Misplaced Pages

Principle of transformation groups

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these messages)
This article's tone or style may not reflect the encyclopedic tone used on Misplaced Pages. See Misplaced Pages's guide to writing better articles for suggestions. (June 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
This article's factual accuracy is disputed. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page. Please help to ensure that disputed statements are reliably sourced. (September 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
(Learn how and when to remove this message)
Part of a series on
Bayesian statistics
Posterior = Likelihood × Prior ÷ Evidence
Background
Model building
Posterior approximation
Estimators
Evidence approximation
Model evaluation

The principle of transformation groups is a methodology for assigning prior probabilities in statistical inference issues, initially proposed by physicist E. T. Jaynes. It is regarded as an extension of the principle of indifference.

Prior probabilities determined by this principle are objective in that they rely solely on the inherent characteristics of the problem, ensuring that any two individuals applying the principle to the same issue would assign identical prior probabilities. Thus, this principle is integral to the objective Bayesian interpretation of probability.

Motivation and Method Description

The principle is motivated by the following normative principle, or desideratum:

In scenarios where the prior information is identical, individuals should assign the same prior probabilities.

This rule is implemented by identifying symmetries, defined by transformation groups, that allow a problem to converted into an equivalent one, and utilizing these symmetries to calculate the prior probabilities.

For problems with discrete variables (such as dice, cards, or categorical data), symmetries are characterized by permutation groups and, in these instances, the principle simplifies to the principle of indifference. In cases involving continuous variables, the symmetries may be represented by other types of transformation groups. Determining the prior probabilities in such cases often requires solving a differential equation, which may not yield a unique solution. However, many continuous variable problems do have prior probabilities which are uniquely defined by the principle of transformation groups, which Jaynes referred to as "well-posed" problems.

Examples

Discrete case: coin flipping

Consider a coin with sides head (H) and tail (T). Denote this information by I {\displaystyle I} . For a given coin flip, denote the probability of an outcome of heads as P ( H | I ) {\displaystyle P(H|I)} and of tails by P ( T | I ) {\displaystyle P(T|I)} .

In applying the desideratum, consider the information contained in the event of the coin flip as framed. It describes no distinction between heads and tails. Given no other information, the elements "head" and "tail" are interchangeable. Application of the desideratum then demands that

P ( H | I ) = P ( T | I ) {\displaystyle P(H|I)=P(T|I)} .

As { H , T } {\displaystyle \{H,T\}} is the entire sample space, the probabilities must add to 1; thus

P ( H | I ) + P ( T | I ) = 1 {\displaystyle P(H|I)+P(T|I)=1} 2 P ( H | I ) = 1 {\displaystyle \implies 2P(H|I)=1} P ( H | I ) = 0.5. {\displaystyle \implies P(H|I)=0.5.}

This argument extends to N categories, to give the "flat" prior probability 1/N.

This provides a consistency-based argument for the principle of indifference: If someone is truly ignorant about a discrete or countable set of outcomes apart from their potential existence but does not assign them equal prior probabilities, then they are assigning different probabilities when given the same information.

Alternatively, this can be phrased as: someone who does not use the principle of indifference to assign prior probabilities to discrete variables, either has information about those variables, or is reasoning inconsistently.

Continuous Case: Location Parameter

This is the easiest example for continuous variables. It is given by stating one is "ignorant" of the location parameter in a given problem. The statement that a parameter is a "location parameter" is that the sampling distribution, or likelihood of an observation X depends on a parameter μ {\displaystyle \mu } only through the difference.

p ( X | μ , I ) = f ( X μ ) {\displaystyle p(X|\mu ,I)=f(X-\mu )}

for some normalized probability distribution f ( ) {\displaystyle f(\cdot )} .

Note that the given information that f ( ) {\displaystyle f(\cdot )} is a normalized distribution is a significant prerequisite to obtaining the final conclusion of a uniform prior, because uniform probability distributions can only be normalized given a finite input domain. In other words, the assumption that f ( ) {\displaystyle f(\cdot )} is normalized implicitly also requires that the location parameter μ {\displaystyle \mu } does not extend to infinity in any of its dimensions. Otherwise, the uniform prior would not be normalizable.

Examples of location parameters include the mean parameter of a normal distribution with known variance, and the median parameter of a Cauchy distribution with a known interquartile range.

The two "equivalent problems" in this case, given one's knowledge of the sampling distribution p ( X | μ , I ) = f ( X μ ) {\displaystyle p(X|\mu ,I)=f(X-\mu )} , but no other knowledge about μ {\displaystyle \mu } , is given by a "shift" of equal magnitude in X and μ {\displaystyle \mu } . This is because of the relation:

f ( X μ ) = f ( [ X + b ] [ μ + b ] ) = f ( X ( 1 ) μ ( 1 ) ) {\displaystyle f(X-\mu )=f(-)=f(X^{(1)}-\mu ^{(1)})}

"Shifting" all quantities up by some number b and solving in the "shifted space" and then "shifting" back to the original one should give exactly the same answer as if we just worked on the original space. Making the transformation from μ {\displaystyle \mu } to μ ( 1 ) {\displaystyle \mu ^{(1)}} has a Jacobian of simply 1, while the prior probability g ( μ ) = p ( μ | I ) {\displaystyle g(\mu )=p(\mu |I)} must satisfy the functional equation:

g ( μ ) = | μ ( 1 ) μ | g ( μ ( 1 ) ) = g ( μ + b ) {\displaystyle g(\mu )=\left|{\partial \mu ^{(1)} \over \partial \mu }\right|g(\mu ^{(1)})=g(\mu +b)}

And the only function that satisfies this equation is the "constant prior":

p ( μ | I ) 1 {\displaystyle p(\mu |I)\propto 1}

Therefore, the uniform prior is justified for expressing complete ignorance of a normalized prior distribution on a finite, continuous location parameter.

Continuous case: scale parameter

As in the above argument, a statement that σ {\displaystyle \sigma } is a scale parameter means that the sampling distribution has the functional form:

p ( X | σ , I ) = 1 σ f ( X σ ) {\displaystyle p(X|\sigma ,I)={1 \over \sigma }f\left({X \over \sigma }\right)}

Where, as before, f ( ) {\displaystyle f(\cdot )} is a normalized probability density function. The requirement that probabilities be finite and positive forces the condition σ > 0 {\displaystyle \sigma >0} . Examples include the standard deviation of a normal distribution with a known mean or the gamma distribution. The "symmetry" in this problem is found by noting that

X σ = X a σ a ;   a > 0 {\displaystyle {X \over \sigma }={Xa \over \sigma a};\ a>0}

and setting X ( 1 ) = X a {\displaystyle X^{(1)}=Xa} and σ ( 1 ) = σ a . {\displaystyle \sigma ^{(1)}=\sigma a.} However, unlike in the location parameter case, the Jacobian of this transformation in the sample space and the parameter space is a {\displaystyle a} , not 1, so the sampling probability changes to

p ( X ( 1 ) | σ , I ) = 1 a 1 σ f ( X a σ a ) = 1 σ ( 1 ) f ( X ( 1 ) σ ( 1 ) ) {\displaystyle p(X^{(1)}|\sigma ,I)={1 \over a}\cdot {1 \over \sigma }f\left({Xa \over \sigma a}\right)={1 \over \sigma ^{(1)}}f\left({X^{(1)} \over \sigma ^{(1)}}\right)}

which is invariant (i.e., has the same form before and after the transformation). Furthermore, the prior probability changes to

p ( σ | I ) = 1 a p ( σ ( 1 ) | I ) = 1 a p ( σ a | I ) {\displaystyle p(\sigma |I)={1 \over a}p(\sigma ^{(1)}|I)={1 \over a}p\left({\sigma \over a}|I\right)}

which has the unique solution (up to proportionality)

p ( σ | I ) 1 σ p ( log ( σ ) | I ) 1 {\displaystyle p(\sigma |I)\propto {1 \over \sigma }\implies p(\log(\sigma )|I)\propto 1} .

This is a well-known Jeffreys prior for scale parameters, which is "flat" on the log scale, although it is derived using a different argument to that here, based on the Fisher information function. The fact that these two methods give the same results in this case does not imply they do in general.

Continuous case: Bertrand's paradox

Edwin Jaynes used this principle to provide a resolution to Bertrand's Paradox by stating his ignorance about the exact position of the circle.

Discussion

This argument depends crucially on I {\displaystyle I} ; changing the information may result in a different probability assignment. It is just as crucial as changing axioms in deductive logic - small changes in the information can lead to large changes in the probability assignments allowed by "consistent reasoning."

To illustrate, suppose that the coin flipping example also states as part of the information that the coin has a side (S) (i.e., it is a real coin). Denote this new information by N {\displaystyle N} . The same argument using "complete ignorance," or more precisely the information actually described, gives

P ( H | I , N ) = P ( T | I , N ) = P ( S | I , N ) = 1 / 3 {\displaystyle P(H|I,N)=P(T|I,N)=P(S|I,N)=1/3} .

