Misplaced Pages

Vote-ratio monotonicity

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Property of apportionment methods
A joint Politics and Economics series
Social choice and electoral systems
Single-winner methodsSingle vote - plurality methods

Condorcet methods


Positional voting


Cardinal voting

Proportional representationParty-list

Quota-remainder methods


Approval-based committees


Fractional social choice


Semi-proportional representation

Mixed systemsBy results of combination
By mechanism of combination

By ballot type

Paradoxes and pathologiesSpoiler effects

Pathological response


Strategic voting


Paradoxes of majority rule

Social and collective choiceImpossibility theorems

Positive results

icon Mathematics portal
"Population-ratio monotonicity" redirects here. Not to be confused with Population monotonicity.

Vote-ratio, weight-ratio, or population-ratio monotonicity is a property of some apportionment methods. It says that if the entitlement for A {\displaystyle A} grows at a faster rate than B {\displaystyle B} (i.e. A {\displaystyle A} grows proportionally more than B {\displaystyle B} ), A {\displaystyle A} should not lose a seat to B {\displaystyle B} . More formally, if the ratio of votes or populations A / B {\displaystyle A/B} increases, then A {\displaystyle A} should not lose a seat while B {\displaystyle B} gains a seat. An apportionment method violating this rule may encounter population paradoxes.

A particularly severe variant, where voting for a party causes it to lose seats, is called a no-show paradox. The largest remainders method exhibits both population and no-show paradoxes.

Population-pair monotonicity

Pairwise monotonicity says that if the ratio between the entitlements of two states i , j {\displaystyle i,j} increases, then state j {\displaystyle j} should not gain seats at the expense of state i {\displaystyle i} . In other words, a shrinking state should not "steal" a seat from a growing state.

Some earlier apportionment rules, such as Hamilton's method, do not satisfy VRM, and thus exhibit the population paradox. For example, after the 1900 census, Virginia lost a seat to Maine, even though Virginia's population was growing more rapidly.

Strong monotonicity

A stronger variant of population monotonicity, called strong monotonicity requires that, if a state's entitlement (share of the population) increases, then its apportionment should not decrease, regardless of what happens to any other state's entitlement. This variant is extremely strong, however: whenever there are at least 3 states, and the house size is not exactly equal to the number of states, no apportionment method is strongly monotone for a fixed house size. Strong monotonicity failures in divisor methods happen when one state's entitlement increases, causing it to "steal" a seat from another state whose entitlement is unchanged.

However, it is worth noting that the traditional form of the divisor method, which involves using a fixed divisor and allowing the house size to vary, satisfies strong monotonicity in this sense.

Relation to other properties

Balinski and Young proved that an apportionment method is VRM if-and-only-if it is a divisor method.

Palomares, Pukelsheim and Ramirez proved that very apportionment rule that is anonymous, balanced, concordant, homogenous, and coherent is vote-ratio monotone.

Vote-ratio monotonicity implies that, if population moves from state i {\displaystyle i} to state j {\displaystyle j} while the populations of other states do not change, then both a i a i {\displaystyle a_{i}'\geq a_{i}} and a j a j {\displaystyle a_{j}'\leq a_{j}} must hold.

See also

References

  1. ^ Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2017), Pukelsheim, Friedrich (ed.), "Securing System Consistency: Coherence and Paradoxes", Proportional Representation: Apportionment Methods and Their Applications, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 159–183, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-64707-4_9, ISBN 978-3-319-64707-4, retrieved 2021-09-02
  2. Chakraborty, Mithun; Schmidt-Kraepelin, Ulrike; Suksompong, Warut (2021-04-29). "Picking sequences and monotonicity in weighted fair division". Artificial Intelligence. 301: 103578. arXiv:2104.14347. doi:10.1016/j.artint.2021.103578. S2CID 233443832.
  3. Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (1982). Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-300-02724-9.
  4. Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2017), Pukelsheim, Friedrich (ed.), "Securing System Consistency: Coherence and Paradoxes", Proportional Representation: Apportionment Methods and Their Applications, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 159–183, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-64707-4_9, ISBN 978-3-319-64707-4, retrieved 2021-09-02
  5. Stein, James D. (2008). How Math Explains the World: A Guide to the Power of Numbers, from Car Repair to Modern Physics. New York: Smithsonian Books. ISBN 9780061241765.
  6. Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (1982). Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-300-02724-9.
  7. Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (1982). Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-300-02724-9.
  8. Pukelsheim, Friedrich (2017), Pukelsheim, Friedrich (ed.), "Securing System Consistency: Coherence and Paradoxes", Proportional Representation: Apportionment Methods and Their Applications, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 159–183, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-64707-4_9, ISBN 978-3-319-64707-4, retrieved 2021-09-02
Category: