Misplaced Pages

Cumulativity (linguistics)

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
(Redirected from Cumulativity)
This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (September 2022) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. Please help improve this article by introducing more precise citations. (September 2022) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

In linguistic semantics, an expression X is said to have cumulative reference if and only if the following holds: If X is true of both of a and b, then it is also true of the combination of a and b. Example: If two separate entities can be said to be "water", then combining them into one entity will yield more "water". If two separate entities can be said to be "a house", their combination cannot be said to be "a house". Hence, "water" has cumulative reference, while the expression "a house" does not. The plural form "houses", however, does have cumulative reference. If two (groups of) entities are both "houses", then their combination will still be "houses".

Cumulativity has proven relevant to the linguistic treatment of the mass/count distinction and for the characterization of grammatical telicity.

Formally, a cumulative predicate CUM can be defined as follows, where capital X is a variable over sets, U is the universe of discourse, p is a mereological part structure on U, and p {\displaystyle \oplus _{p}} is the mereological sum operation.

( X U p ) ( C U M ( X ) x , y ( X ( x ) X ( y ) x y ) x , y ( X ( x ) X ( y ) X ( x p y ) ) ) {\displaystyle (\forall X\subseteq U_{p})(CUM(X)\iff \exists x,y(X(x)\wedge X(y)\wedge x\neq y)\wedge \forall x,y(X(x)\wedge X(y)\Rightarrow X(x\oplus _{p}y)))}

In later work, Krifka has generalized the notion to n-ary predicates, based on the phenomenon of cumulative quantification. For example, the two following sentences appear to be equivalent:

John ate an apple and Mary ate a pear.
John and Mary ate an apple and a pear.

This shows that the relation "eat" is cumulative. In general, an n-ary predicate R is cumulative if and only if the following holds:

( x 1 , , x n , y 1 , , y n ) ( R ( x 1 , , x n ) R ( y 1 , , y n ) ) R ( x 1 y 1 , , x n y n ) {\displaystyle (\forall x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n},y_{1},\ldots ,y_{n})(R(x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n})\wedge R(y_{1},\ldots ,y_{n}))\rightarrow R(x_{1}\oplus y_{1},\ldots ,x_{n}\oplus y_{n})}

References

Krifka, Manfred (1989). "Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics". In Renate Bartsch, Johan van Benthem and Peter van Emde Boas (eds.), Semantics and Contextual Expressions 75–115. Dordrecht: Foris.

Krifka, Manfred. 1999. "At least some determiners aren’t determiners". In The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view, ed. K. Turner, 257–291. North-Holland: Elsevier Science.

Scha, Remko. 1981. "Distributive, collective, and cumulative quantification". In Formal methods in the study of language, ed. T. Janssen and M. Stokhof, 483–512. Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts.

Formal semantics (natural language)
Central concepts
Topics
Areas
Phenomena
Formalism
Formal systems
Concepts
See also
Categories: