Misplaced Pages

Induction-recursion

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Concept in mathematical logic

In intuitionistic type theory (ITT), a discipline within mathematical logic, induction-recursion is a feature for simultaneously declaring a type and function on that type. It allows the creation of larger types than inductive types, such as universes. The types created still remain predicative inside ITT.

An inductive definition is given by rules for generating elements of a type. One can then define functions from that type by induction on the way the elements of the type are generated. Induction-recursion generalizes this situation since one can simultaneously define the type and the function, because the rules for generating elements of the type are allowed to refer to the function.

Induction-recursion can be used to define large types including various universe constructions. It increases the proof-theoretic strength of type theory substantially. Nevertheless, inductive-recursive recursive definitions are still considered predicative.

Background

Induction-Recursion came out of investigations to the rules of Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory. The type theory has a number of "type formers" and four kinds of rules for each one. Martin-Löf had hinted that the rules for each type former followed a pattern, which preserved the properties of the type theory (e.g., strong normalization, predicativity). Researchers started looking for the most general description of the pattern, since that would tell what kinds of type formers could be added (or not added!) to extend the type theory.

The "universe" type former was the most interesting, because when the rules were written "à la Tarski", they simultaneously defined the "universe type" and a function that operated on it. This eventually lead Dybjer to Induction-Recursion.

Dybjer's initial papers called Induction-Recursion a "schema" for rules. It stated what type formers could be added to the type theory. Later, he and Setzer would write a new type former with rules that allowed new Induction-Recursion definitions to be made inside the type theory. This was added to the Half proof assistant (a variant of Alf).

The idea

Before covering Inductive-Recursive types, the simpler case is Inductive Types. Constructors for Inductive types can be self-referential, but in a limited way. The constructor's parameters must be "positive":

  • not refer to the type being defined
  • be exactly the type being defined, or
  • be a function that returns the type being defined.

With Inductive types, a parameter's type can depend on earlier parameters, but they cannot refer to ones of the type being defined. Inductive-Recursive types go further and parameter's types can refer to earlier parameters that use the type being defined. These must be "half-positive":

  • be a function depending on an earlier parameter if that parameter is wrapped in the function being defined.

So, if D {\displaystyle D} is the type being defined and f {\displaystyle f} is the function being (simultaneously) defined, these parameter declarations are positive:

  • a : A {\displaystyle a:A}
  • d : D {\displaystyle d:D}
  • g : A T y p e {\displaystyle g:A\to Type}
  • h : A D {\displaystyle h:A\to D}
  • i : A B D {\displaystyle i:A\to B\to D}
  • j : g   a {\displaystyle j:g\ a} (Depends on earlier parameters, none of which are type D {\displaystyle D} .)

This is half-positive:

  • k : ( f   d ) D {\displaystyle k:(f\ d)\to D} (Depends on parameter d {\displaystyle d} of type D {\displaystyle D} but only through call to f {\displaystyle f} .)

These are not positive nor half-positive:

  • k : D A {\displaystyle k:D\to A} ( D {\displaystyle D} is a parameter to the function.)
  • l : ( A D ) A {\displaystyle l:(A\to D)\to A} (The parameter takes a function that returns D {\displaystyle D} , but returns A {\displaystyle A} itself.)
  • m : z   d {\displaystyle m:z\ d} (Depends on d {\displaystyle d} of type D {\displaystyle D} , but not through the function f {\displaystyle f} .)

Universe example

A simple common example is the Universe à la Tarski type former. It creates a type U {\displaystyle U} and a function T {\displaystyle T} . There is an element of U {\displaystyle U} for every type in the type theory (except U {\displaystyle U} itself!). The function T {\displaystyle T} maps the elements of U {\displaystyle U} to the associated type.

The type U {\displaystyle U} has a constructor (or introduction rule) for each type former in the type theory. The one for dependent functions would be:

c o n s t r u c t o r Π ( u : U ) ( u : T ( u ) U ) : U {\displaystyle constructor_{\Pi }(u:U)(u':T(u)\to U):U}

That is, it takes an element u {\displaystyle u} of type U {\displaystyle U} that will map to the type of the parameter, and a function u {\displaystyle u'} such that for all values x : T ( u ) {\displaystyle x:T(u)} , u ( x ) {\displaystyle u'(x)} maps to the return type of the function (which is dependent on the value of the parameter, x {\displaystyle x} ). (The final : U {\displaystyle :U} says that the result of the constructor is an element of type U {\displaystyle U} .)

The reduction (or computation rule) says that

T ( c o n s t r u c t o r Π ( u , u ) ) {\displaystyle T(constructor_{\Pi }(u,u'))} becomes x : T ( u ) T ( u ( x ) ) {\displaystyle \prod _{x:T(u)}T(u'(x))} .

After reduction, the function T {\displaystyle T} is operating on a smaller part of the input. If that holds when T {\displaystyle T} is applied to any constructor, then T {\displaystyle T} will always terminate. Without going into the details, Induction-Recursion states what kinds of definitions (or rules) can be added to the theory such that the function calls will always terminate.

Usage

Induction-Recursion is implemented in Agda and Idris.

See also

References

  1. Dybjer, Peter (June 2000). "A general formulation of simultaneous inductive-recursive definitions in type theory" (PDF). Journal of Symbolic Logic. 65 (2): 525–549. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.6.4575. doi:10.2307/2586554. JSTOR 2586554. S2CID 18271311.
  2. Dybjer, Peter (1999). "A Finite Axiomatization of Inductive-Recursive Definitions". Typed Lambda Calculi and Applications. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 1581. pp. 129–146. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.219.2442. doi:10.1007/3-540-48959-2_11. ISBN 978-3-540-65763-7.
  3. Bove, Ana; Dybjer, Peter; Norell, Ulf (2009). "A Brief Overview of Agda – A Functional Language with Dependent Types". In Berghofer, Stefan; Nipkow, Tobias; Urban, Christian; Wenzel, Makarius (eds.). Theorem Proving in Higher Order Logics. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 5674. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. pp. 73–78. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-03359-9_6. ISBN 978-3-642-03359-9.

External links

Category: