Misplaced Pages

Epoché

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
For the academic journal, see Epoché (journal).

Definition: According to Webster's dictionary, Epoche is "the act of refraining from any conclusion for or against anything as the decisive step for the attainment of ataraxy".

Part of a series on
Pyrrhonism
Pyrrhonists
Concepts
Similar philosophies
Modern influence
Philosophy portal

In Hellenistic philosophy, epoché (also epoche; pronounced /ˈɛpɒki/ or /ˈɛpəki/; Greek: ἐποχή, romanizedepokhē, lit.'cessation') is suspension of judgment but also "withholding of assent".

Pyrrhonism

Main article: Pyrrhonism

Epoché plays an important role in Pyrrhonism, the skeptical philosophy named after Pyrrho, who is regarded as the founder of ancient skepticism. The Pyrrhonists developed the concept of "epoché" to describe the state where all judgments about non-evident matters are suspended to induce a state of ataraxia (freedom from worry and anxiety). The Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus gives this definition: "Epoché is a state of the intellect on account of which we neither deny nor affirm anything." This concept is similarly employed in Academic Skepticism but without the objective of ataraxia.

Pyrrhonism provides practitioners with techniques for achieving epoché through the use of the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus, the Five Modes of Agrippa, and the Pyrrhonist maxims. Pyrrhonism is mostly known today through the writings of the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus whose surviving works appear to be an encyclopedia of Pyrrhonist arguments for inducing epoché across a breadth of philosophical and other intellectual issues of antiquity. Sextus Empiricus was able to elaborate on the 10 tropes of Aenesidemus and argue syllogistic proofs in every area of speculative knowledge.

Stoicism

In Stoicism, the concept is used to describe the withholding of assent to Phantasia (impressions). For example, Epictetus uses the term in this manner: "If what philosophers say is true, that in all men action starts from one source, feeling, as in assent it is the feeling that a thing is so, and in denial the feeling that it is not so, yes, by Zeus, and in epoché, the feeling that it is uncertain: so also impulse towards a thing is originated by the feeling that it is fitting, and will to get a thing by the feeling that it is expedient for one, and it is impossible to judge."

Husserl & Epoche

Summaries From : https://www.proquest.com/docview/1847465599?fromopenview=true&pq-origsite=gscholar&sourcetype=Scholarly%20Journals To new researchers hoping to adopt Husserl’s way of thinking, it can be a difficult and daunting task. One of the biggest problems researchers faces is the fact that Husserl constantly changed how he described key parts of epoche, as well as reductions. There are many good guides to help researchers understand how to use phenomenological study. A problem accrues when researchers want to gain a deeper understanding of phenomenology.

           Epoche suggests that we block the way to phenomena, letting go of preconceptions in the goal of true understanding. The problem becomes apparent in this fact, people assume they have dropped all bias in pursuit of epoche. They come to the false conclusion that they have let go of bias, but they have really fallen back to personal beliefs without noticing. It is a cycle of trying to get rid of bias but intern falling to other biases.

            There are guides and manuals as stated earlier to help one understand these concepts. To truly understand phenomenological research, you cannot use or rely heavily on these manuals. To understand Husserl’s intentions, the researchers have to find their own way of understanding these concepts. The researcher must be able to let go of everything that makes them, them. They must become the blank slates to use the epoche as intended by Husserl.

Reduction In Epoche

Summaries From : https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10746-018-09482-3 Reduction plays a significant role in Epoche and how it is understood. Many have argued that it key to understanding that everything that is not part of transcendental domain has to be broken down and reduced. The questions then arise that, is the theory of reduction worth it or justified? It is commonly understood that reduction is reducing the transcendental in immanence of consciousness. It does not explain the beginning of reductionism which causes reduction to somewhat be inside the world. Attitude changes place motivations of reductionism in the world of volition.

           Reduction allows philosophers to leave the natural attitude of the ideas. It means that you can no longer be what you were. There is a paradox when it comes to reductions because its purpose is to break down the world but to break it down you must understand it. The dogma of the world comes out after the reductionism is used. Epoche is the shock for humans and destruction of the natural attitude in the world. At first a human feels strangeness of being until he becomes one with it. The combination can be rattled if a man realizes he has the burden of work, it is shown that the second movement.

            The theory proposals presented, differ in several important areas, like understanding individual’s stages of reduction. Its purpose is positive meaning as it is filled with content on the foundation of certain knowledge. Epoche like this can be understood as ontologically neutral. It is an expression of negativity as it goes to preexisting and is not worldly or unworldly. Epoche makes it so we can account for nothing transcendental life that cannot be made real. It shows itself in possibilities that are unfulfilled  and cannot be fulfilled.

Legacy

Main article: Bracketing (phenomenology)

The term was popularized in Phenomenology by Edmund Husserl in 1906. Husserl elaborates the notion of 'bracketing' or 'phenomenological epoché' or 'phenomenological reduction' in Ideas I. Through the systematic procedure of 'phenomenological reduction', one is thought to be able to suspend judgment regarding the general or naive philosophical belief in the existence of the external world, and thus examine phenomena as they are originally given to consciousness. Husserl broke epoché into two distinct categories, "universal epoché" and "local epoché", the former having a stronger effect than the latter. Universal epoché required leaving behind all assumptions of existence while local epoché requires setting aside only certain assumptions, often of what is being focused on. One such way this could be applied is the act of seeing a horse. By using local epoché the viewer would suspend or set aside all prior knowledge of that particular horse, presenting an objective view. In applying universal epoché, the viewer would suspend all knowledge of all horses, or even of all mammals. This essentially creates a blank slate for the object to be viewed as objectively as possible. Husserl also noted that the very process of using epoché never leads to the complete description of an object. What is subject to change is the relationship between the subject and object through the ever-changing consciousness. Husserl uses the term "intentionality" as new levels of meaning present themselves. Acting as a pre-categorical method of separating the object from the subject, Husserl believed that this process will not have an end when applied correctly as there are infinite modalities we can connect subjects to objects.

Notes and references

  1. "Definition of EPOCHE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2024-10-24.
  2. ^ "epoché". Oxford English Dictionary (Online ed.). Oxford University Press. (Subscription or participating institution membership required.)
  3. ^ "Definition of EPOCHE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 4 September 2024.
  4. ἐποχή in Liddell and Scott's Greek–English Lexicon.
  5. Benson Mates, "The Skeptic Way" p225
  6. "Dodge, John Vilas [1909–1991]", Who Was Who, Oxford University Press, 2007-12-01, doi:10.1093/ww/9780199540884.013.u172122, retrieved 2021-11-23
  7. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, I.18.
  8. Morison, Benjamin (2019), "Sextus Empiricus", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-10-06
  9. Christensen, T.M., Brumfield, K.A. (2010). Phenomenological designs: The philosophy of phenomenological research. In C.J Sheperis, J.S Young, & M.H. Daniels (Eds.), Counseling research: Quantitative, qualitative, and mixed methods. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education, Inc.
  10. "Husserl, Edmund | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2021-03-19.
  11. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. "The Phenomenological Reduction".

External links

  • The dictionary definition of epoche at Wiktionary
Ancient Greek philosophical concepts
Categories: