p. 5; Doyle, p. 90 n. 1.
- Smith, s.v. Ate.
- Sommerstein, p. 7; Aeschylus, Agamemnon 385–386.
- Aeschylus, Agamemnon 681–781. For a discussions of this stasimon see Scott, pp. 51–56; Otis, pp. 32–34.
- Scott, p. 54; Otis, p. 33; Aeschylus, Agamemnon 736.
- Aeschylus, Agamemnon 1372.
- Aeschylus, Agamemnon 1432–1433.
- Probably referring to Hades, see Sommerstein 2009, p. 261 n. 85.
- Sommerstein, p. 7.
- Aeschylus, Persians, 1007.
- Sommerstein 2009, p. 255 n. 143; Aeschylus, Seven Against Thebes 954–960.
- Sappho or Alcaeus, fr. 25B.
- Dodds, p. 174; Empedocles fr. D24 Laks-Most .
- Panyassis, fr. 20 West; compare with fr 22 West.
- Apollonius of Rhodes, Argonautica 4.817; English translation: Rieu, p. 169.
- Nonnus, Dionysiaca 11.113 ff.
- Julius Caesar 3.1/296–299, Folger Shakespeare Library.
- Much Ado About Nothing 2.1/251–252, Folger Shakespeare Library.
- King John 2.1/63, Folger Shakespeare Library.
- Love's Labor's Lost 5.2/761–762, Folger Shakespeare Library.
References
- Aeschylus, Agamemnon, in Aeschylus: Oresteia: Agamemnon, Libation-Bearers, Eumenides, edited and translated by Alan H. Sommerstein, Loeb Classical Library No. 146. Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-674-99628-1. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Aeschylus, Libation Bearers in Aeschylus, with an English translation by Herbert Weir Smyth, Ph. D. in two volumes, Vol 2, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1926, Online version at the Perseus Digital Library.
- Aeschylus, Persians in Aeschylus: Persians. Seven against Thebes. Suppliants. Prometheus Bound, edited and translated by Alan H. Sommerstein. Loeb Classical Library No. 145, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-674-99627-4. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Apollodorus, Apollodorus, The Library, with an English Translation by Sir James George Frazer, F.B.A., F.R.S. in 2 Volumes. Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. 1921. ISBN 0-674-99135-4. Online version at the Perseus Digital Library.
- Apollonius of Rhodes, Argonautica, edited and translated by William H. Race, Loeb Classical Library No. 1, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-674-99630-4. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Apollonius of Rhodes, The Voyage of Argo: The Argonautica, translated with an introduction by E. V. Rieu, Penguin Books, 1969.
- Cairns, Douglas, Cairns, F. (ed.), "Atê in the Homeric poems", The University of Edinburgh Research Explorer. Original print publication: Papers of the Langford Latin Seminar, vol. 15, pp. 1–52, Oxbow Books, 2012. ISBN 978-0-905-20555-7.
- Caldwell, Richard, Hesiod's Theogony, Focus Publishing/R. Pullins Company (June 1, 1987). ISBN 978-0-941051-00-2. Internet Archive.
- Campbell, David A., Greek Lyric, Volume I: Sappho and Alcaeus, Loeb Classical Library No. 142, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1990. ISBN 0-674-99157-5. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- The Cambridge Greek Lexicon, edited by J. Diggle et al, Cambridge University Press, 2021 ISBN 978-0-521-82680-8.
- Coray, Marina, Homer's Iliad: The Basel Commentary. Book XIX, edited by Anton Bierl, Joachim Latacz, S. Douglas Olson, translated by Benjamin W. Millis, Sara Strack, De Guyter, 2016. ISBN 978-1-5015-1224-7.
- Davies, Malcom, "Agamemnon's Apology and the Unity of the Iliad", The Classical Quarterly, Vol. 45, No. 1 (1995), pp. 1-8. JSTOR 639711.
- Demosthenes, Orations, Volume II: Orations 18-19: De Corona, De Falsa Legatione. translated by C. A. Vince, J. H. Vince, Loeb Classical Library No. 155, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1926. ISBN 978-0-674-99171-2. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Dodds, E. R., The Greeks and the Irrational, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1951. Internet Archive: 1957 paperback edition, Beacon Press, Boston.
- Doyle, Richard E., Atē, Its Use and Meaning : A Study in the Greek Poetic Tradition from Homer to Euripides, New York, Fordham University Press, 1984. ISBN 0-8232-1062-6. Internet Archive.
- Dräger, Paul, s.v. Ate, in Brill’s New Pauly Online, Antiquity volumes edited by: Hubert Cancik and, Helmuth Schneider, English Edition by: Christine F. Salazar, Classical Tradition volumes edited by: Manfred Landfester, English Edition by: Francis G. Gentry, published online: 2006.
- Empedocles, in Early Greek Philosophy, Volume V: Western Greek Thinkers, Part 2. , edited and translated by André Laks, Glenn W. Most, Loeb Classical Library No. 528, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2016. ISBN 978-0-674-99706-6. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Gantz, Timothy, Early Greek Myth: A Guide to Literary and Artistic Sources, Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996, Two volumes: ISBN 978-0-8018-5360-9 (Vol. 1), ISBN 978-0-8018-5362-3 (Vol. 2).
- Grimal, Pierre, The Dictionary of Classical Mythology, Wiley-Blackwell, 1996. ISBN 978-0-631-20102-1. Internet Archive.
- Hard, Robin, The Routledge Handbook of Greek Mythology: Based on H.J. Rose's "Handbook of Greek Mythology", Psychology Press, 2004, ISBN 9780415186360. Google Books.
- Held, George F., "Phoinix, Agamemnon And Achilleus: Parables and Paradeigmata" in The Classical Quarterly 1987, 37 (2): 245-261. doi:10.1017/S0009838800030470.
- Homer, Iliad, Volume I: Books 1-12, translated by A. T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt, Loeb Classical Library No. 170, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1999. Online version at Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-99579-6.
- Homer, Iliad, Volume II: Books 13-24, translated by A. T. Murray, revised by William F. Wyatt, Loeb Classical Library No. 171, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1999. Online version at Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-99580-2.
- Homer, The Iliad with an English Translation by A.T. Murray, Ph.D. in two volumes. Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann, Ltd. 1924. Online version at the Perseus Digital Library.
- Lattimore, Richard, The Iliad of Homer, translated with an introduction by Richard Lattimore, University of Chicago Press, 1951.
- Liddell, Henry George, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, revised and augmented throughout by Sir Henry Stuart Jones with the assistance of Roderick McKenzie, Clarendon Press Oxford, 1940. Online version at the Perseus Digital Library.
- Lloyd-Jones, Hugh. "The Guilt of Agamemnon." The Classical Quarterly, Nov., 1962, Vol. 12, No. 2 (Nov., 1962), pp. 187-199. JSTOR 637867.
- Lycophron, Alexandra (or Cassandra) in Callimachus and Lycophron with an English translation by A. W. Mair; Aratus, with an English translation by G. R. Mair, London: W. Heinemann, New York: G. P. Putnam 1921. Internet Archive.
- Most, G.W., Hesiod, Theogony, Works and Days, Testimonia, Edited and translated by Glenn W. Most, Loeb Classical Library No. 57, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2018. ISBN 978-0-674-99720-2. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Nonnus, Dionysiaca, Volume I: Books 1–15, translated by W. H. D. Rouse, Loeb Classical Library No. 344, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 1940 (revised 1984). ISBN 978-0-674-99379-2. Online version at Harvard University Press. Internet Archive (1940).
- Otis, Brooks, Cosmos & Tragedy : An Essay on the Meaning of Aeschylus, edited by Christian Kopff, the University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, 1981. ISBN 0-8078-1465-2. Internet Archive.
- Padel, Ruth, Whom Gods Destroy, Elements of Greek and Tragic Madness, Princeton University Press, 1995. ISBN 0-691-03360-9. Internet Archive.
- Panyassis, in Greek Epic Fragments: From the Seventh to the Fifth Centuries BC, edited and translated by Martin L. West, Loeb Classical Library No. 497, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2003. ISBN 978-0-674-99605-2. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Quintus Smyrnaeus, Posthomerica, edited and translated by Neil Hopkinson, Loeb Classical Library No. 19, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2018. ISBN 978-0-674-99716-5. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Rose, Herbert Jennings, and B. C. Dietrich, s.v. Ate, published online 22 December 2015, in the Oxford Classical Dictionary, edited by Tim Whitmarsh, digital ed, New York, Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-938113-5.
- Smith, William, Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, London (1873). Online version at the Perseus Digital Library.
- Scott, William, C., Musical Design In Aeschylean Theater, University Press of New England, 1984. ISBN 978-1-61168-181-9.
- Sommerstein, Alan H. (2009), Aeschylus: Persians. Seven against Thebes. Suppliants. Prometheus Bound, edited and translated by Alan H. Sommerstein. Loeb Classical Library No. 145, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-674-99627-4. Online version at Harvard University Press.
- Sommerstein, Alan H. (2013), "Ate in Aeschylus" in Tragedy and Archaic Greek Thought, D.L. Cairns ed., Swansea, Classical Press of Wales, 2013. ISBN 978-1-905-12557-9. pp. 1-15.
- Stephanus of Byzantium, Stephani Byzantii Ethnicorum quae supersunt, edited by August Meineike (1790-1870), published 1849. Google Books.
- Tripp, Edward, Crowell's Handbook of Classical Mythology, Thomas Y. Crowell Co; First edition (June 1970). ISBN 069022608X.
- Tzetzes, John, Scholia eis Lycophrona, edited by Christian Gottfried Müller, Sumtibus F.C.G. Vogelii, 1811. Internet Archive.
- West, M. L. (1966), Hesiod: Theogony, Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-814169-6.
- West, M. L. (1978), Hesiod: Works and Days, Clarendon Press Oxford, 1978. ISBN 0-19-814005-3.
- Yamagata, Naoko, "Disaster revisited: Ate and the Litai in Homer's Iliad ", in Personification in the Greek World: From Antiquity to Byzantium, edited by Emma Stafford and Judith Herrin, Ashgate, 2005. pp. 21-28. ISBN 978-0-7546-5031-7.
Ancient Greek deities | |||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Early deities | |||||||||||||
Titans |
| ||||||||||||
Olympian deities |
| ||||||||||||
Water deities |
| ||||||||||||
Personifications |
| ||||||||||||
Other deities |
|