Misplaced Pages

Creatio ex materia

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.

View that the universe originates from pre-existing matter This article is about creation of the universe from preexisting material. For creation of the universe out of nothing, see Creatio ex nihilo.

Creatio ex materia is the notion that the universe was formed out of eternal, pre-existing matter. This is in contrast to the notion of creatio ex nihilo, where the universe is created out of nothing. The idea of creatio ex materia is found in ancient near eastern cosmology, early Greek cosmology such as is in the works of Homer and Hesiod, and across the board in ancient Greek philosophy. It was also held by a few early Christians, although creatio ex nihilo was the dominant concept among such writers. After the King Follet discourse, creatio ex materia came to be accepted in Mormonism.

Greek philosophers came to widely frame the notion of creatio ex materia with the philosophical dictum "nothing comes from nothing" (Greek: οὐδὲν ἐξ οὐδενός; Latin: ex nihilo nihil fit). Although it is not clear if the dictum goes back to Parmenides (5th century BC) or the Milesian philosophers, a more common version of the expression was coined by Lucretius, who stated in his De rerum natura that "nothing can be created out of nothing".

Alternatives to creatio ex materia include creatio ex nihilo ("creation from nothing"); creatio ex deo ("creation from God"), referring to a derivation of the cosmos from the substance of God either partially (in panentheism) or completely (in pandeism), and creatio continua (ongoing divine creation).

Greek philosophy

Greek philosophers widely accepted the notion that creation acted on eternally existing, uncreated matter. Parmenides' articulation of the dictum that "nothing comes from nothing" is first attested in Aristotle's Physics:

τί δ᾽ ἄν μιν καὶ χρέος ὦρσεν ὕστερον ἢ πρόσθεν, τοῦ μηδενὸς ἀρξάμενον, φῦν; οὕτως ἢ πάμπαν πελέναι χρεών ἐστιν ἢ οὐχί.

In English translation:

 Yet why would it be created later rather than sooner, if it came from nothing; so, it must either be created altogether or not .

Though commonly credited to Parmenides, some historians believe that the dictum instead historically traces back to the Milesian philosophers. In any case, Parmenides believed that non-existence could neither give rise to existence (genesis), nor could something that exists cease to exist (perishing). That which does not exist has no causal powers, and therefore could not give rise to something.

A typical expression of it can be found in the writings of Plutarch, which conditions that the structured and formed things that exist now derive from earlier, unformed and unshaped matter. Therefore, the creation act was the process of ordering this unordered matter.

The Roman poet and philosopher Lucretius expressed this principle in his first book of De rerum natura (On the Nature of Things) (1.149–214). According to his argument, if something could come from nothing, it would be commonplace to observe something coming from nothing all the time, even to witness any animal emerge fully-made or to see trees at one point bearing an apple but later producing a pear. This is because there is no prerequisite for what would come out of nothing, as prior causes or matter would have no place in limiting what comes into existence. In short, Lucretius believed that creatio ex nihilo would lead to a lack of regularity in nature.

In their interaction with earlier Greek philosophers who accepted this argument/dictum, Christian authors who accepted creatio ex nihilo, like Origen, simply denied the essential premise that something cannot come from nothing, and viewed it as a presumption of a limitation of God's power; God was seen as in fact able to create something out of nothing.

See also

References

Citations

  1. De Almeida 2021.
  2. ^ Chambers 2021, p. 96–103.
  3. Harrell 2011, p. 233–234.
  4. ^ Roecklein 2011, p. 37–56.
  5. ^ Mumford 2021, p. 8.
  6. Oord 2014, p. 3.
  7. McQuillan 2019, p. 140.
  8. "Parmenides, Fragments 1-19". Lexundria.com. Retrieved 2020-02-04.
  9. "Parmenides, Fragments 1-19". Lexundria.com. Retrieved 2020-02-04.
  10. Young 1991, p. 139–140.
  11. Chambers 2021, p. 98–99.
  12. Rasmussen 2019, p. 92–93.

Sources

External links

Categories: