Misplaced Pages

Complete partial order

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
(Redirected from Chain complete) Mathematical phrase

In mathematics, the phrase complete partial order is variously used to refer to at least three similar, but distinct, classes of partially ordered sets, characterized by particular completeness properties. Complete partial orders play a central role in theoretical computer science: in denotational semantics and domain theory.

Definitions

The term complete partial order, abbreviated cpo, has several possible meanings depending on context.

A partially ordered set is a directed-complete partial order (dcpo) if each of its directed subsets has a supremum. (A subset of a partial order is directed if it is non-empty and every pair of elements has an upper bound in the subset.) In the literature, dcpos sometimes also appear under the label up-complete poset.

A pointed directed-complete partial order (pointed dcpo, sometimes abbreviated cppo), is a dcpo with a least element (usually denoted {\displaystyle \bot } ). Formulated differently, a pointed dcpo has a supremum for every directed or empty subset. The term chain-complete partial order is also used, because of the characterization of pointed dcpos as posets in which every chain has a supremum.

A related notion is that of ω-complete partial order (ω-cpo). These are posets in which every ω-chain ( x 1 x 2 x 3 . . . {\displaystyle x_{1}\leq x_{2}\leq x_{3}\leq ...} ) has a supremum that belongs to the poset. The same notion can be extended to other cardinalities of chains.

Every dcpo is an ω-cpo, since every ω-chain is a directed set, but the converse is not true. However, every ω-cpo with a basis is also a dcpo (with the same basis). An ω-cpo (dcpo) with a basis is also called a continuous ω-cpo (or continuous dcpo).

Note that complete partial order is never used to mean a poset in which all subsets have suprema; the terminology complete lattice is used for this concept.

Requiring the existence of directed suprema can be motivated by viewing directed sets as generalized approximation sequences and suprema as limits of the respective (approximative) computations. This intuition, in the context of denotational semantics, was the motivation behind the development of domain theory.

The dual notion of a directed-complete partial order is called a filtered-complete partial order. However, this concept occurs far less frequently in practice, since one usually can work on the dual order explicitly.

By analogy with the Dedekind–MacNeille completion of a partially ordered set, every partially ordered set can be extended uniquely to a minimal dcpo.

Examples

  • Every finite poset is directed complete.
  • All complete lattices are also directed complete.
  • For any poset, the set of all non-empty filters, ordered by subset inclusion, is a dcpo. Together with the empty filter it is also pointed. If the order has binary meets, then this construction (including the empty filter) actually yields a complete lattice.
  • Every set S can be turned into a pointed dcpo by adding a least element ⊥ and introducing a flat order with ⊥ ≤ s and s ≤ s for every s in S and no other order relations.
  • The set of all partial functions on some given set S can be ordered by defining f ≤ g if and only if g extends f, i.e. if the domain of f is a subset of the domain of g and the values of f and g agree on all inputs for which they are both defined. (Equivalently, f ≤ g if and only if f ⊆ g where f and g are identified with their respective graphs.) This order is a pointed dcpo, where the least element is the nowhere-defined partial function (with empty domain). In fact, ≤ is also bounded complete. This example also demonstrates why it is not always natural to have a greatest element.
  • The set of all linearly independent subsets of a vector space V, ordered by inclusion.
  • The set of all partial choice functions on a collection of non-empty sets, ordered by restriction.
  • The set of all prime ideals of a ring, ordered by inclusion.
  • The specialization order of any sober space is a dcpo.
  • Let us use the term “deductive system” as a set of sentences closed under consequence (for defining notion of consequence, let us use e.g. Alfred Tarski's algebraic approach). There are interesting theorems that concern a set of deductive systems being a directed-complete partial ordering. Also, a set of deductive systems can be chosen to have a least element in a natural way (so that it can be also a pointed dcpo), because the set of all consequences of the empty set (i.e. “the set of the logically provable/logically valid sentences”) is (1) a deductive system (2) contained by all deductive systems.

Characterizations

An ordered set is a dcpo if and only if every non-empty chain has a supremum. As a corollary, an ordered set is a pointed dcpo if and only if every (possibly empty) chain has a supremum, i.e., if and only if it is chain-complete. Proofs rely on the axiom of choice.

Alternatively, an ordered set P {\displaystyle P} is a pointed dcpo if and only if every order-preserving self-map of P {\displaystyle P} has a least fixpoint.

Continuous functions and fixed-points

A function f between two dcpos P and Q is called (Scott) continuous if it maps directed sets to directed sets while preserving their suprema:

  • f ( D ) Q {\displaystyle f(D)\subseteq Q} is directed for every directed D P {\displaystyle D\subseteq P} .
  • f ( sup D ) = sup f ( D ) {\displaystyle f(\sup D)=\sup f(D)} for every directed D P {\displaystyle D\subseteq P} .

Note that every continuous function between dcpos is a monotone function. This notion of continuity is equivalent to the topological continuity induced by the Scott topology.

The set of all continuous functions between two dcpos P and Q is denoted . Equipped with the pointwise order, this is again a dcpo, and pointed whenever Q is pointed. Thus the complete partial orders with Scott-continuous maps form a cartesian closed category.

Every order-preserving self-map f of a pointed dcpo (P, ⊥) has a least fixed-point. If f is continuous then this fixed-point is equal to the supremum of the iterates (⊥, f (⊥), f (f (⊥)), … f(⊥), …) of ⊥ (see also the Kleene fixed-point theorem).

Another fixed point theorem is the Bourbaki-Witt theorem, stating that if f {\displaystyle f} is a function from a dcpo to itself with the property that f ( x ) x {\displaystyle f(x)\geq x} for all x {\displaystyle x} , then f {\displaystyle f} has a fixed point. This theorem, in turn, can be used to prove that Zorn's lemma is a consequence of the axiom of choice.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Markowsky, George (1976), "Chain-complete posets and directed sets with applications", Algebra Universalis, 6 (1): 53–68, doi:10.1007/bf02485815, MR 0398913, S2CID 16718857
  2. Abramsky S, Gabbay DM, Maibaum TS (1994). Handbook of Logic in Computer Science, volume 3. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Prop 2.2.14, pp. 20. ISBN 9780198537625.
  3. Tarski, Alfred: Bizonyítás és igazság / Válogatott tanulmányok. Gondolat, Budapest, 1990. (Title means: Proof and truth / Selected papers.)
  4. Stanley N. Burris and H.P. Sankappanavar: A Course in Universal Algebra
  5. See online in p. 24 exercises 5–6 of §5 in . Or, on paper, see Tar:BizIg.
  6. Goubault-Larrecq, Jean (February 23, 2015). "Iwamura's Lemma, Markowsky's Theorem and ordinals". Retrieved January 6, 2024.
  7. Cohn, Paul Moritz. Universal Algebra. Harper and Row. p. 33.
  8. Goubault-Larrecq, Jean (January 28, 2018). "Markowsky or Cohn?". Retrieved January 6, 2024.
  9. Barendregt, Henk, The lambda calculus, its syntax and semantics Archived 2004-08-23 at the Wayback Machine, North-Holland (1984)
  10. This is a strengthening of the Knaster–Tarski theorem sometimes referred to as "Pataraia’s theorem". For example, see Section 4.1 of "Realizability at Work: Separating Two Constructive Notions of Finiteness" (2016) by Bezem et al. See also Chapter 4 of The foundations of program verification (1987), 2nd edition, Jacques Loeckx and Kurt Sieber, John Wiley & Sons, ISBN 0-471-91282-4, where the Knaster–Tarski theorem, formulated over pointed dcpo's, is given to prove as exercise 4.3-5 on page 90.
  11. Bourbaki, Nicolas (1949), "Sur le théorème de Zorn", Archiv der Mathematik, 2 (6): 434–437 (1951), doi:10.1007/bf02036949, MR 0047739, S2CID 117826806.
  12. Witt, Ernst (1951), "Beweisstudien zum Satz von M. Zorn", Mathematische Nachrichten, 4: 434–438, doi:10.1002/mana.3210040138, MR 0039776.

References

Category: