Misplaced Pages

Principle of explosion

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
(Redirected from Ex falso quodlibet) Theorem in formal logic "EFQ" redirects here. For the literary baseball journal, see Elysian Fields Quarterly. "Ex falso quodlibet" redirects here. For the musical form, see Quodlibet. For the audio player and library organizer, see Quod Libet (software).
This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Principle of explosion" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (August 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

In classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and similar logical systems, the principle of explosion is the law according to which any statement can be proven from a contradiction. That is, from a contradiction, any proposition (including its negation) can be inferred; this is known as deductive explosion.

The proof of this principle was first given by 12th-century French philosopher William of Soissons. Due to the principle of explosion, the existence of a contradiction (inconsistency) in a formal axiomatic system is disastrous; since any statement can be proven, it trivializes the concepts of truth and falsity. Around the turn of the 20th century, the discovery of contradictions such as Russell's paradox at the foundations of mathematics thus threatened the entire structure of mathematics. Mathematicians such as Gottlob Frege, Ernst Zermelo, Abraham Fraenkel, and Thoralf Skolem put much effort into revising set theory to eliminate these contradictions, resulting in the modern Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.

As a demonstration of the principle, consider two contradictory statements—"All lemons are yellow" and "Not all lemons are yellow"—and suppose that both are true. If that is the case, anything can be proven, e.g., the assertion that "unicorns exist", by using the following argument:

  1. We know that "Not all lemons are yellow", as it has been assumed to be true.
  2. We know that "All lemons are yellow", as it has been assumed to be true.
  3. Therefore, the two-part statement "All lemons are yellow or unicorns exist" must also be true, since the first part of the statement ("All lemons are yellow") has already been assumed, and the use of "or" means that if even one part of the statement is true, the statement as a whole must be true as well.
  4. However, since we also know that "Not all lemons are yellow" (as this has been assumed), the first part is false, and hence the second part must be true to ensure the two-part statement to be true, i.e., unicorns exist (this inference is known as the Disjunctive syllogism).
  5. The procedure may be repeated to prove that unicorns do not exist (hence proving an additional contradiction where unicorns do and do not exist), as well as any other well-formed formula. Thus, there is an explosion of true statements.

In a different solution to the problems posed by the principle of explosion, some mathematicians have devised alternative theories of logic called paraconsistent logics, which allow some contradictory statements to be proven without affecting the truth value of (all) other statements.

Symbolic representation

In symbolic logic, the principle of explosion can be expressed schematically in the following way:

P , ¬ P Q {\displaystyle P,\lnot P\vdash Q} For any statements P and Q, if P and not-P are both true, then it logically follows that Q is true.

Proof

Below is the Lewis argument, a formal proof of the principle of explosion using symbolic logic.

Step Proposition Derivation
1 P ¬ P {\displaystyle P\land \neg P} Premise
2 P {\displaystyle P} Conjunction elimination (1)
3 ¬ P {\displaystyle \neg P} Conjunction elimination (1)
4 P Q {\displaystyle P\lor Q} Disjunction introduction (2)
5 Q {\displaystyle Q} Disjunctive syllogism (4,3)

This proof was published by C. I. Lewis and is named after him, though versions of it were known to medieval logicians.

This is just the symbolic version of the informal argument given in the introduction, with P {\displaystyle P} standing for "all lemons are yellow" and Q {\displaystyle Q} standing for "Unicorns exist". We start out by assuming that (1) all lemons are yellow and that (2) not all lemons are yellow. From the proposition that all lemons are yellow, we infer that (3) either all lemons are yellow or unicorns exist. But then from this and the fact that not all lemons are yellow, we infer that (4) unicorns exist by disjunctive syllogism.

Semantic argument

An alternate argument for the principle stems from model theory. A sentence P {\displaystyle P} is a semantic consequence of a set of sentences Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } only if every model of Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } is a model of P {\displaystyle P} . However, there is no model of the contradictory set ( P ¬ P ) {\displaystyle (P\wedge \lnot P)} . A fortiori, there is no model of ( P ¬ P ) {\displaystyle (P\wedge \lnot P)} that is not a model of Q {\displaystyle Q} . Thus, vacuously, every model of ( P ¬ P ) {\displaystyle (P\wedge \lnot P)} is a model of Q {\displaystyle Q} . Thus Q {\displaystyle Q} is a semantic consequence of ( P ¬ P ) {\displaystyle (P\wedge \lnot P)} .

Paraconsistent logic

Paraconsistent logics have been developed that allow for subcontrary-forming operators. Model-theoretic paraconsistent logicians often deny the assumption that there can be no model of { ϕ , ¬ ϕ } {\displaystyle \{\phi ,\lnot \phi \}} and devise semantical systems in which there are such models. Alternatively, they reject the idea that propositions can be classified as true or false. Proof-theoretic paraconsistent logics usually deny the validity of one of the steps necessary for deriving an explosion, typically including disjunctive syllogism, disjunction introduction, and reductio ad absurdum.

Usage

The metamathematical value of the principle of explosion is that for any logical system where this principle holds, any derived theory which proves (or an equivalent form, ϕ ¬ ϕ {\displaystyle \phi \land \lnot \phi } ) is worthless because all its statements would become theorems, making it impossible to distinguish truth from falsehood. That is to say, the principle of explosion is an argument for the law of non-contradiction in classical logic, because without it all truth statements become meaningless.

Reduction in proof strength of logics without ex falso are discussed in minimal logic.

See also

Notes

  1. Latin: ex falso quodlibet, 'from falsehood, anything '; or ex contradictione quodlibet, 'from contradiction, anything '.
  2. Also known as the principle of Pseudo-Scotus (falsely attributed to Duns Scotus).
  3. Burgess2005 uses 2 and 3 as premises instead of this one

References

  1. Carnielli, Walter; Marcos, João (2001). "Ex contradictione non sequitur quodlibet" (PDF). Bulletin of Advanced Reasoning and Knowledge. 1: 89–109.
  2. Smith, Peter (2020). An Introduction to Formal Logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. Chapter 17.
  3. MacFarlane, John (2021). Philosophical Logic: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge. Chapter 7.
  4. Başkent, Can (2013). "Some topological properties of paraconsistent models". Synthese. 190 (18): 4023. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0246-8. S2CID 9276566.
  5. Carnielli, Walter; Coniglio, Marcelo Esteban (2016). Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, Contradiction and Negation. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Vol. 40. Springer. ix. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-33205-5. ISBN 978-3-319-33203-1.
  6. Priest, Graham. 2011. "What's so bad about contradictions?" In The Law of Non-Contradicton, edited by Priest, Beal, and Armour-Garb. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 25.
  7. ^ McKubre-Jordens, Maarten (August 2011). "This is not a carrot: Paraconsistent mathematics". Plus Magazine. Millennium Mathematics Project. Retrieved January 14, 2017.
  8. de Swart, Harrie (2018). Philosophical and Mathematical Logic. Springer. p. 47.
  9. Gamut, L. T. F. (1991). Logic, Language and Meaning, Volume 1. Introduction to Logic. University of Chicago Press. p. 139.
  10. ^ MacFarlane, John (2021). Philosophical Logic: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge. p. 171. ISBN 978-1-315-18524-8.
  11. Lewis, C I; Langford, C H (1959). Symbolic Logic (2nd ed.). Dover. p. 250. ISBN 9780486601700.
  12. Burgess, John P (2005). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic (ed Stewart Shapiro). Oxford University Press. p. 732. ISBN 9780195325928.
Classical logic
General Law of noncontradiction
Classical logics
Principles
Rules
Introduction
Elimination
People
Works
Categories: