C. D. BroadFBA | |
---|---|
Broad in 1959 | |
Born | Charlie Dunbar Broad (1887-12-30)30 December 1887 Harlesden, Middlesex, England |
Died | 11 March 1971(1971-03-11) (aged 83) Cambridge, Cambridgeshire, England |
Alma mater | Trinity College, Cambridge |
Era | 20th-century philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | Analytic |
Institutions | Trinity College, Cambridge |
Academic advisors | J. M. E. McTaggart |
Doctoral students | Knut Erik Tranøy |
Main interests | Metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, philosophy of mind, logic |
Notable ideas | Growing block universe Rate of passage argument The "critical philosophy" and "speculative philosophy" distinction The "occurrent causation" and "non-occurrent causation" distinction |
Charlie Dunbar Broad FBA (30 December 1887 – 11 March 1971), usually cited as C. D. Broad, was an English epistemologist, historian of philosophy, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, and writer on the philosophical aspects of psychical research. He was known for his thorough and dispassionate examinations of arguments in such works as Scientific Thought (1923), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (1925), and Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy (2 vols., 1933–1938).
Broad's essay on "Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism" in Ethics and the History of Philosophy (1952) introduced the philosophical terms occurrent causation and non-occurrent causation, which became the basis for the contemporary distinction between "agent-causal" and "event-causal" in debates on libertarian free will.
Biography
Broad was born in Harlesden, in Middlesex, England.
He was educated at Dulwich College from 1900 until 1906. He gained a scholarship in 1906 to study at Trinity College, Cambridge, graduating in 1910 with First-Class Honours, with distinction. He became a Fellow of Trinity College the following year.
Career
As his fellowship at Trinity College was a non-residential position, he was also able to accept a position as an assistant lecturer that he had applied for at St Andrews University, where he remained until 1920. That year, he was appointed professor at Bristol University, working there until 1923, when he returned to Trinity as a lecturer. From 1926 until 1931, he was a lecturer in 'moral science' at Cambridge University's Faculty of Philosophy.
Later at Cambridge, he was appointed in 1931 as 'Sidgwick Lecturer', a role he would keep until 1933, when he was appointed Knightbridge Professor of Moral Philosophy at the university, a position he held for twenty years (until 1953). In 1927 he gave the British Academy's Master-Mind Lecture, entitled "Sir Isaac Newton."
In addition, Broad was President of the Aristotelian Society from 1927 to 1928, and again from 1954 to 1955. He was also President of the Society for Psychical Research in 1935 and 1958.
Personal life
Broad was openly homosexual at a time when homosexual acts were illegal. In March 1958, Broad along with fellow philosophers A. J. Ayer and Bertrand Russell, writer J.B. Priestley and 27 others sent a letter to The Times which urged the acceptance of the Wolfenden Report's recommendation that homosexual acts should "no longer be a criminal offence."
Theory
Psychical research
Broad argued that if research could demonstrate that psychic events occur, this would challenge philosophical theories of "basic limiting principles" in at least five ways:
- Backward causation (i.e., the future affecting the past) is rejected by many philosophers, but would be shown to occur if, for example, people could predict the future.
- One common argument against dualism (i.e., the belief that, while bodies are physical entities, minds are a different, non-physical sort of entity) is that physical and non-physical things cannot interact. However, this would be shown to be possible if people can move physical objects by thought (telekinesis).
- Similarly, philosophers tend to be skeptical about claims that non-physical 'stuff' could interact with anything. This would also be challenged if minds are shown to be able to communicate with each other, as would be the case if mind-reading is possible.
- Philosophers generally accept that we can only learn about the world through reason and perception. This belief would be challenged if people were able to psychically perceive events in other places.
- Physicalist philosophers believe that there cannot be persons without bodies. If ghosts were shown to exist, this view would be challenged.
In his 1949 paper The Relevance of Psychical Research for Philosophy, Broad examined the implications of research by British parapsychologist Samuel Soal, who claimed to have discovered a subject, Basil Shackleton, capable of guessing the identity of Zener cards with odds of 'billions to one'. However, the validity of these findings was later questioned by Betty Markwick, following testimony from a colleague suggesting that Soal had manipulated both data and experiment methods . At the time, this evidence prompted Broad to speculate on which philosophical frameworks could account for telepathic and precognitive events that seem to contradict Basic Limiting Principle 4.1. ("It is impossible for a person to perceive a physical event or a material thing except by means of sensations which that event or thing produces in his mind."). He makes a passing reference to the process philosophy of perception and memory advanced by Henri Bergson as a candidate. In Aldous Huxley's 1954 book The Doors of Perception, this passage from Broad is misquoted removing key words that Broad had used to qualify Bergson's theory as one of 'normal' perception and 'potential' memory. These misquotations remained unnoticed until 2023.
Free will
In his essay "Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism", Broad argued for non-occurrent causation as "literally determined by the agent or self." The agent could be considered as a substance or continuant, and not by a total cause which contains as factors events in and dispositions of the agent. Thus, our efforts would be completely determined, but their causes would not be prior events. New series of events would then originate, which he called "continuants", which are essentially causa sui.
Peter van Inwagen says that Broad formulated an excellent version of what van Inwagen has called the "Consequence Argument" in defence of incompatibilism.
Metaphilosophy and science
Broad distinguished between critical philosophy and speculative philosophy. He described critical philosophy as analysing "unanalysed concepts in daily life and in science" and then "expos them to every objection that we can think of". While speculative philosophy's role is to "take over all aspects of human experience, to reflect upon them, and to try to think out a view of Reality as a whole which shall do justice to all of them".
One aspect of critical philosophy was the Principle of Exceptional Cases, whereby everyday concepts are considered in highly abnormal cases, so as to "clear up the meaning" of a concept.
Broad saw philosophy and science as supplemental to one another. Scientists who ignore philosophy expose themselves to a "danger to which the natural scientist is peculiarly liable. The extraordinary success of physics and chemistry within their own sphere tempts men to think that the world is simply a physico-chemical system". Whereas philosophers who ignore science are ignoring properties which are "very pervasive" and can shed light on things.
In terms of empirical propositions Broad distinguished between inspective empirical propositions which he defined "one which asserts of some particular existent with which the mind is acquainted at the time some property which the mind can notice by inspection to belong to it" and inferred empirical propositions which are "derived from a number of perceptual propositions either directly by pure inductive generalization, or indirectly by deduction from one or more inductive generalizations".
Works
- 1914. Perception, physics and reality. An Enquiry into the Information that Physical Science can Supply about the Real. London: Cambridge University Press.
- 1923. Scientific thought. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.
- 1925. The Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Kegan.
- 1926. The Philosophy of Francis Bacon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- 1930. Five types of ethical theory. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.
- 1931. War Thoughts in Peace Time. London: Humphrey Milford.
- 1933. Examination of McTaggart's philosophy. Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.
- 1934. Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- 1938. Examination of McTaggart's philosophy. Vol. 2. Cambridge University Press.
- 1943. Berkeley's Argument about Material Substance. Annual Philosophical Lecture, Henriette Hertz Trust, British Academy
- 1952/2000. Ethics and the History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-22530-2.
- 1953/2000. Religion, Philosophy and Psychic Research. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-22558-2.
- 1955. Human Personality and the Possibility of Its Survival. University of California Press.
- 1958. Personal Identity and Survival. London: Society for Psychical Research.
- 1962. Lectures on Psychical Research. Incorporating the Perrott Lectures given in Cambridge University in 1959 and 1960. New York: Humanities Press.
- contains Saltmarsh's Investigation of Mrs Warren Elliott's Mediumship". Lectures on Psychical Research. Incorporating the Perrott Lectures given in Cambridge University in 1959 and 1960. New York: Humanities Press.
- 1968. Induction, Probability, and Causation. Selected Papers of C. D. Broad. Dordrecht: Reidel.
- 1971. Broad's Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy, New York: Humanities Press.
- 1975. Leibniz: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-20691-X
- 1976. Berkeley's Argument.. Haskell House Pub Ltd.
- 1978. Kant: An Introduction. (ed.) C. Lewy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-21755-5
- 1985. Ethics. (ed.) C. Lewy, Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
- 2023. C. D. Broad: Key Unpublished Writings, (ed.) Joel Walmsley
Notes
- Harlesden was part of Middlesex until 1965; today it is part of the London Borough of Brent in Greater London.
References
- Knut E. Tranøy, "Wittgenstein in Cambridge 1949–1951: Some Personal Recollections", in: F. A. Flowers III, Ian Ground (eds.), Portraits of Wittgenstein: Abridged Edition, Bloomsbury Academic, 2018, p. 452.
- C. D. Broad (1978), "Ostensible temporality." In Richard M. Gale (ed.), The Philosophy of Time: A Collection of Essays, Humanities Press.
- Ned Markosian, "How fast does time pass?", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53(4):829–844 (1993).
- C. D. Broad. "Critical and Speculative Philosophy". In Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements (First Series), ed. J. H. Muirhead (London: G. Allen and Unwin, 1924): 77–100.
- Hodges, S. 1981. God's Gift: A Living History of Dulwich College. London: Heinemann. p. 87.
- ^ "Charlie Dunbar Broad". Trinity College Chapel.
- Broad, C. D. (1927). "Sir Isaac Newton". Proceedings of the British Academy. 13: 173–202. Annual Lecture on a Master Mind. Henriette Hertz Trust. Read July 15, 1927. Reprinted in Ethics and the history of philosophy, pp. 3–28.
- N. G. Annan, Attlee, A. J. Ayer, Robert Boothby, C. M. Bowra, C. D. Broad, David Cecil, L. John Collins, Alex Comfort, A. E. Dyson, Robert Exon, Geoffrey Faber, Jacquetta Hawkes, Trevor Huddleston, C. R. Julian Huxley, C. Day-Lewis, W. R. Niblett, J. B. Priestley, Russell, Donald O. Soper, Stephen Spender, Mary Stocks, A. J. P. Taylor, E. M. W. Tillyard, Alec R. Vidler, Kenneth Walker, Leslie D. Weatherhead, C. V. Wedgwood, Angus Wilson, John Wisdom, and Barbara Wootton. 7 March 1958. "Letter to the Editor." The Times.
- Broad, C. D. (1949). "The Relevance of Psychical Research to Philosophy" (PDF). Philosophy. 24 (91): 291–309. doi:10.1017/S0031819100007452. S2CID 144880410.
- Markwick, Betty (1978). "The Soal-Goldney experiments with Basil Shackelton: New evidence of data manipulation". Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research. 56: 250–277.
- Webb, Adrian (27 November 2023). "Nested hermeneutics: Mind at Large as a curated trope of psychedelic experience". Interdisciplinary Science Reviews. 48 (25): 768–787 – via Taylor and Francis Online.
- van Inwagen, Peter (1 September 2008). "How to Think about the Problem of Free Will" (PDF). The Journal of Ethics. 12 (3): 337. doi:10.1007/s10892-008-9038-7. ISSN 1572-8609. S2CID 144635471.
- ^ Broad, C. D. (1953). "Critical and Speculative Philosophy". Contemporary British Philosophy Personal Statements · Volume 20. London, Allen & Unwin. pp. 87–100.
- Walmsley, Joel (13 June 2022). C.D. Broad: Key Unpublished Writings (1 ed.). London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781003081135. ISBN 978-1-003-08113-5.
Sources
- Brown, Robert (1967) "Broad, Charlie Dunbar" in: Borchert, Donald M., ed. 2006. Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 1 (2nd ed.). Farmington Hills, MI: Macmillan Reference. pp.695–700
Further reading
- Britton, Karl. 1978. "Charlie Dunbar Broad, 1887–1971." Proceedings of the British Academy 64:289–310.
- Schilpp, Paul. 1959. The Philosophy of C. D. Broad. Tudor: New York.
- van Cleve, James (2001) "C. D. Broad (1887–1971)" in A Companion to Analytic Philosophy (eds A.P. Martinich and D. Sosa).
External links
- Charlie Dunbar Broad entry at The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- C. D. Broad: a bibliography. Provides full pdf's of most of Broad's writings.
- C. D. Broad on Digital Text International
- Papers of Charlie Dunbar Broad
Analytic philosophy | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Related articles |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theories | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Concepts |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Philosophers |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
- 1887 births
- 1971 deaths
- 20th-century English male writers
- 20th-century English philosophers
- 20th-century English essayists
- Academics of the University of St Andrews
- Action theorists
- Alumni of Trinity College, Cambridge
- Analytic philosophers
- Aristotelian philosophers
- British ethicists
- English male essayists
- British consciousness researchers and theorists
- English essayists
- English gay writers
- English historians of philosophy
- English logicians
- English writers on paranormal topics
- British epistemologists
- Fellows of Trinity College, Cambridge
- George Berkeley scholars
- Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz scholars
- British historians of science
- Kant scholars
- British LGBTQ historians
- LGBTQ philosophers
- English LGBTQ rights activists
- British LGBTQ rights activists
- English LGBTQ writers
- Libertarian theorists
- Metaphysics writers
- Ontologists
- British parapsychologists
- People educated at Dulwich College
- People from Harlesden
- British philosophers of logic
- British philosophers of mind
- British philosophers of religion
- British philosophers of science
- Philosophers of time
- Philosophers of war
- Presidents of the Aristotelian Society
- Probability theorists
- Writers about activism and social change
- Writers about religion and science
- Knightbridge Professors of Philosophy
- 20th-century British psychologists