Intuition tells us that we should have P ( S ) {\displaystyle P(S)} very close to zero. This is because most people's intuition does not see "symmetry" between a coin landing on its side compared to landing on heads. Our intuition says that the particular "labels" actually carry some information about the problem. A simple argument could be used to make this more formal mathematically (e.g., the physics of the problem make it difficult for a flipped coin to land on its side)—we make a distinction between "thick" coins and "thin" coins (here thickness is measured relative to the coin's diameter). It could reasonably be assumed that:

P ( S | thin coin ) P ( S | thick coin ) {\displaystyle P(S|{\text{thin coin}})\neq P(S|{\text{thick coin}})}

Note that this new information probably wouldn't break the symmetry between "heads" and "tails," so that permutation would still apply in describing "equivalent problems", and we would require:

P ( T | thin coin ) = P ( H | thin coin ) P ( H | thick coin ) = P ( T | thick coin ) {\displaystyle P(T|{\text{thin coin}})=P(H|{\text{thin coin}})\neq P(H|{\text{thick coin}})=P(T|{\text{thick coin}})}

This is a good example of how the principle of transformation groups can be used to "flesh out" personal opinions. All of the information used in the derivation is explicitly stated. If a prior probability assignment doesn't "seem right" according to what your intuition tells you, then there must be some "background information" that has not been put into the problem. It is then the task to try and work out what that information is. In some sense, combining the method of transformation groups with one's intuition can be used to "weed out" the actual assumptions one has. This makes it a very powerful tool for prior elicitation.

Introducing the thickness of the coin as a variable is permissible because its existence was implied (by being a real coin) but its value was not specified in the problem. Introducing a "nuisance parameter" and then making the answer invariant to this parameter is a very useful technique for solving supposedly "ill-posed" problems like Bertrand's Paradox. This has been called "the well-posing strategy" by some.

A strength of this principle lies in its application to continuous parameters, where the notion of "complete ignorance" is not so well-defined as in the discrete case. However, if applied with infinite limits, it often gives improper prior distributions. Note that the discrete case for a countably infinite set, such as { 0 , 1 , 2 , . . . } {\displaystyle \{0,1,2,...\}} also produces an improper discrete prior. For most cases where the likelihood is sufficiently "steep," this does not present a problem. However, in order to be absolutely sure to avoid incoherent results and paradoxes, the prior distribution should be approached via a well-defined and well-behaved limiting process. One such process is the use of a sequence of priors with increasing range, such as f ( M ) = I ( M [ b , b ] ) 2 b {\displaystyle f(M)={I(M\in ) \over 2b}} where the limit b {\displaystyle b\rightarrow \infty } is to be taken at the end of the calculation, i.e. after the normalization of the posterior distribution. What this effectively does is ensure that one is taking the ratio limit and not the ratio of two limits. See Limit of a function#Properties for details on limits and why this order of operations is important.

If the limit of the ratio does not exist or diverges, then this gives an improper posterior (i.e., a posterior that does not integrate into one). This indicates that the data are so uninformative about the parameters that the prior probability of arbitrarily large values still matters in the final answer. In some sense, an improper posterior means that the information contained in the data has not "ruled out" arbitrarily large values. Looking at the improper priors this way, it seems to make some sense that "complete ignorance" priors should be improper because the information used to derive them is so meagre that it cannot rule out absurd values on its own. From a state of complete ignorance, only the data or some other form of additional information can rule out such absurdities.

References

  1. Jaynes, Edwin T. (1968). "Prior Probabilities" (PDF). IEEE Transactions on Systems Science and Cybernetics. 4 (3): 227–241. doi:10.1109/TSSC.1968.300117. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2023-06-21. Retrieved 2023-06-30.
  2. Jaynes, Edwin T. (1973). "The Well-Posed Problem" (PDF). Foundations of Physics. 3 (4): 477–492. Bibcode:1973FoPh....3..477J. doi:10.1007/BF00709116. S2CID 2380040. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-30.
  3. Jaynes, E. T. (1984). "Monkeys, Kangaroos, and N" (PDF). In Justice, James H. (ed.). Maximum Entropy and Bayesian Methods in Applied Statistics. Fourth Annual Workshop on Bayesian/Maximum Entropy Methods. Cambridge University Press. Retrieved 2023-11-13.
  4. Shackel, Nicholas (2007). "Bertrand's Paradox and the Principle of Indifference" (PDF). Philosophy of Science. 74 (2): 150–175. doi:10.1086/519028. JSTOR 519028. S2CID 15760612. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-01-28. Retrieved 2018-11-04.

Further reading

  • Edwin Thompson Jaynes. Probability Theory: The Logic of Science. Cambridge University Press, 2003. ISBN 0-521-59271-2.
Category: